Download - Afterword What Has Philosophy to Learn From Tort Law

Transcript
  • Afterword What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?

    Page 1 of 11

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    UniversityPressScholarshipOnlineOxfordScholarshipOnline

    ThePhilosophicalFoundationsofTortLawDavidG.Owen

    Printpublicationdate:1997PrintISBN-13:9780198265795PublishedtoOxfordScholarshipOnline:March2012DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198265795.001.0001

    AfterwordWhatHasPhilosophytoLearnfromTortLaw?BERNARDWILLIAMS

    DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198265795.003.0022

    AbstractandKeywords

    Philosophymightlearnfromtortlawthedifferencebetweenpracticalrealityandphilosophicalfrivolity.J.L.Austinwasdisposedtogivethatanswer.Austinsaidthatitwascommonsenseor,perhaps,ordinarylanguage,andonereasonhesometimesgaveforthisjudgementwasaquasi-evolutionaryone.Thischapterpresentswhatitcallsaquasi-evolutionaryaccountofthestrengthofsomelegalconceptsanddistinctions,thePicture.ThePictureiswithoutdoubthighlyidealised.Thereareperhapstwomaindirectionsfromwhichthissuggestionmaycome.OneobjectionisthatthePictureoverestimatestheeffectsoflegalargument.Theideahereisthatcasesaredecidedonthebasisofexternalvaluesorprinciplessuchaswealthmaximisation,utility,orequalfreedomandthatthelegalargumentsandtheconceptsinvokedinthem(fault,negligence,intention,proximityofcausation,orwhatever)are,atthelimit,merelyrhetoricaldecorations.

    Keywords:philosophy,tortlaw,J.L.Austin,legalargument,wealthmaximisation,utility,equalfreedom,fault,negligence,intention

  • Afterword What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?

    Page 2 of 11

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    I.TestingCommonSense:ThePictureOneanswertomyquestionisthatphilosophymightlearnfromtortlawthedifferencebetweenpracticalrealityandphilosophicalfrivolity.J.L.Austinwasdisposedtogivethatanswer.Austinwas,likeWittgensteinandNietzsche,struckbytheirresponsibilityofphilosophy,itslight-headedwillingnesstosupposethatlargeproblemscouldbeusefullyaddressedbysomedistinctionsorformulationsthatweresimplythoughtupofaSundayafternoon.(TherewasadifferencebetweenAustinandthoseothers:unlikethem,hedidmoreorlesstakeitforgrantedthattherewasasubject,philosophy,whichmightcometoconductitselfmoreseriouslyandusefullyintheserespects,evenifhewaslessthanclearabouttheformthatthesubjectmighttake.)

    Whatisthiscontrast?Whatisitthatsupposedlyprovidesuswithdistinctionsmoreadequatethanthoseofferedbyphilosophy?Austinsaid(withsomereservations)thatitwascommonsenseor,perhaps,ordinarylanguage,andonereasonhesometimesgaveforthisjudgementwasaquasi-evolutionaryone,thatcommonsense(asIshallcallit)1hadbeen,atleastwithregardtocentralhumanconcerns,underheavyselectivepressureforaverylongtime,andthedistinctionsthathadsurvivedandflourishedinitwerelikelytoanswerfairlyreliablytohumanneeds.Thiswasnotaverygoodanswer,formorethanonereason,anditisnoteasytotellhowseriouslyAustintookit.However,itdoesatleastprovideastartingpointforthinkingaboutsomethinglessgeneral,acontrastdrawninsimilartermsbetweenphilosophyandthelaw.Austinalsoappealedtothelaw,andthefamousarticleAPleaForExcuses,inwhichhesetsoutsomeofhismethodological(p.488) concerns,mentionsa(rathergrisly)exampledrawnfromanineteenthcenturycase.2

    Ifthelawforinstance,thelawofnon-intentionaltorts3usescertainconceptsordistinctionsthathavebeenvariouslyapplied,modified,andreinterpretedwithinalegaltraditionoveraperiodoftime,doesthisofferanyreasonatallforthinkingthatthoseconceptsanddistinctionsprovideasoundandreliablewayofthinkingabouttherelevantareasofexperience?Moreexactly,thequestioniswhethersuchfactsprovideanyindependentreason,sinceitmightbethatthelegaluseofcertainideasdidnomorethanwitnesstowhatwasclearanyway,thatthoseideasseemedobvioustocommonsense.Iftheuseofcertainideasinthelawdoesmoretoshowthatthoseideashavestrengththanisdonebythemerefactthattheyarepartofthecurrencyofcommonsense,thiswillhavetobeconnectedwithspecialfeaturesofthelawwiththeidea,mostplausibly,thatthelegalcontextisoneinwhichalotturnsontheoutcome,andhenceontheargumentsthatleadtoorlegitimatelegaloutcomes.Thisisitselfakindofevolutionaryargument.Thesenseinwhichalotturnsontheoutcomeisthattheissueislikelytobevigorouslydisputedbythepartiesinvolved,thatthedecisionmayhaveimplicationsforotherpartieswhowillwatchtheoutcomewithinterest,andsoforth,withtheresultthatonlyrobustlyarguedconclusions,whichareatleastconsistentwithpublicconceptionsofwhatmakessensinsuchconnections,arelikelytosurvive.Ishallcallthisquasi-evolutionaryaccountofthestrengthofsomelegalconceptsanddistinctions,thePicture.

    II.TwoObjections

  • Afterword What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?

    Page 3 of 11

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    ThePictureiswithoutdoubthighlyidealized.Itmaybesuggestedthatitisworsethanidealized,andrests,rather,onsomemistakeofprinciple.Thereareperhapstwomaindirectionsfromwhichthissuggestionmaycome.OneobjectionisthatthePictureoverestimatestheeffectsoflegalargument.Theideahereisthatcasesaredecidedonthebasisofexternalvaluesorprinciplessuchaswealthmaximization,utility,equalfreedomandthatthelegalargumentsandtheconceptsinvokedinthem(fault,negligence,intention,proximityofcausation,orwhatever)are,atthelimit,merelyrhetoricaldecorations.TheotherobjectionisthatthePictureunder-estimatestheautonomyandpeculiarityoflegalconcepts:thattherequirements,(p.489) purposes,andtraditionsofthelawarespecialenoughforitsdistinctionsandprinciplestostandatadistancefromcommonsenseandfromwhatpeopleneedtosayandthinkinextra-legalcontexts.

    Thetwolinesofobjectionmayseemtoruninoppositedirections,butthisisnotnecessarilyso.Onecancombinethem,inclaimingboththatlegalargumentishighlytechnicalandthatitfailstodeterminetheoutcome.Indeed,thesuggestionmaybethatthereasonlegalargumentneedstobeverytechnicalisinordertoconcealthefactthatitfailstodeterminetheoutcome:thetechnicalitiesprovideamystificationthatconcealstheunderlyingprocesses.Whethertheobjectionsarecombinedinthiswayornot,theydobetweenthemthreatenthePicture,whichwasinvokedtoexplainhowprocessesofthelawcouldremindphilosophyofrealitybyshowingdistinctionsrecognizabletocommonsenseunderpressurewheremuchturnsontheoutcome.Broadlyspeaking,thefirstobjectionisthatthedistinctionsinvokedarerecognizabletocommonsense,butarenotunderpressure;thesecondisthatthedistinctionsmayperhapsbeunderpressure(iftheyarenotsimplyactingasamystification),buttheyandtheoutcomesthattheyareinvokedtosupportareonlyremotelyrelatedtocommonsense.Oneithershowing,theideathatthelawcanshedlightoncommonsense,orindeedonanythingoutsideitself,losesmomentum.

    Neitherobjectionisfatal.Evenifwhatthefirstobjectionclaimsistrue,itisnotclearthatverymuchfollowsfromitforthepresentquestion.Rationalizationsmusthavesomeforceeventoserveasrationalizations,andtherationalizationswhich,onthisaccount,serveastherhetoricofthelegalprocessthroughwhichoptimalallocationsofcostsaremade(orwhateverthesupposedunderlyingprincipleorvalueistakentobe)musthavesomestrengthinordertodischargethisrole.Indeed,itmaybethattheywillturnouttohavealmostasmuchstrengthasthePicturerequires.

    Thelatenteconomiccriteria,orwhatevertheymaybe,which,accordingtothetypeoftheoryinvokedbythefirstobjection,determinetheoutcomesatthefundamentallevelarenotmanifestlyinoperation.Iftheywere,thetheorywouldnotbecontroversial,anditwouldalsohavenothingnewtorecommendnormatively,if(assomesuchtheoriesdo)ithasthataim.Theargumentsthatdotheworkatthemanifestlevelmustbethefamiliarones.Thetheoryregardsthemasrationalizations,buttheymustneverthelessdosomework,sincesomeprocessisactuallygoingonatthemanifestlevel,andthatprocessmusthavesomeofthecharacteristics(ofclaimsbeingarguedagainstcounter-claimsandso

  • Afterword What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?

    Page 4 of 11

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    on)thatwereidentifiedinthePicture.

    Ofcourse,ifthetheoryclaimsthattheprocessesatthemanifestlevel(conventionalargumentaboutnegligence,proximatecause,andsuch)concealsomeothercriteria(economicorwhatever)whichactuallydeterminetheoutcome,itmustgivesomeaccount(asallsuchfunctionalisttheoriesmust)ofthewaysinwhichthoseothercriteriacanguide,beservedby,and(p.490) mostgenerallyrelatetothemanifestlevelofargument.Thiswillhavecertainimplicationsaboutthenatureoftheargumentsatthemanifestlevel:suchconventionalargumentsmay,forinstance,havetodisplayacertainflexibilityorporositywhichallowsthemtorespondtothefunctionalrequirementsoftheconsiderationsthatoperateatthelatentlevel.Butifthetheorycangiveanaccountofthis(anditwillnotbeacredibleorinterestingtheoryunlessitcan),thisresultitselfwillmaketheoperationsofthelawinterestingandindeedinstructivetophilosophy.Forthisporositycanscarcelybeafeatureoftheconventionalcriteriasimplyastheyareusedinthelaw.Ifthatwereso,theycouldnotsustainacrediblerationalization.Theporositywillratherhavetobeafeature,oratleastapotentiality,ofsuchcriteriaastheyareusedevenoutsidethelaw,andthisissomethingthatphilosophyshouldunderstandaboutthem.Moreover,itmaybethattheporosityoftheeverydaycommonsensecriteriaservestosomedegreethesamefunctionoutsidethelawas(accordingtothetheory)itservesinsidethelaw,ofallowingthecriteriatobemanipulatedinaccordancewitheconomicorotherlatentconsiderations,andifthatisso,itisequallysomethingthatphilosophyshouldunderstand.

    Thesecondobjectionwasthattheargumentsandconceptsusedinthelawweretoospecialist,tooremovedfromextra-legalthought,toprovidephilosophywithanyinsightintothewaysinwhichextra-legalthoughtworks.Thereare,obviously,technicalaspectsofthelawforwhichthisistrue,butsofarasthemostimportantmattershereareconcernedmatterssuchasfault,intention,carelessness,proximatecauseandconsequence,andsoontheclaimissimplynotconvincing,atleastwhenanimportantconcessionhasbeenmade.Itistruethatthelawmustoftenreachaconclusionaboutquestionstowhichcommonsensewouldbehappytoleavetheanswerindeterminatetowhich,indeed,inmanycases,itwouldbeunhappytodoanythingbutleavetheanswerindeterminate.Therearefamiliarexamplesofthisinthecriminallaw.Iftheassailantpullsthetriggerinonejurisdictionandthebullethitsthevictiminanother,commonsensemaywellbecontenttosayjustthatmuch,butthelawneedstodecidewherethevictimwaskilled.Moresignificantly,therearequestionsofanagentsstateofmind,andasaninterestingifmarginalconsequenceofwhoisthecriminalagentincases,forinstance,ofhypnoticsuggestion.4Inallthesematters,thelawcanbeseenasforcingtheissuerelativetowhatIamcallingcommonsense;thoughIshallsuggestlaterthatincertainconnectionsthelawmaymerelybeamoredeterminedaccompliceofcommon(p.491)senseindoingthis,andindeedthatthisisonerespectinwhichphilosophymaylearnfromtheoperationsofthelaw.

    III.ForcingTheIssueThelawoftortsinitsownwaysalsoforcestheissue,notablyontheextentand

  • Afterword What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?

    Page 5 of 11

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    directnessofcausation,andonquestionsofstateofmindthatpresentthemselvesinrelationtosuchmattersasintent,recklessness,and,tosomeextent,negligence.Ithastoforcetheissue,forareasonthatsuperficiallyisthesameasthatforwhichthecriminallawhastodosothatitneedsaresult.Butthatphrase,thoughitappliestobothcases,concealssomeimportantdifferencesbetweenthem.Thecriminallawneedsaresultinthesensethatanaccusedperson,onceheorsheisaccused,mustbefoundguiltyornotguilty.Intort,5oncetheactionisunderway,eithertheplaintifforthedefendantmustsucceed,whichmeansinturnthatoneorotheroftheparties(orinsomeproportionboth)mustbearthecostofthelossordamage.Butthereisthebanaldifferencethatwithcrime,itis,aboveall,clearcasesthatcometocourt,andwithtortitis,aboveall,hardcases.Withtort,itisthelegalcharacteristicofbeingahardcasethathelpstogetittocourtinthefirstplace,butincrimeitisthearrestofasupposedcriminal.Someonemightsaythatinanabsolutelyidealworldallandonlyguiltycriminalswouldbeprosecuted,6buttherecouldbenoworldinwhichitwasonlysuccessfulplaintiffswhosecaseswereheard.Tort,byitsnature,mustbemorelikeasystemfortheallocationofcoststhanthecriminallawis,anditfollowsfromthisthattherecanbesystemsthatperformthatfunctioninadifferentway,suchasnofaultinsurancesystems,or,presumably,theprinciplesofwealthmaximizationiftheywereexplicitlyemployed.7

    Itfollowsthatthesensesinwhichthecriminallawandtorthavetohaveananswerareratherdifferent.Inbothtypesofcase,ofcourse,therehastobeananswer,grantedthatthesystemexistsandthepartiesareincourt;buttheconditionsofbeingincourtarenotthesame,anditisalsoclearerwithtortthanwithcrimewhatadifferentsystemmightbe.Thismakesitspeciallyimportantthatthereshouldbeatheoryofwhattortlawis(p.492)supposedtobedoing,andthisinturnhasconsequencesforitsrelationstophilosophy.IfphilosophycanbeinstructedbythelawinthetermsofferedbythePicturethatistosay,throughseeingwhatdistinctionsandconsiderationsproverobustincircumstancesinwhichwehavetohaveanansweritwillneedanunderstandingofwhattheforcesarethatoperateonthelawandareexpressedinit,and,inparticular,ofwhatitisforthelawtohavetohaveananswer.Philosophy,then,willnotonlyhavetoattendtotheprinciplesandgoalsoftortlaw;itwillalsohavetounderstandatatheoreticallevelwhyithasthoseprinciplesandgoals.

    IV.ThePlaceofTheoryThistheoreticalunderstandingmayitselfbeinpartphilosophical,andtothatextenttherelationsbetweenphilosophyandlawwillbe,unsurprisingly,reciprocal.Buttheunderstandingrequiredwillalsobepolitical.Inthisdimension,besidesthespecialreasonsforneedingatheoryofwhattortlawisupto,namelythattherearealternativesystemsthatmightperformsomeofitsfunctions,thereisamoregeneralreasonwhichtortlawshareswiththecriminallaw:thatbothoftheseoperationsoflawinvolvethedirectedexerciseofstatepower,anditisanaspirationofaliberalsocietythattheoperationsofpowershouldbesofaraspossibletransparent,inatleastthemodestsensethattheirsupposedlegitimationshouldnotrestonsystematicmisunderstanding.

    Thismodestrequirementdoesnotimplythateverypoliticalpracticemustbelegitimated

  • Afterword What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?

    Page 6 of 11

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    intermsofsometheory,stilllessthatallofthemmustbelegitimatedintermsofthesametheory.Butinastategovernedbylawtheoperationsofthelawrepresentthemostdirectapplicationofpowertotheindividual,andgrantedfurtherthehighlycontestedjustificationsoftheseoperationsinmodernliberalsocieties,itisinfactthecasethatinsuchsocietiesthedemandsoftransparencyareunlikelytobemetwithouttheresourcesofatheoreticalaccount.Someofthataccount,thoughpolitical,willundoubtedlyoverlapwiththephilosophicalcontributionandconstitutepartofapoliticalphilosophy.

    ThecallontheoryatthispointisquitedifferentfromtheideaexpressedbyRichardWrightinhiscontributiontothisvolume,8thatrationalityrequiresatheorywhichoffersaunified,monistic,basisforbotheverydaymoralityandthelaw.Ihavearguedelsewhere9thattheaimofturningeverydaymoralityintoatheory,andindeedtheideathatithasorshouldhaveamonisticbasis,aremisguided.Thesituationwithpoliticalphilosophyisnotentirelythesame,andthereismoreplacefortheoryinit.The(p.493) reasonsforthisarespecialtopoliticalphilosophy.Theyaregroundedbothinthegeneralpointthatpoliticsisimmediatelyinvolvedintheapplicationofpower,10andalsoinamorelocalpoint,thatlegitimationinthemodernliberalstaterequiresonsuchmattersahighlevelofdiscursiveexplanation.Ifouraimweretodevelopaunitarytheoreticalaccountofeverydaymoralityandthelawonamonisticbasis,theseconsiderationswouldseemtofavorapicture(thoughitwouldnotstrictlyimplyit)inwhichtherewasaprimacyofphilosophyoverthelaw.Philosophicalreflectionandthetheorywhich,onthisview,itgenerateswouldbethoughttomaketheworkingofthelawintelligible,ortoprescribehowitmightbeimprovedsoastobemoreintelligible.Onthisview,itwouldbeamatterofwhatphilosophycoulddoforthelaw.ButontheaccountIamsuggesting,philosophytriestolearnfromtheoperationsofthelaw,inconjunctionwithatheoryofwhatthelawisuptoatheorypartlyprovidedbyphilosophyitself.

    V.InTheMicrowaveWhatmayphilosophylearnfromlaw?Theoriginalsuggestionwasthatitmightlearntherobustnessofsomefamiliardistinctions,judgedfromthewayinwhichtheybehaveunderpressure,whenthelawhastohaveananswer.Thereareindeedexamplesthatfitthismodel.Itisimportantthattheyarenotmostlikelytoshowupinconnectionswhichfromthepointofviewoflegaltheoryarethemostcontroversial.Theirrobustnessmayshowup,rather,inthefactthattheyaretakenforgrantedinlegalargument,andarenotmadethefocusofattackbyanyoftheparties.Considerthematterofintentintortorcriminallaw.Itmayindeedbecontroversialinaparticularconnectionwhetheritmattersornotthattheagentintendedtheoutcome;anditmay,further,becontroversialwhatwouldcountasshowingthathedidintendtheoutcome(oratanyrateshouldbetreatedassomeonewhointendedtheoutcome).Butbehindallthistherewillbeasteadystreamofassumptionsaboutsituationsinwhichitisabsolutelyclearthathedidintendtheoutcome,andthatitisrelevantthatheintendedtheoutcome.

    Again,evenwhenitisindisputewhethertheagentintendedthisoutcome,thedisputeitselfrepresentshimashavingdonesomethingsintentionally.Itmaybethoughtthatthisissimplyuninteresting,sincetothis(p.494) extentthelawisuncontroversiallyusing

  • Afterword What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?

    Page 7 of 11

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    thematerialsofcommonsensematerials,forinstance,thatmayhavebeenofferedinevidencebycitizenswhoaremerely,intheserespects,usingtheresourcesofcommonsense.Butthatisthepoint,thatacertainstoreofsharedinterpretationsandconceptssurvivescrutiny,everyday,underlegalprocessandprovidethestructureofthelawsoperations.Theyarelikecontainersthatcanwithstandthemicrowave.Onanygivenoccasionitisthestufftheycontainthatisthecenterofinterest,andthelegalprocessisdirectedtoseeinghowthatstuffwillturnout;butitissignificant,asthePicturesuggesteditwas,thattherearesomefamiliarmaterialsthatservetoholdandpresentthisstuff,andhaveastructurethatenablesthem,dayinanddayout,towithstandradiationatcourtroomintensity.

    However,itwouldbeverysurprisingifphilosophycouldlearnonlyfromthelesscontroversialpartsoflegalargumentanddoctrine,anditisitselfsignificantthatsomeconceptsconstantlycausetroubleinthelawandprovideafocusforreinterpretationandcontroversysuchastherobustandpersistentdebateoverthesuperiorityoffault(negligence)orstrictliabilityforaccidentallycausedharm.AsIhavealreadysuggested,thisisnotonly,orprimarily,becauseitprovidesanopportunityforphilosophytocometothelawsrescue.Itmay,inacertainsense,givephilosophyoccasiontocometotheconceptsrescue.Butifso,thiswillonlybebecausephilosophycanlearnsomethingaboutthenatureoftheconceptsfromtheirsufferingsundertheconditionsofthelaw.

    VI.ResponsibilityandtheVoluntaryThisisnotablysowithideasofthevoluntaryandwithnotionsofresponsibilitythatinvariouswaysarecloselyrelatedtoit.Therearetwotruthsinparticularthatthelawmayhelpphilosophyseeabouttheseideas.11One,whichemergesfromtheexperienceofboththecriminallawandthelawoftorts,isthatgraveproblemsariseforthenotionofthevoluntarywhenweseektodeepenit,tomove,forinstance,fromissuesofwhatonagivenoccasionanagentsoughttobringaboutandofwhatstateofmindhewasimmediatelyin(andthosequestionscanbehardenough),toquestionsofhowfarsuchstatesofmindwerenormal,ornormaltohim,andoftheextenttowhichheisresponsibleforbeingapersonwhowouldcommittheactinthatstateofmind.Suchlinesofthought,asweallknow,mayrapidlyleadintoswampsofskepticism,someofthemmarkedbyrustingsignsbearingthelegendFreeWill.

    (p.495) Theothertruth,onethatemergesunequivocallyfromthelawoftorts,isthatresponsibilityinthesenseofadutytocompensateinevitablyrunsbeyondresponsibilityfortheoutcomeinthesenseofanintentionorevenadesiretobringitabout.Disputesaboutfaultandtheabsenceofjustification,suchasarediscussedinthechaptersofTonyHonorandDavidOwen,12areconcernedtoaskwhethertheremustatanyratebeagrainof(somethinglike)thevoluntaryonwhichtogrowtheelaboratecrystalofliability;butno-one,certainly,deniesthatthecrystalmayvastlyoutgrowitsseed.

    Thereisatemptationtothinkthatsomehowtherecanbedefinedanotionofthevoluntarywhichisbothdeepandadequate;andthat,evenifliabilityinunintentionaltortcould,inprinciple,neverbemadesimplycommensuratewithwhattheagentinthatsensevoluntarilydid,atleastthenotionwouldprovideafoundationforthinkingcorrectly

  • Afterword What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?

    Page 8 of 11

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    aboutthewaysinwhichliabilitymustinevitablyextendbeyondit.Thetendencytothinkinthesetermscanfigureinthetheoryofthelawitself.Oneimportantwayinwhichitisdisplayedisbynegation,intheideathatnotionsofthevoluntaryandofresponsibilitycloselyalliedtothevoluntaryrequireadeepaccount,andsincenosuchaccountistobehad,thelawhadbetterdowithoutsuchnotionsaltogether.

    Thetendencytothinkinthiswayis,Ithink,misguided.Thisisaplaceatwhich,asIputitearlierinthischapter,commonsensecanbeinconspiracywithlaworatleastwithcertaintheoristsoflawtoforcetheissue,inthiscasetoforcethepsychologicalandmetaphysicalissuesbeyondthesuperficialphenomena.Bothcommonsenseandthetheoryoflawhavesomereasontosustainanideaofthevoluntaryasadeepnotion,whichhas,ifonlywecouldfindit,adeepaccount.Infact,asIhavesuggestedelsewhere,13theideaofthevoluntaryisanessentiallysuperficialnotion,whichworksonconditionthatonedoesnottrytodeepenit.Thistruth,itseemstome,canberecoveredfromstudyingthelawinpractice,asopposedtothenormativeaccountthatsometheoristsgiveofit,andexaminingtheevasions,approximations,andmisadventureswhichtheideaofthevoluntaryregularlyencountersthere.Thepressuresthatthelawappliescaninthiscasehelpphilosophytoseewhatcommonsensemoralityandphilosophysownargumentsonthesesubjectscanhelpittooverlook,thattheconceptofthevoluntaryaddsuptonotmuchmorethanweareofferedbyitssurfacecriteria,bywhichavoluntaryactis,roughly,anintentionalaspectofanactdoneinanormalstateofmind.Thereisastorytobetoldofhow(p.496) suchaconcept,limitedasitis,hasvaluableworktodo,inparticularinthecriminallaw.Butthatstorydoesneedtobetold;thisisoneofthepointsatwhichphilosophyhastolearnnotonlyfromwhatthelawdoesbutfromatheoryofwhatthelawshouldbetryingtodo,theorytowhich,asIhavealreadysaid,philosophy(aboveall,politicalphilosophy)willhavealreadycontributed.

    Inthematterofliabilityintort,thesituationisslightlydifferent.Here,onceagain,themanifestpracticeofthelaw,itsstruggleswithconceptsoffaultandjustification,canconcentratephilosophersmindsontherealityofsituationsinwhichpeoplecan(andthoseinwhichtheycannot)befairlytreatedasanswerableforoutcomeswhichtheydidnotintendandcouldnothaveforeseen.Thesecanremindusofthemanywaysinwhichwedothinkintermsofoutcomeresponsibility,inHonorisphrase.Inthiscase,itmightbethatfurtherpoliticalreflectioncouldsuggestthatthiswasnotthebestwayforthelawtotrytodealwiththeallocationofcosts;itiscertainlypossiblethatthestrugglesofthelawwithoutcomeresponsibilitycouldencourageustothinkthatthelawitselfmightdobetterbyshiftingtheemphasistootherschemes.Ihavenoideawhether,ortowhatextent,thismightturnouttobethecase(whereastheargumentforthecriminallawsinvestmentinarelativelyundemandingconceptofthevoluntaryis,Ithink,fairlyunproblematic.)

    However,evenifoutcomeresponsibilitywerenotultimatelythebestconceptualinstrumentforthelawoftorts,thiswouldnotcanceltheenlightenmentthatphilosophycangainbylookingatthelawsdealingswiththisconcept.Wewouldstillhavecometosee,underthelawsextremeconditions,howsuchaconceptworks,andwhatmayseem

  • Afterword What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?

    Page 9 of 11

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    reasonableorunreasonableapplicationsofit.Weshallhaveseenalottoremindusthattheconceptisnotperfectible,andthatitisprobablynotreplaceablebyaconceptofmoralresponsibilitythatwilleliminateresponsibilityforeverythingexceptwhatisintheimmediatecontroloftheagentswill.Theseremaintruthsaboutresponsibility,andevenifthelawoftortsweretodecideonthebasisofanimprovedpoliticaltheorythatitwouldbetosomesubstantialextentbetteroutoftheresponsibilitybusiness,theexperienceofthelaw,andtheconsiderationsspecialtothelawthatwouldbemobilizedbythepoliticaltheory,wouldstillgivehelpinunderstandingwhatwecanreasonablyexpectofanideaofresponsibilityinthoseareasofourliveswheresuchanideawill,unremovably,continuetohaveauthority.

    VII.ConclusionThePicturewithwhichIstartedhassometruthinit.Importantly,itisnotjustthesuccessofourconceptsundertheextremeconditionsofthelaw(p.497) thathassomethingtotellphilosophy,butalsotheiroccasionalfailuretosurvivethatexposure.Philosophywillbeabletolearntherightlessons,however,onlyifthereisanadequatetheory(inpartprovidedbypoliticalphilosophyitself)aboutwhatfeaturesoftheconcepts,andwhatspecialfeaturesofthelaw,havecontributedtothosesuccessesandfailures.(p.498)

    Notes:(1)SomephilosophersofAustinstendencymayhavethoughtthatcommonsensewasconsistent,self-validating,andfreeofideology.Thepresentdiscussionmakesnosuchassumptions.

    (2)J.L.AUSTIN,APleaforExcuses,inPHILOSOPHICALPAPERS(1961);Reginav.Finney,[1874]12Cox625.

    (3)Muchofmyargumentwillbeatagenerallevel,wheredistinctionsbetweendifferentlegalareaswillnotbeveryrelevant,butthelawofnon-intentionaltortsiswhatIshallprincipallyhaveinmind,andthishassomesignificanceinrelationtoacontrastwiththecriminallaw.Seeinfranote5.

    (4)Thisisoneofseveraldimensions(asherecognizes)inwhichtherearelimitationstoMichaelMooresprojectofgroundingthecriminallawsrequirementsoncriminalagencyinageneralmetaphysicsofaction:seeMICHAELS.MOORE,ACTANDCRIMETHEPHILOSOPHYOFACTIONANDITSIMPLICATIONSFORCRIMINALLAW(1993)andfordiscussion,thesymposium,ActandCrime,142U.PA.L.REV.1455(1994).Ontheparticularissueofsomnambulisticandothernon-standardstates,seemyTheActusReusofDr.Caligari,supra,at1661.

    (5)Iamprimarilyconcernedherewithnon-intentionaltorts,seesupra,note1.Thedistinctionbetweenintentionaltortsandcrimeraisesfurtherissues.

    (6)Iamnotclearwhetheranyonetakessuchanidealseriously.Anyonewhodiddosowouldhavetorecognizethatitimpliesconstraintsonwhatcancountasacrime.

  • Afterword What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?

    Page 10 of 11

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    (7)RichardPosner,inthediscussionofhiswealthmaximizationconceptioninWealthMaximizationandTortLaw:APhilosophicalInquiry,thisvolume,drawsbyimplicationacontrastwithcrime,butIamnotclearwhatitis.Theutility(inthesenseusedbyutilitarians)toathiefofagoodthathecouldnotaffordtobuyhasnoethicalstatusorlegitimacyinwealthmaximization.Itisnotademandbackedbyanofferprice:id.atnote20.Onthefaceofit,thisseemstoreplacetheplatitudethatunjustsatisfactionshavenoclaiminjusticewiththefalsehoodthatifIcannotaffordtobidforanitemIcanhavenojustclaimtoit.

    (8)RichardW.Wright,TheFoundationsofLegalResponsibility,thisvolume.

    (9)BERNARDWILLIAMS,ETHICSANDTHELIMITSOFPHILOSOPHY(1985).

    (10)Undersomeinterpretations,ofabroadlyNietzscheantype,moralityisalsodeeplyinvolvedintheapplicationofpower.Ihavesomesympathywiththoseinterpretations,andinsomeconnections,suchastraditionalsexualmorality,theclaimismanifestlytrue.Liberation,totheextentthatitmaybepossible,requiresanunderstandingofthosetruths,andhencetosomeextentatheoryofmoralityitself.Butitdoesnotrequireturningmoralityintoatheory,anditislikelytobeobstructedbytheprojectofdoingso;thatprojectitselftypicallyhelpstoconcealthosetruths.

    (11)Ihavediscussedthesematters,withsomereferencebothtomodernlawandtoancientGreeklaw,inBERNARDWILLIAMS,SHAMEANDNECESSITY(1993),ch.3.

    (12)TonyHonors,MoralityofTortLawQuestionsandAnswers,andDavidOwen,PhilosophicalFoundationsofFaultinTortLaw,bothinthisvolume.

    (13)BernardWilliams,HowFreeDoestheWillNeedtoBe?,LindleyLectureattheUniversityofKansas(1985),andBernardWilliams,VoluntaryActsandResponsibleAgents,10OXFORDJ.LEGALSTUD.1(1990),bothreprintedinBERNARDWILLIAMS,MAKINGSENSEOFHUMANITY(1995).

    Accessbroughttoyouby: PontificiaUniversidadCatolicadelPeru(PUCP)

  • Afterword What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?

    Page 11 of 11

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015