Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

download Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

of 34

Transcript of Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    1/34

    EXAMINING THE DETERMINANTS OF UPPER HOUSE ASSERTION

    David FiskDepartment of Political Science

    University of California-San DiegoSocial Sciences Building 3019500 Gilman Drive, #0521La Jolla, CA 92093-0521

    [email protected]

    Draft of:14 April 2006

    Prepared for presentation at the annual conference of the Midwest Political ScienceAssociation held on 20-23 April 2006. The author would like to thank the National

    Science Foundation for providing funding assistance for this project (Doctoral

    Dissertation Research Improvement project number 0418503), in addition to thankWilliam Chandler, Matthew S. Shugart, Emily Beaulieu and Nathan Batto for helpful

    comments on this draft.

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    2/34

    Abstract

    The literature on legislatures has tended to disregard the role of the upper

    chamber in the policy process. Recent research has suggested that even under

    circumstances where the legislative prerogatives of the upper chamber are relatively

    weak compared to that of the government, that policy outcomes are different under

    bicameralism than they would be under unicameralism. Discussion of when upper

    chambers use their authority, however, has been limited to case studies or empirical

    testing relying primarily on one case. This paper seeks to address the circumstances under

    which upper houses use their authority to obtain desired policy outcomes (what I refer to

    as assertion). Using an original dataset including votes on government legislation from

    1993-2003 with over 50,000 observations in four parliamentary systems, the paper

    examines the role of institutional authority (veto strength) and legislative timing, party

    reach, and policy preferences in shaping upper chamber willingness to assert themselves

    in a more comparative manner than previous research. Statistical testing provides support

    for examining party composition within both the upper and lower chambers, as well as

    the policy preferences of the upper chamber in explaining upper house assertion.

    Introduction

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    3/34

    All upper chambers possess constitutional standing, suggesting that they should

    have influence within the legislative process. Legislative studies, however, have tended to

    disregard the role of the upper house in the legislative process contending that upper

    chambers are too weak or inconsequential to exert any influence on legislative outcomes.

    This decision is usually based on arguments centered on the congruence between many

    upper and lower houses in terms of their composition, and the asymmetrical institutional

    relationship between the chambers in terms of constitutional authority, which tends to

    favor governments in the lower chamber.

    It is unclear, however, that a blanket rejection of the effects of the upper chamber

    on policy outcomes is warranted. In fact, we find significant variation in levels of

    institutional authority within upper chambers. The German Bundesrat is an example of an

    upper chamber that possesses a great deal of authority (an absolute veto over

    approximately two-thirds of legislation) with which to obstruct passage of the

    governments agenda, and in recent years, the Bundesrat has used this authority to amend

    or block government legislation. But even in cases where the upper chamber is classified

    as weak, as in the case of the British House of Lords, members of the upper house have

    used their institutional prerogatives to frustrate attempts made by governments of both

    parties to pass legislation crucial to their agenda1.

    This discussion has become more relevant as it has been suggested that some

    upper chambers are using their authority with greater frequency than they have in the

    past, requiring governments to spend more time dealing with upper house delays and

    amendments (see Shell 1992, Shell and Beamish 1993, Shell 1999, Franks 1999, Patzelt

    1999, Uhr 1999). This expansion of upper house influence into policy areas formerly

    1 Examples of this include the War Crimes Bill under the government of John Major, and Section 28 reformunder the Blair government.

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    4/34

    dominated by governments in the lower house has sparked debate in several established

    democracies (such as Canada, the United Kingdom, France, Germany, Australia) as to the

    appropriate role of the upper house in regards to the ability of the government to pass its

    agenda given the fact that many upper chambers are not directly elected but use a variety

    of alternative selection mechanisms (indirect election, electoral colleges, appointment,

    heredity, etc.). Emerging democracies have also debated whether or not to create or

    reform their upper house (e.g. Hungary, Poland, and the Czech Republic).

    Bicameral institutional structures have also been a subject for debate for those

    who discuss the role of institutions in promoting political stability in deeply divided

    societies (Lijphart 1968 and 2000, Roeder forthcoming). As a result, recognition that the

    upper house can affect policy outcomes makes examination of how upper houses

    function, as well as how they affect these outcomes, a crucial focus of political

    institutional research. While the determinants of upper house activity should be

    consequential in explaining policy outcomes, with the exception of Lijphart (1999)and

    Tsebelis and Money (1997) little work has been done to determine under what

    circumstances upper chambers will use their legislative authority to affect policy

    outcomes.

    This paper examines the circumstances under which upper chambers use their

    legislative authority to obtain their desired policy outcomes, what I refer to as upper

    house assertion. I argue that when faced with a policy proposal offered by the

    government, the upper chamber decides whether or not to assert itself in the policy

    process, and that this decision is a function of three factors: veto strength, party reach and

    the policy preferences of the upper chamber. First, I argue that veto strength (actual veto

    versus suspensory veto) coupled with timing of the legislative session alter the costs

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    5/34

    associated with overriding the upper chamber (in terms of agenda time, supermajority

    requirements to override etc.), all of which can increase upper house legislative

    bargaining leverage vis--vis the government.

    Second, party reach into the upper chamber (ability of political parties to

    discipline their members in the upper chamber) is theorized to play a strong role in

    determining the ability of the upper house to assert themselves. Under circumstances

    where members of the upper chamber are dependent upon national parties or

    governments for re-selection, they will be more likely to be acquiescent than in those

    chambers where upper houses members are further removed from the governments

    whips or are appealing to different selectorates. Where the government possesses fewer

    carrots and sticks with which to encourage agreement with their policies, or where

    upper chambers are dependent upon actors other than the national party (e.g. appealing to

    constituencies at the state rather than federal level), upper chambers will be more

    assertive.

    Third, upper chambers generally possess greater flexibility than their lower house

    counterparts to pursue policy related goals. Where party reach in the upper chamber is

    weaker, the median voter in the upper house is in a better position to enact his or her ideal

    policy point than the median voter in the lower chamber, because she/he is less likely to

    face credible threats from their political party for not voting the party line. As a result, the

    policy preferences of the median voter in the upper chamber should play a larger role in

    determining upper house assertion.

    In the next section, I will examine the literature on upper chambers. In the third

    and fourth sections, I explain my theory and discuss my research design and the

    construction of my dataset. I present my findings in the fifth section, and conclude with a

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    6/34

    discussion of the limitations of this framework, as well as outline an agenda for future

    research.

    Literature Review

    Many legislative studies ignore the role of the upper chamber in explaining

    policy outcomes on the assumption that they have a negligible affect on policy outcomes

    due to a lack of institutional strength (e.g. Buchanan and Tullock 1962, Sartori 1996) or

    not meeting the criteria of a legislature due to its composition or its selection mechanism

    (Mezey 1979). Recent works have attempted to classify upper chambers on the basis of

    their expected influence, suggesting that certain types of houses will be more likely to

    exert an independent influence on policy outcomes than others.

    While recent research has taken various approaches to explain the effects of

    bicameralism, comparative empirical work has been relatively rare. Patterson and

    Mughan (1999) provide a series of case studies highlighting several upper chambers,

    suggesting that examining how upper houses function internally, is a crucial area for

    future research. They also argue that the role of the upper house as a policy improving

    body is taken quite seriously in many upper chambers, and that governments in the lower

    chamber that attempt to ignore their input, do so at their own risk. Questions regarding

    the legitimacy of upper houses as well as a discussion of how upper houses,

    comparatively speaking, arrive at decisions are also suggested as areas for further

    research.

    Lijphart (1999) divides bicameral legislatures into three categories (strong

    bicameralism, medium bicameralism, and weak bicameralism) on the basis of two

    variables: symmetry and congruence. Lijphart classifies upper houses as symmetrical if

    they possess institutional authority commensurate to that of the lower house. Houses are

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    7/34

    considered to be congruent if the method of selection suggests that the two houses will be

    composed similarly. It is suggested that congruence and asymmetry greatly diminish the

    independent effects of action taken by the upper chamber. Strong bicameralism exists

    when an upper house is both symmetric and non-congruent (e.g. the United States Senate,

    Australian Senate, Swiss Federation Council and the German Bundesrat), medium

    bicameralism exists when one of the two characteristics is missing (e.g. the British House

    of Lords, Canadian Senate, French Senate, the Belgian Senate, and the Italian Senate),

    and weak bicameralism exists when an upper house is both asymmetric and congruent

    (e.g. Irish Seanad and the Austrian Bundesrat).

    Money and Tsebelis (1992) take an innovative approach, suggesting that

    senatorial power or influence can be operationalized as a function of navette rules

    (number of times a bill can shuttle between two houses of parliament) and other

    institutional factors (such as stopping rules, intercameral dispute resolution mechanisms,

    and confidence procedures). Tsebelis and Money (1997) expands on this definition,

    suggesting that the ability to deal with financial legislation, presence of conference

    committees, uncertainty over the lower chambers ideal point, and the upper houses

    relative level of patience (desire to pass legislation), all influence of ability of the upper

    chamber to affect policy outcomes.

    Tsebelis and Money (1997) model the process of inter-cameral bargaining using a

    Rubinstein bargaining model, characterized by two players who make a series of

    proposals and counterproposals such that when the first player proposes, the second can

    either accept the offer, or reject it and make a counteroffer (Rubinstein 1982). Payoffs in

    this game are a function not only of expected utility of the offer, but also of the level of

    impatience/discount factor that each player possesses (the weight each player places on

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    8/34

    gains received in the future). As each round passes, each player in this model gets a

    reduced amount of utility for the outcome based on their degree of discounting, leading

    players to prefer an agreement sooner rather than later. Players that are more patient are

    able to extract more from their opponent, and the order in which players make offers

    (who makes the first offer and who concludes the bargaining) affects the equilibrium

    outcome. In the Tsebelis and Money model, the legislative bargaining process is driven

    by the upper chambers uncertainty of the resolve of the lower house (concept of

    uncertainty) as well as both chambers desire to reach a policy resolution sooner rather

    than later (concept of impatience). They operationalize this impatience as a function of

    strength and cohesion of the lower house governing coalition, and argue that the

    bargaining game is structured in such a way that when the navette runs out, the lower

    house can unilaterally select its ideal point.

    Under these assumptions, Tsebelis and Money argue that the upper house extracts

    policy concessions when the coalition is small or non cohesive, and acquiesces when the

    government coalition is large or is very cohesive. They suggest that assertion will be

    greatest, under situations where the upper house is unsure of the resolve of the

    government, which they contend occurs when the governing coalition is of intermediate

    strength and cohesion. They also control for cameral learning and cycling. The learning

    hypothesis suggests that the upper house will be more acquiescent near the end of the

    term as they become more knowledgeable of the ideal point of the lower chamber.

    Electoral cycling refers to the idea that cameral negotiation breakdown will be

    increasingly more likely near the middle of a parliamentary term as the lower house is

    more patient directly following an election, and the upper chamber becomes stronger as a

    new election draws nearer, as the governments relative patience evaporates. They

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    9/34

    conclude that regardless of the strength or weakness of the upper house, the presence of

    an upper house makes it more difficult to change policy, and generates a different policy

    outcome than expected under unicameralism.

    Tsebelis and Money (1997) provide a useful framework in terms of analyzing the

    relationship between upper and lower houses, but do not examine how or under what

    circumstances upper house dynamics should affect this process. In addition, their

    theoretical testing relies primarily on one case (France), which restrains comparability.

    Analyzing the French case may be problematic on two bases. First, during the French

    Fifth Republic, the French Senate has been relatively static in its composition, as the right

    has dominated the upper chamber since its reformation and the left did not enter

    government in the lower chamber in the French Fifth Republic until the early 1980s,

    relatively late in Tsebelis and Moneys data set which covers the French Fifth Republic

    until 1985. This makes it difficult to examine how changes in the party composition of

    the two chambers affect this process. The model presented here will explicitly examine

    party strength and party reach in the upper chamber, as well as outline policy preferences

    in explaining upper house assertion more explicitly in a wider range of cases.

    Second, the legislative rules in the National Assembly (the lower house) are

    unique in that it is relatively easy for the government and its majority in the National

    Assembly to override the upper house (the Senate) when the government uses the censure

    vote. The censure vote (Article 49) is just one of many unique institutional tools that the

    French executive possesses to allow it to dominate the legislative arena. The censure vote

    allows the government to make any bill a vote of confidence, in which the members of

    parliament do not vote on the bill itself, but on whether to keep the current government in

    office. As long as this motion of no confidence is not filed and passed, the bill is

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    10/34

    considered passed in the form designated by the government without debate. This is a

    parliamentary rule that is relatively rare,2 which alters the bargaining situation by

    skewing the costs of overriding the upper chamber in a manner that is not generalizable

    to other cases. Models analyzing intercameral relations need to examine the tradeoffs

    between the costs and benefits of overriding the upper house in a wider range of cases.

    Theory:

    This paper addresses the costs endured by governments in overriding the upper

    house, examining legislative timing and veto strength, party reach, and the policy

    preferences of the upper chamber, all of which are theorized to alter levels of upper house

    assertion. I take each of these variables in turn, outlining previous theories and

    hypotheses derived from these theories as well as my own hypotheses regarding

    assertion. By extending the analysis to include internal characteristics of the upper

    chamber theorized to affect upper house assertiveness, as well as testing prevailing theory

    against a wider range of cases, this paper intends to provide a more comprehensive

    explanation of the conditions under which upper houses assert themselves in the

    legislative process.

    Veto strength and Legislative timing

    While Tsebelis and Moneys (1997) contention that both the lower and upper

    chambers take advantage of their bargaining position to obtain their preferred policy

    outcomes is fairly straightforward, it is unclear that the logic underlying the learning

    hypothesis as formulated should frame upper house behavior. 3 It may be the case that

    upper houses do learn about the resolve or the impatience of the upper house as the

    parliamentary session draws to a close, but this may not reduce upper house

    2 See Shugart and Carey (1992) on decree powers.3 Tsebelis and Money contend that further research should be done to confirm or reject this hypothesis.

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    11/34

    intransigence, but increase it, as their institutional prerogatives become more absolute

    (e.g. costs of overriding them becomes prohibitive). This is increasingly more likely as

    the parliamentary session draws to a close and governments have a scarce supply of

    agenda time with which to respond (see Doering 1995 on agenda scarcity). Under these

    circumstances, governments rather than being able to unilaterally select their preferred

    policy outcome at the end of a constitutionally specified time, may choose to drop a bill

    rather than incur further override costs (be they expenditures of agenda time on additional

    votes or conference committees and/or political risks associated with a failed attempt to

    override the upper chamber) associated with the decision to attempt to override the upper

    house. The strength of the veto coupled with legislative timing can affect the calculus of

    the government as to whether or not to attempt to override the upper chamber, by

    affecting agenda scarcity as well as what decision rules are to be followed.

    Explaining cameral relations as a game where after a specified number of rounds,

    the stronger house (predominantly the government in the lower house) gets to unilaterally

    select its ideal point is problematic, as overriding the upper chamber always involves

    costs. While overriding the upper chamber is always costly, not all upper chambers,

    possess the same ability to affect these costs. While policy matters for upper houses, it is

    not the case that all upper houses possess the same institutional authority to assert their

    policy preferences. The veto authority held by the upper chamber frames these override

    costs, as it is the veto authority of the upper chamber that determines the decision rules

    under which the government must proceed if they wish to override the will of the upper

    house. Some upper chambers possess suspensory rather than absolute vetoes, which

    allow them to delay policy, not block it indefinitely.

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    12/34

    I suggest that upper chambers that possess suspensory veto authority function

    somewhat along the lines of a fire alarm (McCubbins and Schwartz, 1984), by acting

    like a policy watchdog, possessing the ability to review legislation, raise alternative

    policies, and in some cases embarrass the government by alerting the populace that the

    ideal point of the government is different from that of the electorate. Chambers that

    possess an absolute veto, act more akin to an institutional veto player (Tsebelis 1995),

    and passage of a given policy under this institutional framework requires the consent of

    the both houses. In both instances, overriding the upper chamber involves creating

    agenda costs or the need to create supermajorities for governments.

    While previous studies of legislatures have suggested that upper houses should be

    examined only when they possess absolute vetoes, Cox (2000) suggests that suspensory

    vetoes are important, especially when agenda time is scarce (e.g. end of a parliamentary

    session). Under these circumstances, I argue that suspensory vetoes can be considered as

    being transformed to absolute vetoes as the ability to override the upper chamber in this

    situation has dissipated due to time constraints. In addition, by pointing out weaknesses

    in bills passed by the lower house, upper houses can inflict political costs on the

    governing coalition in the lower house. As a result, these types of chambers should not be

    overlooked, as upper houses that possess primarily policy watchdog authority may use

    their institutional prerogatives strategically near the end of the term, to get their desired

    outcome.

    The empirical record suggests that there are instances whereby the lower house

    drops bills (in cases where the upper house acts as a fire alarm and as a veto player)

    rather than face a protracted fight to overturn the decision of the upper house. I argue that

    this occurs when the cost of override (e.g. agenda time, need for a supermajority)

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    13/34

    outweighs the benefits associated with it (enactment of proposal), and that legislative

    timing and veto strength can affect these costs. A model of the interaction between

    houses should include an interactive variable accounting for upper house institutional

    strength as well as the year in the parliamentary session, which structures the bargaining

    by transforming suspensory vetoes into something more akin to an absolute veto, creating

    additional costs for the government in terms of both agenda time/systemic impatience and

    reputation that the upper house can take advantage of to increase their policy bargaining

    leverage. This leads to the first hypothesis:

    Hypothesis One (Veto Transformation): Upper houses will be more assertive as their

    veto approximates an absolute veto. This will occur throughout the entire term when the

    house is a veto player, and only during the end of the parliamentary session

    corresponding to the length of the suspensory veto in policy watchdog chambers.

    Party Reach

    The model presented here suggests that the composition of the upper house should

    also be included to explain upper house assertion in the legislative process. We may

    anticipate that the government would take upper house composition into consideration

    when determining the probability of passage of its legislative agenda, suggesting that

    when the government controls a larger number of seats in the upper chamber, this would

    reduce the likelihood of upper house intransigence. Passage of the governments agenda

    would arguably be less likely in cases where the opposition controls a majority in the

    upper chamber. In these situations, the upper house may view itself as a second

    opposition. This leads to the second hypothesis:

    Hypothesis Two (Upper House Composition): High levels of opposition parties in the

    upper house will increase levels of upper house assertion.

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    14/34

    It is unclear, however, that the same level of party discipline that we see amongst

    backbenchers in the lower chamber can be assumed to carry over into the upper chamber.

    While parties certainly frame the debate in most upper houses, many upper house

    members are selected by alternate methods or constituencies (indirect or direct election at

    different constituency levels) or for longer periods of time than members of the lower

    house. This theoretically weakens the delegation chain between the party and government

    in the lower house and party members of the upper house.4 Weaker party discipline

    associated with many upper houses provides more of an opportunity for members of

    upper houses to pursue policy rather than party related goals. In terms of principal-agent

    theory, members of lower chambers generally face greater consequences for deviating

    from the party line (including de-selection, reduced probability of being promoted to

    ministerial positions, and loss of government office), than members of the upper house.

    As a result, where party reach is weaker, agency slippage in the lower house should be

    less than that observed in the upper house. Due to lower levels of screening (e.g. via re-

    selection mechanisms) as well as fewer opportunities to constrain agency slack (e.g.

    reduced opportunities for de-selection, removal of party label at election time, etc), party

    reach in the upper chamber can be weaker than that in the lower chamber. As a result,

    in many instances, upper house members can afford to be more flexible in terms of

    seeking policy goals than their lower house counterparts.

    Lijphart (1999) suggests that difference in selection mechanisms can have a

    critical affect on the type of bicameralism observed, affecting whether or not the upper

    chamber can be viewed as more of a rubber stamp for government policy rather then a

    legislative hurdle for governments. Levels of party reach can be observed by examining

    re-selection mechanisms. In instances where upper house members are appointed for a

    4 See Strom (1997) on parliamentary delegation.

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    15/34

    short term by their political party, or are elected on the basis of a closed list system, we

    should expect to see political parties playing a stronger role in influencing votes within

    the upper chamber, as upper house members see their future membership as dependent

    upon convincing the political party to re-select them. In instances where members are

    directly elected on the basis of open lists, indirectly elected, or serve for life, we should

    expect to see political parties playing less of a role in influencing upper house assertion,

    as the party nomination is less critical for their continued membership in the upper

    chamber.

    Electoral cycles and office seeking incentives may also spark intransigence within

    the same party when different constituencies or audiences elect members of each house.

    In many cases, the constituencies for upper chambers are based on a state/territorial

    distinction, while members of lower chambers are elected on a different basis. In these

    situations, members of the upper chambers may view their policymaking role as one of a

    legislative agent to a different principal than those elected in the lower chamber, as their

    mandate is to serve an alternative constituency (e.g. state party organizations, state voters,

    electoral colleges, etc.) than members in the lower chamber (national political party).

    This interplay between alternative selection mechanisms as well as alternative audiences

    to which upper house members respond, can undercut a political partys ability to

    credibly threaten upper chamber members that do not toe the party line. This leads to the

    third hypothesis:

    Hypothesis Three (Re-Selection Hypothesis): Upper houses that are dependent upon

    parties in the lower house (e.g. national leadership) for re-selection will be more

    acquiescent than those elected by other means.

    Policy Preferences

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    16/34

    Tsebelis and Money use the French Senate as their main case, but the composition

    of the French Senate has remained relatively stable due to the over-representation of rural

    and agricultural interests in the electoral college which selects members of the Senate that

    support parties of the right (the UDF and the RPR). As a result, the dataset used in their

    model does not test for the composition of the upper chamber to vary significantly, nor

    does their statistical analysis investigate the role of government allies in the upper

    chamber in creating uncertainty in the intercameral bargaining game, or in reducing the

    effects of assertion.5

    I contend that upper houses are concerned about policy outcomes, and that as a

    result, and that regardless of institutional authority, we may not expect to see the upper

    house acquiescing to the demands of the government solely on the basis of the governing

    coalitions strength. The idea that political actors care about policy is not a new

    suggestion. Research in coalition theory as well as in the party system literature, suggests

    that parties are concerned with both policy and office goals, and that whether policy is

    considered as an end, or as a means for procuring office, policy is still an important factor

    to consider (Laver and Schofield 1998, Strom and Mueller 1999, Druckman and Thies

    2001).

    After suggesting that upper houses are concerned with policy and that their

    members often posses greater flexibility to pursue policy goals, I maintain that upper

    houses use their institutional powers strategically to achieve policy outcomes that are

    closer to the ideal point of the chambers median voter. Under this framework, upper

    houses have incentives to be viewed as an effective legislative body rather than merely a

    rubber stamp. This can arise as a result of the need to appeal to different audiences for re-

    5 Although Tsebelis and Moneys (1997) main statistical model does not explicitly address the compositionof the upper house in explaining legislative policy outcomes, their case studies do deal with this issue.

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    17/34

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    18/34

    Case Selection

    Case selection will be confined to developed bicameral parliamentary

    democracies, thus removing presidential systems from the field of cases included in my

    data set. While I concede that the interaction between presidentialism and bicameralism

    in an interesting question, I am confining this project to parliamentary systems as a useful

    starting point for examining the role of the upper chamber in the legislative process.

    Future studies should examine the effects of a presidential veto player on upper house

    assertion, but this lies outside of the scope of this paper. Because I am investigating the

    role of political parties in explaining upper house assertion, I am confining myself to

    cases where parties and institutions are developed and entrenched. Whether or not the

    same patterns exist within developing democracies as exist in developed democracies as

    regards upper chambers is an interesting question for future research, but will not be

    examined here.

    In terms of the cases that will be included in the data set, I will use four cases

    (Belgium, Germany, Ireland, and the United Kingdom), which provide variation along

    the independent variables in which I am interested (see table 1).

    Table 1: Case Selection

    Hypotheses: Belgium Germany Ireland UnitedKingdom

    VetoTransformation

    Watchdog andVeto Player

    Veto Player Watchdog Watchdog

    Upper HouseComposition

    Has varied by party controlandcomposition.

    Has varied byparty control.

    Has varied byparty strength.

    Has varied by party controlandcomposition.

    Re-Selection Direct Election IndirectElection

    Election byVocationalBoards andPrime Minister

    Appointed bythe PrimeMinister

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    19/34

    PreferenceDifferential

    Congruent Not Congruent Congruent Not Congruent

    In terms of the veto transformation hypothesis, I have two veto players (Germany

    and Belgium on issues of ethnicity and statehood) and two-plus watch dog chambers

    (Ireland, the United Kingdom and the remainder of bills in the Belgian case). As regards

    re-selection mechanisms, each case uses a different method of re-selection from direct

    election in Belgium, indirect election in Germany, lifetime appointment/no re-selection in

    the United Kingdom, and party membership/vocational boards/prime minister in Ireland.

    As regards policy preferences, Lijphart classifies two of the cases as congruent (Ireland

    and Belgium) and two as non-congruent (the United Kingdom and Germany), and all

    have had varying compositions in their upper chambers.

    Dependent Variable:

    Upper house assertion is the dependent variable in this study.I am using votes on

    government legislation as my unit of analysis, operationalizing the dependent variable by

    examining whether or not a governing party gets rolled on any vote held on

    government legislation in the upper chamber. Cox et al. (2000) define a party as being

    rolled when a majority of a given party is unsuccessful in their opposition to a bill. A

    governing party getting rolled on a government bill in the upper chamber suggests that

    the upper house is asserting its institutional prerogatives (be it a suspensory or an

    absolute veto) and that support for the bill as proposed in the upper chamber is weak. For

    the purposes of this paper, high roll rates for government parties on government bills in

    the upper chamber suggests a greater amount of negotiation breakdown, and in turn a

    greater amount of time (higher cost of override) that will need to be expended on the part

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    20/34

    of the government in the lower chamber to overturn the will of the upper house. As a

    result, the government will have to expend agenda time and create coalitions in the lower

    chamber to overturn these wrecking amendments. Where the upper house refines or

    improves legislation, we should not expect to see the governing parties being rolled in

    the upper chamber, as governments may see the upper chambers policy refining function

    as useful, and they will therefore not be rolled on these amendments.

    I have coded votes on government legislation from 1993-20036, with a total of

    50,103 observations. I have coded each bill with a 1 if a government party gets rolled, or

    a 0 if a governing party does not get rolled. In cases where the roll call data is not

    available, I will adopt the approach used by Cox et al. (2000), and code a party as getting

    rolled if its leader on the given issue area (be it party leader or relevant minister) in the

    upper chamber speaks against a bill that is eventually passed. In the German Bundesrat,

    votes are cast en bloc by land government delegations. This will provide for a special

    kind of roll call vote, but one that is fundamentally similar to roll call votes in other

    cases.

    This approach improves on the Tsebelis and Money (1997) approach by

    examining the role of the upper chamber in greater detail. For their study, Tsebelis and

    Money use percentage of bills that are adopted before a conference committee is called as

    their operationalization. Under this operationalization, it is unclear whether or not the

    upper house or the government is holding up the policy process. The benefit of the

    operationalization used here is that it more effectively shows when the upper chamber is

    6 This dataset includes all votes on government measures from 1993-2003 for Ireland, Belgium and theUnited Kingdom. Data from Germany from the fall of 1999 to the end of 2003 has also been included. Theremainder of the data from the German case will be included in the final dataset, but it was not available forthis paper.

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    21/34

    asserting their prerogatives by removing the ambiguity over which chamber is

    responsible for stalling the policy process.

    Hypotheses:

    Veto Strength:

    Hypothesis One (Veto Transformation):Upper houses will be more assertive as their

    veto approximates an absolute veto. This will occur throughout the entire term when the

    house is an institutional veto player, and only during the end of the parliamentary

    session corresponding to the length of the suspensory veto in policy watchdog chambers.

    This hypothesis suggests that when the upper houses refusal authority is more

    solid, they will be more intransigent. Under these circumstances, the upper house may

    have learned of the resolve of the lower house, but electoral cycles, legislative timing,

    and the institutional strength of the upper chamber add to its bargaining power, by raising

    the costs of the government overriding the upper house in terms of agenda time and the

    political risks associated with failing to override the upper house. This variable allows for

    the coding of upper house prerogatives in a more flexible fashion than that provided by

    Lijphart and Tsebelis and Money, by introducing both legislative timing and veto

    strength into the equation.

    This hypothesis will be tested using a variable based on legislative session and

    veto strength to be coded as follows: I will code veto player chambers (identified as

    chambers which possess an absolute veto over a majority of policy proposals) with a 1,

    and policy watchdog chambers (identified as chambers which possess a suspensory veto

    over a majority of policy proposals) with a 0 until the duration of parliament when their

    suspensory vetoes become absolute. For instance, the British House of Lords can delay

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    22/34

    bills for one year. Bills vetoed in this regard by the House of Lords in the last year of a

    parliamentary session must be re-submitted in the next year. This requirement of

    resubmission re-sets the clock in terms of the governments ability to use its legislative

    authority (in this case, the Parliament Acts) to override the will of the upper chamber and

    get their desired outcome.

    Units of analysis corresponding to the legislative years where a veto is suspensory

    will be coded with a 0, with years corresponding to an absolute veto coded with a 1. 7 I

    will also include an interactive variable, multiplying veto with the year in the

    parliamentary term. Because some parliamentary systems have fixed terms while many

    others do not, I will code fire alarms for the time frame prior to the election where their

    veto becomes absolute,8 suggesting that rumors of electoral date decision making coupled

    with systemic norms of government length, will make the upper house somewhat likely

    to be able to foresee when the next election will be called.

    I will also include variables for the strength of the governing coalition in the

    lower chamber, and a variable squaring this value, to control for Tsebelis and Moneys

    theory of cameral uncertainty and impatience. In addition, I will also control for the

    learning and cycling hypotheses, including a variable corresponding to year in the

    legislative term and a term squaring that value.

    Party Reach

    7 The German Bundesrat possesses an absolute veto over two-thirds of all legislation. The Belgian Senatepossessed an absolute veto iin all policy areas between 1993-1995, and maintains an absolute veto in somepolicy areas in the years following 1995. For the veto transformation hypothesis, units of analysis fallingunder these areas are coded with a 1, all others coded with a 0. The Irish Seanad can delay legislation forsix months, and the British House of Lords can delay it for a year. As a result, votes conducted within thelast six months of the parliamentary session in the Seanad, or within the last year of the parliamentarysession within the House of Lords, will be coded with a 1.8 Votes falling within six months of the election date in Ireland, and those within one year of an election inthe House of Lords, will be coded with a 1.

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    23/34

    Hypothesis Two (Upper House Composition): High levels of opposition parties in the

    upper house will increase levels of upper house assertion.

    This value will be constructed by calculating the percentage of seats held by the

    opposition in the upper house, and a second variable will be created squaring this value.

    When this value is high (suggestive of alternate party control of the upper house), I

    expect disagreement to be high (high roll rates). When this value is low, I expect an

    earlier conclusion to bargaining between the chambers. In their model, Tsebelis and

    Money (1997) do not include a variable for investigating uncertainty regarding the upper

    chamber. In this model, I will control for uncertainty in the upper chamber by including a

    variable squaring the percentage of members of the opposition in the upper chamber.

    Hypothesis Three (Re-Selection Hypothesis):Upper houses that are dependent upon

    parties in the lower house (e.g. government/national leadership) for re-selection will be

    more acquiescent than those elected by other means.

    This hypothesis suggests that when members of the upper house are dependent

    upon the government in the lower house for re-selection (e.g. party list position, re-

    appointment etc.), they will be more acquiescent, as they may view their continued

    membership in the chamber as beholden to the party. Upper house members that owe

    their election due to other means (e.g. lifetime appointment, or indirect

    election/appointment at a different level) can afford to deviate from the party line more

    often. I hypothesize that members that are elected on the basis of closed party lists or

    direct election by party members will be most likely to be acquiescent (e.g. Ireland)

    followed by: those elected by open lists that are created by national parties (e.g.

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    24/34

    Belgium),9 those elected at the sub-national level without national party involvement (e.g.

    Germany), with those members that are appointed for life as being least likely to fear

    sanctions from their party (e.g. Great Britain). In cases where a number of different

    methods are used, I will code those cases with the selection mechanism used to elect the

    majority of the members of the upper chamber. I will code members in the first category

    with a 0, with each group being coded by increasing units, with lifetime appointments

    being coded with a 3.

    Policy Preferences:

    Hypothesis Four (Preference Divergence): Greater levels of preference divergence

    between the two chambers will result in greater amounts of upper house assertion.

    I expect policy proposals that shift the status quo away from the ideal point of the

    upper house to be more likely when the ideological bent of the government is further

    away from the ideal point of the upper chamber, than when this ideological space

    differential is more compact. As a result, I expect roll rates to be higher on government

    bills when this ideological distance is larger. To test for this, I will use the Comparative

    Manifesto Project data on party placement to determine the policy position of the median

    legislator within the lower chamber (to which arguably the governing coalition responds),

    and the location of the median legislator in the upper chamber on the left-right

    dimension.10 Taking the absolute value of the difference between these values should

    9 Despite being classified as an open list system, the quota that is required for a candidate to shift their partyranking in the Belgian system is quite high. I have decided to code Belgium differently than Ireland,

    because it is theoretically possible for voters to be able to change party ranking on the list, even though it isrelatively unlikely to occur.10 Comparative Manifesto Data was not available for the final elections conducted in the four countriesincluded in this dataset. In cases where the median voter in both chambers belonged to the same political

    party, this did not pose a problem. In instances where this was not the case, I have calculated the left-rightdistance between the median voters using the last election cycle included within the ComparativeManifesto Project dataset. In the case of the British House of Lords, a substantial number of peers(members of the House of Lords), hold no party affiliation, and organize themselves as the Crossbench. Forthe purposes of this study, I have calculated their ideological placement as being halfway between the

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    25/34

    provide some leverage on the ideological distance between the two chambers. While this

    operationalization is certainly not perfect (chambers may make offers that concede some

    points to members of the other chamber in return for acquiescence on other portions), it

    will provide some leverage on policy preference divergence and upper house activity.

    Data Analysis:

    I have used probit to estimate the model, using robust standard errors. The results

    of the probit estimate for the model can be found in table 2.

    Table 2 Probit Estimate of Model of Upper House Assertion

    Number of Observations: 50,130

    Log Likelihood: -2751.62

    Variable Coefficient (RobustStandard Errors)11

    Lower House Strength 94(30.3)***

    Lower House StrengthSquared

    -83.38(26.7)***

    Term -.04(.05)

    Term Squared -.01(.02)

    Veto .14(.08)*

    Preference Difference -.002(.007)

    Selection .05(.07)

    Upper House Opposition 14.38(1.94)***

    Upper House OppositionSquared

    -9.53(1.38)***

    Interactive Variable-Veto -.03(.04)

    Constant -33.66(8.53)

    The model as specified finds strong support for the hypothesis that as the

    oppositions percentage of seats in the upper chamber grows, the upper chamber will be

    more likely to be assertive, and are also consistent with Tsebelis and Moneys quadratic

    Conservative party and the Labour party.11 * denotes significant at p.1, ** denotes significant at p .05 and *** denotes significant at p.01

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    26/34

    specification of lower house cameral impatience, however the learning and cycling

    hypotheses included in their analysis are not confirmed. The coefficient added to the

    model to test uncertainty over the upper houses level of patience (not included in

    Tsebelis and Moneys account), is also significant. The veto hypothesis estimated using a

    dummy variable for veto reaches significance in a one tailed test, but the model does not

    support the veto transformation model. The sign on the coefficients for the re-selection

    hypothesis is in the right direction, but does not reach significance at conventional levels.

    The sign on the coefficient for the policy preferences hypotheses is neither

    significant, nor is it in the direction predicted by the hypothesis. Reviewing the dataset

    there are a large number of observations during the government of John Major in the

    United Kingdom, with a policy preference differential that is unusually large, which may

    be biasing the estimate.12 I have estimated the model after excluding observations

    associated with this case, the results of which can be found in table 3:

    12 Observations associated with the Major government in the House of Lords are associated with apreference differential of 29.15, a function of the ideological polarization between Labour and theConservatives at this time. It is unclear, however, that this accurately reflects the ideological position of theCrossbench. The next highest differential in the dataset is 14.725 corresponding with the Schroedergovernment (SPD) and the CDU-FDP opposition in the Bundesrat, suggesting that this case is an outlier.

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    27/34

    Table 3 Probit Estimate of Model of Upper House Assertion (without Major government

    observations)

    Number of Observations: 40,100

    Log Likelihood: -2399.57

    The model estimated without the

    observations associated with the Major

    government supports the preference

    differential hypothesis (larger differences

    in policy preferences are associated with

    higher levels of upper house assertion), as

    well as confirms the upper house

    composition hypothesis (higher percentages of opposition seats are associated with higher

    levels of assertion). The selection and veto transformation hypotheses are not confirmed,

    although the sign for the selection hypothesis is in the expected direction. Hypotheses

    relating to cameral patience and uncertainty are consistent with the model as estimated.

    Conclusion

    Variable Coefficient (RobustStandard Errors)

    Lower House Strength 145.92(25.82)***

    Lower House StrengthSquared

    -129.31(22.97)***

    Term -.03(-.54)

    Term Squared .01(.02)

    Veto -.03(.1)

    Preference Difference .05(.02)***

    Selection .13(.08)

    Upper House Opposition 6.52(2.9)**

    Upper House Opposition

    Squared

    -4.75(1.88)**

    Interactive Variable-Veto -.08(.47)

    Constant -45.66(7.54)**

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    28/34

    By unpacking the upper chamber, the model here uses an original dataset to

    examine when upper houses use their legislative authority, investigating the effects of

    veto authority, party reach, and policy preferences in explaining upper house assertion,

    providing empirical testing against a wider range of cases than in previous studies. The

    results support the contention that both party and policy preferences matter in

    explaining responses to policy in the upper chamber, suggesting that an examination of

    assertion focusing solely on one or the other overlooks important internal aspects of

    decision-making in the upper chamber. Given the smaller size (in general) of upper

    chambers, as well as the presence of policy areas that are considered to lie within the

    upper chambers area of expertise, it seems possible that while party effects are important

    to examine within the upper chamber, different electoral audiences or privileged issue

    areas (areas of expertise) may shape preferences in the upper chamber differently than

    they would in the lower chamber. Future research should be conducted to determine

    whether or not expected relationships between party and preference models of voting

    behavior that are observed in the lower house can be carried over to the upper house..

    While this paper is an attempt to expand the discussion on the role of the upper

    house in the policymaking process, the role of upper house authority requires further

    research. This paper is confined to an explanation of assertion, which is not necessarily

    the same thing as legislative power. One can think of instances where an upper chamber

    could theoretically be very assertive, but they may not necessarily be powerful in terms

    of shifting final policy outcomes towards their ideal point. Additionally, it may be the

    case that approval of policy outcomes in certain policy areas is traded in order to obtain

    approval in other policy areas.13 While the literature suggests that the presence of an

    13 The debate relating to institutional reforms within the House of Lords fits this pattern. In this instance,the Blair government negotiated with groups within the House of Lords on constitutional reform, with theBlair government accepting a compromise bill on House of Lords reform in exchange for an agreement by

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    29/34

    upper chamber alters policy outcomes, determining how far these chambers can push

    these outcomes towards their ideal point is a subject for further research.

    It has also been suggested that upper chambers are using their authority with

    higher frequency then has historically been the case (Patterson and Mughan, 1999). A

    discussion of whether or not upper houses have become more assertive over time is an

    interesting research question, but one that was not included within the scope of this paper.

    As several countries debate the appropriate role that the upper house should play in the

    legislative process, future research should examine whether or not upper chambers are

    using their authority more frequently, and examine the consequences of increases in

    upper house assertion on the policymaking process.

    Bibliography

    Brennan, Geoffrey and Alan Hamlin. Bicameralism and Majoritarian Equilibria.Public

    Choice. 74: 169-179. (1992).

    Buchanan, James M. and Gordon Tullock. The Calculus of Consent: Logical

    Foundations

    of Constitutional Democracy. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.

    1962.

    Cox, Gary W. On the Effects of Legislative Rules.Legislative Studies Quarterly. 25:2

    (May 2000): 169-192.

    the peers in the upper chamber to refuse to stall debate on other bills deemed critical to the government.

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    30/34

    Cox, Gary W. and Richard McKelvey. A Ham Sandwich Theorem for General

    Measures. Social Choice and Welfare. 1:75-83. (1984).

    Diermeier Daniel, and Roger B. Myerson. Bicameralism and Its Consequences for the

    Internal Organization of Legislatures.American Economic Review. 89: 1182-

    1196. (1999).

    Doring, Herbert.Parliaments and Majority Rule in Western Europe.New York, NY: St.

    Martins Press. 1995.

    Druckman, James N. and Michael F. Thies. The Importance of Concurrence: The

    Impact of Bicameralism on Government Formation and Duration.Presented to

    Midwest Political Science Association 19-22 April 2001.

    Groseclose, Tim and Nolan McCarty. The Politics of Blame: Bargaining Before an

    Audience.American Journal of Political Science. 45.1 (January 2001): 100-119.

    Hammond, Thomas H. and Gary J. Miller. The Core of the Constitution.American

    Political Science Review. 81: 1154-1174. (1987).

    Jeffrey, Charlie. Party Politics and Territorial Representation in the Federal Republic of

    Germany. West European Politics. 22.2 (April 1999): 130-166.

    Laver, Michael and Norman Schofield. Multiparty Government. Ann Arbor, MI: Ann

    Arbor UP. 1998.

    Levmore, Saul. Bicameralism: When Are Two Decisions Better Than One?

    International Review of Law and Economics. 12:145-162. (1992).

    Lijphart, Arend.Patterns of Democracy.New Haven, CT: Yale UP. 1999.

    Longley, Lawrence D. and David M. Olson. Two Into One: The Politics and Processes

    of National Legislative Cameral Change. Boulder, CO: Longview. 1991.

    McCubbins, Mathew, and Thomas Schwartz. Congressional Oversight Overlooked:

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    31/34

    Police Patrols versus Fire Alarms.American Journal of Political Science. 1984.

    Mezey, Michael L. Comparative Legislatures. Durham, NC: Duke UP. 1979.

    Miller, Gary J. and Thomas H. Hammond. Committees and the Core of the

    Constitution.Public Choice. 66: 201-227. (1990).

    Money, Jeanette and George Tsebelis. Ciceros Puzzle: Upper House Power in

    Comparative Perspective.International Political Science Review. 13:25-43.

    (1992).

    Money, Jeanette and George Tsebelis. The Political Power of the French Senate:

    Micromechanisms of Bicameral Negotiations.Journal of Legislative Studies. 1:

    192-217. (1995)

    Patterson, Samuel C. and Anthony Mughan. Senates: Bicameralism in the Contemporary

    World. Columbus, OH: Ohio State UP. 1999.

    Riker, William H. The Justification of Bicameralism.International Political Science

    Review. 13:101-116. (1992a).

    Riker, William H. The Merits of Bicameralism.International Review of Law and

    Economics. 12:166-168. (1992b).

    Roeder, Phillip with Donald Rothschild.. Longer Term Stability of Powersharing and

    Divided-Power Constitutions. Forthcoming.

    Rubinstein, Ariel. Perfect Equilibrium in a Bargaining Model.Econometrica. 50: 97-

    109. (1982).

    Russell, Meg. What Are Second Chambers For?Parliamentary Affairs. 54: 442-458.

    (2001).

    Sartori, Giovanni. Comparative Constitutional Engineering: An Inquiry into Structures,

    Incentives, and Outcomes. Basingstoke, UK: Macmillan Press. 1997.

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    32/34

    Shell, Donald. The House of Lords.New York, NY: Harvester Wheatsheaf. 1992.

    Shell, Donald and David Beamish. The House of Lords at Work. Oxford, UK: Clarendon.

    1993.

    Shugart, Matthew Soberg and John M. Carey.Presidents and Assemblies: Constitutional

    Design and Electoral Dynamics. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge UP. 1992.

    Silvia, Stephen J. Reform Gridlock and the Role of the German Bundesrat in German

    Politics. West European Politics. 22.2 (April 1999): 130-166.

    Strom, Kaare and Wolfgang Mueller.Policy, Office, or Votes: How Political Parties in

    Western Europe Make Hard Decisions. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge UP. 1999.

    Thaysen, Uwe. The Bundesrat, the Lander, and German Federalism. German Issues.

    1994.

    Tsebelis, George. Decision Making in Political Systems: Veto Players in

    Presidentialism, Parliamentarism, Multicameralism, and Multipartyism.British

    Journal of Political Science. 25: 289-326. (1995).

    Tsebelis, George and Jeanette Money.Bicameralism. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge UP.

    1997.

    Tsebelis, George and Jeanette Money. Bicameral Negotiations: The Navette System in

    France.British Journal of Political Science. 25:101-129. (1995)

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    33/34

  • 8/6/2019 Upper House Assertion - Ljiphart

    34/34