Walker Body of Persuasion

download Walker Body of Persuasion

of 21

Transcript of Walker Body of Persuasion

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    1/21

    The Body of Persuasion: A Theory of the EnthymemeAuthor(s): Jeffrey WalkerSource: College English, Vol. 56, No. 1 (Jan., 1994), pp. 46-65Published by: National Council of Teachers of EnglishStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/378216

    Accessed: 24/05/2010 23:49

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless

    you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you

    may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

    Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ncte.

    Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed

    page of such transmission.

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    National Council of Teachers of Englishis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

    College English.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/stable/378216?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=nctehttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=nctehttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/378216?origin=JSTOR-pdf
  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    2/21

    46

    THE

    BODY

    OF

    PERSUASION: A

    THEORY

    OF THE

    ENTHYMEME

    Jeffrey

    Walker

    hegenerally revailingoncept ftheenthymeme,r theonemost requent

    in the world of

    rhetoric and

    composition

    studies,

    tends to

    define

    it

    either as

    a

    kind

    of

    elliptical,

    informal

    syllogism

    based

    on

    probable

    rather

    than certain

    premises

    and

    on

    tacit

    assumptions

    shared

    by

    audience and

    rhetor,

    or

    as a kind

    of

    Toulmin

    argument,

    or as a

    general

    mode of

    intuitive

    reasoning representable

    in

    syllogistic

    or Toulminian

    terms, or,

    most

    simply,

    as

    the

    juxtaposition

    of

    any

    idea

    with another

    that

    is

    offered

    as

    a reason for

    believing

    it.

    All

    such

    thinking

    starts

    from

    Aristotle's

    famous

    dicta

    that the

    enthymeme

    is

    a

    kind of

    syllogism

    or

    rhetorical

    syllogism,

    and that

    rhetoric is

    a

    counterpart

    of dialectic

    (Rhetoric

    1.1 [1355a]; 1.2 [1356b]; 1.1 [1354a]).' This prevailing definition, however, has

    recently

    been

    put

    in

    question

    (see

    in

    particular

    Conley, Enthymeme ; Gage,

    Theory ).

    And,

    as

    we

    will

    see,

    it is

    inadequate.

    In

    what

    follows,

    we

    will

    first reexamine the

    primary

    (and

    not

    exclusively

    Aristotelian)

    ancient sources

    from

    which a more

    adequate

    concept

    of the en-

    thymeme

    can be derived.

    Then,

    we will

    consider the

    relevance

    of that

    concept

    to

    the

    analysis

    of modern

    discourse-specifically,

    to the

    analysis

    of Roland Barthes'

    The

    World

    of

    Wrestling

    and

    Martin

    Luther

    King,

    Jr.'s

    Letter

    from

    Birming-

    ham

    Jail,

    both

    of which

    appear

    in

    popular anthologies

    used in

    composition

    courses,

    and both

    of which

    provide good examples

    of modern-but

    unrecog-

    nized-enthymeming.

    The

    prevailing

    definition

    has,

    of

    course,

    some

    very

    real

    advantages.

    Chief

    among

    them

    is

    its

    tendency

    to

    emphasize

    the

    dialogic

    relation

    between writer

    and

    audience

    by requiring

    the writer to include

    the

    audience's

    thinking

    in

    the inven-

    Jeffrey

    Walker has

    just

    returned

    from a

    Fulbright

    Lectureship

    in

    Athens,

    Greece,

    where

    this

    article

    was

    completed.

    He is Associate

    Professor of

    English

    and Director of

    Composition

    at Penn State

    University.

    His

    publications

    include two

    previous

    articles in

    CollegeEnglish,

    and

    a

    book,

    BardicEthos

    and the American

    Epic

    Poem:

    Whitman,

    Pound,

    Crane, Williams,

    and

    Olson

    (LSU

    Press,

    1989).

    He is

    coauthor,

    with Glen

    McClish,

    of the

    anthology

    Investigating

    Arguments:Readingsor College

    Writing

    (Houghton Mifflin, 1991).

    COLLEGE

    ENGLISH,

    VOLUME

    56,

    NUMBER

    1,

    JANUARY

    1994

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    3/21

    A

    THEORY

    OF THE ENTHYMEME

    47

    tion

    process,

    rather than

    merely

    adapting

    the

    discourse to an audience consid-

    ered

    after the

    fact,

    or considered

    only

    as an external other to be

    manipulated

    or accommodated

    by

    the writer's

    unilateral,

    monologic

    action

    (Gage,

    Epistemol-

    ogy

    162-165).

    Such an

    approach

    to

    enthymematic

    rhetoric

    emphasizes

    both

    the

    ethics

    and the

    techniques

    of

    persuasion,

    as well as the

    epistemological

    and ideo-

    logical

    nature

    of

    rhetoric

    by

    requiring

    the writer to examine

    carefully

    the

    system

    of

    presuppositions

    underlying

    any given

    line of

    reasoning.

    And since it is

    the

    epistemology/ideology

    of an audience

    that is in

    question,

    and not

    merely

    that of

    a

    romantically

    isolated

    individual,

    this

    approach

    then leads to some form

    of

    cultural

    criticism or

    to

    something

    like the ancient

    sophists'

    skeptical

    mode

    of

    inquiry

    into conventional

    belief.

    It is also the

    case,

    however,

    that the

    currently prevailing

    notion of the

    enthymeme

    as a rhetorical

    syllogism

    is

    problematic

    in

    several

    ways, especially

    as we

    find it too often

    oversimplified

    in

    English

    handbooks

    currently

    in

    use

    in

    composition

    classes.

    First,

    it all too

    easily

    permits

    an

    appropriation

    of the

    concept

    that takes

    inadequate

    account

    of what

    syllogism might

    mean

    in

    a rhetorical

    context

    or what it means

    in

    ancient Greek

    apart

    from

    (or

    before)

    the

    technical,

    specialized significance

    developed

    in

    Aristotle's

    treatises

    on

    logic

    and dialectic.

    Plato,

    for

    example, appears

    to

    have

    used

    the

    term

    syllogismos

    to

    mean,

    simply,

    add

    up

    the results

    (Quandahl 133).

    Similarly,

    we find

    the

    great sophist

    Isocrates

    using the word syllogisamenoin reference to the way an ordinary person intui-

    tively

    derives an inference or

    judgment

    from

    a bundle of observations

    (Against

    the

    Sophists

    7-8).

    This

    intuitive

    syllogizing,

    moreover,

    is

    set

    in

    opposition

    to

    what

    Isocrates

    calls

    eristics,

    the

    logic-chopping

    verbal combat of

    professional

    dialec-

    ticians who

    claim to have

    precise

    or exact

    knowledge.

    Even

    Aristotle,

    at the

    beginning

    of the

    Topics,

    dopts

    a

    casual,

    informal

    definition

    of the

    syllogism

    as

    a

    logos,

    a

    reasoning

    or

    discourse

    in

    which certain

    things having

    been laid

    down,

    other

    things

    necessarily

    derive from them

    (1.1

    [100a]).

    At

    this

    point

    he is

    probably drawing

    on a

    commonly

    received

    conception,

    one that

    would

    be

    familiar

    for the audience of an introductory lecture. In the same place, dialectical syllo-

    gizing

    is

    defined as

    reasoning

    from

    doxa,

    generally

    accepted opinions,

    or

    more

    specifically

    as

    reasoning

    from doxa

    granted

    or

    accepted by

    one's

    interlocutor(s),

    one's

    audience

    (1.1 [100b]).

    My

    point

    is

    that

    the

    nontechnical

    meaning

    of

    syllogism

    in

    ancient

    Greek

    seems

    to

    be

    nothing

    more than

    ordinary,

    informal

    reasoning

    and

    inference,

    and

    that,

    in

    the context of

    discussion and

    debate,

    this

    meaning

    includes informal

    (as

    well as

    formal)

    reasoning/inference

    from

    probable

    assumptions

    granted by

    one's

    audience.

    If, then,

    syllogism

    can be

    used

    in

    such a sense with reference to

    everyday thought and discourse, why use enthymeme to name the same thing?

    By carelessly invoking

    enthymeme

    as the rhetorical

    syllogism,

    we

    may

    be

    making

    a

    distinction without a difference.

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    4/21

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    5/21

    A THEORY OF THE ENTHYMEME

    49

    motive,

    of the sometimes

    uncontrollable

    forces

    of

    desire

    and wish

    that

    drive

    human

    intentionality. Thymos s, moreover,

    often linked to both the

    production

    and

    the

    reception

    of

    passional thought

    and

    eloquent, persuasive

    discourse.

    Pin-

    dar,

    for

    example,

    tells

    how

    the

    crafty

    Hippolyta

    strove

    with all

    her

    heart

    (thymos)

    o

    seduce

    the

    ever-virtuous

    Peleus

    with

    beguiling

    words and

    falsely

    inventing

    wove

    a

    tale

    to

    persuade

    her husband that Peleus had tried

    to

    seduce

    her

    (Nemean

    5,

    lines

    26-31);

    Hesiod in the

    prologue

    of Works nd

    Days

    (line

    27)

    tells

    his

    addressee, Perses,

    to

    lay

    up

    these

    things

    in

    your

    heart

    (thymos).

    The word

    enthymema

    and its relatives

    clearly

    are

    grounded

    in

    such a field

    of

    meanings.

    As Miller

    and Bee have

    noted,

    for

    example,

    the

    verb

    enthymeomai

    as

    a semantic

    range

    that includes such

    meanings

    as

    lay

    to

    heart,

    consider

    well,

    reflect

    on,

    think

    deeply

    about,

    be hurt or

    angry

    at,

    form

    a

    plan,

    infer,

    conclude

    202).

    En-

    thymeming,

    then,

    would

    appear

    to

    include

    both

    the

    inference-making

    of

    the

    heart and the

    strategic intentionality

    of

    forming plans.

    In the

    case of

    rhetoric,

    moreover,

    this

    strategic intentionality

    includes what I

    will

    call kairotic

    nventive-

    ness -that

    is,

    an

    inventiveness

    responsive

    to

    what ancient

    rhetoricians called

    kairos,

    the

    opportune

    at

    any

    given

    moment in a

    particular

    rhetorical

    situation.

    For

    a

    pre-

    or

    non-Aristotelian

    notion

    of

    the

    enthymeme

    in

    rhetoric,

    our

    best

    sources are

    probably

    Isocrates and the

    otherwise

    unknown

    writer

    of the

    Rhetoric to

    Alexander,

    Anaximenes of

    Lampsacus.

    For

    Isocrates,

    enthymeme-

    making is not only a matter of kairotic inventiveness, but is also linked to matters

    of

    style.

    In

    the

    Panegyricus,

    or

    example,

    he tells us

    that

    to

    suit the kairos

    of a

    discourse with

    fitting

    enthymemes

    and

    with words

    well

    arranged

    s

    the

    special

    gift

    of

    those

    of

    good

    intelligence

    (9-10).

    In

    Against

    the

    Sophists,

    ikewise,

    he

    portrays

    the

    ability

    to see

    what

    kairos

    demands,

    and

    speak

    a discourse

    wholly

    wrought

    with

    fitting

    enthymemes

    and words both

    rhythmic

    and musical

    as

    the

    essence of

    rhetorical

    skill

    (16-17).

    These statements

    are

    fairly

    typical

    (see,

    for

    example,

    Evagoras

    10-11

    and Antidosis

    46-47,

    319).

    In

    Isocrates,

    a

    mention of

    the

    enthymeme

    is seldom

    without,

    and

    seldom far

    from,

    a

    reference to

    stylistic

    matters; and indeed they often occur together in the same sentence.

    Isocrates'

    notion of

    the

    enthymeme,

    then,

    appears

    to

    include,

    or to

    be

    linked

    to,

    passional

    thought,

    kairotic

    inventiveness,

    and

    style-and

    it

    clearly occupies

    a

    central

    place

    in

    his

    conception

    of

    rhetorical skill.

    But

    Isocrates

    will

    not

    give

    us

    the

    satisfaction

    of

    a

    rigidly

    precise

    or

    systematic

    account

    of the

    enthymeme,

    since

    in

    general

    he

    denies the

    possibility

    or

    usefulness of

    exact

    knowledge

    and

    does

    not

    consider rhetoric

    reducible to

    techne

    for

    a

    discussion of this

    denial,

    see

    Cahn).

    For

    more

    explicit

    codification,

    we

    must

    turn

    to

    Anaximenes'

    Rhetoric o

    Alexander,

    a

    sophistic

    techne

    written

    probably

    in

    the

    generation

    after

    Aristotle (and for

    many

    centuries incorrectly attributed to Aristotle). What Anaximenes offers is the

    fullest

    surviving presentation

    of a

    sophistic

    notion of

    enthymeme

    that

    is

    gener-

    ally

    taken both to

    precede

    and to

    follow

    Aristotle's

    Rhetoric,

    and that with a

    long

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    6/21

    50

    COLLEGE ENGLISH

    survival

    in

    Hellenistic, Roman,

    and

    Byzantine

    treatises

    appears

    to be the

    domi-

    nant

    tradition

    in

    antiquity (see Grimaldi,

    Studies

    67-82; Conley, Enthymeme ).

    According

    to

    Anaximenes,

    enthymemes

    are

    oppositions

    or

    contradictions

    not

    only

    in

    words or

    in

    actions..,

    .but

    also

    in

    anything

    else.

    Enthymemes,

    he

    says,

    are

    to

    be invented

    by inspecting

    an

    opponent's

    discourse

    or

    an action for

    anything

    that is

    contradictory

    either with

    itself or

    with

    the

    principles

    of

    justice,

    law,

    expediency,

    honor,

    feasibility, facility

    or

    probability,

    or

    with the character

    of the

    speaker

    or

    the usual course

    of

    events. The

    speaker

    is then

    to

    make his

    own

    case

    by

    showing

    that his words

    or

    actions are

    exactly contrary

    to

    those that are

    unjust,

    unlawful

    and

    inexpedient,

    and to

    the usual conduct of bad

    men,

    in

    brief

    to whatever

    is

    deemed

    evil,

    phrasing

    his

    enthymemes

    or

    oppositions

    as

    briefly

    and

    economically

    as

    possible

    (10

    [1430a]).

    Anaximenes

    expands

    this account

    by

    noting

    that one invents and

    deploys

    enthymemes

    by

    following

    the

    methods

    of what

    he calls exetastic

    discourse,

    meaning

    what

    we

    might

    call

    inquiry,

    investigation,

    or

    critique.

    Exetasis,

    for

    Anaximenes,

    is an exhibition

    of

    inconsistencies

    in

    someone's

    intentions, deeds,

    or

    words

    (5

    [1427b]),

    and is

    not

    a

    separate

    genre

    but a

    general

    method that is used

    in

    every

    kind

    of

    public

    discourse

    (37

    [1445a]).

    The

    actual

    deployment

    of exetasis

    is

    to

    go

    as

    follows:

    first,

    one introduces

    plausible pretexts

    for

    proceeding

    to an

    examination;

    then,

    one examines

    the

    actions, words,

    or

    intentions

    in

    question,

    exposing

    the contradictions into which they fall. Finally, Anaximenes advises the

    speaker,

    when

    you

    have

    carefully

    examined

    everything

    and have

    amplified

    your

    points,

    conclude

    by giving

    a concise

    repetition, recalling

    what

    you

    have

    said to

    your

    hearer's

    memory

    (37 [1445a-b]).

    For

    Anaximenes,

    then,

    it

    would

    appear

    that

    an

    enthymeme

    is,

    or

    is

    like,

    the

    argumentational

    cap

    that finishes

    an

    exetastic

    movement: a

    concise,

    emphatic

    statement

    of an

    emotionally

    charged

    opposition,

    one that serves

    not

    only

    to draw

    conclusions

    but also

    to

    foreground

    stance

    or

    attitude

    toward the

    subject

    under

    discussion

    and

    to motivate

    the audience

    to

    strongly

    identify

    with that stance

    (this

    is identification as Kenneth Burke uses it [Rhetoric17-29, 55-59]). The audi-

    ence

    is to feel

    not

    simply

    that

    the

    speaker's

    claims

    are true or

    probable,

    but

    that

    both

    speaker

    and

    claims are

    good

    and

    admirable,

    and the

    very

    opposite

    of what is

    false, bad,

    and detestable.

    Like

    Isocrates,

    Anaximenes

    appears

    to

    link

    stylistic

    with

    enthymematic

    con-

    cerns.

    Only

    seven

    of

    the

    thirty-eight

    chapters

    in the Rhetoric

    to Alexander

    are

    directly

    concerned

    with

    style,

    or

    with

    what Anaximenes

    calls

    the sources

    of

    urbanity,

    but,

    significantly,

    he

    begins

    with

    reference

    to the

    enthymeme:

    Ur-

    banity

    is

    achieved

    in

    this

    way--you

    state

    half an

    enthymeme,

    so that the audience

    may understand the other half for themselves (22 [1434a]). Moreover, of the ten

    sources of

    urbanity

    Anaximenes

    discusses,

    seven seem

    highly

    relevant

    to the

    concise and

    emphatic

    statement

    of

    emotionally charged

    oppositions:

    brevity,

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    7/21

    A

    THEORY

    OF THE

    ENTHYMEME

    51

    adapting

    the ethos

    of the words to that of the

    audience,

    methods of

    framing

    twofold

    statements,

    clarity,

    antithesis,

    and

    parallelisms

    of structure and

    of

    sound.

    Moreover,

    while the other three sources

    of

    urbanity

    do not seem

    clearly

    related

    to

    the statement

    of

    brief,

    emphatic

    enthymemes-these

    are

    lengthening

    (by

    creating

    and

    multiplying

    divisions

    within a

    topic

    and

    dwelling

    on

    each),

    speaking

    at moderate

    length,

    and

    composition

    (the

    choice and

    arrangement

    of

    words)-they

    do seem relevant to the

    build-up

    of

    an exetastic movement and

    may

    perhaps

    also

    be

    seen as variant

    strategies

    for the statement of elaborated

    enthy-

    memes.

    Anaximenes's discussion of

    style,

    in

    sum,

    seems

    mainly

    (though certainly

    not

    exclusively)

    concerned

    with the

    methods

    of

    effectively

    stating

    enthymemes-

    that

    is,

    with the methods

    of

    enhancing

    an

    enthymeme's

    prominence

    and

    memorability

    or what Perelman would call its

    presence

    in its audience's mind

    (New

    Rhetoric

    115-120,

    144-148).

    There

    are, however,

    important

    differences

    between

    Anaximenes and

    Isocrates,

    and a failure to note them will commit us to

    an

    excessively

    narrow

    concept

    of the

    enthymeme.

    Anaximenes,

    after

    all,

    is the

    kind

    of

    sophist

    Isocrates

    most

    despises:

    one who

    considers rhetoric reducible

    to

    techne

    and

    has therefore

    written

    a

    manual),

    and

    who, moreover,

    focuses his

    teachings

    chiefly

    on

    the

    methods

    of

    winning

    lawsuits

    (for

    Isocrates'

    disapproval

    of

    such

    rhetoricians,

    see

    Against

    the

    Sophists

    19-20

    and Antidosis

    47-50).

    This

    emphasis

    is what

    explains

    the

    rather prosecutorial, inquisitorial nature that Anaximenes gives to both the en-

    thymeme

    and the exetastic: he

    sounds

    very

    much like

    the eristical or

    combative

    kind

    of

    sophist,

    always

    on the watch for

    contradictions,

    whom

    Isocrates takes

    to

    task. For

    Isocrates,

    enthymemes

    are used not

    only

    in

    the rhetorical

    combats of

    courts and

    assemblies,

    and not

    only

    in

    eristics,

    but

    also

    in

    poetry

    and

    what he

    calls

    the

    philosophical

    and

    panegyric

    kinds

    of

    discourse that he

    himself

    practices

    and

    teaches;

    and indeed the

    enthymemes

    in

    these latter

    genres

    he

    considers

    most

    lofty

    and

    original

    (Evagoras

    10-11;

    Antidosis

    46-47, 319).

    It

    is difficult

    to see how

    one could

    generate

    enthymemes

    in

    such

    genres

    exclusively by

    indicting

    the

    flaws

    and inconsistencies of an opponent. In a famous passage of the Panegyricus,one

    can see

    Isocrates

    exploiting

    oppositions

    in

    a

    noninquisitorial

    way

    to

    motivate

    identification,

    or

    what

    Perelman

    calls

    adherence

    (New

    Rhetoric

    1-44,

    49-54,

    104-110),

    with his

    vision

    of

    Pan-Hellenism:

    Athens...

    has honored

    eloquence,

    which

    all

    desire in

    the

    wisely

    skilled;

    or she

    realized hat

    by

    this

    alone we

    are

    unique

    among

    all

    creatures,

    nd that

    because

    of

    this

    advantage

    we

    have

    surpassed

    hem

    altogether;

    and she

    saw that

    in

    other

    pursuits

    ortune s

    so

    capricious

    hat

    often

    the

    wise

    fail

    and

    the

    foolish

    succeed,

    whereaswords

    possessing

    both

    beauty

    and art arenot the

    fool's but are

    truly

    the

    work

    of an

    intelligent

    soul,

    and

    in

    this

    respect

    the wise and the

    ignorant

    most

    completelydifferfrom eachother;andshe knew, urthermore,hatwhethermen

    havebeen

    liberally

    ducated

    romthestart s shown

    not

    in

    their

    courage

    or

    wealth

    or such

    advantages,

    ut is

    most

    certainly

    made

    manifest n

    speech,

    which

    is

    of

    all

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    8/21

    52

    COLLEGE

    ENGLISH

    such

    signs

    the

    surest

    proof

    of

    culture

    n

    everyone,

    and

    that those

    who use

    discourse

    well are

    not

    only

    influential

    among

    their

    friends

    but

    also are

    truly

    held

    in

    high

    esteembyothers.Andso farhasourcityoutpacedallothers n thoughtandspeech

    that her students

    havebecomethe

    teachers

    of

    the

    rest,

    so that the

    word

    Hellenes

    suggests

    no

    longer

    a race but a

    way

    of

    thought,

    and the title Hellenes

    pplies

    o

    those

    who share our culture

    rather than to

    those

    who share a common blood.

    (48-50)

    In this

    enthymeme

    of

    great

    persuasive

    force

    and

    enormous cultural

    power,

    Isocrates establishes

    the

    vision

    that

    defined the Hellenistic ideal of

    paideia

    for

    centuries to

    come.

    Its

    power

    derives not

    only

    from

    a

    syllogistic

    marshaling

    of

    evidence

    to

    justify

    a conclusion

    (the

    claim that Athens has

    become

    the

    school

    of

    all Hellas because it has most honored

    eloquence

    is, in truth,

    weakly supported

    here,

    though

    earlier

    passages

    do

    give

    it some

    evidential

    ground).

    Rather,

    this

    enthymeme's power

    lies in its use

    of

    emotively significant

    oppositions

    (hu-

    man/animal,

    wise/foolish,

    cultured/ignorant,

    achievement/luck,

    etc.),

    defining

    eloquence

    as the

    distinguishing

    feature

    of

    human-ness

    and the distinctive

    sign

    of

    an

    accomplished

    and wise

    intelligence,

    to motivate

    the audience's

    admiration

    and

    desire-the

    wish

    that Athens

    should

    indeed be

    the

    school

    of

    Hellas-a desire

    that

    drives

    (or

    simply

    is)

    adherence

    with

    Isocrates' vision

    of a

    cosmopolitan

    cultural

    identity

    defined

    by thought

    (the

    distinctly

    human,

    the

    discursively

    constructed)

    rather than by blood (the animal and accidental).

    In

    considering

    the

    differences

    between

    Anaximenes and

    Isocrates,

    moreover,

    we

    should

    recall

    Isocrates'

    emphasis

    on

    the

    kairotic

    aspect

    of

    enthymemes,

    in

    particular

    his notion

    that the best

    enthymemes

    will be

    what he

    calls

    apotomos,

    abrupt

    (Evagoras

    10-11).

    Abruptness may

    signify,

    from

    one

    point

    of

    view,

    simply

    the

    concise,

    emphatic

    quality

    that

    Anaximenes

    attributes

    to the

    en-

    thymeme,

    or the

    idea

    that

    in

    public

    speaking

    enthymemes

    should

    be

    plain-spoken

    and

    to

    the

    point.

    But

    the

    adjective

    apotomos

    nd the verb

    apotemno

    rom

    which

    it

    derives

    have

    other

    kinds

    of

    significance

    also,

    including

    cut off or

    sever,

    and

    in the adjective a sense of precipitousness, or metaphorically of surprise, as in the

    feeling

    of

    coming

    suddenly upon

    the

    edge

    of a cliff. What this

    suggests

    is

    that,

    as

    opposed

    to

    Anaximenes'

    somewhat

    mechanistic

    picture

    of

    an exetastic

    movement

    grinding

    out

    an

    inquisitorial

    investigation,

    which

    is then

    pithily

    summed

    up

    by

    an

    enthymeme,

    for

    Isocrates

    the best and

    most

    effective

    enthymemes

    will in

    some

    sense come

    as

    a

    surprise

    and stand

    apart

    from

    or

    go

    beyond

    what

    precedes

    them.

    They

    will seize

    the

    kairos

    of the

    moment

    to

    move

    the

    audience

    to

    a decisive

    recognition

    that

    is

    or seems

    lofty

    and

    original,

    while

    at

    the same time

    cutting

    off

    or

    shifting

    into the

    background

    other

    possible

    recognitions

    that

    may

    be

    latent

    in the buildup.

    This

    is what

    we

    see,

    again,

    in the

    passage

    from Isocrates'

    Panegyricus.

    The

    culminating

    vision

    or stance of

    that

    passage,

    while motivated

    and made

    persuasive

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    9/21

    A

    THEORY OF THE ENTHYMEME

    53

    by

    the

    preceding

    exetasis,

    does not

    inevitably

    follow

    from it and

    certainly

    does

    not

    summarize

    it. Isocrates

    might,

    for

    example,

    turn to

    blaming

    Athens'

    disas-

    trous failure

    in

    the

    recently

    ended

    Peloponnesian

    War on failure to

    honor

    eloquence

    and a

    consequent

    descent to

    politics

    determined

    by

    wealth,

    blood-

    loyalties,

    and brutal force. Such

    a turn

    would

    not serve his

    purpose

    in the

    Panegyricus,

    but it

    is

    latent

    in his

    exetasis;

    and

    it is

    pushed

    into

    the

    background by

    what he

    foregrounds.

    (In

    the

    following passage,

    he

    explicitly

    confronts

    this

    point

    by declaring

    that he

    does not

    want

    to

    seem

    to be

    praising

    Athens'

    cultural

    achievement because

    I

    lack

    grounds

    for

    praising

    her conduct

    in

    war

    [51].)

    Isocrates'

    enthymeme,

    in

    sum,

    arrives

    (for

    its

    audience)

    as

    a

    brilliant,

    inspirational

    stroke of

    insight,

    a

    decisive turn

    that

    brings suddenly

    into focus and

    gives

    memo-

    rable

    presence

    to a

    particular

    turn of

    thought

    the kairosof its moment has made

    possible;

    it is

    indeed

    apotomos.

    Between Anaximenes and

    Isocrates, then,

    we

    might

    derive

    a

    reasonably

    full

    picture

    of

    a

    sophistic,

    non-Aristotelian notion of

    the

    enthymeme

    that is

    pervasive

    in

    the Hellenistic

    rhetorical tradition: the

    enthymeme

    is a

    strategic,

    kairotic,

    argumentational

    turn

    that

    exploits

    a

    cluster

    of

    emotively

    charged,

    value-laden

    oppositions

    made available

    (usually) by

    an

    exetastic

    buildup,

    in

    order to

    generate

    in

    its audience a

    passional

    identification

    with

    or

    adherence

    to

    a

    particular

    stance,

    and that

    (ideally)

    will

    strike

    the audience as an

    abrupt

    and

    decisive flash of

    insight. To be most effective, this enthymematic turn will exploit a range of

    stylistic

    schemes

    (antithesis,

    parallelism,

    and

    compactness

    in

    particular)

    to

    inten-

    sify

    its

    impact

    and enhance its

    presence

    and

    memorability

    in

    the

    audience's

    psyche.

    As

    such,

    the

    enthymematic

    turn

    is

    the

    rhetorical move

    par

    excellence or

    guiding

    an

    audience's

    inference-making

    and

    attitude-formation in a

    particular

    direction.

    From

    this

    perspective,

    we can

    understand

    why

    the

    ability

    to

    see what

    kairos

    demands,

    and

    speak

    a

    discourse

    wholly

    wrought

    with

    fitting

    enthymemes

    figures

    so

    prominently

    in

    Isocrates'

    account

    of

    discursive

    skill,

    and

    why,

    after

    Isocrates,

    the enthymeme would figure so prominently in Aristotle's account of rhetoric.

    For

    if

    the

    function of

    rhetoric is

    to

    guide

    an

    audience

    toward a

    particular

    recognition

    or

    stance

    or

    a

    choice

    of

    actions,

    then the

    setting-up

    and

    deployment

    of

    impressive

    enthymemes

    is

    indeed the

    essence and

    sum of

    what an

    effective

    rhetor does. All

    else

    is,

    as

    Aristotle

    says,

    accessory

    o

    enthymeming

    (Rhetoric

    1.1

    [1354a]).

    Aristotle's

    appropriation

    of

    the term

    enthymema

    must,

    I

    think,

    be

    considered

    to

    presuppose

    all

    that

    we have

    reviewed

    thus far. It

    is

    significant,

    for

    example,

    that

    the

    so-called common

    material

    topics

    for

    enthymematic

    invention in Rhetoric

    2.19-the possible and the impossible, past fact and future fact, and largeness and

    smallness

    (of

    goods

    and

    evils)-are

    largely

    matters of

    opposition

    or

    contrast. It

    is

    significant,

    too,

    that

    the famous

    catalogue

    of

    twenty-eight

    formal

    topics

    in

    2.23

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    10/21

    54 COLLEGE ENGLISH

    begins

    with

    opposites,

    and

    that,

    though

    not

    all of

    the

    remaining twenty-seven

    are

    clearly

    matters of

    opposition

    or

    contrast,

    most

    of

    them are

    (seventeen, by my

    count).

    Even

    those that

    are not

    obviously

    matters

    of

    exploiting

    oppositions

    tend

    to be illustrated

    with

    examples

    that do

    just

    that,

    as

    in

    topic

    #5,

    looking

    at the

    time

    (from

    Iphicrates' speech

    against

    Harmodius):

    If,

    before

    accomplishing

    anything,

    I

    asked

    to be honored with

    a

    statue

    if I

    succeeded,

    you

    would

    have

    granted

    it. Will

    you

    not

    grant

    it now when

    I

    have succeeded? Do

    not

    then make

    a

    promise

    in

    anticipation

    but

    refuse it in

    realization

    (1397b).

    All

    this

    is

    consistent

    with the

    picture

    we

    get

    from

    Anaximenes and

    Isocrates.

    The same

    is true

    for Aristotle's statements that the normal

    language

    of

    enthy-

    memes

    is

    compact,

    antithetical utterance

    (2.24 [1401a])

    and that

    opposites

    stand

    out more

    clearly

    when

    juxtaposed

    (3.27

    [1418b]);

    or his discussion of the advan-

    tages

    of

    periodic

    style, rhythm,

    antithesis,

    metaphors,

    and

    bringing-before-the-

    eyes

    for

    enthymemes

    (3.9-10);

    or his advice that the

    proof

    section

    of a

    speech

    should

    not consist

    of a continuous

    string

    of

    enthymemes,

    but rather

    that the

    enthymemes

    should

    be mixed

    in

    (3.17 [1418a]).

    As Thomas

    Conley

    has ob-

    served,

    these

    kinds

    of remarks

    suggest

    that Aristotle is

    thinking

    of

    enthymemes

    as

    nicely

    turned sentences

    or

    [elenctic, rhetorical]

    questions

    raised at climactic

    points

    ( Enthymeme

    171).

    Further,

    Aristotle's inclusion

    of

    pathos

    and

    ethos

    among

    the

    enthymematic

    sources of

    persuasion

    in

    2.2-17

    suggests

    that,

    like

    Anaximenes and Isocrates, he considers enthymemes to be something more than

    an act

    of... reason

    (Grimaldi,

    Studies

    82)

    and

    to

    carry

    affective

    force-although

    he

    also

    says

    that

    enthymemes

    should

    not

    be

    used when

    one is

    trying

    to arouse

    pathos

    or

    project

    ethos,

    in

    which

    he seems to differ

    from his

    sophistic

    colleagues.

    One

    might,

    however,

    resolve

    the

    seeming

    contradiction

    by

    noting

    that it is

    mainly

    the

    exetastic

    buildup

    that will

    generate

    the affective

    charge

    and ethical

    posture

    that

    an

    enthymeme

    will then

    exploit;

    and

    one

    might

    note,

    as

    Kennedy

    does

    in his

    translation

    of the Rhetoric

    [123],

    that

    Aristotle does

    give

    examples

    of

    emotional

    appeals

    that

    take the

    form

    of

    enthymemes.

    (For

    discussion

    of this

    issue,

    see

    Grimaldi, Studies 147-151 and Commentary349-356; Fortenbaugh 11-18; Con-

    ley,

    Pathe

    and

    Pisteis ;

    Wisse

    20-29;

    Walker,

    Enthymemes

    of

    Anger. )

    Aristotle's

    contribution

    to

    the notion

    of

    enthymeme

    is,

    of

    course,

    his

    insistence

    on its

    underlying

    rationality-his

    crucial

    and

    enormously productive

    recognition

    that,

    like the

    dialectical

    syllogism,

    the

    enthymeme

    relies

    on a

    basic,

    intuitive

    capacity

    for

    deriving

    inferences

    and

    forming judgments

    from relation-

    ships

    between

    ideas-so

    that

    condensed,

    antithetical

    expression

    alone does

    not

    make an

    enthymeme

    (Rhetoric

    1.1

    [1355a],

    2.24

    [1401a]).

    Aristotle's

    dialectical

    syllogism

    is,

    in

    effect,

    a kind

    of

    explanatory

    metaphor,

    a

    simplified

    one,

    for

    the

    kind of inferential process on which enthymemes depend for their effects. But, as

    Aristotle is careful

    to

    note

    (1.1 [1355a]),

    the

    enthymeme

    and

    syllogism

    arenot the

    same,

    and

    the differences

    are

    more than matters

    of

    probability

    vs. truth

    or

    explicit

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    11/21

    A THEORY OF THE ENTHYMEME

    55

    vs.

    implicit premises

    or

    reasoning

    from shared

    presuppositions,

    all

    of which

    are

    characteristic

    of

    both

    rhetoric and dialectic

    and are for the most

    part

    confined

    to

    the realm

    of

    propositional

    reasoning.

    We

    must,

    I

    think,

    consider

    Aristotle's

    account of the

    dialogic rationality

    of

    enthymemes

    as an addition to and

    emenda-

    tion of a

    sophistic

    notion of

    enthymeme

    that he has inherited

    from

    his

    prede-

    cessors.

    The

    enthymeme,

    in

    sum,

    shares with the dialectical

    syllogism

    an

    underlying

    rationality

    grounded

    in

    the

    psychology

    of

    inference-making

    and

    of

    reasoning

    in

    a

    conversational

    exchange;

    but it is

    also,

    and

    distinctively,

    what

    Anaximenes and Isocrates describe.

    EXAMPLES OF MODERN ENTHYMEMING

    We

    can

    argue

    that the ancient

    concept

    of

    enthymeme

    has a direct

    bearing

    on

    contemporary

    discourse.

    One

    might,

    for

    example,

    point

    to

    John

    E

    Kennedy's

    famous ask not

    what

    your country

    can

    do for

    you;

    ask what

    you

    can do for

    your

    country

    as an

    enthymematic

    turn of

    Isocratean

    elegance;

    or one

    might point

    to

    Lloyd

    Bentsen's

    memorable

    gutting

    of

    Dan

    Quayle

    in

    the

    1988

    Vice

    Presidential

    debate- I

    knew

    Jack

    Kennedy;

    Jack

    Kennedy

    was a

    friend

    of

    mine;

    and

    believe

    me, Senator,

    you're

    no

    Jack

    Kennedy -as

    an

    enthymematic

    zinger

    worthy

    of

    Anaximenes. But

    probably

    some reservations and

    qualifications

    need to be

    kept

    in mind. The most obvious is the fact that very few modern writers (or speakers)

    have had a

    training

    in

    argumentation

    centered

    on,

    or

    even

    including,

    an

    explicit

    theory

    of

    the

    enthymeme,

    and thus are

    unlikely

    to

    be

    self-consciously

    turning

    enthymemes,

    though they may

    in

    fact

    be

    turning

    them.

    We should not

    then

    expect contemporary

    enthymeming

    to

    take the

    conventional

    stylistic

    form

    of

    ancient

    enthymeming.

    But as

    Aristotle

    points

    out,

    it

    is

    ultimately

    not

    any particu-

    lar

    stylistic

    form

    that

    makes

    an

    enthymeme

    an

    enthymeme.

    What

    remains

    characteristic

    of

    the

    enthymeme

    today,

    I

    think,

    is

    that it

    is

    a

    stylistically

    intensified

    argumentative

    turn

    that

    serves not

    only

    to draw

    conclu-

    sions but also, and decisively, to foreground stance and motivate identification

    with

    that stance.

    And,

    further,

    its

    motivating

    force

    will

    derive

    not

    simply

    from

    a

    propositional

    logic

    (the

    kind

    that can be

    analyzed

    with

    syllogistic

    or

    Toulminian

    diagrams),

    but from what

    Perelman

    has called a

    web or

    network of

    emotively

    significant

    ideas and

    liaisons

    that

    may

    or

    may

    not

    appear

    as a

    structure

    of

    value-

    laden

    oppositions.

    A

    good example

    of

    modern

    enthymeming-without-knowing-it

    is

    Roland

    Barthes'

    sophistical

    performance

    in

    the lead-off

    essay

    of

    Mythologies,

    The World

    of

    Wrestling

    (reprinted

    in

    Waysof

    Reading

    [ed.

    David Barholomae

    and

    Anthony

    Petrosky] and in InvestigatingArguments[ed. Jeffrey Walker and Glen McClish]).

    Barthes,

    is,

    of

    course,

    aware of

    the classical

    rhetorical

    tradition,

    or

    a certain

    neoclassical

    interpretation

    of

    it,

    and of

    the

    enthymeme

    as

    well. In

    S/Z he

    calls it

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    12/21

    56

    COLLEGE ENGLISH

    the foundation

    of all

    proof'

    (201,

    LXXXI/5

    10).

    But

    for

    Barthes the

    enthymeme

    is

    only

    an

    imperfect syllogism

    or

    deduction,

    being

    fallacious,

    incomplete,

    or

    merely

    probable,

    and founded

    on a

    current

    opinion,

    an

    endoxa,

    ather than a

    scientific

    verity.

    He

    consistently presents it-along

    with that other

    old

    rhetori-

    cal

    deity, example/ induction -as

    a

    lure

    by

    which Balzac's

    Sarrasine

    deludes

    himself,

    a

    lure

    made

    of

    social discourse that

    ultimately

    constitutes his blind-

    ness

    and

    conducts

    ...

    the

    subject

    to

    the

    final

    castration

    (S/Z

    153-154, LXIII;

    see also

    172-173,

    LXXII).

    As

    Barthes

    portrays

    it,

    the

    enthymeme

    is

    a

    tool

    or form

    of false

    consciousness,

    an

    instrument

    of

    ideological

    domination.

    It seems

    unlikely,

    then,

    that

    Barthes conceives

    himself as one who

    argues

    enthymematically.

    But

    in The World of

    Wrestling,

    Barthes

    does

    exactly that-although

    the

    enthymeme

    as he

    actually

    uses it is not what he thinks it

    is; indeed,

    it is more like

    what

    Anaximenes and

    Isocrates describe.

    Here,

    for

    example,

    is

    the

    enthymeme

    with

    which Barthes ends

    his

    essay

    (it

    is,

    in

    fact,

    his

    final

    sentence):

    In

    the

    ring,

    and

    even

    in

    the

    depths

    of their

    nvoluntarygnominy,

    wrestlers emain

    gods

    because

    hey

    are,

    for

    a

    few

    moments,

    the

    key

    which

    opens

    Nature,

    the

    pure

    gesture

    which

    separates

    Good

    from

    Evil and

    unveilsthe

    figure

    of

    a

    Justice

    at last

    intelligible.

    21)

    This flourish

    of

    enthymematic

    eloquence clearly

    functions

    in

    its context

    as a

    stylistically

    intensified

    argumentative

    turn that

    is meant to

    stand forth

    as an

    abrupt

    and

    culminating

    flash of

    insight,

    and

    clearly

    serves also to

    project

    a

    stance-opposing

    the

    wrestler's

    actual

    (if

    momentary) glory

    to

    his

    apparent

    igno-

    miny-a

    stance

    with which the

    reader

    is asked to

    identify.

    Whatever

    power

    this

    enthymeme

    has

    to

    motivate

    adherence

    derives

    not

    only

    and indeed not

    primarily

    from its

    quasi-syllogistic

    structure

    of

    claim-because-premise,

    which taken

    in isola-

    tion seems

    more

    than

    a

    little

    unpersuasive,

    but

    chiefly

    from its

    exploitation

    of

    a

    network

    of

    oppositions

    and

    what Perelman would

    call

    liaisons,

    which are estab-

    lished

    in the

    preceding

    discourse.

    The chief

    (though

    not

    only)

    constituents

    of this

    network

    are

    a

    linkage

    of

    wrestling

    to the

    associative

    cluster

    of

    spectacle/thea-

    ter/Greek

    theater/religious

    ritual,

    and an

    opposition

    of the

    supposed

    ignobility

    of

    professional

    wrestling

    as fake

    sport

    to

    the

    nobility

    of

    theater as

    sacred

    spectacle.

    (There

    is also

    an

    opposition

    of

    the

    greater

    nobility

    of theater

    to the

    lesser

    nobility

    of

    athletic

    contests.)

    These

    liaisons

    and

    oppositions

    are

    themselves

    set

    up,

    early

    on,

    by

    a

    number

    of

    minor

    enthymemes

    such

    as

    in

    the

    first

    paragraph,

    Even

    ...

    in the

    most

    squalid

    Parisian

    halls,

    wrestling partakes

    of

    the nature of the

    great

    solar

    spectacles,

    Greek

    drama,

    and

    bullfights:

    in

    both,

    a

    light

    without

    shadow

    generates

    an

    emotion

    without

    reserve,

    or

    in

    the

    second

    paragraph,

    There are

    people

    who

    think

    that wrestling is an ignoble sport; it is a spectacle, and it is no more ignoble to

    attend a wrestled

    performance

    of

    Suffering

    than

    a

    performance

    of the

    sorrows

    of

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    13/21

    A

    THEORY OF THE

    ENTHYMEME

    57

    Arnolphe

    or

    Andromaque

    (15).

    These

    two

    enthymemes

    themselves are

    oppor-

    tunistic

    turnings

    of

    comparisons

    and

    linkages

    set

    up

    in

    preceding

    sentences

    such

    as

    Here

    we find a

    grandiloquence

    which

    must have been that of ancient

    theatres

    (15).

    Insofar as the

    reader

    is

    willing

    at least to

    entertain

    Barthes'

    opening

    en-

    thymemes, they

    form the kernel of the entire suasive

    procedure

    that

    follows.

    This

    procedure

    consists,

    for

    the

    most

    part,

    of

    an

    extended

    amplification

    and

    elaboration

    of

    the

    wrestling/spectacle/theater/ritual

    nexus,

    chiefly by way

    of

    an

    exetasis

    in

    which

    the

    wrestling

    match and

    the wrestlers themselves are

    examined

    as a

    system

    of

    signs

    representing

    the

    grand mythologies

    of

    Suffering,

    Defeat,

    and

    Justice

    (19)

    for its

    lower-class

    public.

    This

    exetasis,

    which takes

    up virtually

    all

    but the last two

    paragraphs

    of the

    essay,

    is itself

    punctuated by

    a number of

    minor

    enthymemes

    that serve to establish and

    foreground

    its

    major points.

    Most

    appear

    as

    pseudo-syllogistic

    inferences,

    announced

    usually

    with

    a

    therefore,

    that

    in-

    voke

    an

    insight

    (or

    what is

    meant

    to

    be seen

    as

    one)

    arising

    from

    the

    paragraph

    or

    paragraphs preceding

    them,

    and that are

    given

    what

    might

    be

    called

    syntactic

    prominence

    by being

    placed

    at the

    beginning

    (or

    sometimes the

    end)

    of

    their own

    paragraphs.

    What then

    follows

    usually

    takes the

    enthymeme

    as

    its

    point

    of

    departure,

    amplifying

    or

    extending

    the idea and

    leading

    to

    the next

    enthymematic

    turn.

    Much

    of

    what

    Barthes

    presents

    through

    this

    procedure

    is

    quite

    simply

    enter-

    taining and cajoles the reader into granting the notion of wrestling as theater

    while

    giving

    Barthes

    himself the

    sympathetic

    ethos

    of an

    interested,

    witty

    ob-

    server

    who is not a

    culture-snob. But the

    major

    function

    of

    this web of

    enthy-

    memes and

    amplifications

    is

    to

    foreground

    and

    give

    presence

    to the

    nobler

    implications

    of

    the

    wrestling-theater

    nexus,

    as

    in

    this

    enthymeme:

    But what

    wrestling

    is

    above all

    meant to

    portray

    is

    a

    purely

    moral

    concept:

    that of

    justice.

    The idea of

    'paying'

    is

    essential to

    wrestling,

    and

    the crowd's

    'Give it to

    him'

    above all

    else means

    'Make him

    pay '

    (21).

    At

    the same

    time,

    the

    persistent,

    varied

    amplification

    of such

    ideas

    also

    serves

    to

    keep

    well

    out of

    sight

    opposite

    argu-

    ments that could plausibly be drawn from the same topological nexus-for exam-

    ple,

    the

    argument

    that

    considering wrestling

    as theater

    reveals

    what

    shabby

    theater it is.

    By

    means

    of

    this

    exetasis

    interspersed

    with

    fitting

    enthymemes,

    Barthes

    gives

    himself

    the

    opportunity

    to

    declare,

    with

    another

    enthymematic

    flourish

    in

    his

    penultimate

    paragraph,

    This

    grandiloquence

    s

    nothing

    but the

    popular

    and

    age-old

    image

    of the

    perfect

    intelligibility

    of

    reality.

    What

    is

    portrayed

    by

    wrestling

    is

    therefore an ideal

    understanding

    f

    things;

    it is

    the

    euphoria

    of men

    raisedfor

    a

    while

    above

    the

    constitutive

    ambiguity

    of

    everyday

    ituationsand

    placed

    before the

    panoramic

    view of a univocalNature, in which

    signs

    at last

    correspond

    o causes,without

    obstacle,

    without

    evasion,

    without

    contradiction.

    25)

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    14/21

    58

    COLLEGE

    ENGLISH

    Barthes is here

    drawing

    on

    Aristotelian notions of

    catharsis

    and

    the

    philosophic

    function of dramatic

    mimesis

    (representation

    of

    experiential universals),

    notions

    that are

    linked,

    at least for the educated reader

    his

    essay

    presupposes

    and

    requires,

    to the theater/Greek

    theater/ritual nexus. From the

    position

    established

    in this

    enthymeme

    Barthes

    can

    move,

    in

    his

    final

    paragraph

    and

    closing enthymeme,

    to

    the

    transmuting

    of wrestlers-who

    have now

    become

    the

    figures

    of

    a

    transcen-

    dent rite-into

    momentary gods.

    Barthes'

    penultimate

    and

    final

    enthymemes,

    then,

    are

    kairotic,

    opportunistic

    exploitations

    of

    argumentative potentials

    avail-

    able from

    a

    cluster

    of

    value-charged, emotively significant

    ideas

    already

    made

    present

    to the reader's

    thought

    by

    the

    strategic

    deployment

    of

    oppositions

    and

    liaisons,

    amplifications,

    and

    paragraph-level

    minor

    enthymemes

    in

    the

    preceding

    discourse. And from this

    cluster,

    a virtual chord of

    adherence-motivating

    notions,

    Barthes'

    culminating

    enthymemes

    derive whatever suasive

    force

    they

    have.

    What we find

    in

    Barthes

    we

    see

    more

    clearly

    still

    in

    Martin

    Luther

    King,

    Jr.'s

    Letter

    from

    Birmingham

    Jail.

    Unlike

    Barthes,

    of

    course,

    King

    is a

    modern

    writer

    who

    quite

    explicitly

    conceives

    himself as a rhetor. Some of his

    enthymemes

    clearly

    manifest

    the ancient

    paradigm,

    as in:

    Just

    as

    Socrates

    elt

    that it was

    necessary

    o create a tension

    in

    the

    mind so that

    individuals

    ould rise

    from the

    bondage

    of

    myths

    and

    half-truths o

    the unfettered

    realm of

    creative

    analysis

    and

    objective

    appraisal,

    o must we see the

    need for

    nonviolentgadflies o create he kind of tensions n societythatwillhelpmen rise

    from the

    dark

    depths

    of

    prejudice

    and

    racism

    to the

    majestic

    heights

    of

    under-

    standing

    and

    brotherhood.

    (?110)

    One

    can,

    of

    course,

    see this

    enthymeme

    as a Toulminian datum-so-claim

    kind

    of

    movement;

    which,

    again,

    is

    Aristotle's

    point.

    But

    clearly

    it is more than that.

    Its

    real

    adherence-motivating

    power

    lies

    in

    its

    exploitation

    of

    a

    web

    of

    oppositions-

    bondage/freedom,

    myth/creative

    analysis,

    half-truth/objective

    appraisal,

    dark

    depths/majestic heights,

    racism/brotherhood-and

    the

    relation

    of this web

    to

    ideas

    and

    liaisons established

    in

    the

    immediately

    preceding

    passages,

    such

    as

    King's alignment of himself with the Apostle Paul, the implicit opposition of

    Paul/Socrates

    and their

    persecutors,

    and

    King's

    narration

    of the

    frustrations

    and

    injustices

    that

    have

    impeded

    his

    campaign

    (and

    behind

    all

    this,

    perhaps,

    the

    grand

    mythic

    narratives these

    oppositions

    organize).

    This web

    is

    what

    lends

    salience

    and

    significance

    to the

    enthymeme's

    controlling

    opposition

    of Socrates

    to

    society,

    the

    alignment

    of

    as Socrates felt..

    .

    so

    must we

    see,

    and the

    varied

    repetition

    of

    individuals

    could

    rise..

    .

    help

    men

    rise. The

    elaborately

    schematized

    and

    fig-

    ured

    style,

    moreover,

    makes the

    enthymeme

    stand out

    from what

    precedes

    it as

    a

    moment

    of

    high-spoken,

    impressive,

    and even

    aesthetically

    suasive

    eloquence.

    This enthymeme, in short, exploits the kairosof its moment to present a stance

    with

    which the reader

    is

    given

    a

    complex

    chord of rational and

    passional

    reasons

    to

    identify.

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    15/21

    A THEORY OF THE

    ENTHYMEME

    59

    Not

    all of

    King's

    enthymemes,

    however,

    are so

    clearly

    classical-as in

    the

    garment

    of

    destiny passage:

    I

    cannot

    sit

    idly by

    in Atlanta and not be

    concerned

    about

    what

    happens

    in

    Birmingham.

    njusticeanywhere

    s

    a

    threatto

    justice everywhere.

    We are

    caught

    in an

    inescapable

    network of

    mutuality,

    tied

    in

    a

    single garment

    of

    destiny.

    Whatever

    affectsone

    directly,

    affectsall

    indirectly.

    Never

    again

    can we

    afford

    o

    live with the

    narrow,

    provincial

    outside

    agitator

    dea.

    (?4)

    or, likewise,

    the

    enthymeme consisting

    mainly

    of

    King's one-page litany

    of

    when

    you

    have

    seen,

    which

    I

    can

    quote

    here

    only

    in

    abbreviated

    form:

    Perhaps

    it is

    easy

    for those who have never

    felt the

    stinging

    darts of

    segrega-

    tion to

    say,

    Wait.

    But

    when

    you

    have seen vicious mobs

    lynchyour

    mothers

    and

    fathersat

    will and

    drown

    your

    sisters

    and

    brothers

    at

    whim;

    when

    you

    have

    seen... then

    you

    will

    understand

    why

    we

    find

    it difficult o wait. There comes

    a

    time when the

    cup

    of

    endurance

    uns

    over,

    and men are no

    longer willing

    to be

    plunged

    nto the

    abyss

    of

    despair.

    hope,

    sirs,

    you

    can

    understand ur

    legitimate

    and

    unavoidable

    mpatience.

    ?14)

    I do not

    propose

    to offer a

    detailed

    analysis

    of

    these familiar

    (to

    many) passages,

    but

    only

    to note that

    what makes them

    enthymematic

    is,

    once

    again,

    a

    grounds-

    claim

    kind

    of

    movement,

    in

    which the claim s not

    simply

    a

    proposition

    but an

    inferential and

    attitudinal

    complex-a

    stance-and

    the

    grounds

    consist not

    simply of a quasi-syllogistic premise but, more fully, of a cluster of

    emotively

    significant

    ideas

    (or

    images)

    that work to motivate a

    passional

    identification

    with

    that

    speaker's

    stance. Both

    enthymemes,

    moreover,

    arise

    from

    and

    respond

    to an

    exetasis

    in

    the

    paragraphs

    preceding

    them

    and

    are

    given

    prominence

    and

    memorability

    by

    means of

    striking figuration-the

    metaphors

    and

    parallelisms

    in

    the

    first,

    and the

    insistent

    anaphoras

    of

    the when

    you

    have seen

    passage

    in

    the

    second.

    What

    makes

    these

    passages

    seem

    less

    obviously

    enthymematic

    is the

    absence of an

    explicitly

    invoked set of

    oppositions.

    (A

    careful

    look,

    however,

    would

    make evident

    what kinds of

    oppositions

    are

    implicit,

    such

    as

    Providence,

    destiny, and God's elect vs. provinciality, the damned, and what one cannot

    afford. )

    Moreover,

    both

    enthymemes

    are,

    aside from

    their

    key

    middle

    parts,

    somewhat

    loosely

    structured: the

    second,

    for

    example,

    finishes off

    with

    what

    Aristotle would call a

    maxim and an

    epilogue

    (Rhetoric

    2.21

    [1394b]).

    King's argumentation

    can

    be

    seen,

    like that of

    Barthes,

    as

    a

    process

    of

    setting

    up

    and

    turning enthymemes.

    This is

    especially

    evident

    in

    the first

    part

    of

    the

    Letter

    (?11-22),

    as

    King responds

    point-by-point

    to

    the

    criticisms that

    have

    been

    lodged against

    him. Each

    segment

    is,

    in

    effect,

    an

    Anaximenean

    exetasis

    leading

    to an

    enthymeme.

    Significantly,

    King's

    enthymematic

    turns,

    like the two

    I have quoted above, include what are for most readers the most potent and

    memorable moments in

    the text.

    Further,

    they

    include not

    only

    those

    passages

    conventionally

    taught

    as

    examples

    of

    logical appeal,

    such as

    the

    enthymemes

    in

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    16/21

    60

    COLLEGE ENGLISH

    the

    segment

    on

    just

    and

    unjust

    laws

    (?115-22),

    but also

    those

    taught

    as

    examples

    of emotional

    appeal.

    A

    fuller

    concept

    of

    enthymeme

    makes evident that such

    distinctions are to

    a

    large degree meaningless:

    the three traditional

    sources of

    persuasion-ethos,

    logos,

    pathos-are

    not

    separate

    kinds of

    proof'

    but

    simultane-

    ous

    dimensions of the

    enthymeme.

    As

    Aristotle,

    modern

    philosophical

    psychol-

    ogy,

    and

    Chaim Perelman

    all

    affirm,

    reason and

    affect

    are

    inseparably

    interwoven

    (Aristotle,

    Rhetoric

    2.1-11; Perelman,

    New Rhetoric

    140, 149-150;

    the

    rationality

    of

    emotion

    is

    discussed at

    length

    in

    Fortenbaugh,

    Solomon,

    de

    Sousa,

    Rorty,

    and

    Searle).

    Finally,

    King's argumentation

    well

    exemplifies

    the kairotic

    aspect

    of

    the

    enthymeme,

    its

    ability

    to

    seize the

    possibilities

    available at

    any

    given

    moment

    and

    to

    give

    those

    possibilities

    a

    particular

    realization and salience. We see this

    clearly

    in

    the two

    major

    enthymemes

    that conclude the Letter.

    The

    first is the culmi-

    nating

    moment of

    a

    lengthy

    exetasis

    (?12 3-44)

    in

    which

    King

    has

    been

    criticizing

    the failure of

    white moderates and the white church to

    actively

    support

    his

    cause:

    If

    the

    inexpressible

    ruelties

    of

    slavery

    could

    not

    stop

    us,

    the

    opposition

    we now

    face

    will

    surely

    fail. We

    will win

    our

    freedombecause he sacred

    heritage

    of our

    nation

    and the

    eternal

    will of

    God are embodied

    n

    our

    echoing

    demands.

    144)

    This is

    immediately

    followed

    by

    the

    major

    segment

    of

    King's

    peroration

    (1?45-47), an additional exetasis in which he chides his white critics for com-

    mending

    the

    restraint of the

    Birmingham

    police

    in

    dealing

    with the demonstra-

    tors,

    and then

    turns the second

    of his

    concluding

    enthymemes:

    One

    day

    the South

    will know

    that

    when

    these disinherited

    childrenof God sat

    down

    at lunch

    counters,

    they

    were

    in

    reality

    standing

    up

    for

    what is best

    in

    the

    American

    dream

    and for

    the

    most sacredvalues

    n

    our

    Judeo-Christian

    eritage,

    thereby bringing

    our nation

    back

    to those

    great

    wells

    of

    democracy

    which

    were

    dug

    deep

    by

    the

    founding

    athers

    n

    their

    formulation f the Constitution

    and the

    Declaration

    of

    Independence.

    $47)

    Clearly, and as every careful reader of the Letter recognizes, both of these

    culminating enthymemes

    are

    capitalizing

    on

    the

    many

    liaisons

    and

    oppositions

    that

    the

    argumentation

    of

    the

    Letter has accumulated

    and made

    present

    to the

    reader-and

    giving

    that

    reader a

    powerful

    chord of motives

    for

    identifying

    with

    King's position.

    My point,

    however,

    is

    that each

    of these

    concluding enthymemes

    turns

    the

    argument

    differently,

    the

    first

    foregrounding

    the

    inevitability

    of

    victory,

    the second

    foregrounding

    the

    ethico-political

    nobility

    of

    the

    demonstrators.

    Each,

    in

    short,

    exploits

    a

    different

    kairotic

    possibility

    inherent

    in

    the

    structure

    of

    ideas

    that

    King

    has

    built,

    bringing

    the force of the adherences/identifications

    established earlier to bear in different ways. Neither enthymeme is a summing up

    or a

    restatement

    of

    the whole

    argument

    of Letter

    from

    Birmingham

    Jail,

    nor,

    like Barthes'

    concluding enthymemes

    (or Isocrates'),

    is either

    fully predictable

    or

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    17/21

    A

    THEORY OF THE

    ENTHYMEME

    61

    made inevitable

    by

    what

    precedes.

    King,

    for

    example, might

    have ended

    with

    denunciations

    of

    his

    detractors;

    and

    indeed

    such a

    denunciation

    is

    implicit,

    but

    left

    tacit,

    as

    part

    of the immediate

    background

    (or

    the

    flipside)

    of the

    enthymemes

    he turns.

    King's culminating enthymemes

    are,

    as

    Isocrates would

    say,

    apotomos,

    abrupt,

    decisive and

    fitting

    exploitations

    of the kairos

    of their

    particular

    discur-

    sive moments.

    CONCLUSION

    For

    both

    King

    and

    Barthes,

    argumentative

    or

    suasory

    procedure

    is

    very

    much

    what it was for

    Anaximenes and

    Isocrates,

    that

    is,

    a

    matter of

    setting up

    and

    turning

    enthymemes-or,

    in a

    large

    and

    complex

    argument,

    a

    progression

    from

    enthymeme

    to

    enthymeme

    to

    enthymeme, building up

    an

    accumulated

    fund of

    value-laden,

    emotively significant

    ideas

    (oppositions,

    liaisons,

    etc.)

    that are vari-

    ously brought

    to

    bear,

    forcefully

    and

    memorably,

    in

    the rhetor's

    final

    enthyme-

    matic turns.

    The

    enthymeme

    remains,

    in

    sum,

    a

    vital

    principle

    in

    modern

    discourse,

    even when an

    adequate

    conception

    of

    the

    enthymeme

    is

    unavailable.

    And

    indeed,

    as Aristotle

    says,

    it could

    hardly

    be

    otherwise

    (Rhetoric

    1.1

    [1354a],

    1.2

    [1356b]).

    Enthymeming

    is

    simply

    what

    people

    do,

    whether

    they

    think

    of

    themselves

    as

    doing

    so or

    not,

    whenever

    they attempt

    to

    persuade

    by

    means

    of

    discourse.

    Can

    we then

    say,

    with

    Aristotle and

    (perhaps)

    with

    Isocrates,

    that

    enthyme-

    matic skill is

    the

    essential

    or

    crucial

    skill

    in

    rhetoric,

    or at

    least

    in

    argumentation?

    If,

    as

    rhetoricians,

    we

    are

    to

    conceive

    virtually

    all

    discourse

    as

    rhetorical and

    therefore

    suasory-and

    thus as

    either

    explicitly

    or

    implicitly argumentational-

    then I think

    we

    can.

    But with

    some

    qualifications.

    One is that

    enthymemes

    or

    enthymematic

    procedure

    may

    be

    different in

    different

    kinds

    of

    discourse such

    as,

    for

    example,

    fiction

    or

    poetry,

    or the

    belletristic

    essay,

    or the

    various

    kinds of

    scholarly,

    scientific,

    technical,

    and

    administrative

    prose.

    We

    need to

    consider

    what enthymemes are like, and how they work, in these discursive realms and at

    different

    points

    in

    history.

    Another

    important

    qualification

    is

    to

    say

    that,

    while

    enthymematic

    skill

    may

    be the

    crucial skill in

    rhetoric

    (or

    argumentation),

    Aristotle's

    notion

    that

    all

    the

    other

    skills of

    rhetoric

    are

    supplementary

    or

    accessory

    to

    enthymeming

    may

    be

    looking

    at the

    matter

    backwards.

    Can we

    not

    say

    as

    well that

    enthymematic

    skill

    depends

    on all

    the

    other skills?

    For all the

    means

    of

    persuasion

    available

    to

    rhetoric

    are

    brought

    together

    by,

    and

    contribute

    to,

    the

    enthymematic

    turn. As

    Isocrates

    says,

    to

    speak

    (or write)

    a

    discourse

    wholly

    woven

    with

    fitting

    enthy-

    memes, one must be able to choose from the elements of discourse those things

    that

    should

    be used

    for the case in

    hand,

    and

    the

    tropes

    for

    joining

    and

    arranging

    them,

    be able

    to see

    what

    kairos

    demands,

    and be

    able as well

    to

    speak

    (or

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    18/21

    62

    COLLEGE

    ENGLISH

    write)

    in

    words

    rhythmically

    and

    musically arranged

    (Against

    the

    Sophists

    16-

    17).

    In more

    contemporary

    terms,

    one must

    must know

    well

    enough

    the

    topoi

    of

    a discursive

    field

    (such

    as

    those that

    Aristotle

    lists

    for

    political,

    juridical,

    and

    epideictic

    argument

    in

    Rhetoric

    1.3-14)

    to select

    what should be

    used for

    the

    particular

    case

    in

    hand;

    one must know

    the various

    discourse-level

    gambits,

    schemes,

    and

    strategies

    by

    which a

    discourse

    using

    and

    combining

    those

    topoi

    can

    be

    plotted

    as an

    argumentative

    progression

    (as

    opposed

    to

    merely arranged

    according

    to some static

    outline);

    one must be

    able to

    analyze

    one's

    rhetorical

    situation

    as well as

    recognize

    the

    shifting

    demands and

    possibilities

    of the

    imme-

    diate discursive moment

    (arguments

    arise

    in

    response

    to

    preceding

    arguments,

    or

    in

    anticipation

    of

    arguments

    to come or

    audience

    responses);

    and one

    must have

    a fluent command of the

    stylistic

    resources of the

    language

    in which one writes

    or

    speaks.

    All

    this,

    Isocrates

    suggests,

    is

    needed for

    genuine mastery

    of the

    strategic,

    kairotic

    skill

    of

    setting up

    and

    turning

    eloquent,

    powerful

    enthymemes.

    No

    wonder

    he thinks such

    mastery

    requires

    study,

    and

    is

    the work of a

    vigorous

    and

    thoughtful

    mind

    (Against

    the

    Sophists

    17).

    This is

    not to

    say

    that

    enthymeming

    is an advanced skill that

    cannot be

    learned before

    other,

    more basic

    ones,

    for as Isocrates and

    Aristotle

    recognize,

    everyone

    turns

    enthymemes.

    But

    it

    is

    to

    say

    that

    a

    trained excellence

    in

    en-

    thymeming requires

    what Isocrates would call an

    extensive discourse education

    that cultivates not only advanced literacy but alsophronesis judgment and intelli-

    gence)

    and

    sophia

    wisdom, skill)

    through

    critical,

    argumentative engagement

    with

    the

    argumentation

    of

    others

    in

    many

    discursive

    genres

    and in

    many

    fields of

    thought.

    This is the

    sophistic

    kind of discourse education we see

    represented

    in

    Plato's

    Protagoras,

    both

    in

    the

    symposiastic

    debate

    on

    issues

    of

    ethical

    and

    political

    philosophy

    and

    in

    the

    critique

    of an

    argument

    in a

    poem

    by

    Simonides. A

    genuine

    understanding

    of

    enthymematic

    art cannot be

    acquired

    from

    simplified, prescrip-

    tive

    recipes

    and formalistic

    models,

    but

    only

    from

    analytical

    and critical

    study

    of

    actual

    argumentation

    and from one's own

    accumulated

    experience

    as a

    producer

    of argumentation (in symposiastic debate, in declamation exercises, etc.) over an

    extended

    period

    of time.

    There

    is,

    in

    sum,

    a

    great

    deal more to skillful

    enthymem-

    ing,

    or

    to

    argumentation,

    than

    knowing

    something

    about Toulmin

    logic,

    Venn

    diagrams,

    or the

    basic forms of the

    syllogism-though

    such models

    might

    be

    presented

    (with

    the

    reminder that

    they

    are

    ultimately

    inadequate)

    as

    simplified,

    approximate analogies

    for the kind

    of

    inferential

    process

    that underlies

    the en-

    thymeme

    and

    gives

    it

    its

    persuasive

    force.

    Such reductions

    may

    be

    helpful

    for the

    novice,

    but

    they eventually

    must be discarded.

    The view of

    enthymemes

    that

    we have taken in this

    essay

    is

    not,

    in

    fact,

    incompatible with what has been the conventional view. Effective argumentation

    that is

    ethically

    and

    intellectually

    responsible

    is indeed

    a matter of

    dialogic

    reasoning

    that seeks to

    incorporate

    the audience's

    knowledge

    and beliefs

    as

    well

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    19/21

    A THEORY OF THE ENTHYMEME

    63

    as the

    rhetor's,

    and an

    enthymeme

    is still

    a

    figure-any

    figure-

    that connects

    an

    idea

    with reasons for

    believing

    it and that relies on its

    audience's

    inferential

    powers.

    But that is not all

    it

    is and does. The

    enthymeme

    is

    also,

    and

    distinctively,

    a

    stylistically striking, kairotically

    opportunistic, argumentative

    turn that not

    only

    presents

    a claim

    but

    also

    foregrounds

    an

    inferential

    and

    attitudinal

    complex,

    a

    stance;

    that invokes

    not

    only

    a

    premise

    (or

    warrant)

    as

    justification

    but a

    chord

    of

    value-charged, emotively

    significant

    ideas to motivate

    a

    passional

    adherence

    or

    identification with its

    stance;

    and that

    is

    not

    only

    a form of

    passional

    reasoning

    but

    also an architectonic

    principle

    for both the

    invention and

    structuring

    of

    suasive discourse

    (for

    a similar

    view,

    see

    Gage, Theory ).

    This

    way

    of

    looking

    at the

    enthymeme

    seems

    richer,

    more

    complex,

    and

    more flexible than the conventional

    view,

    more consistent with modern theories

    of

    persuasion

    and

    argument-particularly

    those

    of

    Kenneth Burke and

    Chaim

    Perelman-and more

    descriptive

    of

    actual

    argumentational practice.

    We

    have,

    in

    sum,

    a double view of

    enthymemes:

    enthymeme

    as a

    complex

    structure of

    intuitive inference and

    affect that constitutes

    the substance

    of

    an

    argument;

    and

    enthymeme

    as a

    structural/stylistic

    turn

    that

    caps

    an

    exetasis,

    gives

    the inferen-

    tial/affective substance a

    particular

    realization with a

    particular

    salience

    for

    a

    particular

    discursive

    moment,

    and

    by doing

    so

    constructs or

    shapes

    its

    audience's

    perception

    of

    just

    what the

    argument

    is.

    The latter is

    what

    Anaximenes and

    Isocrates describe; the former is what Aristotle tries to analyze. The enthymeme

    is

    both,

    and

    is

    in

    both

    senses

    truly

    the

    body

    of

    persuasion.

    NOTE

    1.

    For recent

    discussion

    of the

    enthymeme,

    see Michael

    Hood's

    bibliography.

    The

    most

    relevant sources for

    the

    present

    study

    are:

    Lloyd

    Bitzer,

    Aristotle's

    Enthymeme

    Revisited ;

    George

    P.

    Boss,

    The

    Stereotype

    and Its

    Correspondence

    in

    Discourse to the

    Enthymeme ;

    Thomas

    Conley,

    The

    Enthymeme

    in

    Perspective ;

    Jesse

    G.

    Delia,

    The

    Logic Fallacy ;

    John

    T.

    Gage,

    A

    General

    Theory

    of the

    Enthymeme

    and

    The

    Shape

    of

    Reason;

    Lawrence

    Green,

    Enthymemic

    Invention ;

    William M. A.

    Grimaldi,

    Studies in the

    Philosophyof Aristotle's

    Rhetoric

    53-82; andJames Raymond,

    Enthymemes,

    Examples,

    and Rhetorical

    Method. The

    arguments

    of

    Conley

    and

    Gage

    are

    the

    closest to

    the

    position

    that

    I

    take

    here.

    WORKS CITED

    Anaximenes of

    Lampsacus.

    Rhetoricaad

    Alexandrum.

    Trans. H.

    Rackham. Cam-

    bridge:

    Harvard

    UP,

    1957.

    Aristotle.

    Rhetoric.

    3

    translations:]

    Freese,

    J.

    H.

    Cambridge:

    Harvard

    UP,

    1926.

    Kennedy,

    George.

    New

    York: Oxford

    UP,

    1991.

    Roberts,

    W.

    R.,

    and I.

    Bywater.

    New

    York:

    Modern

    Library,

    1954.

  • 8/10/2019 Walker Body of Persuasion

    20/21

    64

    COLLEGE

    ENGLISH

    --

    .