Assertion Sep

42
 Search the SEP  Advanced Search  Tools  RSS Feed Table of Contents  What's New  Archives  Projected Contents Editorial Information  About the SEP  Editorial Board  ow to Cite the SEP  S!ecial Characters Support the SEP  P"Fs #or SEP Friends  $a%e a "onation  SEP&A #or ibraries Contact the SEP © Metaphysics Research Lab  , CSLI  ,Stanford Univ ersity (!en access to the SEP is )ade !ossible b* a world+wide #undin, initiative- Please Read ow .ou Can el! /ee! the Enc*clo!edia Free Cite this entry | Friends PDF Preview | InPho Search | PhilPapers Biblioraphy Assertion  First published Mon Jan 22, 2! An assertion is a speech act in which something is claimed to hold, e.g. that there are infinitely "any pri"e nu"bers , or, with respect to some time t , that there is a traffic con#estion on $roo%ly n $rid#e at t , or, of some person & with respect to some time t ,that & has a tooth ache at t . The concept of assertion has often occupied a central place in the philosophy of language, since it is often thought that making assertions is the use of language most crucial to linguistic meaning, and since assertions are the natural expressions of cognitive attitudes, and hence of importance for theories of knowledge and belief. The nature of assertion and its relation to other categories and phenomena have  been subject to much contr oversy. Va rious accounts of assertion are presented

Transcript of Assertion Sep

Page 1: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 1/42

 Search the SEP

• Advanced Search• Tools • RSS Feed

Table of Contents• What's New• Archives• Projected Contents

Editorial Information• About the SEP• Editorial Board• ow to Cite the SEP• S!ecial Characters

Support the SEP• P"Fs #or SEP Friends• $a%e a "onation• SEP&A #or ibraries

Contact the SEP

© Metaphysics Research Lab , CSLI  ,Stanford University

(!en access to the SEP is )ade !ossible b* a world+wide #undin, initiative-

Please Read ow .ou Can el! /ee! the Enc*clo!edia Free

Cite this entry | Friends PDF Preview | InPho Search | PhilPapers Biblioraphy

Assertion

 First published Mon Jan 22, 2! 

An assertion is a speech act in which something is claimed to hold, e.g. that

there are infinitely "any pri"e nu"bers, or, with respect to some time t , that

there is a traffic con#estion on $roo%lyn $rid#e at t , or, of some person & withrespect to some time t ,that & has a tooth ache at t . The concept of assertion hasoften occupied a central place in the philosophy of language, since it is often

thought that making assertions is the use of language most crucial to linguisticmeaning, and since assertions are the natural expressions of cognitive attitudes,and hence of importance for theories of knowledge and belief.

The nature of assertion and its relation to other categories and phenomena have been subject to much controversy. Various accounts of assertion are presented

Page 2: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 2/42

in the sections below. For instance, the %no'led#e account  is presented insection . !There is no section dedicated to assertion accounts generally." Theaccounts presented include #talnaker$s rules of assertion !section %.&,supplement on pragmatics"' principles directly relating truth and assertion

!section (.%"' norms of truth)accounts centering on the aim of truth !section(.*"' the principle of correctness !section (.("' norms of belief or sincerity!section "' norms of knowledge !section .%"' +ricean or eo-+riceanaccounts !section "' #earle$s account !section "' and assertibility ofconditionals !section /".

The article is also organi0ed into a main part for the basic material andsupplementary parts for more speciali0ed or advanced material. The main partconstitutes a self-contained presentation and is sufficient for readers with ageneral interest in assertion. There are links to supplementary material at the

ends of sections and subsections.

• &. #peech acts• %. 1ragmatics

o %.& 1resuppositiono %.% 2mplicatureo %.3 2ndirect speech acts

• 3. 4onvention• *. 4ontent

• (. Trutho (.& The truth predicateo (.% Assertion as truth-claimo (.3 Truth as aim5 fact-statingo (.* Truth as aim5 norms of speakers$ intentionso (.( Truth and correctness

• . 6elief and knowledgeo .& 6elief o .% 7nowledge

. #ocial character • /. 8ogic• 6ibliography• 9ther 2nternet :esources• :elated ;ntries

Page 3: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 3/42

Page 4: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 4/42

are such acts as asserting, asking a uestion, warning, threatening, announcinga verdict or intention, making an appointment, giving an order, expressing awish, making a reuest. An utterance of a sentence, i.e. a locutionary act, bymeans of which a uestion is asked is thus an utterance with interro#ative

 force, and when an assertion is made the utterance has assertoric force. ;achtype of illocutionary act is a type of act with the corresponding illocutionaryforce.

The perlocutionary act is made by means of an illocutionary act, and dependsentirely on the hearer$s reaction. For instance, by means of arguing the speakermay convince the hearer, and by means of warning the speaker may frighten thehearer. 2n these examples, convincing and frightening are perlocutionary acts.

The illocutionary act does not depend on the hearer$s reaction to what has been

said. #till, according to Austin !&B(, &&D&", it does depend on the hearer$s being aware of the utterance and understanding it in a certain way. For instance,2 haven$t warned someone unless he heard and understood what 2 said. 2n thissense the performance of an illocutionary act depends on the <securing ofuptake= !&B(, &&". However, although Austin$s view is intuitively plausiblefor speech acts verbs with speaker-hearer argument structure!like & congratulates y" or speaker-hearer-content argument structure ! & reuestsof y that p", it is not obviously as plausible when the structure is speaker-content ! &declares that p". <Assert= is of the latter kind, as opposed to e.g. <tell=.

2t may be said that 2 failed to tell him that the station was closed, since he hadalready left the room when 2 said so, but that 2 still asserted that  it was closed,since 2 believed he was still there. As we shall see, several theories of assertionfocus on hearer-directed beliefs and intentions of the speaker, without reuiringthat those beliefs are true or the intentions fulfilled.

1art of the tasks of general theory of speech acts is to provide a systematictaxonomy of speech acts. Austin had earlier !&B(" initiated the development of speech act taxonomy by means of the distinction

 between constative and perfor"ative utterances. The purpose then was more polemical than systematic, since Austin thought that the philosophy of languageat the time had neglected to note other uses of language than the assertoric.:oughly, whereas in a constative utterance you report an already obtaining stateof affairs)you say something)in a performative utterance you createsomething new5 you dosomething !Austin &B(, %3(". 1aradigm examples of

 performatives were utterances by means of which actions such as bapti0ing,

Page 5: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 5/42

congratulating and greeting are performed. Assertion, by contrast, is the paradigm of a constative utterance.

However, when developing his general theory of speech acts, Austin abandonedthe constativeIperformative distinction, the reason being that it is not so clear inwhat sense something is done e.g. by means of an optative utterance,expressing a wish, whereas nothing is done by means of an assertoric one.Austin noted e.g. that assertions are subject to infelicities, just like

 performatives !Austin &B(, &3D". For instance, an assertion isinsincere incase of lying as a promise is insincere when the appropriate intention is lacking!Austin &B(, *E". This is an infelicity of the abuse kind. Also, an assertion is,according to Austin, void  in case of referential presupposition, such as in:ussell$s

!%" The present 7ing of France is bald

!Austin &B(, %E". This is then an infelicity of the same kind)  fla'(type

"ise&ecutions )as the use of the wrong formula in a legal procedure !Austin&B(, 3", or of the same kind) "isinvocations )as when the reuirements ofa naming procedure aren$t met !Austin &B(, (&", or when 2 try to sell yousomething that isn$t mine !Austin &B(, &3".

Further, Austin noted that when it comes to appraisals, there is not a sharpdifference between acts that are simply true and false, and acts that are assessedin other respects !Austin &B(, &*ED*". 9n the one hand, a warning can beobjectively proper or improper, depending on the facts. 9n the other hand,assertions !statements" can be assessed as suitable in some contexts and not inothers, and are not simply true or false. An example is

!3" France is hexagonal?3@

As an alternative to the performativeDconstative dichotomy, Austin suggestedfive classes of illocutionary types !or illocutionary verbs"5 verdictives,

exercitives, commissives, behabitives and expositives !Austin &B(, &(&D*".Jou exemplify a verdictive e.g. when as a judge you pronounce a verdict' anexercitive by appointing, voting or advising' a commissive by promising,undertaking or declaring that you will do something' a behabitive byapologi0ing, critici0ing, cursing or congratulating' an expositive by actsappropriately prefixed by phrases like <2 reply=, <2 argue=, <2 concede= etc., of ageneral expository nature.

Page 6: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 6/42

2n this classification, assertion would best be placed under expositives, sincethe prefix <2 assert= is or may be of an expository nature. However, an assertionneed not in itself be expository. As a classification of illocutionary typesAustin$s taxonomy is thus not completely adeuate.

9ther taxonomies have been proposed, e.g. by #tephen #chiffer !&B%", Cohn#earle !&B(b", 7ent 6ach and :obert >. Harnich !&BB", and FranKois:ecanati !&B/". 9ne leading idea, for instance in #earle$s taxonomy, is todistinguish between speech acts according to direction of fit . An assertion hasword-world direction of fit, since an assertion is correct if what is said agreeswith what the world is like. 6y contrast, a command has a world-word directionof fit, since a command is satisfied if the addressee of the commandsubseuently performs what is ordered.

For some further points on taxonomy and the special status of assertion, see thesupplementary text on speech acts.

2. Pragmatics

Assertion is generally thought of being open, explicit and direct, as opposede.g. to conveying something indirectly, without explicitly saying it. 2n thisrespect assertion is contrasted with presupposition and i"plicature. Thecontrast is, however, not altogether sharp, partly because of the idea of indirect

 speech acts, including indirect assertions.

2.1 Presupposition

A sentence such as

!*" 7epler died in misery

is not true unless the singular term <7epler= has reference. #till, Frege arguedthat a speaker asserting that 7epler died in misery, by means of !*" does not

also assert that <7epler= has reference !&/B%, (*". That <7epler= has referenceis not part of the sense of the sentence. Frege$s reason was that if it had been,the sense of its negation,

!(" 7epler did not die in misery

Page 7: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 7/42

would have been that )epler did not die in "isery or *)epler+ does not

havereference, which is absurd. According to Frege, that <7epler= has referenceis rather  presupposed , both in an assertion of !*" and in an assertion of itsnegation.

The modern treatment of presupposition has followed Frege in treating survivalunder negation as the most important test for presupposition. That is, if it isimplied that p, both in an assertion of a sentence s and in an assertion of thenegation of s, then it is presupposed that p in those assertions. 9ther typicalexamples of presupposition !cf. 8evinson &B/3, &/D/&" include

!" Cohn managed ?didn$t manage@ to stop in time

implying that Cohn tried to stop in time, and

!" >artha regrets ?doesn$t regret@ drinking Cohn$s home brew

implying that >artha drank Cohn$s home brew.

2n the case of !*", the presupposition is clearly of a semantic nature, since thesentence <#omeone is identical with 7epler=, which is true just if <7epler= hasreference, is a logical conseuence both of !*" and of !(". 6y contrast, in thenegated forms of !" and !" the presupposition can be canceled by context, e.g.as in

!/" Cohn didn$t manage to stop in time. He didn$t even try.

This indicates that in this case the presupposition is a pragmatic phenomenon.2t is the speaker or speech act rather than the sentence or the propositionexpressed that presupposes something. The presupposing should still be keptdistinct from asserting. 9ne further reason is that the presupposition occurs inother illocutionary types as well. For instance, in asking

!B" Lid Cohn ?didn$t Cohn@ manage to stop in timeM

the speaker normally assumes that Cohn tried and is only asking about thesuccess.

For further connections between assertion and presupposition, see thesupplementary text on pragmatics.

Page 8: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 8/42

2.2 Implicature

Frege noted !&/B, %E" that there is no difference in truth evaluable content, between sentences such as

!&E" a. Cohn works with real estate and likes fishing b. Cohn works with real estate but likes fishing

<And= and <but= contribute the same way to truth and falsity. However, whenusing !&Ea", but not when using !&Eb" the speaker indicates that there is acontrast of some kind between working with real estate and liking fishing. Thespeaker is not assertin#  that there is a contrast. For instance, forming aconditional with !&Eb" in the antecedent preserves the contrast rather than makeit hypothetical5

!&&" 2f Cohn works with real estate but likes fishing, 2 think we can bring himalong

2n an utterance of a conditional like !&&" the content of the antecedent is notasserted. The speaker may sincerely assert the conditional while denying or

 being agnostic about the antecedent. #ince the contrast indicated by <but=survives in the antecedent context, it is natural to say that the contrast is not

 part of the asserted content in !&Eb" either, and therefore not part of what ceasesto be asserted.

2t is usually said that the speaker in cases like !&Eb" and !&&", i"plies that thereis a contrast. These are then examples of implicature. H. 1aul +rice !&B(,&B/B" developed a general theory of implicature. +rice called implicatures ofthe kind exemplifiedconventional , since it is a standing feature of the word<but= to give rise to them. >ost of +rice$s theory is concerned with thecomplementing kind, the conversational  implicatures. These rely on generalconversational maxims, not on features of expressions. These maxims arethought to be in force in ordinary conversation. For instance, the maxim $e

orderly reuires of the speaker to recount events in the order they took place.This is meant to account for the intuitive difference in content between

!&%" a. Cohn took off his shoes and sat down b. Cohn sat down and took off his shoes

Page 9: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 9/42

According to +rice$s account, the speaker doesn$t assert, only implicates thatthe events took place in the order recounted. Nhat is asserted is just that bothevents did take place.

:eal or apparent violations of the maxims generate implicatures, on theassumption that the participants obey the over-arching 4o-operative 1rinciple.For instance, in the following conversation

!&3"  -5 Nhere does Cohn spend the summerM $5 #omewhere in 4anada.

 $ implies that he doesn$t know where in 4anada Cohn spends the summer. Thereasoning is as follows. $ violates the Ouantity principle to be as informative asreuired. #ince $ is assumed to be co-operative, one can infer that he cannot

satisfy the Ouantity principle without violating the Ouality principle not to sayanything for which one lacks sufficient evidence. Hence, one can infer that hedoesn$t know. Again, $ has not asserted that he doesn$t know, but still managedto convey it in an indirect manner.

2.3 Indirect speech acts

This clear distinction between assertion and implicature is to some extentundermined by acknowledging indirect assertion as a kind of assertion proper.A standard example of an indirect speech act is given by

!&*" 4an you pass the saltM

6y means of uttering an interrogative sentence the speaker reuests theaddressee to pass the salt. The reuest is indirect. The uestion, concerning theaddressee$s ability, is direct. As defined by #earle !&B(a, (BDE", and also6ach and Harnich !&BB, E", an indirect illocutionary act is subordinate toanother, more primary act and depends on the success of the first. Analternative definition given by #adock !&B*, 3" is that an act is indirect just if

it has a different illocutionary force from the one standardly correlated with thesentence-type used.

;xamples of indirect assertions by means of uestions and commands orreuests are given by

!&(" >ay 2 tell you that, obviously, the suare root of a uarter is a half.

Page 10: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 10/42

!&" 8et me tell you that, obviously, the suare root of a uarter is a half.

!8evinson &B/3, %". :hetorical uestions also have the force of assertions5

!&" 2s not #wit0erland a peace-loving nationM

Another candidate type is irony5

!&/" #wit0erland is known for its aggressive foreign policy.

assuming the speaker does mean the negation of what is literally said.However, although in a sense the act is indirect, since the speaker assertssomething different from what she would do on a normal direct use of thesentence, and relies on the hearer to reali0e this, it is not an indirect assertion by

either definition. 2t isn$t on the first, since the primary act !the literal assertion"isn$t even made, and it isn$t on the second, since there is no discrepancy between force and sentence type.

2rony does, however, ualify as indirect assertion on the definition given by:ecanati !&B/, &%(". According to :ecanati, an indirect speech act is a specialkind of conversational implicature, where the speaker not only implicates some

 proposition p, but also that she intends to convey that p. 2n the case of !&/",there is an apparent flagrant violation of the Ouality principle to say only whatis true. 9n the assumption that the speaker is co-operative, together with

 background knowledge of her political awareness, the hearer can infer that shedoes not mean what she literally says, but rather the opposite, i.e. that whatshe 'ants to communicate is the negation of what she says. For :ecanati, thecommunicative intention is what brings this act under the category of assertion

 proper !see section ".

Although #earle$s definition of indirect speech acts is different, #earle toothinks that they work by means of an inferential mechanism, including that ofconventional implicature. The hearer is supposed to understand that the speaker 

cannot merely be performing the primary act, since that would violateconversational principles, and then again conclude by conversational reasoningwhat other act has been performed.

#o, if indirect assertions are assertions proper as well as conversationalimplicatures, the idea that assertions in general are explicit and direct has to begiven up. An alternative is to simply deny that indirect assertions are assertion

Page 11: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 11/42

 proper, and to distinguish between implicatures according to whether they areassertoric, imperative, or interrogative, or perhaps uasi-assertoric, uasi-imperative etc.

The very idea of indirect speech acts is, however, controversial. 2t is notuniversally agreed that an ordinary utterance of !&*" is indirect, since it has

 been denied e.g. by 8evinson !&B/3, %3D" that a uestion has really beenasked, over and above the reuest. #imilarly, 8evinson have uestioned the ideaof a standard correlation between force and sentence type, by which a reuestwould count as indirect on #adock$s criterion. This brings us to the topic ofconventionality.

3. Convention

Austin held that illocutionary acts as opposed to perlocutionary actsare conventional , in the sense that they can be made explicit by the so-called

 performative formula !Austin &B(, &E3". According to Austin one can say <2argue that= or <2 warn you that= but not <2 convince you that= or <2 alarm youthat=. 1resumably, the idea was that a speech act type is conventional just ifthere exists a convention by which an utterance of a sentence of a certain kindensures !if uptake is secured" that a speech act of that type is performed. Austin

 probably thought that in virtue of the performative formulas this condition ismet by illocutionary but not by perlocutionary act types.

The more general claim that illocutionary force is correlated by conventionwith sentence type has been advocated by >ichael Lummett !&B/&, 3E%, 3&&".9n this view, it is a convention that declarative sentences are used for assertion,interrogative for uestions and imperative for commands and reuests. #imilarviews have been put forward by #earle !&BB" and 1etr 7otatko !&BB/".According to #earle !&BB, 3/, *E", illocutionary acts are conventional, and theconventions in uestion govern the use of so-called force-indicating devices!#earle &BB, *" specific to each language. #earle does not claim that thestandard sentence types are force indicating devices !but speculates that a

representation of illocutionary type would be part of the syntactic deepstructure".

However, the view that illocutionary acts types are conventional in this sensehas met with much opposition. 1eter #trawson !&B*, &(3D(*" objected earlyon that ordinary illocutionary acts can be performed without relying on anyconvention to identify the force, e.g. when using a declarative sentence like

Page 12: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 12/42

Page 13: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 13/42

it seems clear that when normally uttered, the speaker is saying somethingabout the weather at a certain time and at a certain !limited" location. 4learly,the meaning of !%E" does not contain reference to any particular time orlocation.

#o we must distinguish between sentence meaning and assertion content. 2t isoften assumed that the assertoric content nevertheless systematically dependson the meaning of the sentence. Typically, the meaning of the sentence isdescribed so as to provide a proposition as determined by the context ofutterance of the sentence. Nithin his truth-theoretic program in semantics !cf.Lavidson &B/*a, 8arson and #egal &BB(", Lavidson proposed the following so-called T-sentence for characteri0ing the meaning of !%E"

!%&" <2t is raining= is true as uttered by a speaker S  at a time t  if, and only if, it is

raining near S  at t .

!&B3, &3(". 6y Lavidson$s T-sentence, the speaker asserts that  it is rainingnear her at the time !provided the following holds5 if her utterance is true iff p,then what she asserts is that p". 2n his different framework Lavid 7aplan !&B/B"calls the meaning of a context dependent sentence like !%E" its character . Thecharacter is a function from contexts of utterance to content , and the content ofan assertoric utterance in a context is a proposition. The effect is that what aspeaker asserts with a sentence s in a context c is the value of the character

of s for the argument c.

2t seems plausible, then, to revise the original euation of assertoric contentwith sentence meaning, and instead euate assertoric content with the kaplaniancontent of the sentence in the context, or again with the davidsonian truthconditions of the utterance in that context. That such an euation holds has

 been affirmed by e.g. by Cohn >cLowell !&B/E, &%E" and by Cason #tanley!%EEE, 3B(".

6ut even this revised euation is problematic. 2n the pragmatics literature of

recent decades it has been pointed out that the content of what is assertedusually !at least" goes beyond the proposition expressed by the sentence in thecontext. 9ne of the standard examples is due to +eoffrey unberg !&BB". Thesentence

!%%" The ham sandwich left without paying

Page 14: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 14/42

can be used, e.g. when uttered by one waiter to another at a restaurant, to assertthat

!%3" .he #uest that had ordered  the ham sandwich left the restaurant  without paying.

This does not seem to be an indirect speech act or implicature. 2t is the primaryact, but has a content different from anything that would be specified by ameaning theory, truth theoretic or other.

How does one draw the line between linguistic meaning in context and contentthat is added because of further factors of various sortsM This is currently atopic of much dispute. 9ne view in particular has conseuences for the generaltheory of speech acts. 4appelen and 8epore !%EE(" have argued that the

 boundary of semantics must be drawn very narrowly5 if we freely followintuitions about what is said by means of some sentence in different scenarios,we are on a slippery slope and cannot in the end draw any line at all. However,4appelen and 8epore still claim that the semantic content is asserted, since thisis what connects speech act content with sentence meaning. This holds even incases where the speaker intuitively wants to communicate something different.2n the case of !%E", the correct semantic description according to 4appelen and8epore !%EE(, &D3" is not !%&" but rather 

!%*" <2t is raining= express the proposition that it is rainin#  and is true iff it$sraining

!when disregarding the time indexicality". Here, no location is mentioned. Thespeaker of !%E" therefore asserts that it is raining !simpliciter" at t , for somecontextually salient time t . However, over and above this, the speakertypically also asserts that it is raining at l  at t , for some contextually salientlocation l  and some contextually salient time t . That the speaker performs bothassertions by means of the same utterance is part of 4appelen$s and 8epore$sdoctrine of #peech Act 1luralism !%EE(, *". According to this doctrine, by

means of a single utterance a speaker performs indefinitely many assertions, infact every assertion that can reasonably be attributed to her on the basis of theutterance.

This doctrine is very controversial. A similar but less radical thesis is advanced by #cott #oames !%EE%". #oames also wants to combine an austere semantictheory !in this case the thesis that proper names are rigid designators" with

Page 15: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 15/42

intuitions that the contents of assertions are richer than can be accounted for bythe semantics.

For more on pragmatic enrichment and discourse content, see thesupplementary text oncontent.

5. Truth

2t has often been noted that there is a close relation between the concepts ofassertion and truth. 4onnections between assertion and truth have sometimes

 been appealed to for defining the concept of assertion, and sometimes fordefining the concept of truth. Four different connections with assertion have

 been especially emphasi0ed5 with the use of the truth predicate, with truth asthe aim or norm of assertion, with the role of truth in meaning theory, and with

truth as related to correctness of assertions.

5.1 The truth predicate

As often noted in discussion of the truth predicate, there is a close connection between using a sentence like

!%(" 7afka wrote many letters to >ilena

for making an assertion, and saying of it that it is true, e.g. by means of 

!%" <7afka wrote many letters to >ilena= is true

or by means of 

!%" That$s true

with reference to !%(", or to an utterance of !%(". #trawson !&B*B' &B(E, %E("claimed that using !%" is not to make a ne' assertion, but to endorse a

 previous one. #imilarly, N. V. Ouine !&BE, &%" said that to call the sentence

<snow is white= true is to call snow white. 2n #trawson$s case in particular, theidea was that this use of <true= for signaling agreement is basic, and the key tounderstanding the truth predicate. This has been called the reassertion theory of truth !1rice &B/, %E".

2n Ouine$s case it is less clear that the endorsement signaling function is basic.:ather, Ouine emphasi0ed that the truth predicate is a disuotational device

Page 16: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 16/42

!Ouine &BE, &%". That is, applying the truth predicate to the uotation of asentence, as in !%", has the same effect as removing the uotes. That is, ingeneral an expression occurring within uotes is mentioned, not used, but whenthe truth predicate is applied to a uoted sentence, what is within uotes is

effectively brought from mention to use.

For more on assertion and the truth predicate, see the supplementary texton truth.

5.2 Assertion as truth-claim

The simple connection between truth and assertion that #trawson and Ouine pointed to for characteri0ing truth, can also be used for characteri0ing assertion.According to 4rispin Nright !&BB%, %3D%*", the principle

!TA" Asserting a proposition is claiming that it is true.

is a platitude and its correctness is <partly constitutive= of the concepts ofassertion and truth. #o, according to Nright, !TA" serves both to partlycharacteri0e truth in terms of assertion, and assertion in terms of truth.

2t is natural to understand <claim that= as pretty much synonymous with <assertthat=. #o understood, !TA" seems to say that to assert that p is the same as toassert that p is true. However, if they are the same, then it seems that what is

asserted must be the same5 that is, the proposition that p and the proposition that p is true are one and the same. #uch a view belongs in thefamily of deflationary views about truth, and it was Frege$s view !Frege &/B%,%E3". 2f it is correct, however, !TA" does not say anything moreabout assertionthan that asserting that p is the same as asserting that p, and thatdoes not really characteri0e assertion.

2t is better, then, to understand <claim that= in some other way. Nright uses oneformulation !Nright &BB%, 3*" that is fairly common5

!1T" To assert is to present as true.

This natural-sounding phrase presumably suggests the idea be that in uttering asentence one presents a proposition, and in uttering it with assertoric force one

 present it as having some particular property, that of being true. Analogously,when a speaker utters a sentence with imperative force, she presents a

Page 17: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 17/42

 proposition as having the property that the addressee is to make it true. 6utalready when it comes to the interrogative force, it is not clear what property 2

 present the proposition as having. 2t cannot really be the property that its truthvalue is desired by the speaker to be known, for that would fail to make a

distinction between !%/a" and !%/b" or !%/c"5!%/" a. 2s ;lsa at homeM

 b. 2 would like to know whether ;lsa is at home.c. 2nform me whether ;lsa is at homeP

#o it is not so easy to see in general that the illocutionary force corresponds tosome property ascribed to the proposition expressed. This makes it less clearwhat the locution <present as= amounts to. !1T" is then not as illuminating as itmight at first seem.

Frege had a more specific idea about /ud#"ent 5 to judge is to advancefrom sense !#inn" to reference !6edeutung" !Frege &/B%". According to Frege,

 judging cannot be the same as ascribing to a proposition !a Thought, in Frege$ssense" the property of being true, since moving from the proposition that p tothe proposition that p is true is just moving from a proposition to a proposition5adding judgmental force must be something else !Frege &/B%, %E3' this can beconstrued as a regress argument". 2n Frege$s view, the truth value of a !sentenceexpressing a" proposition is its referent. 2n a judgment the thinkeracknowledges the truth of the proposition considered, and thereby advancesfrom the proposition to the acknowledgment that the referent is the truth valueThe True. #o Frege$s idea is that in judging the thinker in a distinct way relatesa proposition to a particular object, The True. 9n this point Frege has not beenfollowed by many.

#ince judging that p or asserting that p clearly is different from just thinkingthe thoughtthat p is true, we must characteri0e the relation between assertion,or judgment, and truth in other terms than ascribing truth as a property, just asFrege observed. 6ut it is difficult do to this in clear and convincing way. 9ne

might therefore suspect that the relation between truth and assertion simplyderives from the euivalence schema

!;#" 2t is true that p iff p

Page 18: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 18/42

!according to Nright, this is entailed by !TA""5 asserting that p is by !;#"euivalent to asserting that p is true. 6ut that euivalence derives from theeuivalence of the contents, and need not say much about assertion as such.

A more complex version of this connection between truth and assertion issuggested by >ichael Lummett !&B(B, /". According to this suggestion, thetruth of an assertion is like the winning of a game5 this is not just aclassification of an outcome, but something the speaker or the player ai"s at .2n this sense, an assertion !a statement" is false if one of the state of affairs thatthe speaker meant to e&clude with the assertion obtains. 2f no such state ofaffairs obtains, the statement is true. This introduces the theme of truth as anaim, here as means of characteri0ing truth in terms of assertion.

5.3 Truth as aim !act-stating

2t is a commonly held idea, mainly used for characteri0ing assertion in terms oftruth, that assertion ai"s at truth. This is stated e.g. both by 6ernard Nilliams!&B" and by >ichael Lummett !&B/&". 2t can be understood in two ratherdifferent ways, the one intended by Nilliams and the other by Lummett !forsome ways of understanding what it could be for belief  to aim at truth, see;ngel %EE*".

9n Nilliams$s view, the property of aiming at truth is what characteri0es fact(

 statin# discourse, as opposed to e.g. evaluative or directive discourse. 2t isnatural to think of 

!%B" The moon is about 3/*,EEE km from the ;arth

as stating a fact, and of 

!3E" 6ardot is good

as expressing an evaluation, not corresponding to any fact of the matter. 9n

Nilliams$s view, to regard a sincere utterance of 

!3&" 2t is wrong to steal

as a moral assertion, is to take a realistic attitude to moral discourse5 there aremoral facts, making moral statements objectively true or false. This view againcomes in two versions. 9n the first alternative, the existence of moral facts

Page 19: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 19/42

renders the discourse fact-stating, whether the speaker thinks so or not, and thenon-existence renders it evaluative, again whether the speaker thinks so or not.9n the second alternative, !3&" is an assertion if the speaker has a realisticattitude towards moral discourse and otherwise not.

9n these views, it is assumed that truth is a substantial property !Nilliams&B, %E%", not a concept that can be characteri0ed in some deflationary way.As a conseuence, the sentence

!3%" <6ardot is good= is true

is to be regarded as false, since !3E" is objectively neither true nor false' there isno fact of the matter.

For more on assertion and fact-stating, see the supplementary text on truth.

5.4 Truth as aim norms o! spea"ers# intentions

The other idea of truth as an aim for assertion is that this is what the speakeraims at in making an assertion. The speaker tries to say something true.#tatistically, it is no doubt the case that speakers usually believe what theyassert to be true, and usually this belief is no doubt part of the reason formaking the assertion. However, we cannot go from there to take a speaker$shaving this aim as necessary for her utterance to be assertoric, for lies are

assertions as much as honest utterances. The relation between assertion and theaim of truth has then to be indirect.

There are basically two ways of effecting such an indirect connection. 9ne is tocomplicate speaker intentions. For instance, instead of aiming to say somethingtrue, we could say that

!A&" The speaker of an assertion aims at making the hearer believe that sheaims at saying something true.

Ne might then want to say that if the speaker does not have this primary, hearer oriented intention, she is not really making an assertion, and if she does have it,it is an assertion whether she is honest or not.

The other way is to appeal to the notions of rule, norm or convention. Forinstance, we might try

Page 20: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 20/42

!A%" 2t is a norm for making an assertion that the speaker aims at sayingsomething true.

9n this alternative, an utterance is assertoric just in case it is governed by thisnorm, whatever the speaker in fact aims at in the particular case.

These two ideas have complementary problems. The problem with !A&" is thatutterances are made, even if infreuently, that are intuitively assertoric, butwhere the speaker does not have the reuired intention. The speaker may befully aware that she will be taken as a liar, whether she aims at the truth or not,and whether or not she tries to make the addressee believe she does aim at thetruth. 6eing convinced that this hearer oriented aim is unreachable, she will noteven have it, but is nonetheless making an assertion !for a testimony ofconversations of this kind, see 8evi &B(/, chapter /". 9ne may try to overcome

this by complicating the speaker intentions even further, but it hard to see thatany necessary condition of this kind could be immune to counterexamples.

The problem with !A%" is that it needs a supplementary criterion for when theassertion norm is in force. 2f we don$t know how to tell whether the normapplies to an utterance, we cannot tell whether it was an assertion or not.

Lummett has combined the two strategies. He has suggested the followingdefinition !Lummett &B/&, 3EE"5

!>L" A man makes an assertion if he says something in such a manner asdeliberately to convey the impression of saying it with the overriding intentionof saying something true.

Lummett$s proposal is presumably intended to give necessary as well assufficient conditions. There are problems of sufficiency with this proposal ofthe kind that will be discussed in section . There are also problems ofnecessity of exactly the same kind as afflicts !A&" above. However, Lummettcan overcome these necessity problems by his appeal to convention. That is, it

can be a convention that when uttering a declarative sentence, unless there areexplicit indications to the contrary !such as a theater setting", thespeaker counts as conveying that he has the overriding intention of speakingtruly. Then it is no longer reuired that the speaker tries to convey it, as long asthe circumstances make her count as doing so.

Page 21: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 21/42

This proposal has the problems that afflict convention theories in general !seesection 3". 6ut there is a further point. 9nce the burden of determiningassertionhood is shifted to a convention about means and ways of expressingoneself !setting aside the problems with this idea", we need to check whether

assertion is adeuately characteri0ed in the convention. 2n Lummett$s case, it isnot, because of a problem with the very idea of appealing to the aim of truth.

For it is not only in assertions that we normally aim at saying something true.Ne have that aim also in guesses, presumptions, conjectures and and the like,all normally aimed at saying something true, but all somehow falling short of

 being assertions. #imilarly, if 2 believe in the truth of, say, +oldbach$sconjecture, 2 will deliberately convey the impression of pronouncing it with theintention of saying something true, but because of my low degree of certitude, 2don$t want to outright assert it. Assertoric force can be said to differ in %ind from

interrogative and imperative force, but only in de#ree or intensity from e.g.conjectural force. 4onventions of the aiming kind don$t discriminate betweenassertion and weaker forms of propounding.

Ne would therefore need a more demanding norm5

!T" #ay only what is trueP

The idea is again that an utterance is an assertion just if it is governed by thisnorm. +uesses aren$t, for guesses are, in some sense !in need ofclarification", allo'ed  to be wrong. A speaker trying to comply with !T" willnot only avoid asserting what she believes to be false, but she will also tryto "a%e  sure that what she says isn$t false unbeknownst to her. 6ecause of thisshe will assert only that for which she has adeuate evidence. #he can even be

 blamed for asserting something which was in fact true, if she didn$t have goodenough reasons for believing it was. This is in accordance with +rice$ssupermaxim of Ouality5 .ry to "a%e your contribution one that is true !+rice&B/B, %".

From this standpoint of the norm of !T", assertion is characteri0ed by the wayassertions are evaluated . There are several ideas of how to assess assertionsas correct  or incorrect . This theme will be pursued in the present section and thenext.

5.5 Truth and correctness

Page 22: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 22/42

There is a family of uestions about the conditions for an assertion to be correct . As has often been noted, an assertion can be correct in differentrespects. ;.g., a speaker can say something true but be impolite in saying it,thereby making an assertion that is incorrect with respect to etiuette. Also,

even if we disregard such social aspects on a speech act, an assertion may havee.g. an i"plicature that is incorrect, even though the primary act is correct.

8et$s for now concentrate on the semanticIepistemic correctness of the primaryact. For that respect, the principle

!;4" An assertion that p is correct if, and only if, the speaker has good evidencethat it is true that p

is almost universally accepted !for problems concerning conditionals, see

section /". 2n the case of mathematics, for instance, an assertion it thought of ascorrect if the speaker knows a proof of what is asserted !see 1rawit0 &BB/a, *(,and many other places". There is room for doubt that there is anything likereasonably sharp and stable standards of assertoric correctness in ordinarylinguistic practice, and in fact speakers pretty rarely engage in evaluatingutterances in these terms, beyond assessing them for truth or falsity, or blamingthe speaker for breach of confidence and the like. There is therefore not muchevidence from actual practice that the intended notions of correctness play anyimportant role. They can nevertheless belong in the linguistic or philosophical

enterprises of reflecting over that practice.

A second preliminary issue concerns the status of the notion of correctnessinvolved. 2s it an inherently nor"ative notion, or is it just descriptiveMAccording to e.g. !an earlier view of" 1aul 6oghossian !&B/B, (&3" the merefact that we can evaluate assertions as correct or incorrect show that words aregoverned by norms of use. According to 7athrin +lQer !%EE&, ED(' cf.Nikforss %EE&, and 6oghossian %EE3", on the other hand, there is no reason tosee in the notions of correctness and incorrectness anything more than adescriptive classification, which may then be coupled with certain a preference

for correct assertions over incorrect ones, both in making and in taking. Those preferences may then be explained e.g. by appeal to social psychology, or thedesire for knowledge.

#etting these uestions aside, we can note that the !;4" biconditional has beenused in two different ways5 as a way of characteri0ing assertoric correctness interms of truth and evidence, or as a way of characteri0ing truth in terms of

Page 23: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 23/42

correctness and evidence. 2t is the second alternative that has been mostimportant. Ne shall return to the first alternative in the next section.

Nhen using !;4" to account for truth it is crucial how <good evidence= isunderstood. Typically, it is the best possible evidence, i.e. the best evidencethat can be had or could be had !as opposed to something that only could have

been had but cannot anymore", that is relevant. There is also a uestion of howto understand <has=, as we shall see.

Cohn Lewey !&B3/" seems to have been the first to characteri0e truth in termsof assertoric correctness, with his notion of 'arranted assertibility, eventhough this idea had a clear affinity with the verifiability principle of >orit0#chlick !&B3". Lewey was later followed by, notably, >ichael Lummett!&B" and Hilary 1utnam !&B/&". 4ommon to them is the position that there

cannot be anything more to truth than being supported by the best availableevidence. Lewey, following 4. #. 1eirce, regarded truth as the ideal limit ofscientific inuiry !Lewey &B3/, 3*(", and a proposition warrantedly assertedwhen known in virtue of such an inuiry. Narranted assertibility is the propertyof a proposition for which such knowledge potentially exists !&B3/, B".

1utnam !&B/&, (*D(" operated with an idea of assertibility under idealepistemic conditions. Rnder normal conditions, a speaker can be justified inmaking an assertion even though what she asserts is false. The evidence is

enough for truth under normal circumstances, but because of abnormalinterference the evidence falls short. For instance, improbable changes, say because of a fire, may have taken place after the speaker$s observation.However, in ideal epistemic conditions evidence that is sufficient for justifyingan assertion also is conclusive. #pelling out what the ideal epistemic conditionsare, in a non-circular fashion, has of course been a main problem for this view.

Lummett$s views are more complex, but in general focus on actual evidencerather than ideali0ed conditions.

For more on assertion, truth and correctness, see the supplementary texton truth.

$. %elie! and "no&ledge

Page 24: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 24/42

Two common ideas about assertion are that the speaker says what she believesand that she says what she knows. +iven that assertions often are made thatdon$t fit these descriptions, the uestion is how those ideas can be worked out.

$.1 %elie! 

According to Frege !&B&/, %%", an assertion is an outward sign ofa /ud#"ent  !Rrteil". The term <judgment= has been used in several ways !cf.section (.%". 2f it is used to mean either belief , or act by 'hich a belief is

 for"ed or reinforced , then Frege$s view is pretty much euivalent with the viewthat assertion is the expression of belief .

How should one understand the idea of expressing hereM 2t is natural to think of a belief state, i.e. a mental state of the speaker, as causally co-responsible for

the making of the assertion. For instance, a speaker has a belief and wants tocommunicate it. This motivates an assertoric utterance. The having of the

 belief, i.e. the belief state, together with the desire to communicate, motivatethe action, and jointly cause it !if reasons are causes' cf Lavidson &B3". Theassertion therefore gives evidence that the speaker has a belief suitably relatedto the meaning of the sentence uttered. 9n this conception, an assertion is theexpression of belief like a running nose is the expression of a virus infection, or groaning is the expression of pain.

However, assertion is intentional and groaning can be. 2 can intentionally groanto make my pain known to others, and my belief that there are black swans canmotivate my intention to assertorically utter 

!33" There are black swans

!4f. 9wens %EE." 9n the other hand, 2 can also pretend to be in pain bygroaning, and pretend to believe that there are black swans by means of anassertoric utterance of !33". 2n this case the utterance isn$t caused or motivated

 by the corresponding belief, but since it is an assertion nonetheless, not all

assertions are expressions of belief in the sense suggested.

The utterance may still be evidence for the existence the belief state. o doubt,a speaker will not try mislead the addressee about the facts, by means of anassertion, unless she assumes !tacitly, for the most part" that her assertion doescount as evidence for the addressee that the she does have the belief inuestion. This idea, of intendin#  the addressee to take the utterance as evidence

Page 25: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 25/42

for belief of is a key idea in 6ach$s and Harnich$s understanding of whatexpressing is. They say

!;" For S  to e&press an attitude is for S  to R-intend the hearer to take S $sutterance as reason to think S  has that attitude

!6ach and Harnich &BB, &(' italics in the original." <:-intend= is short for<reflexively intend=, a notion we will return to in the next section. 9n this view,expressing is wholly a matter of hearer-directed intentions. 4f. section .

However, a speaker can clearly make an assertion even if the addressee has a prior conviction that the speaker is dishonest and will not treat the assertion asevidence for belief, and intuitively she can also make an assertion even if sheis convinced  that that is so. 2t can happen e.g. in interrogation situations, where

the speaker officially insists on an account of what has happened, knowing fullwell she will be taken as a liar. #he will not then intend the interrogators to takeher utterance as evidence for belief. 2nsisting can be a conversational strategy,whether she is lying or not.

2ntuitions are surely debatable here, but the possibility of such situations makesit problematic to treat the existence of such hearer-directed intentions as anecessary condition for an utterance to be an assertion.

A more neutral way of trying to capture the relation between assertion and believing was suggested both by >ax 6lack !&B(%" and by Lavidson !&B/*b,%/"5 in asserting that pthe speaker represents herself as believing that p. Thissuggestion appears to avoid the difficulties with the appeal to hearer-directedintentions, because representation belongs more to semantics than to personal

 psychology. However, it is not so clear what representing oneself amounts to. 2tmust be a sense different from that in which one represents the 'orld  as having

 black swans by means of a normal assertoric utterance of !33". The speakerdoes claim that there are black swans but does not also claim that she believesthat there are black swans. 2t must apparently be some weaker sense of

<represent=, since it is not  just a matter of being, as opposed to not being, fullyexplicit. 6y means of answering the uestion what 2 believe with an utteranceof !33" 2 do represent myself as believing that there are black swans,euivalently with asserting it. Nhat 2 assert then is wrong if 2 don$t have the

 belief, despite the existence of black swans.

Page 26: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 26/42

9n the other hand, it must also be stronger than the sense of <represent= bywhich an actor can be said to represent himself as believing something onstage. The actor says

!3*" 2$m in the biology department

thereby representing himself as asserting that he is in the biology department,since he represents himself as being a man who honestly asserts that he is in the

 biology department. 6y means of that he in one sense represents himself as believing that he is in the biology department. 6ut the hearer is no way invitedto believe that the speaker, i.e. the actor, has that belief.

Apparently, the relevant sense of <represent= is not easy to specify. Analternative is again to go normative, with the rule

!6" Assert only what you believeP

This accords with but is stronger than +rice$s first submaxim of Ouality5 0o

not say 'hat you believe to be false !+rice &B/B, %". An immediate objectionto this is that !6" is a moral rule rather than a rule that accounts for assertion assuch. #peakers may be subject to this rule, but as moral agents more than asspeakers. 6ut this objection can be met. 2t can be agreed that being honest, orsincere, indeed is something reuired by a moral rule. However, you can beinsincere in many different ways. Nhat !6" specifies is what %ind  of insincerity,and thereby sincerity, is specific to assertion. That is, you can regard the appealto !6" as euivalent with a statement about what counts as being sincere5

!#6" An act of type 1  is sincere if, and only if, the speaker believes what shesays

Then you can go on to claim that assertion is a value of 1 , or even the uniuevalue of 1 , that makes !#6" come out true. This idea is part of #earle$s account,as we shall in the next section.

For more on assertion, belief and >oore$s paradox, see the supplementary texton belief and assertion.

$.2 'no&ledge

Page 27: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 27/42

Page 28: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 28/42

some implicit way. For instance, the uestion <How do you know thatM= mightsimply be a way of inuiring about the grounds for the assertion.

Nith respect to the uestion of the correctness of assertions !section (.(", the position of the knowledge account is that an assertion is incorrect if the speaker doesn$t know that the proposition asserted is true.

For more on knowledge and assertion, see the supplementary text on belief andknowledge.

(. Social character

The social character of a speech act can be of two kinds. 9n the one hand, therecan be an institutional  change of relation between speaker and addressee

occurring because of a characteristic property of the act. For instance, by meansof a sincere utterance of 

!3(" 2 promise to call the repair shop

the speaker has committed herself, in relation to the addressee, to dosomething. 6oth speaker and hearer will regard the speaker as having incurredan obligation to the addressee. The first to view assertion from this angle was

 probably 4. #. 1eirce, who said that <to assert a proposition is to make oneselfresponsible for its truth= !&B3*, 3/*".

9n the other hand, there can be hearer-directed intentions which the speakerhas in performing a speech act. The speaker may intend the hearer to come to

 believe something or other about the speaker, or about something else, orintend the hearer to come to desire or intend to do something. #uch intentionscan concern institutional changes, but need not. 2ntentions that are immediatelyconcerned with communication itself, as opposed to ulterior goals, arecalled co""unicative intentions.

The distinction between these two kinds of social character does not coincidewith the distinction between conventional and non-conventional. For instance,you can hold that there is a form-force convention in ;nglish without acceptingany institutional theory about illocutionary types.

>ost social accounts have tended to focus either on theconventionalIinstitutional or on the intentional features !#earle, as we shall see,

Page 29: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 29/42

combines them". An example of the former is 6random !&BB*". According to6random !&BB*, &3D(", the nature of assertion consists in the fact that inassserting the speaker achieves two different normativeIinstitutional results atthe same time5 on the one hand she authori0es the hearer to claim anything that

follows from what is asserted and on the other she undertakes the responsibilityof justifying it. 6random has recently been followed by Cohn >acFarlane!%EE3, %EE(" in the context of semantic relativism. 9ther examples include7otatko !&BB/, %3D3B", who like #earle stresses the importance of socialconventions about what counts as making a commitment or undertaking, and+ary Natson !%EE*". Also, +reen !&BBB, %EEE" has worked out the idea ofassertoric commitment in the setting of conversational score.

The idea of communicative intentions derives from +rice$s &B( article<>eaning=, where +rice defined what it is for a speaker to non(naturally

"ean something. +rice$s idea can be set out as follows5

!" S  non-naturally means something by an utterance u if, and only if, there isa hearer 3  such that!i" S  intends u to bring about a response R in 3 

!ii" S  intends 3  to recogni0e that !i"!iii" S  intends 3 $s reason for R to be that !i".

!Here <that !i"= is short for <that S  intends u to bring about a response R in 3 =."

That is, the speaker intends the hearer to react in a certain way because ofrecogni0ing that the speaker wants him to react in that way. 9ften, and in+rice$s original examples, the intended reaction is one of coming to believesomething, and that is a reaction that typically fits the speaker$s intention or atleast desire when making an assertion. Although +rice did not explicitlyattempt to define assertion, the idea can be straightforwardly applied to provideone5

!1+" S  asserts that p by the utterance u iff there is a hearer 3  such that!i" S  intends u to produce in 3  the belief that p

!ii" S  intends 3  to recogni0e that !i"!iii" S  intends 3  to believe that p for the reason that !i"

2n the early to mid &BEs Austin$s speech act theory and +rice$s account ofcommunicative intentions began to merge. The connection is discussed in#trawson &B*. #trawson inuired whether illocutionary force could be madeovert by means of communicative intentions. He concluded that when it comes

Page 30: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 30/42

to highly conventionali0ed utterances communicative intentions are largelyirrelevant, but that on the other hand convention does not play much role forordinary illocutionary types. #trawson also pointed out a dfficulty with +rice$sanalysis5 it may be the case that all three conditions are fulfilled, but that the

speaker intends the hearer to believe that they aren$t, e.g. by intending thehearer to believe that the speaker wants him to believe that p for an entirelydifferent reason.

#uch intentions to mislead came to be called snea%y intentions !+rice &BB",and they constituted a problem for speech act analyses based on communicativeintentions. The idea was that genuine communication is essentially open5 thespeaker$s communicative intentions are meant to be fully accessible to thehearer. #neaky intentions violate this reuirement of openness, and thereforeapparently they must be ruled out one way or another. #trawson$s own solution

was to add a fourth clause about the speaker$s intention that the hearerrecogni0e the third intention. However, that solution only invited a sneakyintention one level up !cf #chiffer &B%, &D*%".

Another solution was to make the intention refle&ive. This was proposed by#earle !&BB", in the first full-blown analysis of illocutionary types made byappeal to communicative intentions. #earle combined this with an appeal toinstitutional relations as created by rules. #uch rules are the so-called constitutive rules, as opposed tore#ulative rules !the terminology is taken

from 7ant". :oughly, whereas regulative rules regulate a pre-existing activity,such as traffic regulations regulate traffic, constitutive rules in a sense create anew activity. 1aradigm examples are rules of games as defining games, andthus making it possible to play them. The distinction was introduced by :awls!&B((", and also suggested by 4. +. C. >idgley !&B(B" in the same terms andformat as later by #earle !&BB, 33D*%' cf. +lQer and 1agin &BBB".

#earle suggests five rules for the use of force indicating devices. 2n the case ofassertion, they are as follows. S  is the speaker and 3  the hearer5

!C#&" !&" The propositional content rule5 what is to be expressed is any proposition p.

!%" First preparatory rule5 S  has evidence !reasons etc." for the truth of p.

!3" #econd preparatory rule5 2t is not obvious to both S  and 3  that 3  knows !doesnot need to be reminded of, etc." p.

!*" #incerity rule5 S  believes p.

Page 31: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 31/42

!(" 4onstitutive rule5 4ounts as an undertaking to the effect that p represents anactual state of affairs.

The fifth rule is constitutive. That is, according to #earle, without this rule the

 practice of assertion would not exist. The existence of the undertaking is aninstitutional fact created by the utterance. According to #earle !&BB, (", thespeaker e&presses the state reuired by the sincerity rule, i.e. in the case ofassertion, expresses belief. Also, the speaker i"plies that the preparatoryconditions are met.

The making of an assertion also involves the speaker$s communicativeintentions. #earle critci0ed +rice for reuiring the speaker to intend

 perlocutionary effects, such as what the speaker shall come to do or believe, pointing out that such intentions aren$t essential !&BB, *D*". 2nstead,

according to #earle, the speaker intends to be understood , and also intends toachieve this by means of the hearer$s recognition of this intention. >oreover, ifthe intention is recogni0ed, it is also fulfilled5 <we achieve what we try to do bygetting our audience to recogni0e what we try to do= !#earle &BB, *".

For more about assertion and social analysis of assertion, see the supplementarytext onsocial character .

). *ogic

Frege introduced the turnstile, <⊢=, as a so-called assertion si#n. 2t firstappeared in the $e#riffsschrift  !Frege &/B". According to Frege, it servesto e&press a /ud#"ent !&/B, &&". The sign was meant to be composed from thehori0ontal part, the so-calledcontent stro%e, and the vertical part, the so-called /ud#"ent   stro%e. The content stroke would mark that what follows it is a

 judgeable content.

Frege demanded that what follows the the content stroke must have a contentthat can become a judgment, which is to say a propositional content. Nith the

content stroke attached, but not the judgment stroke, we have an expression ofthe kind <the circumstance that =, or <the proposition that = !&/B, &&". Healso characteri0ed <⊢= as a common predicate for all judgments, like the

 predicate <is a fact= as occurring in sentences such as

!3" The violent death of Archimedes at the capture of #yracuse is a fact.

Page 32: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 32/42

Here the argument is a noun phrase denoting an event rather than a state ofaffairs. This difference in syntactic format between that-clauses and event termsis of less significance than the basic idea that there really is just one kind of

 judgment. There are not e.g. any hypothetical or disjunctive /ud#"ents, only

conditional or disjunctive contents. The contents vary, the nature of the judgment remains the same !Frege &/B, &3".

This view was retained in the 4rund#eset5e der -rith"eti%  !Frege &/B3". Theassertion sign is here still composed of the vertical part, the /ud#"ent stro%e,and the hori0ontal, now called the hori5ontal  !der 6a#erechte". Nhile the

 judgment stroke is more or less the same, Frege$s conception of the hori0ontalhas changed. The hori0ontal is now part of the expression of content. 2t denotesa function from objects to truth values !&/B3, B"5 it maps the True on the Trueand any other object on the False. 2t can occur in the interior of formulas.

:emember that on Frege$s view at the time, truth values are among the objectsof the universe.

#ince the judgment stroke is always followed by a hori0ontal, this constructionhas the effect that what is judged always denotes a truth value, at least if whatfollows the hori0ontal is a meaningful closed expression !not containing gapsor free variables". 9n the view that Frege had developed sincethe $e#riffsschrift , and which he argued for in <Uber #inn und 6edeutung=,

 judging is passing from the level of sense !#inn" to the level of reference

!6edeutung". Cudging that p is passing from the mere thought that p, toacceptance of the truth of the thought that p. Thus, in judging you advance froma sense to a truth value. 4onversely, advancing from a sense to a truth valueconstitutes judging. Therefore, we have a well-formed judgment, correct orincorrect, if what follows the judgment stroke denotes a truth value. Nith thenew conception of the hori0ontal, the judgment is guaranteed to be well-formed.

Frege$s conception of his assertion sign fits well in with his own system ofdeduction. ;very sentence occurring in a deduction in the $e#riffschrift  orthe 4rund#eset5e is either asserted or a proper constituent of a sentence that isasserted. ;ach sentence asserted is either an axiom or is derived from axioms

 by means of accepted rules of deduction. There is no such thing as anunasserted assumption occurring as a premise of a deduction step, and a

 fortiori no conclusion of a deduction step that depends on an assumption.4orrespondingly, the judgment stroke itself only occurs initially in each

Page 33: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 33/42

expression of judgment. There is no such thing as a complex judgment withother judgments as proper parts. 2n particular, there are no hypothetical

 judgments, in the sense of a judgment that is the conseuent of a conditional.

#everal interesting connections between logical issues and the notion ofassertion have arisen because of transcendence of these Fregean limitations.The first was crossed by +erhard +ent0en in the mid-&B3Es, and, depending oninterpretation, maybe the second, too. Nith +ent0en$s atural Leductionsystem !&B3*D3(", a system of deduction was formulated with the possibility of making assumptions, making inferences from these assumptions, and alsoof dischar#in#  assumptions in certain deduction steps !e.g. -2ntroduction".⊃

Nith +ent0en$s work, and the later developments by Lag 1rawit0 !&B(", atural Leduction has become a well-established and almost standard systemof deduction. However, there is still a uestion of how to understand the act of

inferring from an assumption, since it seems itself to be neither an assumption,nor an assertion proper.

2t might be natural to think of such an act as a kind of conditional  assertion.2deas about conditional assertion have been proposed, but then chiefly inconnection with natural language indicative conditionals, i.e. sentences of theform

!3" 2f p, then

!in ;nglish". 1roblems with interpreting such sentences as materialconditionals,

!3/" p ⊃ 

led to the suggestion, first in Ouine &B(%, that an assertoric utterance of anindicative conditional really is a conditional assertion, in the following sense5 2f the antecedent is true, then the speaker has asserted the proposition expressed

 by the conseuent, and if the antecedent is false, no assertion has been made.

This idea has been rather controversial.

Finally, generali0ing the idea that there are forms of judgment with assertionsas proper parts, there has been a development of so-called logics of assertion,and even more generally, illocutionary logic, with complex speech act types,having themselves speech act types as proper parts. 2n the assertion logic case,there is special logical constant !<A=" denoting assertion, and the system is the

Page 34: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 34/42

logic of that constant. 2n the case of icholas :escher !&B/", the basic form of sentence studied is that of 

!3B" & asserts that p

which is abbreviated as

!3B" A &p

A similar system as is developed by 2ngemund +ullvWg !&B/". 2n illocutionarylogic, as e.g. in #earle and Vanderveken &B/(, the study concerns in generallogical relations between speech acts. 2n this case the idea is that each speechact has a particular array of characteristics, and two speech acts may then be sorelated that the characteristics of the one are implied by, or inconsistent with,

the characteristics of the other. 4f. the entry on #peech Acts.

For more on assumptions, conditionals and assertion logic, see thesupplementary text onlogic and assertion.

%i+liograph,

• Adams, ;., &B(, <A 8ogic of 4onditionals=, Inuiry, /5 &DB.• Appiah, A., &B/(, -ssertion and Conditionals, 4ambridge5 4ambridge

Rniversity 1ress.• Austin, C. 8., &B(, <1erformative Rtterances=, in 7hilosophical 7apers,

%33D(%, 9xford5 9xford Rniversity 1ress, 3 edn.•  DDD, &B(, 3o' to do .hin#s 'ith 6ords, 9xford5 9xford Rniversity

1ress, %nd edn.• 6ach, 7., &BB*, <4onversational impliciture=, Mind 8 Lan#ua#e, B5 &%*D 

%.• 6ach, 7. and Harnich, :. >., &BB, Lin#uistic Co""unication and

Speech -cts, 4ambridge, >ass.5 >2T 1ress.• 6arker, #. C., &BB(, <Towards a 1ragmatic Theory of ifG=, 7hilosophical

Studies, B5 &/(D%&&.• 6elnap, . L. C., &B3, <:estricted Ouantification and 4onditional

Assertion=, in H. 8eblanc !ed.", .ruth, Synta& and Modality, Amsterdam5 orth-Holland.

• 6ennett, C., %EE3, - 7hilosophical 4uide to Conditionals, 9xford59xford Rniversity 1ress.

• 6lack, >., &B(%, <#aying and disbelieving=, -nalysis, &35 %(D33.

Page 35: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 35/42

• 6oghossian, 1. A., &B/B, <The :ule-Following 4onsiderations=, Mind ,B/5 (ED*B.

•  DDD, %EE3, <The ormativity of 4ontent=, 7hilosophical Issues, &35 3&D *(.

6random, :., &B, <Truth and Assertability=, Journal of 7hilosophy, 35&3D*B.•  DDD, &BB*, Ma%in# it 9&plicit , 4ambridge, >ass.5 Harvard Rniversity

1ress.• 4appelen, H. and 8epore, ;., %EE(, Insensitive Se"antics: - 0efense

ofSe"antic Mini"alis" and Speech -ct 7luralis", 9xford5 6lackwell.• Lavidson, L., &B3, <Actions, reasons and causes=, Journal of

 7hilosophy, E5 /(DEE' page reference is to the reprint in Lavidson&B/E.

•  DDD, &B, <Truth and >eaning=, Synthese, &5 3E*D%3' page reference isto the reprint in Lavidson &B/*a.

•  DDD, &B3, <:adical 2nterpretation=, 0ialectica, %5 3&3D%/' pagereference is to the reprint in Lavidson &B/*a.

•  DDD, &BB, <>oods and 1erformances=, in A. >argalit !ed.", Meanin#

and  Use, Lordrecht5 :eidel' page reference is to the reprint in Lavidson&B/*a.

•  DDD, &B/E, -ctions and 9vents, 9xford5 4larendon 1ress.•  DDD, &B/*a, Inuiries into .ruth and Interpretation, 9xford5 4larendon

1ress.•  DDD, &B/*b, <4ommunication and 4onvention=, in Lavidson &B/*a, %(D 

/E.• Le:ose, 7., &BB, <7nowledge, Assertion and 8otteries=, -ustralasian

 Journal of 7hilosophy *5(/-/E.•  DDD, %EE%, <Assertion, 7nowledge and 4ontext=, .he

 7hilosophical   Revie', &&&5 &D%E3.• Le:ose, 7. and +randy, :., &BBB, <4onditional Assertions and <6isuit=

4onditionals=, ;ous, 335 *E(D%E.• Lewey, C., &B3/, Lo#ic: .he .heory of Inuiry, ew Jork5 Henry Holt

and 4ompany.• Ludman, V.H., &BB%, <1robability and Assertion=, -nalysis, (%5%E*-&&.• Lummett, >., &B(B, <Truth=, 7roceedin#s of the -ristotelian Society, (B5

&*&D%. ' page reference is to the reprint in Lummett &B/E.•  DDD, &B, <Nhat is a Theory of >eaningM !22"=, in +. ;vans and C.

>cLowell !eds.", .ruth and Meanin# , 9xford5 9xford Rniversity 1ress ' page reference is to the reprint in Lummett &BB/.

Page 36: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 36/42

•  DDD, &B/E, .ruth and <ther 9ni#"as, 8ondon5 Luckworth, %nd edn.•  DDD, &B/&, Fre#e= 7hilosophy of Lan#ua#e, 4ambridge, >ass.5 Harvard

Rniversity 1ress, % edn.•  DDD, &BB&, .he Lo#ical $asis of Metaphysics, 4ambridge, >ass.5

Harvard Rniversity 1ress.•  DDD, &BB/, .he Seas of Lan#ua#e, 9xford5 4larendon 1ress.• ;dgington, L., &BB(, <9n 4onditionals=, Mind , &E*5 %3(D3B.•  DDD, %EEE, <+eneral 4onditional #tatements5 a :esponse to

7Slbel=, Mind , &EB5 &EBD&&.• ;ngel, 1., %EE*, <Truth and the Aim of 6elief=, in L. +illies !ed.",  La's

andModels in Science, 7ing$s 4ollege 1ublications.• Feigl, H. and #ellars, N. !eds.", &B*B, Readin#s in 7hilosophical

 -nalysis, ew Jork5 Appleton-4entury 4roft.• Frege, +., &/B, $e#riffsschrift, eine der arit"etischen

nach#ebildeteFor"elsprache des reinen 0en%ens, Halle5 unknown publisher. Translation in C. van Heijenoort !ed.", Fre#e and 4>del= .'o

 Funda"ental .e&ts inMathe"atical Lo#ic, Harvard Rniversity 1ress,4ambridge, >ass. &BE. 1age reference to the translation.

•  DDD, &/B%, <XRber #inn und 6edeutung=, ?eitschrift f@r 7hilosophie

und7hilosophische )riti% , &EE5 %%D(E. Translated by Herbert Feigl as<9n #ense and ominatum=, in Feigl and #ellars &B*B, /(D&E%' pagereference is to the reprint in >artinich %EE&.

•  DDD, &/B3, 4rund#eset5e der -rith"eti% , Cena5 unknown publisher' page

reference to the &B% edition by +eorg 9lms Verlagsbuchhandlung,Hildesheim.

•  DDD, &B&/, <Ler +edanke=, $eitrA#e 5ur 7hilosophie des

 0eutschen  Idealis"us, &EE5 %(D(E. :eprinted in Frege &B/E. 1agereferences to the reprint.

•  DDD, &B/E, Fun%tion, $e#riff, $edeutun# , +Sttingen5 Vandenhoeck Y:uprecht.

• +arcia-4arpintero, >., %EE*, <Assertion and the #emantics of Force->arkers=, in 4. 6ianchi !ed.", .he Se"anticsB7ra#"atics 0istinction,

#tanford, 4A5 4#82 1ublications.• +each, 1., &BE, <Ascriptivism=, .he 7hilosophical Revie', B5 %%&D%('

 page reference is to the reprint in +each &B/&.•  DDD, &B(, <Assertion=, .he 7hilosophical Revie', *5 **BD(' page

reference is to the reprint in +each &B/&.•  DDD, &B/&, Lo#ic Matters, 9xford5 6asil 6lackwell.

Page 37: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 37/42

• +ent0en, +., &B3*D3(, <Rntersuchungen Qber das 8ogische#chliessen=, Mathe"atische ?eitschrift , 3B5 &D%&E, *E(D3&. Translatedas <2nvestigations into logical Leduction=, in >. ;. #0abo !ed.", .he

Collected 7apers of 4erhard4ent5en, orth-Holland, Amsterdam, &BB.•

+lQer, 7., %EE&, <Lreams and ightmares. 4onventions, orms, and>eaning in Lavidson$s 1hilosophy of 8anguage=, in 1. 7otatko, 1. 1agin,and +. #egal !eds.", Interpretin# 0avidson, (3D*, 4#82 1ublications.

• +lQer, 7. and 1agin, 1., &BBB, <:ules of meaning and 1ractical:easoning=,Synthse, &&5 %ED%.

•  DDD, %EE3, <>eaning Theory and Autistic #peakers=, Mind 8 Lan#ua#e,&/5 %3D(&.

• +reen, >., &BBB, <2llocutions, 2mplicata and Nhat a 4onversation:euires=, 7ra#"atics and Co#nition, 5 (DB&.

•  DDD, %EEE, <2llocutionary Force and #emantic 4ontent=, Lin#uistics

87hilosophy, %35 *3(D3.• +rice, H. 1., &B(, <>eaning=, .he 7hilosophical Revie', 5 3D//.•  DDD, &BB, <Rtterer$s >eaning and 2ntentions=, .he

 7hilosophical   Revie', /5 &*D.•  DDD, &B(, <8ogic and 4onversation=, in >organ &B(, *&D(/' page

reference to the reprint in +rice /B.•  DDD, &B/B, Studies in the 6ays of 6ords, 4ambridge, >ass.5 Harvard

Rniversity 1ress.• +roenendijk, C. and #tokhof, >., &BB&, <Lynamic 1redicate

8ogic=, Lin#uistics 8 7hilosophy, &*5 3BD&EE.• +ullvWg, 2., &B/, <The 8ogic of Assertion=, .heoria, **5 (D&&.• +underson, 7. !ed.", &B(, Lan#ua#e, Mind and )no'led#e, V22 in

>innesota #tudies in the 1hilosophy of #cience, >inneapolis5Rniversity of >innesota 1ress.

• Hare, :. L., &BBB, 6ithout Conscience, ew Jork5 The +uilford 1ress.• Hawthorne, C., %EE*, )no'led#e and Lotteries, 9xford5 9xford

Rniversity 1ress.• Heim, 2., &B/3, <9n the 1rojection 1roblem for 1resuppositions=, in >.

6arlow, L. Fllickinger, and >. Nescoat !eds.", Second -nnual 6estCoast Conference on For"al Lin#uistics, &&*D%(.

• Hintikka, C., &B%, )no'led#e and $elief , 2thaca, J5 4ornell Rniversity1ress.

• Cackson, F., &BB, <9n Assertion and 2ndicative4onditionals=, .he  7hilosophical Revie', //5 ((D/B.

Page 38: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 38/42

• 7amp, H. and :eyle, R., &BB3, Fro" 0iscourse to Lo#ic= Introduction

toModel .heoretic Se"antics of ;atural Lan#ua#e, For"al Lo#ic and

 0iscourse  Representation .heory, Lordrecht5 7luwer.• 7aplan, L., &B/B, <Lemonstratives=, in C. Almog, C. 1erry, and H.

Nettstein !eds.",.he"es fro" )aplan, 9xford5 9xford Rniversity 1ress.• 7arttunen, 8., &B*, <1resupposition and 8inguistic

4ontext=, .heoreticalLin#uistics, &5 &/&DB3.• 7Slbel, >., %EEE, <;dgington on 4ompounds of 4onditionals=, Mind ,

&EB5 BD&E/.• 7otatko, 1., &BB/, <Two otions of Rtterance >eaning=, 7roceedin#s of

the-ristotelian Society, B/5 %%(D3B.• 8arson, :. and #egal, +., &BB(, )no'led#e of Meanin#: -n Introduction

toSe"antic .heory, 4ambridge, >ass.5 >2T 1ress.• 8evinson, #. 4., &B/3, 7ra#"atics, 4ambridge5 4ambridge Rniversity

1ress.• 8ewis, L., &BB, Convention: - 7hilosophical Study, 4ambridge, >ass.5

Harvard Rniversity 1ress.•  DDD, &B(, <8anguages and 8anguage=, in +underson &B(.•  DDD, &B, <1robabilities of 4onditionals and 4onditional

1robabilities=, .he7hilosophical Revie', /(5 %BD3&(' page reference isto the reprint in 8ewis &B/a.

•  DDD, &BB, <#corekeeping in a 8anguage +ame=, Journal of

 7hilosophical   Lo#ic, /5 33BD(B' page reference is to the reprint in 8ewis

&B/3.•  DDD, &B/3, 7hilosophical 7apers: Dolu"e I , 9xford5 9xford Rniversity

1ress.•  DDD, &B/a, 7hilosophical 7apers: Dolu"e II , 9xford5 9xford Rniversity

1ress.•  DDD, &B/b, <1ostscript to 1robabilities of 4onditionals and 4onditional

1robabilitiesG=, in 8ewis &B/a, &(%D(.• >artin-8Sf, 1., &BB/, <Truth and 7nowability. 9n the

1rinciples C  and )  of >ichael Lummett=, in H. +. Lales and +. 9liveri

!eds.", .ruth in  Mathe"atics, 9xford5 4larendon 1ress.• >artinich, A. 1. !ed.", %EE&, .he 7hilosophy of Lan#ua#e, 9xford

Rniversity 1ress.• >cLowell, C., &B/E, <>eaning, 4ommunication and 7nowledge=, in Z.

van #traaten !ed.", 7hilosophical Sub/ects, 9xford Rniversity 1ress.• >acFarlane, C., %EE3, <Future 4ontingents and :elative Truth=, .he

 7hilosophical Euarterly, (35 3%&D3.

Page 39: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 39/42

•  DDD, %EE(, <>aking #ense of :elative Truth=, 7roceedin#s of the

 -ristotelianSociety, &E(5 3%&D3B.• >idgley, +. 4. C., &B(B, <8inguistic :ules=, 7roceedin#s of the

 -ristotelianSociety, (B5 %&DBE.•

>ilne, 1., &BB, <6runo de Finettti and the 8ogic of 4onditional;vents=, $ritishJournal for the 7hilosophy of Science, */5 &B(D%3%.• >oore, +. ;., &B**, <:ussell$s theory of description=, in 1. A. #chilpp

!ed.", .he7hilosophy of $ertrand Russell , 8a #alle, 2ll.5 9pen 4ourt ' page reference is to the reprint in >oore &B(B.

•  DDD, &B(B, 7hilosophical 7apers, 8ondon5 Allen Y Rnwin.•  DDD, &B, 9thics, 9xford5 9xford Rniversity 1ress, %nd edn.• >organ, C. 8. !ed.", &B(, Synta& and Se"antics: Speech -cts, ew

Jork5 Academic 1ress.•  unberg, +., &BB, <The on-Rniueness of #emantic #olutions5

1olysemy=, Lin#uistics and 7hilosophy, 35 &*3D&/*.• 9wens, L., %EE, <Testimony and Assertion=, 7hilosophical Studies, &3E5

&E(D%B.• 1agin, 1., %EE*, <2s Assertion #ocialM=, Journal of 7ra#"atics, 35 /33D 

(B.• 1eirce, 4. #., &B3*, <6elief and Cudgment=, in 4. Hartshorne and 1. Neiss

!eds.",Collected 7apers, volume V, 4ambridge, >ass.5 HarvardRniversity 1ress.

• 1rawit0, L., &B(, ;atural 0eduction: - 7roof(.heoretic Study,

#tockholm5 Almvist and Niksell 2nternational.•  DDD, &BB/a, <Truth and 9bjectivity From a Verificationist 1oint of View=,

in H. +. Lales and alt. !eds.", .ruth in Mathe"atics, *&D(&, 9xford54larendon 1ress.

•  DDD, &BB/b, <4omments on >ichael Lummett$s 1aper=, .heoria, (*5%/3DB%.

• 1rice, H., &B/, <Truth and the ature of Assertion=, Mind , B5 %E%D%E.• 1utnam, H., &B/&, Reason, .ruth and 3istory, 4ambridge5 4ambridge

Rniversity 1ress.

• Ouine, N. V. 9., &B(%, Methods of Lo#ic, 8ondon5 :outledge and 7egan1aul.

•  DDD, &BE, 7hilosophy of Lo#ic, ;nglewood 4liffs, C5 1rentice Hall.• :awls, C., &B((, <Two 4oncepts of :ules=, .he 7hilosophical Revie',

*5 3D3%.• :ecanati, F., &B/, Meanin# and Force: .he 7ra#"atics of

 7erfor"ativeUtterances, 4ambridge5 4ambridge Rniversity 1ress.

Page 40: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 40/42

•  DDD, %EE&, <Rnarticulated 4onstituents=, Lin#uistics 8 7hilosophy, %(5%BBD3*(.

•  DDD, %EE*, Literal Meanin# , 4ambridge5 4ambridge Rniversity 1ress.• :escher, ., &B/, <Assertion 8ogic=, in .opics in 7hilosophical Lo#ic,

Lordrecht5 :eidel.• #adock, C. >., &B*, .o'ard a Lin#uistic .heory of Speech -cts, ew

Jork5 Academic 1ress.• #chiffer, #., &B%, Meanin# , 9xford5 4larendon 1ress.• #chlick, >., &B3, <>eaning and Verification=, .he 7hilosophical

 Revie', *(5 33BDB.• #earle, C., &BB, Speech -cts: -n 9ssay in the 7hilosophy of Lan#ua#e,

4ambridge5 4ambridge Rniversity 1ress.•  DDD, &B(a, <2ndirect #peech Acts=, in >organ &B(, (BD/%.•  DDD, &B(b, <A Taxonomy of 2llocutionary Acts=, in +underson &B(,

3**DB.• #earle, C. and Vanderveken, L., &B/(, Foundations of Illocutionary

 Lo#ic, 4ambridge5 4ambridge Rniversity 1ress.• #lote, >. A., &BB, <Assertion and 6elief=, in C. Lancy !ed.", 7apers

onLan#ua#e and Lo#ic, &DBE, 7eele5 7eele Rniversity 8ibrary.• #oames, #., %EE%, $eyond Ri#idity= the Unfinished Se"antic -#enda of

 ;a"in#  and ;ecessity, 9xford5 9xford Rniversity 1ress.• #orensen, :., &B//, $lindspots, 9xford5 4larendon 1ress.• #perber, L. and Nilson, L., &BB%, Relevance: Co""unication 8

Co#nition, 9xford5 6lackwell, %nd edn.• #tainton, :. C., &BB, <Nhat Assertion is ot=, 7hilosophical Studies, /(5

(D3.• #talnaker, :., &BE, <1ragmatics=, Synthse, %%5 %%D/B.•  DDD, &B*, <1ragmatic 1resuppositions=, in >. 7. >unit0 and 1. Rnger

!eds.",Se"antics and 7hilosophy, ew Jork5 ew Jork Rniversity 1ress.•  DDD, &B(, <2ndicative 4onditionals=, in A. 7asher !ed.", Lan#ua#e in

 Focus, Lordrecht5 :eidel ' page reference is to the reprint in #talnaker&BBB.

•  DDD, &B/, <Assertion=, in 1. 4ole !ed", Synta& and Se"antics , ;e'Gor%= ;e' Gor% -cade"ic 7ress, 3&(D3%' page reference is to the reprintin #talnaker &BBB.

•  DDD, &BBB, Conte&t and Content , 9xford5 9xford Rniversity 1ress.•  DDD, %EE, <4onditional 1ropositions and 4onditional Assertions=, in C.

+ajewski, V. Hacuard, 6. ickel, and #. Jalcin !eds.", ;e' 6or%

on  Modality, 4ambridge, >ass.5 >2T Norking 1apers in 8inguistics.

Page 41: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 41/42

• #tanley, C., %EEE, <4ontext and 8ogical Form=, Lin#uistics 8 7hilosophy,%35 3B&D*3*.

• #trawson, 1. F., &B*B, <Truth=, -nalysis, B5 /3DB.•  DDD, &B(E, <Truth=, 7roceedin#s of the -ristotelian Society,

Supple"entaryDolu"e, %*5 &%BD(' page reference is to the reprint in#trawson &B&.•  DDD, &B*, <2ntention and 4onvention in #peech Acts=, .he

 7hilosophicalRevie', 35 *3BDE' page reference is to the reprint in#trawson &B&.

•  DDD, &B&, Lo#ico(Lin#uistic 7apers, 8ondon5 >ethuen.• Travis, 4., &B/(, <9n Nhat is #trictly #peaking True=, Canadian Journal 

of7hilosophy, &(5 &/D%%B.• Rnger, 1., &B(, I#norance: .he Case for S%epticis", 9xford5 4larendon

1ress.• von Nright, +. H., &B(, Lo#ical Studies, 8ondon5 :outledge and 7egan

1aul.• Narnock, +. C., &B3, <#ome Types of 1erformative Rtterances=, in

6erlin 8 alt. !eds.", 9ssays on J: L: -ustin, 9xford5 4larendon 1ress.• Natson, +., %EE*, <Assserting and 1romising=, 7hilosophical Studies,

&&5 (D.• Nikforss, [., %EE&, <#emantic ormativity=, 7hilosophical Studies, &E%5

%E3D%.• Nilliams, 6., &B, <4onsistency and :ealism=, 7roceedin#s of the

 -ristotelianSociety, E' page reference is to the reprint in Nilliams &B3.•  DDD, &B3, 7roble"s of the Self , 4ambridge Rniversity 1ress.• Nilliamson, T., %EEE, )no'led#e and its Li"its, 9xford5 9xford

Rniversity 1ress.• Nright, 4., &BB%, .ruth and <b/ectivity, 4ambridge, >ass.5 Harvard

Rniversity 1ress.

ther Internet esources

?1lease contact the author with suggestions.@elated /ntries

Austin, Cohn 8angshaw \ convention \ Lavidson, Lonald \ defaults in semanticsand pragmatics \ Frege, +ottlob \ +rice, 1aul \ 1eirce, 4harles

Page 42: Assertion Sep

8/10/2019 Assertion Sep

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/assertion-sep 42/42

#anders \ pragmatics \ Ouine, Nillard van 9rman \ speech acts \ #trawson, 1eter Frederick 

Ac"no&ledgments

2 have been greatly helped by comments on the first version from ananonymous referee. 2 am also grateful for comments from Herman 4appelen,and from participants in a seminar on the first version in #tockholm, especiallyto 7athrin +lQer, 1er >artin-8Sf, Lag 1rawit0 and [sa Nikforss.

Copyright © 2007 by

Peter Pagin < [email protected]>