Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

download Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

of 58

Transcript of Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    1/58

    Professor Stephen MathisWHEATON COLLEGE

    PHILOSOPHY

    AND THE LAW:HOW JUDGES REASON

    COURSE GUIDE

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    2/58

    Philosophy and the Law:How Judges Reason

    Professor Stephen Mathis

    Wheaton College

    Recorded Books is a trademark of

    Recorded Books, LLC. All rights reserved.

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    3/58

    Philosophy and the Law:

    How Judges Reason

    Professor Stephen Mathis

    Executive Producer

    John J. Alexander

    Executive Editor

    Donna F. Carnahan

    RECORDING

    Producer - David Markowitz

    Director - Matthew Cavnar

    COURSE GUIDE

    Editor - James Gallagher

    Design - Edward White

    Lecture content 2008 by Stephen Mathis

    Course guide 2008 by Recorded Books, LLC

    72008 by Recorded Books, LLC

    Cover image Christian Hesse/shutterstock.com

    #UT120 ISBN: 978-1-4361-2909-1

    All beliefs and opinions expressed in this audio/video program and accompanying course guide

    are those of the author and not of Recorded Books, LLC, or its employees.

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    4/58

    Course Syllabus

    Philosophy and the Law:

    How Judges Reason

    About Your Professor...................................................................................................4

    Introduction...................................................................................................................5

    Lecture 1 Legal Realism ........................................................................................6

    Lecture 2 Legal Positivism, Part I ..........................................................................9

    Lecture 3 Legal Positivism, Part II .......................................................................12

    Lecture 4 Theoretical Disagreement in Law ........................................................15

    Lecture 5 Theories of Interpretation ....................................................................19

    Lecture 6 Legal Conservatism .............................................................................23

    Lecture 7 Judicial Activism ..................................................................................26

    Lecture 8 Law as Integrity ...................................................................................29

    Lecture 9 Common Law and Statutes .................................................................32

    Lecture 10 Constitutional Law ...............................................................................36

    Lecture 11 Dualist Democracy...............................................................................40

    Lecture 12 Regime Perspective.............................................................................44

    Lecture 13 Interpretive Synthesis ..........................................................................48

    Lecture 14 Judicial Politics versus Interpretation ..................................................52

    Course Materials ........................................................................................................56

    3

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    5/58

    4

    About Your Professor

    Stephen Mathis

    Stephen Mathis is an associate professor and chairman of the Philosophy

    Department at Wheaton College. He teaches a variety of courses in legal phi-

    losophy as well as in social/political philosophy. Professor Mathis is also the

    co-coordinator of the Legal Studies Minor and Pre-Law Advisor. His primary

    research interest is the philosophy of criminal law, but he has also written on

    topics in political philosophy, moral theory, and ethics. In his spare time,

    Professor Mathis follows politics and the Supreme Court very closely and has

    authored op-ed pieces on constitutional law issues.

    The following books provide an excellent supplement to the lectures

    found in this course:

    Ackerman, Bruce. We the People: Foundations. Cambridge, MA: Belknap

    Press, 1993.

    Dworkin, Ronald. Laws Empire. New ed. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2003.

    PhotocourtesyofStephenMathis

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    6/58

    Introduction

    Do judges deduce their decisions from legal rules and principles, or do they

    decide cases based on what is fair given the facts at hand? The latter view,

    held by Legal Realists, serves as the starting point for Professor Stephen

    Mathiss eye-opening look at how judges reason. In this compelling lecture

    series, the esteemed professor addresses such issues as whether the law is

    distinct from morality. Professor Mathis also attempts to identify a view that

    offers guidance to judges in deciding cases, and one that will provide the

    tools people need to evaluate the interpretations and decisions judges make.

    5

    ChristianHesse/shutterstock.com

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    7/58

    We begin this course with Legal Realism because it marks one of the ear-

    liest attempts at taking a philosophical approach to American

    Jurisprudence. A response to Legal Formalism (the view that judges can

    and do logically deduce decisions from applying legal principles to the

    facts of the case), Legal Realism focuses instead on how things are done in

    the actual practice of law. Almost all of the Legal Realists were jurists andlegal practitioners, and not academic philosophers. Perhaps for this reason,

    Legal Realists drew more from sociological approaches than philosophical

    ones. However, their attention to empirical claims about how judges actually

    decide cases (and not about how judges should decide cases) led later

    philosophers of law to discount Legal Realism as a deeply flawed approach

    to jurisprudence.

    Legal Realism, especially as we see it embodied in the work of Oliver

    Wendell Holmes and Jerome Frank, offers a startling account of what law is:

    it is, fundamentally, a matter of predicting how judges will actually decidecases. This account is startling because at first blush it seems to suggest

    that prior court decisions, statutes, and legal principles are all less important

    than the judges particular leanings (or than what the judge had for break-

    fast1). If true, the Realist view of the law would be a deeply skeptical view,

    holding that the process of adjudication is nothing more than an elaborate

    sham, with all sorts of window dressing for what is essentially the judges

    subjective preference.

    While Legal Realism does espouse a degree of skepticism about the law

    and especially about adjudication, it is unfair to see it as coming down just towhat the judge had for breakfast. It is important to keep in mind that most

    Legal Realists were concerned with the law primarily from the perspective of

    a lawyer, not that of a judge, a Supreme Court Justice, or a philosopher.

    (Holmes also uses this lawyerly point of view to drive a distinction between

    morality and law: he argues that the law and morality are likely to overlap for

    the good man [or client], but all that matters to the bad man is the law.)

    Treated as an empirical claim about the lawyers role with respect to her

    client, saying that the law is essentially a matter of predicting how judges will

    decide cases seems far less objectionable. After all, a judge is a humanbeing who has biases and idiosyncracies, some of which can lead him away

    from or to hold a skewed view of particular legal rules, precedents, and princi-

    ples. But Legal Realists do not believe that the law is about prediction just

    LECTUREONE

    The Suggested Readings for this lecture are Jerome Franks Legal

    Realism in Joel Feinberg and Hyman Gross (eds.) Philosophy of Law

    and Oliver Wendell Holmess The Path of the Law.

    Lecture 1:

    Legal Realism

    6

    1. Realists have long been saddled with claiming that what the judge had for breakfast is the deter-

    mining factor in judicial decisions. However, no Realist actually ever made such a claim. See Brian

    Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism Reconsidered, Ethics, 111:2 (2001), p. 281.

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    8/58

    because some judges have prejudices or foibles: Realists also do not believe

    that the various legal rules and reasons that bear on a given case actually

    justify or require one particular right way of deciding that case. In other

    words, Legal Realism holds that the law is indeterminate or undetermined by

    the legal rules and reasons available to judges. It is in this way that Realism

    is skeptical about law. In the end, this skepticism leads Realists to see judgesplaying a key role in determining the law, which in turn leads Realists to dis-

    cuss the law in terms of predicting outcomes.

    Legal Realists hold that most judges do not deduce their decisions from

    legal rules or principles, but rather they decide cases based on their view of

    what is fair given the facts at hand. This is not to say that judges ignore

    statutes or other legal rules or principles, but rather only that different judges

    will inevitably interpret or weigh legal rules and reasons in different ways,

    and theres nothing in the law that prevents them from doing so. It is also to

    say, however, that judges sometimes decide cases based on extralegaljudgments about what is fair or just, and then they use legal rules and rea-

    sons to justify those decisions after the fact.

    Overall, Legal Realism is best understood as a sociological or descriptive

    theory of law and adjudication in that it tells us what law

    is and how judges actually do decide cases. Legal

    Realism fails, however, to offer a normative or pre-

    scriptive theory of law or adjudication, or a theory of

    what the law should be or how judges ought to

    decide cases. Even though in reality judges may typi-cally decide cases according to what they think is fair

    given the facts of the case, that tells us nothing about

    whether or not it is right or even acceptable for

    them to do so. And while Legal Realism recog-

    nizes a range of possible interpretations of

    existing legal rules and principles (that con-

    tribute to laws indeterminacy), it offers no way

    to evaluate interpretations as within that range

    or unacceptably out there. In fact, LegalRealism offers no means at all of evaluating

    judges decisions and thus can say nothing at

    all about how a judge should decide a partic-

    ular kind of case or about why a particular

    decision may or may not be justified. While

    Legal Realism has interesting things to say

    about the actual practice of the law and the

    way judges decide cases, philosophers of law

    (not to mention judges) need more from ajurisprudential theory: we need a view that

    will offer some guidance to judges in deciding

    cases and one that will give us the tools we

    need to evaluate, among other things, the

    interpretations and decisions judges make.

    7

    Eric

    k

    Jones

    /sh

    utte

    rs

    toc

    k.c

    om

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    9/58

    1. Why is Legal Realism a good starting point for a course focused on how

    judges reason?

    2. From what perspective were most Legal Realists concerned with the law?

    Frank, Jerome. Legal Realism. Philosophy of Law. 8th ed. Pp. 125127.

    Eds. Joel Feinberg and Hyman Gross. Belmont, WA: Wadsworth

    Publishing Company, 2007.

    Holmes, Oliver Wendell. The Path of the Law. Vol. 10. Harvard Law

    Review, p. 457, 1897.

    Frank, Jerome. Law and the Modern Mind. Reprint. Piscataway, NJ:Transaction Publishers, 2008.

    Holmes, Oliver Wendell. The Common Law. New York: Dover

    Publications, 1991.

    Leiter, Brian. American Legal Realism. The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy

    of Law and Legal Theory. Pp. 5066. Eds. W. Edmundson and M. Golding.

    Oxford: Blackwell, 2003.

    Oliver Wendell Holmess The Common Law and a book form of The Path of

    the Law are also available online from Project Gutenberg

    www.gutenberg.org

    Questions

    Suggested Reading

    FOR GREATER UNDERSTANDING

    Other Books of Interest

    Websites to Visit

    LECTUREONE

    8

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    10/58

    The Suggested Reading for this lecture is H.L.A. Harts The Concept

    of Law, chapter V, Law as the Union of Primary and Secondary Rules,

    pp. 7999.

    Lecture 2:

    Legal Positivism, Part I

    9

    Legal Positivism traces its roots back to the famous utilitarian Jeremy

    Bentham (17481832). Though Bentham wrote extensively in political phi-

    losophy, it was his star pupil, John Austin (17901859), who refined and

    codified many of his views on jurisprudence. Austins work helped launch

    an approach to the philosophy of law we now call Analytical Jurisprudence,

    because of its focus on analyzing and trying to define the concept of law.

    1

    The definitions of law Austin and his most influential successors offered all

    described law in terms of its roots in social practice. These philosophers were

    most concerned with law as it is posited (that is, as it is constructed or prac-

    ticed, or perhaps even as it is put into place), and not with law as it would be

    best justified in moral terms; thus the label Legal Positivism.

    In his The Providence of Jurisprudence Determined (1831), Austin seeks out

    the essential features of law, and in particular tries to distinguish law from

    other things that might be confused with that concept. Austin defines law as

    commands, backed by threat of sanctions, from a sovereign, to whom peoplehave a habit of obedience. Austins key insight here is that law has a peculiar

    kind of force, a force we cannot ignore, as we can ignore mere expressions of

    wishes, especially from those with no power to make us want to fulfill those

    wishes. This force, which obliges us to act, is to be distinguished from reward

    or being provided positive incentive to act, since a reward may not move one

    to actand if it doesnt so move one, one is

    made no worse off. The threat of pain, under-

    stood as punishment or fines, has the force

    Austin has in mind here. For Austin, law is alsogeneral in its scope: it applies to types of

    actions, not to one isolated act on one particular

    occasion. Thus, a sovereign (whether a king or

    a legislature or other legitimate authority) com-

    mand that Joe Smith wear blue pants on the

    fourth of October this year would not be a law,

    while a command that everyone wear blue

    pants on the fourth of October each year could

    be. The requirement of the peoples habitual

    obedience can be said to capture this consider-

    ation (since one cannot be in the habit of obey-

    ing terribly specific, one-time commands). But

    more importantly, the stipulation that people

    1. This focus is to be contrasted with Normative Jurisprudence, which centers on the law as it

    should be.

    MaiseiRaman/shutterstock

    .com

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    11/58

    LECTURETWO

    10

    must habitually obey a command in order for it to be properly called a law

    underlines the significance of law as a socially accepted norm.

    H.L.A. Hart criticizes Austins view as overly simplistic, but retained his posi-

    tivist approach to defining law. In The Concept of Law (1961), Hart argues law

    should be understood as a system of what he calls primary and secondary

    rules. Primary rules are rules that either require or prohibit some sort of behav-ior in general terms, though not necessarily on pains of punishment, because

    Hart recognized that while Austins characterization of law as commands

    backed by the threat of punishment applied well to most criminal statutes, it

    hardly seemed to apply at all to most civil law. The law of contracts provides

    the clearest counterexample to Austins view and an argument for something

    more like Harts view, since contract law does not command anything on pain

    of punishment, but rather facilitates various arrangements and relationships,

    almost all of which are completely voluntary. Secondary rules, by contrast, are

    rules that create, repeal, or otherwise regulate the use of primary rules. Hartidentifies three categories of secondary rules: rules of change, which allow

    laws to be repealed or modified; rules of adjudication, which address conflicts

    between rules and other aspects of administering rules; and the rule of recog-

    nition, which validates primary rules as valid instances of law. Though some

    secondary rules are spelled

    out rather explicitly (as a

    constitution, perhaps the

    most common form of a

    rule of recognition, wouldbe), for Hart all of them

    need not be: secondary

    rules can be found among

    the customary practices of

    courts and of legal argu-

    mentation, for example.

    Hart also criticizes and refines Austins view of the special kind of force law

    must have. While Austin sees the threat of punishment that compels individu-

    als to obey as essential to law, Hart believes that law obligates people in adeeper way. On Harts view, the law achieves a high level of social accep-

    tance, high enough that people regularly internalize the duties laid out in the

    law and obligate themselves to uphold it. In this way, Hart sees the force law

    carries with it as much more social and more deeply obligating than it is on

    Austins view. In fact, Hart suggests that Austins view could lead us to say

    that a gunman robbing another individual makes law by commanding his

    assailant to hand over his wallet at gunpoint. One would have to stipulate that

    the people are in the habit of obeying gunmen in order to argue that Austins

    definition entails that the gunman is making law by holding up another per-son, but since so stipulating does not seem like much of a stretch, it seems

    that Austins view could be saddled with this absurd consequent. Hart argues

    that Austins view conflates obliging and obligating, and he thinks the gunman

    does the former and the law does the latter.

    Louis May/shutterstock.com

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    12/58

    1. What is the relationship between peoples habitual obedience and the law?

    2. What are primary and secondary rules?

    Hart, H.L.A. The Concept of Law. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress, 1997.

    Austin, John. The Providence of Jurisprudence Determined. New ed.

    Lecture I, pp. 1837; Lecture VI, pp. 164293. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press, 1995.

    Waluchow, W.J. Inclusive Legal Positivism. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994.

    Questions

    Suggested Reading

    FOR GREATER UNDERSTANDING

    Other Books of Interest

    11

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    13/58

    The Suggested Reading for this lecture is H.L.A. Harts Positivism andthe Separation of Law and Morals, Harvard Law Review, vol. 71, p. 593.

    Lecture 3:

    Legal Positivism, Part II

    LECTURETHREE

    12

    Like the Legal Realists, Legal Positivists recognize that law is distinct from

    morality: in fact, neither Austins model of law as commands backed by

    sanctions nor Harts model of law as a system of primary and secondary

    rules makes any reference to law as morally right, justified, or anything of

    the sort. Positivism focuses almost exclusively on the laws form and pedi-

    gree and little on evaluating its contentif it does so at all. This is not to say,however, that Positivists take the law to have no moral character whatsoever

    either way. Rather they take the question of how just a particular law within a

    system is as a separate issue: whether or not this rule or that command can

    be properly called law plays no part in determinations of its moral value, and

    vice versa. In this way, Legal Positivism can be seen as a direct refutation of

    Natural Law, the view that the law legislatures create and judges enforce

    should closely track the laws of an external moral order.1

    Austin and Hart both reject the view that one can establish whether or not a

    law is valid (or properly understood as law) by appeal to such external stan-dards as Gods law or the moral law or even the law of Reason. Hart goes

    even further, however, and argues that if one wants to understand fully what

    the law is, one must take a perspective internal to the practice of the law. One

    obvious benefit of this approach is that it coincides more with the perspective

    judges take in deciding cases. But this argument brings to light a deeper,

    more important point: that judges are concerned with operating within the legal

    practice, and doing that entails analyzing whether or not the appropriate (legal)

    criteria have been met to say whether one decision or another is the law; it

    does not allow one to make broader moral evaluations of laws and particulardecisions, because to do so would require one to step outside of the practice

    of law. In other words, the standards for legal validity are internal to the law,

    while standards of justice and morality are external to the law, and judges and

    lawyers are in the business of figuring out what the law is, and the appropriate

    perspective for them is internal to the practice. The biggest upshot of this

    argument is that if Positivism is correct, then judges and lawyers are not in a

    position as legal practitioners to say anything about the moral validity of the

    law or a particular law; they are uniquely positioned, however, to speak direct-

    ly to questions of legal validity. In the end, this is why Positivism views what

    the law is and whether or not it is just as separate questions.

    1. Though I will discuss Natural Law theory in more detail in later lectures, I should note here that

    Natural Law theorists vary on the source and character of that external moral order, with some

    appealing to religion and others to various different secular conceptions of morality. Natural Law

    theory is also famously associated with the claim, an unjust law is no law at all, but it is far

    from reducible to this claim.

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    14/58

    13

    This is not to say, however, that Hart thinks law and morality could have no

    connection whatsoever. Hart argues that we may very well have a moral oblig-

    ation to refuse to obey certain unjust laws: this claim allows for laws to be

    unjust (and still be properly called laws), but identifies a point at which the

    moral problems with following them force us to step outside of the internal per-

    spective and refuse to obey. Also, if a system of rules fails to meet minimalmoral requirements (being sufficiently general in scope, treating like cases

    alike, basic impartiality, and so forth), then that system may fail to be a legal

    system in any proper sense of that term. As such, a certain kind of procedur-

    al morality is present in any proper legal system, even if certain particular

    laws are unjust or morally questionable.

    Finally, there is a third, more fundamental way in which morality plays a role

    in Harts understanding of law. In most cases, where law has been clearly

    posited, judges will make decisions by applying the appropriate legal criteria in

    the way I alluded to above. But in cases in which the law is not clearly posited,where it looks like (and where the Realists would say) the law has run-out,

    judges must do something different, because in such cases there is no clear

    positive law to appeal to as they make their decisions. Such cases deal with

    problems of the penumbra, meaning that surrounding many, if not all, legal

    rules is a shadowy area or penumbra from which judges cannot logically

    deduce answers (or mechanically apply the rules to the facts) because in that

    penumbra, the application of the rule is unclear. Realists seem to recognize

    something like penumbral areas as well, though Realists argue that when

    judges find themselves in such areas in the law, they basically fill in the gap byappealing to what they think is most fair in that particular case. But against the

    Realists, Hart argues that when judges decide penumbral cases, they should

    look at social aims, purposes, and policies, and that these serve as another

    level of legal sources (though admittedly less clear and more abstract than, for

    example, statutes on the books). These social aims, purposes, and policies

    judges take into consideration in penumbral cases have some moral content,

    though that content is arguably still internal to the legalor at least social

    system, and that such consideration of aims and purposes does allow for

    some blurring of the line between law as it is and law as it should be. Because

    Hart includes this last set of moral considerations (social aims, purposes, and

    policies) in his view of appropriate legal sources, some have termed his view

    Inclusive or Soft Positivism. Views that reject such social considerations, then,

    are often called Exclusive or Hard Positivism.

    Janice Tuttle/shutterstock.com

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    15/58

    1. How can Legal Positivism be seen as a direct refutation of Natural Law?

    2. In terms of the law, what are problems of penumbra?

    Hart, H.L.A. Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals. HarvardLaw Review. Vol. 71, p. 593, Cambridge, MA: Harvard Law Review

    Association, 1958.

    Fuller, Lon L. The Morality of Law. Rev. ed. New Haven, CT: Yale University

    Press, 1969.

    Hart, H.L.A. Law, Liberty, and Morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1963.

    Questions

    Suggested Reading

    FOR GREATER UNDERSTANDING

    Other Books of Interest

    LECTURETHREE

    14

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    16/58

    15

    Ronald Dworkins Laws Empire (1986) is one of the more influential

    works in jurisprudence to come along in the last forty years. Dworkin was

    H.L.A. Harts star pupil at Oxford University, and in Laws Empire he takes

    his mentor to task for his Positivist views. Though Dworkin is not entirely

    fair to Hart and the Positivists, he does offer something Hart never did: a

    detailed philosophical account of judicial interpretation. Since Laws Empireincludes analysis of most of the popular approaches to judicial interpretation

    along with powerful arguments for his own theory of adjudication, I will spend

    much of the next five lectures (and this one) looking at various aspects of this

    very important work.1

    Early in Laws Empire, Dworkin attacks the widely held view that judges

    should merely follow the law as it is written rather than seek to improve it.

    The problem is that this view presents us with a false dichotomy: it suggests

    that the only options a judge has are to discover the law or to invent it,

    when in fact judges regularly engage in a third option, engaging in theoreticaldisagreement about law. Its important to see that real theoretical disagree-

    ment about law is possible, and once we do, then we can develop a theory of

    how judges work their way through such disagreements to decide the cases

    before them.

    Toward this end, we can identify three general types of issues that judges

    and lawyers regularly face: issues of fact, issues of law, and issues of politi-

    cal morality or fidelity.2 Issues of fact are quite uncontroversial and easy to

    handle, and issues of political morality or fidelity are quite commonplace in

    courtrooms, but the interesting issues are issues of law.3 Still, some issues oflaw are more interesting than others: empirical disagreements about what

    the law is (or arguments about what the text of a law is) hold little interest for

    judges or philosophers (because as often as not, they can just go look it up),

    while theoretical disagreements about what the law is or what the proper

    grounds of law are tend to occupy much more of their time and energy. It is

    The Suggested Reading for this lecture is Ronald Dworkins LawsEmpire, chapter 1, What Is Law?

    Lecture 4:

    Theoretical Disagreement in Law

    1. And it is for these same reasons that I chose Laws Empire as a central text for this course.

    2. Issues of political morality and fidelity have to do with differing views of what our political system

    requires of the law or of what it means to be faithful to the law in a given case. For example,when a lawyer argues that it would be wrong to sentence his defendant in these circumstances

    to the more severe punishment allowed within sentencing guidelines, or when a lawyer argues

    that it does not serve the laws purposes to hold his client liable for damages in a given case.

    3. Dworkin also refers to fidelity issues as ones relating to whether or not a judge should follow the

    law in a given case. He claims, judges rarely consider whether they should follow the law once

    they have settled what it really is (pp. 56). As such, he does not see the widely held view that

    judges should follow the law rather than invent it as a view about fidelity, but rather as a heavily

    disguised example of theoretical disagreement about law.

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    17/58

    LECTUREFOUR

    16

    important to note here that theoretical disagreement involves competing pre-

    scriptive claims, while empirical disagreement involves merely descriptive

    claims, at least one of which will turn out to be wrong. Dworkin argues for a

    prescriptive approach, one focused on theoretical disagreement, by pointing

    out that legal practice is fundamentally argumentative. One can understand

    this argumentative feature of legal practice either by taking an external pointof viewthe point of view of a historian or sociologistor an internal one

    the point of view of a legal practitioner. The first will, at best, tell us what

    kinds of claims legal professionals will make in specific situations, while the

    second will be able to provide arguments for why they will make those claims

    (or why those claims are better than others). Naturally, we should prefer the

    second type of approachthe internal, prescriptive approachbecause this

    is the approach judges and lawyers take and because to a judge, a descrip-

    tive approach, even one that predicts how judges will decide cases, will not

    do enough to tell us why a decision should go one way or another (instead, it

    would only tell us that a decision would go one way or another). In this way,

    this approach explicitly rejects Legal Realism, and it does so for the same

    reasons I did at the end of my first lecture.

    But we can also distinguish this approach from Legal Positivism. One way to

    do this is by understanding Positivism as a sophisticated version of the view

    that the law is what legal institutions have already decided it is. In other

    words, if legal institutions have posited something as law, then it is lawand

    ideas of what the law should be play no part in the process. Since Legal

    Positivism concerns itself with the criteria that must be met for something tobe considered law, the argument goes, it is best understood as a semantic

    theory of law, or a theory focused on defining the term law. A key feature of

    Positivism is the fact that society must accept the criteria laid out for some-

    thing to become lawotherwise, it would not be law as far as the Positivists

    are concerned. Having already cast Positivism as a semantic theory,

    Dworkin extrapolates from this key feature to claim that Positivism is further

    committed to the view that everyone already agrees to the criteria for law.

    The idea is that if everyone did not agree on the criteria, then it would be diffi-

    cult, if not impossible, to judge whether or not law was properly posited, and

    Positivism would seem to have difficulty getting off the ground at all. Dworkin

    uses this move to blast the Positivists, saying that if everyone already agrees

    to the criteria, then what the law is has already been decided, so the only dis-

    agreements possible within Positivism are empirical ones.

    In response, Hart explicitly denied that his view is a semantic view of law,

    and said that the only aspect of law everyone had agreed to on his view is

    the general criteria for law; people dont need to agree about how the law

    must be applied in every specific case. In this way, his view allows for theo-

    retical disagreement about how the law should be applied in some cases. Inthis sense, at least, Dworkins attack on Harts view seems to be unfair.

    Nonetheless, Dworkin does have one argument against Positivism that not

    only appears to be fair, but also damaging. Since Positivism requires that

    everyone agree to the criteria for law in advance, it seems that the Positivist

    view of adjudication is focused on cases in the penumbraborderline

    casesbecause once the law is posited, its set, and we can only disagree

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    18/58

    17

    about specific applications of it. Dworkins argument is that very few cases

    are borderline cases, and those that are turn out to be rather uninteresting.

    The more interesting cases are pivotal cases, cases in which the decision will

    affect the future direction of the law (or at least a big part of it). I think theres

    something to the claim that Positivism does not and cannot account for piv-

    otal cases, only borderline ones, but not because Positivism is a semanticview of law; rather, its because the Positivists were much more worried

    about defining what law is than looking carefully at adju-

    dicating hard cases. As such, Dworkin seems right to

    argue that Positivism neglects a large and very

    important part of the law.

    Mikh

    ail Iva

    novic

    h/sh

    utt

    ers

    tock

    .com

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    19/58

    1. What follows from the realization that theoretical disagreement about law

    is possible?

    2. Why did Dworkin say that the only disagreements possible within

    Positivism are empirical ones?

    Dworkin, Ronald. Laws Empire. New ed. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2003.

    Dworkin, Ronald. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University

    Press, 1978.

    Questions

    Suggested Reading

    FOR GREATER UNDERSTANDING

    Other Books of Interest

    LECTUREFOUR

    18

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    20/58

    19

    One of the knocks against semantic theories of law (theories that focus

    on the criteria something must meet in order to count as law) is that

    the only way semantic theorists can disagree about the law is to have

    an empirical disagreement. The reason they cant disagree in any other

    waylike about what the criteria for law areis because as soon as two

    semantic theorists disagree about the criteria for law, they necessarilydefine law in different ways. So even though they appear to disagree about

    law, they are not really talking about the same thing, but instead are talking

    past one another. Such disagreement would be like two people disagree-

    ing about tanks when one is talking about shirts and the other is talking

    about armored vehicles. An empirical approach that leads us to this point

    will not do: we need an approach that allows us to talk about genuine

    theoretical(and not merely empirical) disagreements about law, the kinds

    real legal practitioners have, even though they do not all agree on the

    criteria for something being law. The approach we need is an interpretive

    one, since competing interpretations of something (for example, a work

    of art) are always directed at the same something, despite the fact that

    individuals use different criteria in developing their different interpretations

    of that something.

    If those interpreting law do not agree on the criteria for law, how do they

    keep from talking past each other and have genuine theoretical disagree-

    ments about law? The answer Dworkin offers begins by examining interpre-

    tation in very general terms. The idea is that taking the interpretive attitude

    with respect to most practices involves first assuming that the practice hasvalue or a purpose that is independent of the basic workings of the practice

    (like the rules), and then assuming that the basic workings of a practice are

    not set in stone, but are instead affected by the practices purpose or value.

    It is important to note that the interpretive attitude is possible only from with-

    in a practice or from the internal perspective. For interpretation to be possi-

    ble, everyone participating in a given practice must see it in many of the

    same ways, and this includes seeing it as having roughly the same value or

    values. They dont all have to agree that every aspect of the practice has to

    be understood in a given way, or that they all agree on criteria. Instead, they

    must have a basic shared understanding of the practiceand their views on

    it must be similar enough that they can understand each other when they

    discuss the practice, but different enough that they can have genuine dis-

    agreement about it. From this perspective, general agreement on a prac-

    tices values does not rule out disagreement about how the practice does or

    should embody those values nor about how to prioritize competing values

    within that practice. Still, that general agreement provides an initial basis for

    The Suggested Reading for this lecture is Ronald Dworkins Laws

    Empire, chapter 2, Interpretive Concepts, and chapter 3,

    Jurisprudence Revisited.

    Lecture 5:

    Theories of Interpretation

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    21/58

    evaluating whether or not an interpretation is viable: if it fails to fit with the

    practice as it is generally understood, then it is not a viable interpretation.1

    With all of this talk of interpretation, its helpful to distinguish three main types

    of interpretationconversational, artistic or creative, and scientificand then

    to see that legal interpretation is a species of artistic interpretation, what

    Dworkin calls constructive interpretation. First, though, we must distinguishlegal interpretation from conversational interpretation, and if we can do that,

    we will in the process undermine many appeals to original or legislative intent,

    since the speakers intention is definitive in cases of conversational interpreta-

    tion. Briefly, the argument goes like this: in conversational interpretation, there

    is one criterion for determining whether or not you have the right interpretation

    of what the other person in the conversation meant, and that criterion is what

    he meant or what he intended his words to mean. But if legal interpretation

    were like that, then Supreme Court justices would focus a lot more than they

    do on historical accounts of what the Framers of the Constitution had in mindwhen they wrote and voted for it and on phone calls to current legislators who

    wrote statutes they review. No, legal interpretation seems to be much less

    about what legislators meant and more what the law itself means (to the

    American people, perhaps). In this way, legal interpretation is much more

    like interpreting a work of art, where the artists intentions do not necessarily

    dictate what the work of art means to a given

    individual or to generations who see it or read it

    hundreds of years later. As such, legal interpreta-

    tion is essentially constructive, in that it tries toprovide an understanding of the law that ultimate-

    ly portrays the law in the best possible light. In

    other words, constructive interpretation seeks to

    put together an understanding of a given practice

    that fits well with the way that practice actually

    works and simultaneously justifies that practice

    according to its own values better than other

    candidate interpretations.

    Dworkin ends chapter two with a long andat times confusing discussion of various kinds

    of skepticism one could have with respect to

    interpreting a practice. There are basically three

    different types of skepticism about interpretation:

    external, internal, and global internal. External

    skepticism, or skepticism about the practice

    being properly justified by reference to some

    value outside of that practice,2 is not particularly

    LECTUREFIVE

    20

    1. For example, it seems fair to say that the point of the practice of dating is to develop romantic

    relationships of one sort or other. Given that claim, an interpretation of dating that depended on

    understanding it as a way of keeping restaurants in business would be, on its face, a bad (or

    nonviable) interpretation of the practice.

    2. Justifying a practice by establishing its link to some external value is precisely what the Natural

    Law Theory (see Lecture 1) advocates: All law must be just or accord with the laws of God or of

    Nature or of Reason in order to be valid law. The external skeptic claims that no such external

    value or law exists, so there is nothing outside of the law we can appeal to that will help us vali-

    date the law.

    MichaelMoran/s

    hutterstock.com

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    22/58

    21

    troubling or threatening, since law seems to have its own internal principles

    that justify it working the way it does, and that fact makes justifying law from

    the outside, by appeal to some external order or law, unnecessary or beside

    the point. Internal skepticism, or skepticism about particular interpretive

    moves within the practice, and global internal skepticism, or skepticism

    about the very interpretive attitude behind a given practice, are both moretroubling to Dworkin because if either turns out to be right, especially global

    internal skepticism, then our understanding of law would fall in on itself. We

    have some work to do before we can answer the internal skeptic: if we can

    show that the values and workings of the practice of law actually can and do

    justify particular interpretations of law, then not only will we be able to prove

    the internal skeptic wrong, but we also will have made a case for a theory

    of legal interpretation.

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    23/58

    1. What is the interpretive attitude?

    2. How is legal interpretation much like interpreting a work of art?

    Dworkin, Ronald. Laws Empire. New ed. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2003.

    Raz, Joseph. The Concept of a Legal System: An Introduction to the Theory

    of Legal Systems. 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980.

    Questions

    Suggested Reading

    FOR GREATER UNDERSTANDING

    Other Books of Interest

    LECTUREFIVE

    22

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    24/58

    23

    This lecture is titled Legal Conservatism because the first interpretive

    approach Dworkin considers in Laws Empire is a view he calls Con-

    ventionalism, many aspects of which coincide with what most of us

    might call legal conservatism. Legal conservatism is the position I dis-

    cussed previously in Lecture 3, and it generally holds that judges should

    enforce the law as it is, not invent it or try to improve it as they go. Ofcourse, there are other views that might fit into the category of legally con-

    servative, and some of those I will discuss in this lecture. Others, however,

    such as those that appeal to original intent, I will leave aside for now, but

    will address in later lectures.

    Conventionalism is the view that the law is only what legal conventions (leg-

    islation, judicial decisions, and so on) explicitly say it is, such that all compe-

    tent legal practitioners would agree about what those conventions require.

    The aspect of Conventionalism that lines up with the laymans view of legal

    conservatism is Conventionalisms demand that judges not enforce anythingother than explicit conventions (such as moral or political views). However,

    unlike the laymans view, Conventionalism recognizes that existing legal con-

    ventions do not provide clear answers in all cases. Conventionalism must

    acknowledge that the law is incomplete in this way because Conventionalism

    is an interpretive approach to the law, and as such, it recognizes the fact that

    despite considerable agreement, there are areas in which one finds gaps

    (at least thats Conventionalisms view). To address

    these gaps, Conventionalism allows judges to use their

    discretion to decide cases when legal conventions donot explicitly require a particular decision one way or

    the otherand once they do, those decisions them-

    selves become legal conventions lawyers and judges

    will follow. This part of Conventionalism is reminiscent

    of moves Legal Realism and Legal Positivism suggest

    for judges when the law runs out.

    We should evaluate Conventionalism using the

    methodology I suggested in the last lecture for

    evaluating constructive interpretations in general:first, we must ask if this interpretation of the law fits

    the law as it is practiced, then ask if it justifies the

    law better than other interpretations. We can use

    this two-stage evaluative process, fit and justifica-

    tion, for all three candidate interpretations Dworkin

    considers in Laws Empire. In the end, Conven-

    tionalism does not actually fit with present practice,

    The Suggested Reading for this lecture is Ronald Dworkins LawsEmpire, chapter 4, Conventionalism.

    Lecture 6:

    Legal Conservatism

    G.

    Maury/shutterstock.com

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    25/58

    LECTURESIX

    24

    though it might seem to at first: since most cases that deal with explicit legal

    conventions would not come before a judge (because they would never be

    brought as cases or would be settled out of court, given that the law would

    be clear in such cases), Conventionalist judges would end up using their

    discretion and filling in gaps far more often than they would just follow the

    law as its written. Such a picture does not fit with present practice: we donot see judges claiming that the law has run out and that they are thus using

    their discretion. To the contrary, judges seem focused on figuring out what

    the law is or demands in a given case. A true Conventionalist would not

    scrutinize law that was controversial or unclearin such cases, he would

    simply use his discretion. Also, the kind of agreement we find in the law

    seems more like a principled consensus rather than mere convention or a

    particular way we just happen to do things. This point is important because

    Conventionalists would not look to principles that underlie the law to help

    them decide cases (as real judges do), because then they would be

    appealing to something other than explicit legal conventions.

    Even if it did fit present practice, however, Conventionalism would still have to

    justify our practice of law better than other interpretations. In order to do that,

    one would have to show that the dominant value behind Conventionalism, the

    political value of protected expectations,1 plays a major role in portraying the

    law in its best possible light. In other words, for Conventionalism to pass

    muster at the level of justification, the law must be best understood as a sys-

    tem that, first and foremost, protects the expectations of those subject to it.

    However, if that is the best goal for the law to have, there seems to be aninterpretation of the law that achieves it and protects expectations far better

    than Conventionalism does. Unilateralism holds that unless there is something

    explicit in the law that would require a judge to decide in favor of the plaintiff,

    the judge must decide for the defendant. Unilateralism would protect expecta-

    tions much better than Conventionalism ever could, but Unilateralism cannot

    even pass the basic threshold of fit: though criminal law resembles Uni-

    lateralism in some ways, no other areas of our law operate this way at all.

    Beyond that point, Unilateralism is too rigid and cannot provide the kind of

    flexibility (and account for undermining rather than protecting expectations

    when that needs to happen) we have and need in the law as it is practiced.

    What we need is the right balance between stability and flexibility. But rather

    than argue directly that Conventionalism does not have the right balance, we

    can look toward Pragmatism, the next theory well consider. Pragmatism holds

    that state coercion is justified not by appeal to legal conventions, but rather by

    how defensible the decision is in general terms. The claim is that Pragmatism

    provides both more flexibility than Conventionalism and as much predictability

    as Conventionalism, though well have to wait until the next lecture to see how

    Pragmatism achieves this. If Pragmatism does in fact offer a better balance of

    predictability and flexibility, then Conventionalism cannot justify the law better

    than the alternatives and thus fails as an overall interpretation of the law.

    1. Protected expectations refers to a kind of stability in the law that keeps surprise changes to a

    minimum. So understood, protecting expectations is clearly valuable in a legal system, as too

    much surprise introduces confusion and inefficiency in the administration of the law.

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    26/58

    1. When and why would a Conventionalist employ discretion?

    2. How does Unilateralism protect expectations better than Conventionalism?

    Dworkin, Ronald. Laws Empire. New ed. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2003.

    Coleman, Jules L. Negative and Positive Positivism. Chicago: The Journal

    of Legal Studies, vol. 11, p. 139, 1982.

    Postema, Gerald. Coordination and Convention at the Foundations of Law.

    Chicago: The Journal of Legal Studies, vol. 11, p. 165, 1982.

    Questions

    Suggested Reading

    FOR GREATER UNDERSTANDING

    Articles of Interest

    25

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    27/58

    The Suggested Reading for this lecture is Ronald Dworkins LawsEmpire, chapter 5, Pragmatism and Personification.

    Lecture 7:

    Judicial Activism

    LECTURESEVEN

    26

    As with Lecture 6, this lecture gets its title from the view that most gener-

    ally resembles Pragmatism, the interpretative approach Dworkin takes up

    in chapter 5 of Laws Empire. Pragmatism rejects the Conventionalist

    claim that past political decisions justify the use of state coercion and

    holds instead that it is the moral or political value of the decision itself that

    justifies such coercion. If the phrase the moral or political value of the deci-sion itself here seems vague, it is: a Pragmatist judge decides cases based

    on her particular view of what decision is best for the communityand differ-

    ent judges will tend to employ different moral or political standards to deter-

    mine what best means.

    Dworkin argues that Pragmatism would likely guarantee predictability as well

    as Conventionalism would, since undermining legal expectations tends to be

    disruptive for the community (because then citizens have a harder time,

    among other things, avoiding sanctions or lawsuits). Just about any approach

    to what is best for the community will recommend that judges generallyuphold the most explicit legal conventions to avoid such disruption. Beyond

    this point, however, Dworkin suggests that Pragmatist judges would tend to

    go even further and guarantee some notion of rights, even though

    Pragmatism would ground legal rights by appeal to moral or political values

    beyond past political decisions. The result would be what Dworkin calls as-if

    rights, or the practice of treating citizens for the most part as if they have

    rightswhen doing so turns out to be best for the communityeven though,

    if pressed, Pragmatists would deny that there are any legal rights in the

    strongest sense (that would override any policy considerations weighingagainst them). So understood, Pragmatism would achieve a level of pre-

    dictability roughly equivalent to Conventionalisms, but with much greater flex-

    ibility to modify the law when doing so would be better for the community.

    On the question of fit, however, Dworkin argues that even though

    Pragmatism fits practice better than Conventionalism does, Pragmatism nev-

    ertheless seems at odds with the way actual judges reason in hard cases. On

    the one hand, actual judges take into account past political and legal deci-

    sions and work hard to reason from them to find principles upon which they

    base their decisions. Pragmatist judges, on the other hand, would not need towork nearly so hard reasoning out their decisions: all they would need to do

    is appeal to their preferred moral or political value systems, since past politi-

    cal and legal decisions have at best only indirect impact on how a Pragmatist

    judge decides a case. Dworkin also seems to think that real judges actually

    worry quite a bit about rights and not just as if they existed. Of course, real

    judges could be Pragmatists in disguise, cloaking their own moral or political

    views under disingenuous talk of legal conventions and rights, but then

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    28/58

    Pragmatism meets the threshold of fit

    only if we understand judges as well-

    meaning liars.1

    Despite these problems, Dworkin suggests

    that Pragmatisms real failure is at the level

    of justification, primarily because it offers aview of rights with which he fundamentally

    disagrees. Before he concludes chapter 5,

    Dworkin suggestswithout much in the way

    of argumentthat rights should be under-

    stood as nonstrategic or grounded in principle

    in such a way that policy considera-

    tions almost never override

    them. Based on this under-

    standing of rights, Dworkinsuggests that insofar as

    Pragmatism would justify the

    practice of law without reference

    to overarching principles and

    rights, Pragmatism cannot justify

    the law better than an interpretative

    approach that requires the law as a

    whole to be consistent in principle or to

    be coherent. Even though Dworkinappears to attack Pragmatism simply for

    failing to share his (undefended) view of rights,

    inasmuch as this rights-based attack leads him to this

    broader claim about coherence (or integrity), Dworkin

    seems to have much more of an argument. Pragmatism

    does seem to allowif not encouragejudges to make decisions that go

    against deeper considerations of principled coherence in the law as a whole,

    primarily because it encourages judges to seek out what is best for the com-

    munity in making their decisions, regardless of how well that decision is con-

    sistent in principle with the rest of the law. To finish off Pragmatism, then,

    Dworkin must show that coherence or integrity in principle is a central value

    in the practice of law. This move mirrors the move he makes with respect to

    Conventionalism at the end of chapter 4, in that he suggests an alternative

    that appears to justify the law better than the approach in question and that

    he will discuss in detail in the next chapter. And like last time, if Dworkin turns

    out to be right that integrity is a central value in our practice of law, then he

    will have proven that Pragmatism does not provide the best justification for

    the law, and Pragmatism will have failed as an interpretation of the law.

    27

    1. Interestingly, those who rail against judicial activism see activist judges in just this way, and that

    is part of their case against such judges: activist judges are problematic, in part at least, because

    they foist their own political and moral views on citizens by smuggling those views into their deci-

    sions and making them look like they are supported by actual legal arguments.

    JozefSzasz-Fabian/shutterstock.com

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    29/58

    1. How is Pragmatism at odds with the way actual judges reason in

    hard cases?

    2. In what way does Pragmatism allow judges to make decisions that go

    against deeper considerations of principled coherence in the law?

    Dworkin, Ronald. Laws Empire. New ed. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2003.

    Dworkin, Ronald. A Matter of Principle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University

    Press, 1986.

    Questions

    Suggested Reading

    FOR GREATER UNDERSTANDING

    Other Books of Interest

    LECTURESEVEN

    28

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    30/58

    29

    At the end of the last lecture, I noted that if we could show that integrity is

    a key political value in the law, then we would be able to demonstrate that

    Pragmatism does not justify the practice of law better than the alterna-

    tives. Perhaps not surprisingly, the alternative Dworkin believes to be

    preferable to Pragmatism is going to depend on integrity as a value in inter-

    pretation, and that alternative will be Dworkins own adjudicative scheme,which he calls Law as Integrity. By integrity here, we mean an overall

    coherence in principle. We can begin defending integrity as a value in law by

    arguing for integrity from the legislative perspective, as opposed to the

    judges point of view. We begin with integrity in legislation because the best

    interpretations of the law will speak not only to deciding cases retrospectively

    or based on existing law, but also to creating law as legislators do. This is

    why Pragmatism is preferable to Conventionalism: Conventionalisms ideal of

    protected expectations is a retrospective value, one that does not address at

    all the forward-looking concerns we have in legal disagreements. Since

    Pragmatism can protect expectations and also explain how we should

    prospectively change the law, Pragmatism is preferable to Conventionalism

    and provides a rival account to Law as Integrity.

    To determine whether or not integrity is a value in legislation, we will use the

    same standards of fit and justification that we have used to evaluate other

    candidate interpretations. Integrity in legislation fits current practice in part

    because it explains why we avoid checkerboard laws, or laws that are noth-

    ing more than a policy compromise between two sides, rather than an

    expression of a principle. An example of a checkerboard law would be a lawthat allowed women born on odd years to have abortions, while criminalizing

    abortions for women born on even years. The fact is that such laws offend

    our legal sensibilities, and they do so because on matters of such importance

    The Suggested Reading for this lecture is Ronald Dworkins LawsEmpire, chapter 6, Integrity, and chapter 7, Integrity in Law.

    Lecture 8:

    Law as Integrity

    EdWhite/RecordedBooks,

    LLC

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    31/58

    LECTUREEIGHT

    30

    (especially in matters of rights), we expect a given law, if not the law as a

    whole, to speak with one principled voice. Since checkerboard laws fail to do

    thatand instead reflect arbitrary policy compromisesthey fail to fit with

    present practice, and that failure serves as evidence that integrity is a key

    value in the law as it is practiced.

    With respect to justification, the question is: Does the law make more sense,is it more easily defended, if integrity is a key value in it? To find the answer,

    we have to think about whether a political system based on a set of coherent

    principles (one that has integrity) would be better than one based on no prin-

    ciples at all.1 It seems safe to say that a community of principle would find it

    easier to generate political obligation and justify state action than would

    unprincipled communities. If thats true, then it is the value of integrity that

    makes communities of principle better. From the perspective of justification,

    integrity then appears to be a key value in the law.

    In the end, however, neither the argument from fit nor the argument fromjustification is conclusive in favor of integrity as a value, and Dworkin admits

    as much.2 Still, these two arguments do at least create a strong presumption

    in favor of integrity as a value in the law, especially as it is practiced. Thats

    really all we need, though, to justify moving on now to exploring integrity in

    adjudication, or Law as Integrity.

    The main device Dworkin uses for explaining the simultaneously retrospec-

    tive and prospective approach of Law as Integrity is the Chain Novel analogy.

    The idea is that a judges work, especially in hard cases, is like the work of

    an author charged with writing the next chapter in an unfinished novel, inwhich the previous chapters were each authored by a different writer. The

    first and more basic aim is to make the next chapter fit with the chapters the

    chain novelist inherits: one could not take the first chapters of The Old Man

    and the Sea, for example, and then write a chapter that tells a science fiction

    story or one that makes no reference to characters or plot lines already

    establishedat least one could not do either of these things and still expect

    anyone to be willing to call this chapter a good candidate next chapter of the

    novel. The second and more difficult aim is to write the next chapter in such a

    way that it both makes the best sense of the preceding chapters and sets uplater chapters so as to make the novel the best it can be. Overall, the goal is

    to write this chapter so that it shows the novel as a whole in its best possible

    light. The chain novelists work, then, is very much like the judges in that

    both must engage in interpreting the subject matter before them before they

    can begin to contribute the next chapter or decision, whatever the case may

    be. And in writing the next chapter or decision, both will make sure that their

    interpretations fit with whats come before and justify the whole workor

    make it the best it can be, both up to this point and as more of it is written.

    1. Here, there are at least two options: A de facto political system, or one in which we merely find

    ourselves, that grows up inadvertently and organically (say, where individuals shipwrecked on

    an island find themselves following the most charismatic member of their group); or a purely con-

    ventional political system, or one based on mere traditions or agreed-to practices (where those

    practices are not grounded in principle).

    2. This is because integrity tries to balance justice or rights against policy, and a perfectly just or

    perfectly efficient society may need no such balancing, and thus have no particular need for

    integrity. Of course, we rarely see perfectly just or perfectly efficient societies.

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    32/58

    1. Are there any current laws that could be considered checkerboard laws?

    2. What is the Chain Novel analogy?

    Dworkin, Ronald. Laws Empire. New ed. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2003.

    Feinberg, Joel. Problems at the Roots of Law: Essays in Legal and Political

    Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988.

    Questions

    Suggested Reading

    FOR GREATER UNDERSTANDING

    Other Books of Interest

    31

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    33/58

    The Suggested Reading for this lecture is Ronald Dworkins LawsEmpire, chapter 8, The Common Law, and chapter 9, Statutes.

    Lecture 9:

    Common Law and Statutes

    LECTURENINE

    32

    With the Chain Novel analogy as a starting point, the next step is to apply

    Law as Integrity to real cases and see how it works. But it will not work

    the exact same way in all sorts of cases. In the Anglo-American legal tra-

    dition, there are three main sources of law: common law (focusing on

    prior judicial decisions or precedents), statutes, and constitutions. As a result,

    cases tend to fall into one of three main categoriescommon law, statutory,and constitutionaland each category has a different focus. Law as Integrity

    reflects those varying concerns and adjusts its focus accordingly. Nonethe-

    less, the general outline of the method Law as Integrity employs to decide

    cases is the same no matter the type of case or area of law: It will evaluate

    candidate interpretations using the same standards we used to evaluate

    Conventionalism, Pragmatism, and integrity in legislation. First, a Law as

    Integrity judge will see if the candidate interpretation fits with the way other,

    similar cases have been decided; and second, she will ask whether that inter-

    pretation justifies the decision better than other candidate interpretations

    meaning that the interpretation and the principle behind it portray the law as a

    whole in its best possible light. At the initial phase, judges will rule out those

    interpretations that do not fit at all (or do not fit adequately) with the pattern of

    decisions in that area of law. Those interpretations that survive the threshold

    of fit are then evaluated in terms of how well the principles they express justi-

    fy the law in that area and as a whole. Exactly what the standards of fit and

    justification look like for a Law as Integrity judge, however, will depend upon

    what type of case she is considering.

    Common law refers to deciding cases based on past precedent decisionsrather than based on statutes or constitutional provisions. In a common law

    case, there is no statute to which a judge can refer to help decide it one way

    or the other. In the United States and the United Kingdom, most civil litigation

    cases (over contracts, personal injury, and the like) are common law cases,

    in which there are relatively few laws on the books and precedent decisions

    play a decisive role.

    A Law as Integrity judge would decide common law cases by focusing first

    and foremost on precedent decisions. She would begin the process of decid-

    ing a case by listing the possible interpretations of the law in the case athand, and then would rule out those interpretations that failed to fit with the

    precedent decisions most directly relevant to the case. She would also rule

    out any candidate interpretations that didnt express a principle on which she

    could decide the case. A good example of an interpretation that failed to

    express a principle would be one that draws an arbitrary line (and not a prin-

    cipled one) between one kind of case and another (as would the checker-

    board laws we discussed in Lecture 8). In this way, Law as Integrity is about

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    34/58

    33

    principles right from the start, and that fact marks a significant difference

    between Law as Integrity and the other views we have discussed. The Legal

    Realists and Positivists, for example, do not count the principles expressed in

    the law as part of what makes something a law.

    Continuing this focus on principles, if more than one interpretation survives

    the initial threshold of expressing a principle and fitting with past decisions inthis area of law, then a Law as Integrity judge would then ask which interpre-

    tation makes the best sense ofor best justifiesthe precedent cases and

    the law in other, related areas. This test of justification requires arguments

    about which principles are at play in a given case and, if they compete, how

    they ought to be weighed with respect to one another. The best arguments

    will treat judges who had made the relevant precedent decisions as earlier

    authors of the chain novel, honoring the principles upon which they had

    based their decisions and striving to carry their story forward in a way that

    makes the most sense and that makes the whole law the best it can be.When a Law as Integrity judge approaches a case dealing with a statute,

    and not common law decisions from the past, she will apply standards of fit

    and justification in much the same way she does in common law cases.

    However, in statutory cases, a Law as Integrity judge will treat the legislative

    body that made the statute, and not other judges, as an earlier author in the

    chain novel of law. She will also ask, at the level of justification, what view the

    statute portrays the political history of that statute and of the law in general in

    the best possible light.

    JohnMackey/shutterstock.com

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    35/58

    The main rival to Law as Integrity when it comes to interpreting statutes is

    the speakers meaning or legislative intent approach (a variant of which is

    what some call original intent theory). To focus on legislative intent to fig-

    ure out a statutes meaning, however, is to abandon a constructive interpre-

    tation in favor of something that operates like a conversational one.1 This

    sort of interpretation poses a number of difficulties for a judge: First andforemost, it is often impossible to determine legislators exact intentions with

    respect to a statute they pass, especially if they died long ago and likely

    never even contemplated the sort of problem a judge might face now with

    respect to an old statute. Furthermore, it is not clear whose intentions should

    count or whose should count more than others when legislators may have

    had different views on, reservations about, and reasons for voting for a

    statute. The difficulties only multiply when one factors in those legislators

    who decided not to repeal or amend the statute after it was passed and thus

    implicitly endorsed the statute and a given understanding of it along the way.

    Considered together, all of these difficulties make the legislative intent

    approach inferior to Law as Integrity.

    Faced with these problems, a thoughtful judge following the legislative intent

    approach will ultimately be forced to focus on the legislators convictions as a

    means of gaining insight into their intentions. By convictions here, we mean

    principles one holds dear and understands as having a particular weight

    when they conflict with each other or other principles. Once the legislative

    intent judge shifts to focusing on convictions, not only is he no longer really

    focusing on legislators intentions, but he is also essentially taking the sameapproach a Law as Integrity judge takes. This move only weakens the legisla-

    tive intent approach further, especially as an alternative to Law as Integrity.

    LECTURENINE

    34

    1. I discuss these two very different approaches to interpretation in detail in Lecture 5.

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    36/58

    1. How would a Law as Integrity judge decide a common law case?

    2. In statutory cases, how will a Law as Integrity judge treat the legislative

    body that made the statute?

    Dworkin, Ronald. Laws Empire. New ed. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2003.

    Greenawalt, Kent. Legislation: Statutory Interpretation: 20 Questions. New

    York: Foundation Press, 1999.

    Questions

    Suggested Reading

    FOR GREATER UNDERSTANDING

    Other Books of Interest

    35

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    37/58

    Despite its title, this lecture is just the first of many devoted to constitution-

    al lawin fact, the remaining lectures in this course will examine constitu-

    tional law issues in one form or another. Constitutional law cases are

    some of the more challenging to interpret, given that constitutional cases

    focus on common law, statutes, the Constitution, and the relationship

    between themall at the same time.

    1

    Also, constitutional law cases tend tobe among the more philosophically complex cases, since they often have to

    do with rights. For these two reasons, along with the fact that constitutional

    law cases attract more interest than most other cases, it is important to see

    how well Law as Integrity handles constitutional law cases. And for these

    same reasons, we will examine in subsequent lectures an alternative to this

    approach as well.

    At the constitutional level,

    Law as Integrity will appeal

    to the same general stan-dards of fit and justification

    it used to decide common

    law cases and statutory

    cases. However, since the

    Constitution is the most

    fundamental law, the Law

    as Integrity approach will

    draw on all aspects of the

    law in deciding constitu-tional cases, including

    previous decisions of

    courts and U.S. political

    and legislative history.

    As such, it will treat the

    American people, as they

    express themselves

    through their laws and

    through their judicial

    system, as prior authors

    in the chain novel of

    constitutional law.

    The Suggested Reading for this lecture is Ronald Dworkins Laws

    Empire, chapter 10, The Constitution, and chapter 11, Law

    Beyond Law.

    Lecture 10:

    Constitutional Law

    LECTURETEN

    36

    1. Most constitutional law cases require the Supreme Court to determine whether a statute is con-

    stitutional or unconstitutional. Of course, constitutional law cases bear on common law decisions

    and on regulations as well, but in this lecture, I will focus on judicial review of statutes.

    M.L.

    Lawson/shutterstock.com

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    38/58

    37

    We can compare this approach to three other popular approaches to decid-

    ing constitutional cases: Historicism, Passivism, and Activism.2 Historicism is

    basically Conventionalism applied to constitutional cases: Historicism requires

    judges to look first at the clear textual meaning of the Constitution and the

    statute in question, and when the texts are not clear, it relies heavily on

    Supreme Court precedents. When neither the texts nor the precedents yield aclear answer, then Historicists turn to legislative intent (which we discussed in

    Lecture 9). Some would argue that current Supreme Court Justices Scalia

    and Thomas are the most obvious examples of real Historicist Justices. The

    problem with Historicism is that, like Conventionalism, it values the stability of

    the law over all else, and it is not clear that stability is the highest value in

    constitutional law: many of our founding principles have found new applica-

    tion as time has passed, and this fact alone undercuts the importance of sta-

    bility in constitutional jurisprudence.

    Activism refers to the stereotypical view of judges who decide cases basedon their political views (as Pragmatism recommends, as we discussed and

    criticized in Lecture 7). Passivism maintains that judges should defer to the

    legislature when it has made a decision on a given issue. The basic approach

    here is skeptical of the view that the judiciary should check the legislative

    branch by enforcing constitutional provisions against it. This fact alone makes

    it hard to see Passivism as presenting a good fit with our practice: checks

    and balances and the Supreme Courts role in judicial review are widely

    accepted in our legal system. Nonetheless, even if somehow Passivism

    passed the test of fit, it would not pass the test of justification, because itplaces democratic values above all else, even though almost all Americans

    understand the Constitution as providing rights against the government (or

    the majority).

    To the extent that we have already explored the faults of Conventionalism,

    Pragmatism, and the speakers meaning (or legislative intent) view, we have

    already seen how Law as Integrity is distinct from and preferable to

    Historicism, Passivism, and Activism. Still, it is helpful to see how a Law as

    Integrity judge will decide a constitutional law case to draw the distinctions

    more clearly. In a case like Brown v. Board of Education (1954), a Law asIntegrity judge would consider a list of candidate interpretations, each one

    appealing to a different way of treating laws that make racial classifications:

    1) suspect classification, 2) banned categories, and 3) banned sources.

    Suspect classification holds that racial classifications are suspect, or that the

    Constitution is predisposed against them, but would nonetheless permit such

    classifications if it can be shown that they treat equally the groups the law

    distinguishes between. This is the standard used in the most direct precedent

    case, Plessy v. Ferguson (1896),3 which established the doctrine of separate

    but equal. A Law as Integrity judge would rule out deciding Brown accordingto suspect classification, because that interpretation did not fit the view of the

    2. Dworkin defines and names these views Historicism, Passivism, and Activism, even though few,

    if any, jurists would refer to themselves as Historicists, Passivists, or Activists. These terms refer

    to groups of interpretive approaches. Aggregating and categorizing them under these labels

    allows one to offer general criticisms of the type of approaches each group represents.

    3. Plessyv. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537 (1896).

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    39/58

    LECTURETEN

    38

    Court or U.S. Constitutional law in 1954. Banned categories holds that the

    Constitution simply forbids laws that make classifications based on certain

    things, and race is one of those. Banned sources holds that the Constitution

    allows laws that make certain kinds of classifications (like racial ones) but

    only when the classification is not motivated by any racial prejudice or bias

    (and it serves some rational purpose of the state). A Law as Integrity judgewould find that either of these candidate interpretative standards would work

    for the sake of deciding Brown, and both would lead the judge to decide in

    favor of Brown, as the Court actually did in 1954. Once the Court is faced

    with an affirmative action case (like Bakke4), however, a Law as Integrity

    judge would say then the better interpretation, the better justification for the

    law as a wholefor both Bakke and Brownwould be the one that appealed

    to banned sources, not banned categories.

    What this shows is that Law as Integrity can respond to changes in society

    and in the countrys political morality. But because Law as Integrity respondsonly to those changes as they are expressed through various sources of

    law, its response is based on various sources of law, not on judicial activism.

    And since Law as Integrity sees the Constitution as the most fundamental

    law and as guaranteeing citizens rights against the legislature, it will not

    decide cases as Passivism recommends. Finally, to the extent that Law as

    Integrity accounts for and well handles change in the law, it is at odds with

    Historicism and its focus on stability.

    Overall, as I have stated several times now, Law as Integrity will strive to

    portray the law in its best possible light. At the constitutional level, that meansconstantly reinterpreting and refining earlier decisions in light of changes in

    the law and in the countrys political morality, opening up the possibility that

    as time goes on, the law will, through the efforts of judges and legislators,

    become more and more unified as a whole, will have more and more integrity.

    4. Regents of the University of California v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265 (1978).

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    40/58

    1. What fact undercuts the importance of stability in constitutional jurisprudence?

    2. What are the distinctions among suspect classification, banned categories,

    and banned sources?

    Dworkin, Ronald. Laws Empire. New ed. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2003.

    Scalia, Antonin. A Matter of Interpretation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University

    Press, 1997.

    Tribe, Laurence H. American Constitutional Law. 3rd ed. Emeryville, CA:

    West Publishing Company, 1999.

    Questions

    Suggested Reading

    FOR GREATER UNDERSTANDING

    Other Books of Interest

    39

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    41/58

    Bruce Ackermans We the People: Foundations offers an understanding

    of the Constitution and constitutional law that is as focused on political

    history as Dworkins view in Laws Empire is focused on legal philosophy.

    At the same time, legal philosophy is as much a part of the background

    Ackerman assumes as political history is part of the background Dworkin

    assumes. Given the way these views complement each other and the influ-ence Ackermans work has had in legal circles, his Dualist Democracy

    approach provides a particularly interesting and helpful alternative to

    Dworkins Law as Integrity.

    Ackerman calls his view Dualist Democracy because it sees in the U.S.

    legal system two tracks for lawmaking: the constitutional or higher law-

    making track and the everyday or normal politics track, which results in

    statutes and regulations. These two tracks are embodied in the U.S.

    Constitution itself: there are separate and different rules expressed in it for

    creating ordinary, everyday laws on the one hand, and for amending theConstitution on the other. Given these different sets of rules, the government

    (via elected representatives) makes normal laws, while the People are

    responsible for making higher law.1 On this view, the Supreme Court plays

    the role of preserving the higher law from being undermined or chipped away

    by normal politics and everyday lawmaking.

    Despite its intuitive appeal, the Dualist approach stands in stark contrast to

    several other popular approaches to understanding our system of constitu-

    tional law. Monism focuses almost exclusively on the democratic decisions of

    elected officials and thus objects when the Supreme Court invalidates somelaw, and it objects on the grounds that the Courts invalidating it is counter-

    majoritarian. As such, Monism seems to collapse the two tracks of Dualism

    into one dominant track (thus its name). Against Monism, its important to

    notice that both of the tracks Dualism suggests are essentially democratic

    and that it is appropriate that the one that requires more people approve of it

    (the higher law track) has prominence over the other.

    Rights Foundationalism holds that rights are more fundamental to our consti-

    tutional law than democratic procedures are, and for this reason, rights serve

    as a check on normal politics. Foundationalists maintain that these rights arebetter understood through appeals to philosophy than through appeals to any

    sort of politics. Against this view, Dualism argues that any understanding of

    constitutional rights must be grounded in democratic processesand not in

    The Suggested Reading for this lecture is Bruce Ackermans We thePeople: Foundations, chapters 1 and 2.

    Lecture 11:

    Dualist Democracy

    LECTUREELEVEN

    40

    1. Here, the People seems the appropriate term, given the supermajorities (two-thirds of the

    House and Senate and three-quarters of the state legislatures) required for higher lawmaking.

  • 7/28/2019 Philosophy and the Law - How Judges Reason (Booklet).pdf

    42/58

    41

    philosophical theoriesto have any legitimacy. Unlike Foundationalism, then,

    Dualism is first and foremost a democratic approach, in which rights play a

    secondary and dependent role.

    Interestingly, Ackerman identifies Dworkin as a Rights Foundationalist. While

    some of Dworkins writings certainly suggest that he leans in this direction, it

    is not clear that Law as Integrity is necessarily a Rights Foundationalist view.Law as Integrity does hold that justiceor an appeal to rightsis the domi-

    nant value at the level of constitutional law, but it understands those rights as

    developing through the political and legislative history of the United States.

    The third view we can contrast with Dualism is Historicism, or the view that

    constitutional change should be incremental and brought about by statesmen

    who can keep the change from being disruptive for the nation. On the one

    hand, Historicism is deeply skeptical of the Peoples ability to understand

    what is best for society and of the Peoples ability to figur