The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

90
The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the Justification of Violence Joseph Harmon Advisor: Jennifer M. Jones, PhD Rutgers University Department of History

Transcript of The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

Page 1: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution

And the Justification of Violence

Joseph Harmon

Advisor:

Jennifer M. Jones, PhD

Rutgers University

Department of History

Page 2: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

1

Table of Contents

Introduction……………………………….........………….2

Chapter 1: The Enlightenment Revolution………………11

Chapter 2: Robespierre and Reason……..……………….38

Chapter 3: The Politics of Terror……….………………..59

Conclusion……………………………….....……………85

Bibliography……………………………………………..88

Page 3: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

2

Introduction

Enlightenment-21st Century

The paradox of the Twentieth Century is the paradox of the nuclear bomb. The

century of unprecedented achievement and progress in terms of technology was the most

violent in our recorded memory. Yet we remain surprisingly optimistic; the human spirit

seems resilient as ever, and we are far more willing to accept the risk of violence than

give up our technology and the advances which human reason has attained. The monsters

in our fairy tales are not fire-breathing dragons bringing violence, but rather such

impersonal entities that seek to withhold our freedom as Big Brother of Orwell’s 1984,

the robots of Asimov’s I, Robot, or the computer programs in The Matrix. Human beings

remain unsatisfied with the Leviathan’s answer to violence and inequity, and we seek to

find our own way to live peaceably with one another without sacrificing the freedoms we

hold dear. This is not the place for a serious study of folklore, but one wonders whether

the dragon has disappeared from our stories because today the danger comes not from

without, but from within our society and within ourselves. The dragon, then, has not

disappeared, but resides, with the unseen lethal power of a dormant volcano, in the risky

bonds of human community.

For what leads the human family to such internal strife? The answer to this

question remains as varied perhaps as its instances, but if we do ask, “What allows for the

human person to strike at his brother or sister?,” we find a commonality that offers itself

as wisdom. And that answer is this: that the human person is allowed to attack brother

and sister, not for lack of some external constraint as Hobbes would have it, but for a

failure to perceive brother and sister as such. As much wisdom as can be found in the

Page 4: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

3

dictum, Love Thy Neighbor, so much evil is also possible when our human brother or

sister is not our neighbor. The lurid tale of systematic violence refutes the child’s rhyme

which fears “sticks and stones” above “words.” “Christians,” “Infidels,” “Jews,”

“Puritans,” “Cockroaches,” “aliens,” and the long list of labels used to dehumanize

certain groups of people and relegate them to the realm of Other manifest not only the

power of words, but also the necessity of dehumanization as a prerequisite for violence. I

may not kill my brother or sister, but I may kill the Other, the monster, the mearcstapa,1

and indeed I perhaps have to duty to do so in order to protect the community. And

because of the availability of technological power, the human person today has a duty to

himself and to the community to safeguard all his brothers and sisters, and to stamp out

any attempts to dehumanize any people through language, for this is one of the steps to

systematic violence.2

But if we both fear constraints on our freedom and have the potential to destroy

life when we are unconstrained, to what utopia do we look forward with such optimism?

That is, why should we speak of clean energy, of medical cure, and of economic equality

in the face of such obvious tendencies toward destructive energy, biological warfare, and

improper use of power? Perhaps we believe in this possibility because we do have on a

micro-level this kind of cooperative work for the common good in families, associations,

and small communities. Then our question is that faced by Hobbes, Montesquieu, Locke,

Rousseau, Mill, and the other thinkers who sought to discover and articulate a

legitimation for government of peoples. How can the social contract both protect the

1 Old English word used to describe Grendel in Beowulf. The word connotes walking the borders between

the community and the realm of the Other. Arnold, Thomas, trans. Beowulf (London: Longmans, Green,

and Co., 1876), line 103. 2 Stanton, Gregory. “The 8 Stages of Genocide,” Genocide Watch,

Page 5: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

4

integrity of the person and the safety of the community? On the one extreme, a monarchy

needs but one man to fail in respect for human life and Mill’s “tyranny of the ” will

ensue, while on the other extreme, majority rule similarly allows for unjust laws to be

instated in the “tyranny of the ”. The apparent middle way, that of constitutional

democracy (democracy plus rules) seems to offer an answer, but here again, who shall

write the constitution and upon what principles and anthropology shall it be written? For

in the constitutional democracy, the question must be “Is this action or measure

constitutional?” or “Is it in keeping with the thought of the Founding Fathers?” Even the

constitutions must have (if we may be permitted to give it a title) the Law of Human

Dignity - what Martin Luther King, Jr. called “the moral law or the law of God” -

expressly written into the man-made code.

We must emphatically defend this moral law in the public square and in every

other forum if we will have any hope for the future. However, such a position demands

justification in this post-Enlightenment epoch, when the “sacred” and the “truth” have

been identified with the “factual” and the “scientifically observable.” For the Law of

Human Dignity necessarily rests upon a religious assumption, and the scientific method

will brook none but the barest of epistemological assumptions about our sensory

perceptions. Unfortunately, sensory perceptions of themselves yield only fact, not

meaning or truth, and the universe is therein reduced to mere activity. Yet the human

person demands meaning; the idea of nihilism jars our very core, nor does our experience

of meaning within our relationships allow us to accept true nihilism. Nearly every

philosophy and religious worldview recognizes this, and even searches for and attempts

to define it. We are not chiefly concerned with nihilism, however, for if Nietzsche was

http://www.genocidewatch.org/aboutgenocide/8stagesofgenocide.html (accessed February 25, 2010].

Page 6: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

5

correct and “God is dead,” the human community is reduced to a Hobbesean State of

Nature or a hedonistic frenzy; such results are impossible due to the human desire for

meaning, but also they do not yield systematic violence, which is only possible in a

“system” which accepts meaning of some form or another. What we are concerned with

is the intellectual malaise that is too complacent to challenge its own logic: the fantasy

that the scientific reductionism can in fact give meaning and support the Law of Human

Dignity. Again, this reductionist paradigm can only support such a law by either

assuming a God (for there to be a “law of God”) or the law itself (simply accepting

human dignity as an unassailable truth). But the fantasy of meaning offered by scientific

reductionism claims human dignity without such an assumption. The reductionist upholds

declarations of human rights on a certain level, but never admits that those rights are

assumed, and in fact believes that the rights are derived from pure rational inquiry. If

only the reductionist would admit the assumption and defend it, or if not admit, at least

uphold it in constancy, there would be no reason for concern. But the reductionist,

believing the Law of Human Dignity to be derived from scientific reason, is particularly

vulnerable to rational offers of utopia which involve as a means subordinating human

dignity to achieve the utopian end. Camus warned us, “[A]s soon as crime reasons about

itself, it multiplies like reason itself and assumes all the aspects of the syllogism.”3

This syllogism of crime is the systematic violence which is part of the paradox of

the Twentieth Century. No violence is desirable, but the violence of the bully is not as

frightening in aspect as systematic violence because one is never deceived into perceiving

the bully as a doctor. The systematic violence of the rational utopia has the mocking

sneer of holy war in the name of God, in that murder is perceived as a good. Again,

3 Camus, Albert. The Rebel (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1965), 3.

Page 7: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

6

Camus, though an atheist, accepted the Law of Human Dignity as an assumption (or at

least the inadmissibility of murder, which is only the negative of the Law); he examines

this fearful aspect of holy war in the name of Reason: “In more ingenuous times, when

the tyrant razed cities for his own greater glory, when the slave chained to the

conqueror’s chariot was dragged through the rejoicing streets, when enemies were thrown

to the wild beasts in front of the assembled people, the mind did not reel before such

unabashed crimes, and judgment remained unclouded. But slave camps under the flag of

freedom, massacres justified by philanthropy or by a taste for the superhuman, in one

sense cripple judgment.”4 Judgment is crippled because the reductionist allows for no

comparison of value beyond what is empirically measurable. Thus the computer monsters

of modern fairy tales are particularly frightening in that they permit injustice to some in a

calculus of total lives preserved. Massacres justified by philanthropy evade the scales of

justice, because those scales are weighted by values uncounted in empirical reductionism.

Today, in the public square of the most prominent (in terms of empirical values)

nation-states the protocol is dominated (though not entirely defined) by the illusion of

reductionist morality. Unspoken almost out of an assumption of universal apparency, this

illusion consists in a belief that human beings and society in general is gradually

emerging from the shadows of ignorance, which was the principle cause of evil, into the

light of knowledge, which provides the basis for the rights of the human person. This

model is not wholly off the mark, in that humankind clearly has advanced in its

recognition and respect for human dignity, and that such perception does indeed remove

the possibility for a right-thinking individual to harm his brother or sister. But the illusory

paradigm, failing to perceive its own assumption, is vulnerable to dangerous promises of

4 Ibid., 3-4.

Page 8: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

7

ending human suffering and inequality through murder, for by perceiving rights as

ordered to the end of a peaceful utopia, this paradigm will accept the utopia over those

rights when the two conflict.

This, then, is the predicament of the Twenty-first Century. Are we to respond to

the hope visible in the human heart, even in the face of such heavy obstacles, by taking a

“leap of faith” in the “law of God”? Or shall we rather carry on the legacy of the previous

century, subordinating the human person to ends noble and ignoble, from lebensraum to a

Great Leap Forward to population control and even to happiness? What shall be the

paradox of the Twenty-first Century? Hopefully, it will be that, when given the sword, by

following the “law of God” we will turn swords into ploughshares.

In order to act, we must first know where we stand, and what is the nature of our

predicament. It is the aim of this thesis to argue that our predicament is a political

worldview begun in the Enlightenment. This worldview is so ubiquitous and so deeply

ingrained in our time that we scarcely perceive it as a worldview. This is the work of the

Enlightenment which brought about a revolution in perception, from a worldview in

which truth was ultimately found in God to one in which people could discover it

themselves through empirical investigation and rational analysis. The secularizing trend

in the Enlightenment has often been pointed out, but we shall look at that specifically, not

simply as a reduction of the power of the institutions of the Church and the monarchy as

revealers of truth, but as the creation of an entirely different value structure oriented

toward rational inquiry as the measure of truth. We will thus first explore this

phenomenon in the Enlightenment, drawing on several historians who looked broadly at

the period, such as Gay, Cassirer, Habermas, Adorno and Horkheimer, as well as the

Page 9: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

8

writings of certain philosophes (Kant, for his reflection on the period, and Rousseau for

his connection to the Revolution) in order to see not so much the individual philosophies

as the underlying framework with which people came to determine progress, truth, and

morality.

We shall then engage the French Revolution, that conjunction of political,

philosophical, religious and indeed all the energetic forces of humanity. The French

Revolution, now seen in a distinct historical bracket, in fact occurred contemporaneously

with the Enlightenment revolution, and therefore offers itself as one of the first

laboratories of the new framework of truth. Again, we shall not look for connections

between specific philosophies of the Enlightenment and beliefs or actions of the

revolutionaries, but rather we will examine how the political violence of the Jacobin

terror came to be justified within a worldview created by the Enlightenment.

This worldview still holds today, and thus we will return to our own time in the

third chapter, and engage with a number of commentators on twentieth century violence

(Hannah Arendt, Isaiah Berlin, Gregory Stanton, and Karol Wojtyla) whose analysis

offers some important insights on the workings of systematic violence. Drawing upon

these commentaries, we hope to provide an argument for how we may approach the

twenty-first century and avoid systematic murder without sacrificing the many positive

contributions of the Enlightenment. This is the vital question of our time, and we argue

that we cannot adequately answer it without recognizing the metaphysical framework

with which our political systems work were founded in the Enlightenment.

Camus adamantly supported the position of the Rebel, who neither gave into

totalitarian justification of murder, nor submitted to the idea of meaningless in the

Page 10: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

9

universe. Indeed, for Camus, rebellion was almost an ontological category (surprisingly

not unlike the ecclesial reality of Communion in the early Christian Church): “I rebel -

therefore we exist.”5 In any case, how can or ought the human person to address his time

today? He and she must rebel against the reductionist protocol and take, over any

constitution or declaration of rights, the Law of Human Dignity as his fundamental

foundation: when one is committed to loving one’s neighbor, ascribing rights (which are

in this view ways to respect the dignity of each human person, rather than empirical data

or means to attaining a utopia) to people and shunning violence are the rational steps. He

and she must insist that constitutions - “man-made codes” - be based firmly on the natural

law, not merely on empirical observation. But to do all this, the person must understand

the nature of this illusion, which we previously identified somehow as a post-

Enlightenment phenomenon (i.e., the rational holy war).

To this end we inspect the Enlightenment as a revolution of perception; a change,

not only in renewed and innovative (classical and modern) emphasis on the power of

human reason, but also in the way in which that reason could be used. The former change

has been well-documented since the Eighteenth Century, and indeed has been unjustly

(and perhaps narrow-mindedly) blamed for the godless evils which have afflicted the

human family in the last two hundred years. But such a charge is both simplistic and

unfair. The Enlightenment comprised such an eclectic collection of philosophies that it is

almost laughable to attribute the total wars of nationalism, pan-Germanism, Nazism,

Communism, revolutionary violence, and terrorism to soulless mechanical tautology.

Besides, the Enlightenment was neither soulless nor a tautology (can one seriously hold

this view and read Rousseau?). Furthermore, the technological progress encouraged and

5 Ibid., 22.

Page 11: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

10

enabled by the Enlightenment has greatly improved living standards around the world

and been used to oppose and depose evil regimes, as well as stoke the optimism which

was an important inspiration to this whole question.

No, we must view the Enlightenment as a revolution in perception: the new

emphasis on reason (which produced so many goods) was in part attributable (and

probably contributed to as well) to a new perception on the uses and boundaries of

reason. Here we shall argue that in the Enlightenment, for the first time Reason was not

only a useful tool (to learn about the universe and about God as in previous centuries) but

an end in itself: a goal to attain, which might of itself divulge moral norms or “truth

value” as well as factual values. We shall look at this Enlightenment proposal (the

illusion), and then at the Terror (which, if it was an excess, was nevertheless allowed by

reason) as a first example of rational holy war, the first crusade of the god called Reason.

Page 12: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

11

Chapter 1

The Enlightenment Revolution

“Enlightenment is man’s release from his self-incurred tutelage” said Kant in

1784 in his famed essay ‘What is Enlightenment?.’ It is difficult to speak of the Age of

Enlightenment in any but the broadest possible terms, and some historians have even

doubted whether it is meaningful to do so, given the enormous span of space, time,

history, philosophy, politics and economics, wars and revolutions that all fall under that

title. The list reads like a modern social studies curriculum. However, historians cannot

help but see in that long eighteenth century a certain something, or an uncertain

everything, that occurred in a tectonic scale and that has left its detectable marks upon

Europe and the rest of the world to this day. Indeed the shape of societies today can be

attributed to conditions and movements in the eighteenth century almost as the shape of

the universe today is traced to conditions and temperatures in its early form.6 The United

States of America, the United Nations, the democratic governments of European

countries and the constitutions of many nations in the world today can trace their origins

to the Enlightenment and to Enlightenment principles, and still other forms of

government whose principles are different were only possible in a post-Enlightenment

world. The principle mark of the Enlightenment that is pertinent to our overarching

question of modern systematic violence is the worldview that perceives truth as that

which is rational.

If Kant was answering the question, ’What is enlightenment?,’ we today are

6 See Foucault, ‘What is Enlightenment?’, in The Enlightenment: A Sourcebook and Reader, edited by

Paul Hyland, Olga Gomez, and Francesca Greensides, 398-400 (London and New York: Routledge, 2003)

and Postman, in Building a Bridge to the 18th

Century (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, Inc., 1999), especially

Chapter 1.

Page 13: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

12

trying to answer the question, ’What was the Enlightenment?’ Kant himself noted that his

was an “age of enlightenment,” and historians, whilst perhaps agreeing that the name is

still meaningful and worth keeping, now argue about which qualities are to be attached to

the name. In this question Peter Gay provides a sound articulation of the problem: how to

avoid “sacrificing unity to variety” (and by implication sacrificing the order which

historians study to chaos) while still respecting the variety.7 Gay has no use for

“interpretations that treat the Enlightenment as a compact body of doctrine” and notes

insightfully that “unity did not mean unanimity,” a statement which is surely reflective of

that age.8 The philosophes may have generally banded together, but they were not of one

“anima”--one soul or mind. And it is the philosophes we are chiefly interested in here in

this argument. Indeed this argument in a large way stems out of an understanding that

action follows from thought, individually and corporately, even given the effects of

environmental influences. Thus in inquiring into any historical action, we would look for

the primary “why” in the thought of the actors, even when their thought was responding

to outside forces. In this aspect of the Enlightenment, the “unity” of which Gay spoke

becomes important--not as a unity of doctrine surely, for the men of the Enlightenment

included Deists, Atheists, and even Christians. We speak here rather of a unity of

“value,” a common importance, so to speak, that marked the philosophes even in their

differences. As Gay puts it, “behind their tactical alliances and personal fellowship there

stood a common experience from which they constructed a coherent philosophy,” with

the common experience being an interest in antiquity, a clash with Christianity, and

progress toward modernity, and the coherent philosophy being what Gay calls “Modern

7 Gay, Peter, The Enlightenment: an Interpretation (New York and London: W.W. Norton and Company,

1966), X.

Page 14: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

13

Paganism.” 9 Whether one agrees with Gay’s determination--and he argues compellingly

for “paganism” as a meaningful and accurate name--we are here concerned with the

common value which gave the philosophy (or philosophies) of the Enlightenment its

coherence.

The common value of the Enlightenment was, simply put, enlightenment--freeing

oneself from the “self-incurred tutelage.” If this statement seems at first redundant or

barren, we must think a little deeper and longer upon its implications. We are taking the

philosophes at their own word (perhaps a dangerous thing for historians): we are

endorsing the century’s self-bestowed title of Enlightenment as its chief marker. As

distinct from pursuing the best economic system, the most honest metaphysical system,

or the fairest political system, the common value of that age was the pursuit of

enlightenment itself. Economic, philosophical, and political systems would reveal

themselves to be “good” or “bad” precisely in whether or not they were “enlightened.”

The image to envision here is the famous metaphor of the Cave from Plato’s The

Republic. Enlightenment is the person escaping the fetters, seeing the fire and the shapes

causing the shadows on the wall, climbing out of the Cave, seeing the reflection of the

form and then finally the form itself in the true light of day. There was no compact body

of doctrine held by the philosophes, no common idea of what the true form was, but each

of them insisted that his or her own particular doctrine was good because it was the way

to “get out of the cave”.

This was a profound revolution. The educated elite of this century wanted more

than anything to scatter the shadows of ignorance and (especially) superstition in order to

8 Gay, X & 4, respectively.

9 Gay, 8.

Page 15: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

14

grasp the truth about the world and about human nature. As Newton had done in the

world of physics, they sought to illuminate human nature. Pope’s witticism, “God said,

‘let Newton be,’ and all was light” was the hope concerning the dealings of the human

person, in the varied and opposing thoughts of the philosophes. Ernst Cassirer, a towering

figure in histories of the Enlightenment, writes that eighteenth-century philosophy was

“not content to look upon analysis as the great intellectual tool of mathematico-physical

knowledge; [it saw] analysis rather as the necessary and indispensable instrument of all

thinking in general.”10 Even in their disunity, this common hope gave coherence to the

philosophes. Thus Rousseau argued that only democracy could be just for people, while

to Kant limited civic freedom was necessary to extend personal enlightenment. But to

each the goal was personal freedom through breaking the shackles of enslavement of

thought. The goal of freedom itself was not revolutionary perhaps. The traditional

message of both Protestant and Catholic Christianity was personal salvation, freedom

from sin, etc. But ultimate freedom is not here on earth in Christian thought: eternal life,

at least in its fullness, is found after death in heaven. Freedom through enlightenment,

however, is more akin to classical Greek philosophy. While most of the philosophes

believed in God, he was a Deist sort of “supreme being,” the ultimate Truth sought by

Newton in his studies of physics and alchemy, the uncaused cause whose existence

Descartes had attempted to prove. As Socrates and Plato had moved from the idea of

gods who were themselves subject to the petty vices of mankind to a concept of spiritual

perfection, so the thought of the philosophes moved from the idea of a Trinity of persons

to the divinity of Reason itself. In the context of this extension of the Lutheran critique,

10

Cassirer, Ernst. “The Philosophy of the Enlightenment,” in The Enlightenment: A

Sourcebook and Reader, edited by Paul Hyland, Olga Gomez, and Francesca Greensides,

Page 16: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

15

the nuanced dogmas and doctrines of Christian belief, particularly in Catholic France,

became more and more removed from “the real.” As Luther had attacked the clerical

hierarchy as an unnecessary block between God and the human person, the philosophes

increasingly questioned the necessity of organized religion in the human person’s

approach to Reason. Enlightenment is a change in an individual mind, which is endowed

by the creator with the power of rational thought--Homo Sapiens, “thinking” or “rational”

human, was the term applied by Carl Von Linne to distinguish human beings among the

animal kingdom in his System of Nature. The philosophes did not all attack religion or the

clergy--Kant accepts that a clergyman will preach and teach--but the clerics themselves

must be enlightened, and the idea of going to a priest to have one’s sins forgiven was

surely the outgrowth of superstition and ignorance.

The depth of this revolution is clear: in the old Catholic worldview, Dante is

guided by Reason in the form of Virgil the classical poet in order to get to God, but in the

Feast of the Supreme Being during the French Revolution, Reason is God. The world of

antiquity was useful in helping to enlighten men to that fact, but man‘s salvation was to

be found in the pursuit of Reason.

In order to better understand the nature of this new worldview, we benefit from

extremely helpful argument by Neil Postman, a twentieth- and eighteenth-century

commentator. His insight is in fact vital to comprehending the reality of the illusion

unintentionally created by the philosophes Postman makes use of an insightful and

radical paradigm for analyzing social groups: insightful, because it is startlingly honest,

and radical because it applies old language to new ideas and constructs. In the beginning

of his book, The End of Education, Postman enters the topic of education by addressing

381-383 (London and New York: Routledge, 2003), 381.

Page 17: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

16

how not only schools but all elements of a society are fundamentally oriented toward a

particular end or goal. How many schools and programs begin with an orientation, how

many businesses place so much stress upon their mission statements, how many nations

and courts toil over the principles upon which their constitutions and laws are founded.

This sense of purpose is vital to human beings, and therefore to human institutions,

because humans have such an innate desire for meaning in a way that is truly unique.

Human beings not only feel pleasure, but joy because their pleasure is somehow

connected to their identity. Human beings not only feel pain, but they suffer because their

pain is connected to their consciousness, and their suffering is worst when it is apparently

meaningless. A person can accept suffering for a cause, can give up life to save others,

but the seemingly careless suffering of a medical mutation, natural catastrophe, or

meaningless murder…this suffering is truly and even ontologically intense, the kind that

shudders the core of a person, because it attacks that basic notion of meaning. The

strongest argument for atheism continues to be the problem of suffering. All this is to say:

whether there really is meaning in life and a connectedness between our own experiences

and the universe, humans desperately need meaning in order to function.11 Radically,

Postman uses the term “god” to describe this sort of meaning. A society needs a “god” in

order to function. Postman defines this god as “a transcendent spiritual idea that gives

purpose and clarity” and also “a great narrative, one that has sufficient credibility,

complexity, and symbolic power to enable one to organize one’s life around it.”12 The

word “god” is perhaps a little surprising in academic work today (not unlike Gay‘s

terming the philosophes “pagans“); it carries the baggage of superstition and lacks the

11

Postman notes that “the idea that there is order to the universe…is a fundamental

assumption of all important narratives” (9).

Page 18: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

17

intellectual rigorism of science, except perhaps in a study of cultural anthropology. But

Postman purposely chooses “god” over “narrative,” “end,” and other such terms to

describe this transcendental purpose in order to point out that even secular narratives such

us communism require “faith and dogma.”13 In this is Postman’s radicalism, for to

suggest that contemporary post-enlightenment societies rely on dogmas is, to use the old

expression, going out on a limb.

Indeed, Postman’s argument has particular importance to our own discussion, for

in looking at the Enlightenment, we are particularly focused on the common value (or

“god”) of the philosophes. When the old critics and reformers from Martin Luther to

Pierre Bayle to Locke, Voltaire, and Holbach attacked the dogmatism of religion, they

attacked it as a hindrance or a shadow that prevented people from learning the truth (of

the universe, of human nature, etc). But these very attacks rested on the assumption that

“truth” was to be found in scientific facts, which was a belief certainly not shared by the

episcopate. This consistency among their critiques points to a common “god,” though the

variety of the philosophes merits deeper study, which we shall soon engage.

A final important assertion by Postman is this: A society has a god whether it

knows it or not. As examples of this point, he notes the phenomena of Communism,

science, and technology. The communist narrative certainly rejected an idea of God, but

its understanding of politics, economics and society became in itself a god toward which

all aspects of social and government life were ordered. The gods of science and

technology are, similarly, often unconscious. Scientific and technological advances seem

to have nothing at all to do with faith or religious beliefs, but for that very reason people

12

Postman, 5 and 6, respectively. 13

Ibid.

Page 19: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

18

can turn to science for larger metaphysical answers. The purpose of life is progress:

learning how the world works, how to improve human standards of living, etc., are

“obviously” part of the road to progress. But that progress itself therefore is the god; in

this narrative, what is censored is questioning the “where” of progress: progress towards

what?

Aided by Postman’s paradigm, we shall look at the common value of the

philosophes in light of this idea of a god, which can ultimately be understood as a basis

and source of moral values. That is, what a person understands to be morally permissible

(or morally obligatory) depends upon his or her god. Thus the radical religious believer

can kill in the name of God, the radical social reformer can kill in the name of society,

and the organized crime thug can kill in the name of the family.14 In this manner, the

person does not deny the action or seek to demonstrate why this particular case is an

exception to the moral rule, but rather holds it as a good in the service of the god. Slavoj

Zizek, in his essay ‘Robespierre, or the “Divine Violence” of Terror,’ notes that in the

revolutionary logic, the necessary violence or terror must be “fully endorsed”15

Maximilien Robespierre articulated this idea famously in his speech to the Convention,

the purpose of which was, tellingly, to delineate the moral principles that should guide

the government. In that speech he declared that terror is justice; it is “an emanation of

virtue.”16

14

This was the major critique of Albert Camus in the twentieth century: that any system

which concedes murder has already nullified itself. He thus saw the only alternative to

the religious murder and godless murder to be the embracing of “the absurd.” See The

Rebel, Chapter 1. 15

Zizek, Slavoj, “Robespierre, or, the ‘Divine Violence’ of Terror,” in Virtue and

Terror, (New York: Verso, 2007), ix. 16

Robespierre, Maximilien, Virtue and Terror, ed. Slavoj Zizek and John Howe (New

York: Verso, 2007), 115.

Page 20: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

19

And here we truly come to the crux of the matter: the question of morality, which

may be outside the scope or expertise of history. But we must at least outline the

fundamental questions, and how they are important today by showing how they were

important yesterday. And the fundamental questions of morality may often be simplified

to a question of whether there is a fundamental moral law, or set of moral principles,

which are abstract and applicable in all places and times (what Zizek described as “a

virtual point of reference”),17 or whether the ideas of moral rules are merely the results of

the evolution of social groups and their need for compromising self-preservation and

group-preservation. Robespierre certainly appealed often to moral principles, a notion

consistent with his belief in the Supreme Being. But the reason this question of normative

ethics must enter our historical discussion is that of course if history is to inform our

thinking presumably there should be a reason for it doing so. And in this case in

discussing the workings of the intellectual revolution of the Enlightenment we hope to

draw meaning from them. For we do not mean here to trace the ideological origins of

terror--or presume that all evil comes from a single ideology--but we do want to think

about what makes a society susceptible to terror, particularly from the inside. A state of

moral anarchy is more or less a state of Nature, the ruthless arena of sinew, tooth, and

claw that Golding was working with in Lord of the Flies. But that is not the world of the

philosophes. The Enlightenment is often simplistically described as a movement toward

moral relativism, a reaction against the Thomistic and Scholastic tradition of objective

truth, but the philosophes in fact mostly believed in a Deity that would be un-phased by

the miniscule caprices of human civilization. Hobbes may have believed morality was

relative to each state, but by and large thinkers like Locke, Hume, Diderot, Voltaire, and

17

Zizek, xviii.

Page 21: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

20

Rousseau, even if they disagreed with one another and with traditional Christian thought

on what was moral behavior, held a concept of objective “inalienable” or

“imprescriptible” (a term used by Robespierre) rights and moral elements. However, the

way one came to know such rights (i.e. the difference between a right and a claim) was

through rational analysis (as opposed to, say, scripture or royal decree).

Thus this common value of the philosophes, this god of Reason if we may, was

one of rational morality, not the meaningless nihilism of later philosophers such as

Nietzsche. In keeping with the value of enlightenment, of getting out of the cave to be

able to see the truth, there was a true form of morality to be found. Though the Church

and establishment may have burned their books and found their ideas of permissible

sexual behavior to be perverse and dangerous, it is clearly inaccurate to denounce the

Enlightenment philosophes as unholy enemies of the Almighty and of moral society.

Unholy they may have been, and critiques of moral norms and teachings of the Church as

well, but generally they were theists (with exceptions like Holbach) and believers in

morality. Gay firmly forbids such oversimplification; though the philosophes may have

attacked religion and longed for secularism (generally) we cannot ignore their moral and

theistic beliefs. Such simplistic interpretations Gay calls “definition by larceny[:]…to

strip the Enlightenment of its wealth and then complain about its poverty.”18 Indeed the

philosophes often had very abstract humanitarian values, quite out of place in political

context of the wars of their time: “[the philosophe] would often exalt the interest of

mankind above the interest of country or clan.”19

The very fundamental principle of enlightenment, of personal intellectual (and

18

Gay, x. 19

Gay, 13.

Page 22: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

21

perhaps spiritual) freedom pre-assumed a moral value: that it is “good” for men and

women to be free. Kant of course, in ‘What is Enlightenment,’ accepts that the clergy

themselves may be vehicles of truth to the people, so long as the cleric remain true to his

“inner religion.”20 Rousseau begins his Contrat Social lamenting that “Man is born free,

and everywhere he is in chains”21; many philosophes in fact saw human beings in

thralldom of some kind--like Kant’s “tutelage“ or even Robespierre’s “habit”--and in

need of liberation.22 Thus the reaction against the Church in the Enlightenment may have

been irreligious, perhaps even immoral, but it was not amoral.

If the Enlightenment was not, after all, a clash between belief and unbelief,

between theism and atheism (as Robespierre suggested in some of his speeches23), how

does the question of morality fit into our discussion at present? To begin with, we must

be clear again that while the philosophes believed in morality and differed from the moral

code of the Church, they did not offer a unified opposing moral code, though they all

20

Kant, 56. Kant’s very reference to some sort of “inner religion” (we may perhaps

interpret this phrase as the conscience of an enlightened individual) points to an idea of a

truth “outside,” which religion seeks in degrees to uncover and conveys through

“symbol.” That he thought religion mere symbol is not so very important to us here as the

fact that he accepts a reality for which there can be symbols. 21

Rousseau, “Contrat Social,” in Political Philosophy (New York and Oxford: Oxford

University Press: 2005), 293. 22

Rousseau, Diderot, and others voiced a common idea of the corruption of Man, though

they differed as to which reasons the corruption was attributable. Rousseau certainly fears

the oppression of absolute rationality devoid of the phenomena of passion, sentiment, and

emotion, and he has been understood by some such as Gregory Dart to be a source for the

Romantics. Diderot was more likely to attribute corruption to the ideas of superstitious

religions. But whatever the cause, it is supremely remarkable that the philosophes found

themselves repeating Augustine’s concept of fallen nature, given their concern over the

Church keeping the common people in submissive obedience. Q 23

Robespierre attacked atheists as enemies of the people (as with most of his opponents),

saying “I do not speak…as a systematic philosopher but as a representative of the people.

Atheism is aristocratic. The conception of a great Being…is democratic.” Scurr, Ruth,

Fatal Purity, (New York: Metropolitan Books, Henry Holt and Company, LLC, 2006),

294.

Page 23: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

22

perhaps believed that they were referring to the same universal Reason as a means of

discovering morality. For instance, in the Supplement, Diderot effectively counsels

people to follow their instincts: his fictional Tahitian character says to the Catholic priest,

“Would you like to know what’s good and what’s bad in all times and places? Stick to

the nature of things and of actions….”24 Bentham, Kant, and others offer different (also

rational) means of discerning moral actions. The Church had also placed importance on

human reason in matters of morality, but the Church’s moral theologians were working

with an understanding of human nature as related in its scriptures and tradition (as

opposed to an understanding gained through pure rational analysis) and, as we shall see,

differing viewpoints on human nature lead to vastly different moral programs. Indeed, a

people’s understanding of human nature is very much related to the “god” it serves. To

Hegel the state is god; to Hegel the human person is the servant of the state. To the

gospel-writer John God is Love; the human person is a beloved child of God. As we can

see, this distinction is cardinal to any moral program. And therefore the reason the moral

question is important is that, whether there is an objective morality which the human

person is capable of attaining or not, the understanding thereof which a person or

community of persons has will influence his or its praxis of action. In other words,

ethicists and philosophers may argue over whether we may pass moral judgment on other

cultures, but for our purposes here, any picture of a society (especially of a political

program within a society) must be informed by the understanding of morality of that

culture in terms of its god and its understanding of the purpose and place of the human

24

Diderot, Denis, “Supplement to the Voyage of Bougainville,” in The Enlightenment: A

Sourcebook and Reader, edited by Paul Hyland, Olga Gomez, and Francesca Greensides,

320-327 (London and New York: Routledge, 2003), 324.

Page 24: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

23

person.25

In the historical picture of the eighteenth century western elite, the philosophes

did not argue that there was no such thing as objective morality or that it cannot be

known, but that they had already discovered it: Reason is god, and therefore Reason

determines moral standards. Few if any philosophes26 argued for complete moral

relativity. It was far more typical for them to decry the evils of their age and proclaim

they had discovered diagnosis of society’s ills.

So the philosophes had found their god, and had found that their god’s dogmas

and commandments taught men and women how to eliminate the evils of society. If there

were yet some ills that seemed beyond the skill of man, these could conceivably be

solved if only more intensive study and thought were applied. It was the Church that was

hindering the innoculations against smallpox in Paris;27 the cure to this disease was found

not in faith in God but through practical rational experiment. The same methods,

employed by the American philosophe Benjamin Franklin, soundly demonstrated the

difference between spurious mesmerism and experimental electricity and magnetism.

Even churchmen such as John Toland and Bishop Butler, amongst whom their was much

disagreement, sought to look at the scriptures through the lens of rational skepticism.

That the philosophes chose Reason for a god may be interesting, but is it so very

25

Here, for instance, we argue that the historical analysis of Marx is flawed in not taking into account the

moral dimension. This is not to say that his philosophy or his economic theory was wrong because it was

materialistic and atheistic, but rather that his understanding of history did not use all the data. Whether

morality is objective or relative, historical analysis must include societal ideas on morality. A paradigm of

class warfare is missing the moral dimension of the classes, the god each serves and the willingness of each

to subordinate the human person to the good of the class. To reiterate, this is not a question of philosophy,

but of historical understanding; indeed, it is to say that philosophy is important in the historical picture just

as is class inequity, social movements, the arts, etc. (This is not a particularly bold claim, but yet a

necessary rule nonetheless: thought precedes action). 26

Perhaps Hobbes came closest in Leviathan, though even there it is debatable whether

he was a complete relativist, as he claimed moral authority in the sovereign.

Page 25: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

24

revolutionary? Was it not part of the great march of progress of humanity from ignorance

to knowledge? A great many philosophes seemed to believe in this idea of progress. Was

the Age of the Enlightenment not just another step in mankind’s evolution, or if one takes

a less optimistic view of human history and doubts progress, was it not simply another

religious narrative? Using language such as Postman’s “god” surely seems to suggest

such a notion. But the claim of Reason as god was truly different in a wholly new, earth-

shaking way. In polytheistic cultures the gods are often fickle, and fight with one another,

and it is up to men and women like Odysseus and Brynhildr to take sides as with a petty

warlord. Often with the non-personal cosmic gods of eastern traditions, a pure

transcendent truth is the ultimate goal, and a good life is ordered toward achieving that

cosmic union. In the great monotheistic religions like Islam and Judaism, the goal of life

is to serve and praise God, perhaps with the hope of life after death in blissful paradise. In

the theology of Christianity, the dominant belief system in Europe at the time of the

Enlightenment, the full life was one participating in the life of the Church and in service

of God and the community.28 The god of Reason was a radical break from each of these.

Where a Moslem, a Jew, or even an unscrupulous, amoral Italian prince knew why he

acted and what was his ultimate goal (serving Allah or ruling the city-state), the servant

of Reason knew only how he was supposed to act, not why. An astrologer and an

astronomer both probe the depths of the heavens and ponder their meaning, yet only the

astronomer could be an honest philosophe, free from the constraints of superstition and

swelling the library of human knowledge. Indeed, for the realm of science, this approach

produced wonders in the Scientific Revolution from which the philosophes of the

27

Gay, 15-17. 28

Obviously the beliefs and actions of individual Christians and even larger elements

Page 26: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

25

eighteenth century were benefiting, as well as in recent advances in medicine through the

use of experimentation. Ernst Cassirer comments, “However much individual thinkers

and schools differ in their results, they agree in this epistemological premise. Voltaire’s

Treatise on Metaphysics, d’Alembert’s Preliminary Discourse, and Kant’s Inquiry

concerning the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality all concur on this point. All

these works represent the true method of metaphysics as in fundamental agreement with

the method which Newton, with such fruitful results, introduced into natural science.”29

Thus this god did indeed seem to be delivering into the hands of enlightened persons not

only miracles, but the power to work them.

But again, this power did not come attached to moral imperatives and

prohibitions, but relied on the already-held notions of its new recipients. In this way, this

new power was not different in kind but only in degree from all earlier advances in

civilization, from the development of strong metals to advances in mathematics to

achievements in engineering and architecture. It can even be useful to view historical

movements through the lens of technology, in that many conquests (military or

otherwise)--from the Hittite civilization in Sumeria to the more recent colonization of the

New World by the European powers--hinged upon technological advantages. Now,

however, the method--or rather the methodology--of improvement was hailed as god. In

the great sixteenth century clashes between Catholic Europe and the Ottoman Empire in

the Mediterranean, the wars provided great impetus for improvements in military and

nautical technology, from the better rifles of the janissaries to the table-turning Venetian

galleons of Lepanto. But throughout the long unrelenting wars of that century in that

within the Church at the time were not in accord with its professed theology. 29

Cassirer, 381.

Page 27: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

26

theater, such improvements were received by each force and each emperor as a new tool

in the service of their gods.30

Neither the Moslem nor the Christian would ever confuse

the power to advance with God himself, whose kingdom each was apparently in the

business of expanding. But the philosophe’s crusade was expanding the kingdom of

enlightenment.31

The new emphasis on rational analysis raised it from “a means to an

end” to “an end” in itself.

Like the aforementioned technological lens, the rational paradigm also offered an

apparently comprehensive scheme of history. Human beings of every culture have moved

slowly toward enlightenment, in a progress which is natural according to Kant: “If only

freedom is granted, enlightenment is almost sure to follow.”32 Religious beliefs were but

a primitive attempt at explaining the world, but which nevertheless bore the mark of the

human person’s innate notion of and desire for the perfection ultimately attained through

rational inquiry. And now, in this self-proclaimed Age of Philosophy, Reason, and

Enlightenment, humanity was finally throwing off the vestiges of the primitive

explanations. This vein of thought was especially pronounced in the more radical atheists

such as Holbach and Hume, but even the Christian philosophes found themselves

defending Christianity, not as the means to salvation, but as a rational worldview. This

had of course been carried out in earlier ages by Aquinas, Anselm, Augustine, Ambrose,

etc., but they had sought to show that the attacks upon their faith were unfounded,

30

Those gods may or may not have been Allah/God; political and financial power seem to have also been

of interest to the Sultan and the Holy Roman Emperor. Roger Crowley’s Empires of the Sea offers not only

a riveting story but an educational look at the relevance of technological advances in the Islamic/Christian

contest, a premodern war strikingly similar to modern total wars ordinarily thought to have begun with

Napoleon. 31

Gay notes that in Kant’s vision of a “revolt against superstition” we see the belief of those crusaders of

light: they “were sure they were the men who were bringing light to others; with sublime self-

satisfaction…they praised their age as an Age of Philosophy” (Gay, 21). 32

Kant, 55.

Page 28: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

27

whereas the Christian philosophes of the eighteenth century (among whom were varied

thinkers such as Locke, Bishop Butler, Bayle, Toland, and even perhaps Newton) meant

to clean up a wrinkled old orthodoxy and present it as a viable option for the enlightened

person. Consider here Thomas Jefferson’s translation of the New Testament in which he

removed any references to the miraculous. This sort of sentiment found more welcome in

Protestant thought (indeed it truly sprang from a uniquely Protestant paradigm through

the types of criticism offered by Luther, Bayle, Toland and others)33 than in the Catholic

faith, which still held the mysteries of the Trinity, transubstantiation, and others as central

to the faith (a stance which obviously could not be wholly comfortable with Toland’s

Christianity Not Mysterious). The reasonableness of God was more important than any

other attributes.

Thus to the philosophe, even to the apparently34 Christian philosophe, explaining

the world was most important, and there was no room for mystery and miracle. Hume’s

writings on miracles are typical of the philosophes’ mindset, in that nothing has

miraculous origin; if phenomena appear to be miraculous, “philosophers … ought to

search for the causes whence it might be derived,”35 and so scientifically learn the true

nature of the phenomenon. We can thus see that rational thought carries with it its own

moral values, or rather its derivation does: it is preferable to be rational than to be

irrational. Again, there is no great shift in that preference, but if Reason is god, then there

33

Crocker III, H.W., Triumph, (Roseville, California: Prima Publishing Forum, 2001),

324-326. 34

While there is room for doctrinal argument within Christian groups, to be included in

‘Christian groups’ one must at least profess to be a follower of Christ. Thus even without

taking any one particular set of Christian beliefs, we can fairly confidently state that

certain thinkers like Newton or Descartes were more intent on proving God’s existence

than on loving him; neither Newton or Descartes wrote poetry about God. 35

Gay, 146 [from Hume’s “Essay on Miracles”].

Page 29: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

28

are no other moral standards (discernable through rational inquiry alone). The revolution

of the Enlightenment was not a new penchant for rational thought, but a dispensation of

attachments to other values. That is the revolution.

* * *

The historical debates about the Enlightenment and its legacy have in large part

been concerned either with it as unified body of doctrine whose flaws led to the radical

“excesses” of the Terror and even of later totalitarian horrors, or as a disconnected

collection of eclectic thinkers with varying goals, or else as an unfinished and

misunderstood project. We are particularly concerned with this last view, offered by

Jurgen Habermas in that last century,36

because it seems to have most hold in our present

civilization, and we shall engage it more thoroughly in chapter V.37 The Marxist historical

picture, being materialistic in its philosophical grounding, focused less on the importance

of the intellectual “roots” of the Revolution that reached deep into the Enlightenment and

beyond. Marx and what became known as the “leftist” (another tribute to the Revolution

itself) historians were more focused on “the facts,” as Timothy Tackett, a more recent

American contributor to the debate writes in his chapter entitled “A Revolution of the

Mind?”38

Tackett himself, whose work represents an in-depth exploration of the personal

36

Jurgen Habermas, in “The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere,” in The Enlightenment: A

Sourcebook and Reader, edited by Paul Hyland, Olga Gomez, and Francesca Greensides (London and New

York: Routledge, 2003), argues how it was in fact through the discourses in the public sphere made

possible during the eighteenth century that ordinary illiterate people developed a sense of autonomy and

other human values, and, in fact, “in a word, humanity” (389). 37

In terms of our present civilization, we speak here along the lines of the current “taste”

described by Zizek as “the name for a basic ideological disposition” Whether or not most

people (or even most political leaders) have studied the Enlightenment and come to their

own conclusions, the “rules of the game” in the public square in most democratic

countries have consciously or unconsciously adopted the “Enlightenment value” as the

rational means of escaping religious, absolutist limits on personal freedom. 38

Tackett, Timothy. Becoming a Revolutionary. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), 48-76.

Page 30: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

29

writings left by the deputies themselves, suggests that philosophical leanings were not

very good predictors of revolutionary (and specifically violent) behavior. Nevertheless,

philosophy played an important role, as we shall discuss (Indeed, the very fact that

disciples of particular philosophes ended up in opposing factions is one of the results of

choosing Reason as god), since it was not the particular philosophy or theory of

metaphysics that shaped the culture and the political structure, but the notion that reason

was the assurance of truth, and this was a “revolution of mind.”

Since our present argument will investigate the Terror as a result of the

Enlightenment Revolution, it may be supposed that we should side with Furet’s

description of the discourses of the Enlightenment, or with Adorno’s and Horkheimer’s

mathematical dialectic paradigm, both of which posit the strict logic which produced the

Terror. However, the view of the Enlightenment as a varied collection of thinkers bound

loosely by the value of “getting out of the cave” is what we work with here. To describe

the Enlightenment as a strict logic is to fall prey to the simplistic explanations Gay

warned us of. To see it as an unfinished project is to fall prey to the mistaken vision of

the philosophes themselves (but we shall arrive there in due time).

In the “strict logic” view, terror is seen as the unavoidable result of ideological

roots in the Enlightenment. Beginning soon after the oft-invoked “excesses” of the

Terror, thinkers on what became the Right linked the new absolutism of the Jacobins, not

with the old absolutism of the Monarchs, but with the liberal-minded philosophes who

had so undermined the intellectual and spiritual foundations for “l’Estate c’est moi”.

Edmund Burke was perhaps the first to articulate these ideas, and the legacy of the

Jacobin administration or regime has been contested ground ever since, the ebb and flow

Page 31: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

30

of the battle lines reflecting changing political climes in which historians wrote. Thus

under the counterpart “excesses” of the Industrial Revolution, the age of the Robber

Barons and mass labor, the interpretations steered away from Burke and were a little

more willing to believe Marx’s depiction of class revolution over the injustices of

inequality. Such Left-leaning interpretations were not ameliorated by the horrific blow

Europe suffered in its First World War, when millions perished for such paltry

motivations--“lions led by lambs” “even for an eggshell.” After the ghastly, yet

systematic experiences of the Second World War (and possibly on the brink of a Third)

Theodor W. Adorno and Max Horkheimer moved back to a vision of the totalitarian logic

of a single enlightenment ideology. For the atrocities of this war had been ruthless and

calculated, not mindless and blind as in 1915. Now Adorno and Horkheimer described

enlightenment, not as illuminating the darkness of ignorance, but as “mathematical

procedure.” To them, the philosophes saw truth as information, and wisdom as

information processing (one also notes the historical context of psychology and early

computers that brought along Alan Turing’s philosophical questioning of the human

mind as a computer): enlightenment “turns thought into a thing, and instrument - which is

its own term for it… [T]hought becomes mere tautology.”39 In the succeeding years, the

world struggled in an East-West paradigm in which both sides seemed to be moving

inexorably toward an end they both feared. In such a context of super-militarization,

Peter Gay published in 1969 a renewed picture of the philosophes (one which would

perhaps have pleased them most) as “modern pagans,” thinkers who valued human rights

above ideology and were cosmopolitan citizens of the world. They were willing to both

39

Adorno, Theodor and Max Horkheimer, “The Dialectic of Enlightenment,” in The

Enlightenment: A Sourcebook and Reader, edited by Paul Hyland, Olga Gomez, and

Page 32: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

31

enter non-Western perspectives and defend non-Western rights. More recent historians40

have returned again to study of the popular and official terror, and in a post-September

11th

world, observers such as Slavoj Zizek return to the terror of the French Revolution to

try and make sense of the current picture in light of the past.

The above interpretations are not to be glossed over as historical and political

thermometers, however, for they do raise important questions. Hopefully our present

conception of a common value (getting out of the cave) without a single body of dogma

can provide a connecting thread through the commentaries that neither sacrifices unity to

variety nor succumbs to definition by larceny. Thus we should not dismiss Adorno and

Horkheimer as mere “polemic,” as did Porter, because they take too great liberties with

the beliefs of the philosophes. Their criticism depicts the world of the philosophe as an

amoral world, a world without right or wrong but rather correctly calculated or

incorrectly calculated. (Here remember Hume’s reasoning for not believing in miracles:

not [if we take him at his word] through emotional distaste for religion, but through

careful weighing of probabilities). Thus if Adorno’s and Horkheimer’s blanket argument

fails to do justice to the beliefs of Rousseau, Voltaire, and Diderot, they still posit a stern

and immovable truth that applies to the common value of enlightenment: if one believes

that moral truth is found through human rational thinking, one risks conflating “truth”

with “fact” and subordinating other human values to the value of enlightenment. This is

indeed the central problem with the god of Reason.

Comments on other interpretations. Cassirer “analysis” as the “necessary and

Francesca Greensides (London and New York: Routledge, 2003), 385. 40

See Jean-Clement Martin, Violence and Revolution: an Essay on the Birth of a National Myth, (Paris:

Editions du Seui, 2006), who shows “that popular violence was considerably more brutal than is usually

thought and that the political elite’s relation to it was considerably more compromised and opportunistic,”

Page 33: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

32

indispensable instrument of all thinking” - philosophes redefining thinking. Good/bad?

Now, if we cannot hold that the Enlightenment was a body of values which lead

to dystopia, should we not then turn to the liberal Habermasian view that “enlightenment”

is a value toward which we must still work, but which was in fact ignored by the dictators

of the past two centuries. After all, was Stalin “enlightened”? One certainly cannot pin

his horrific programs of mass murder and mass terror to the Enlightenment thinkers. And

as Roy Porter wrote, “the Nazis loathed the philosophes.”41 Had the philosophes not

decried such madness, as had Montesquieu, Voltaire, and other satirists? The

contemporary thinker Slavoj Zizek offers an adamant rebuttal to this platform of such

“sensitive liberals” in his essay Robespierre, or, the ‘Divine Violence’ of Terror, in which

he defends the radical Left.42 But as Zizek’s argument deals intensively with moral values

(particularly those of Robespierre) and we are not yet concerned with specific moral

values, we must wait to engage with him until we begin the case study of the Terror as a

result of serving the blind god Reason. For now we shall merely engage Habermas’s

unfinished project question.

We do not necessarily need to agree with Habermas’s value judgment on

enlightenment, while still distancing ourselves from the simplistic approach. This is

because, viewing the philosophes as a body of thinkers with varied goals, we see the true

(and most important) character of accepting ratio dominum est. Michel Foucault, who,

like Porter, does not like to be “‘for’ or ‘against’ the Enlightenment,” insightfully

remarked that the value of enlightenment “is not faithfulness to doctrinal elements, but

in Sutherland’s review. 41

Porter, in The Enlightenment: A Sourcebook and Reader, edited by Paul Hyland, Olga

Gomez, and Francesca Greensides (London and New York: Routledge, 2003), 379. 42

Zizek, vii.

Page 34: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

33

rather the permanent reactivation of an attitude.” However, while Foucault identifies that

attitude as a “permanent critique” of society, we must agree with Gay (and others) that

the philosophes were not merely destructive, but were also seeking to create a uniquely

modern and uniquely true society, in the sense that it be founded on verified truths rather

than on unverified traditions. Constant self-examination is of course essential, but it is not

the end in this scheme, only a means. But we may agree with Foucault that the common

value of enlightenment did not in fact unite the philosophes in a common understanding

of morality. The dictum to keep going forward with one’s eyes open did not entail that all

need be walking in the same direction.

Thus, while Habermas offers important constructive counsel to use a more

comprehensive spectrum of historical study in terms of social context, his “unfinished

project” idea falls prey to the same flaws as the original Enlightenment Revolution.

Nietzsche remarked “he who has a why to live can bear with almost any how,” but in

“enlightenment cave paradigm” we forget Nietzsche’s “why,” and get caught up in the

“how” of living. Most importantly its surface-level anthropology is still “homo sapiens” -

- that is, the human person is a rational entity (rather than, say, a relational being). This

surface-level anthropology can be harnessed to many competing philosophies for good or

ill, from Hegel’s to Marx’s to Ghandi’s. For if the human person is viewed in terms of

rationality, quality-of-life categorization immediately comes into play, the basis for the

mathematical murder that Camus warned against. As we noted above [note 26], this

anthropology is the modus operandi of mainstream social and political philosophy today;

the legitimacy for law is accepted to be its rational justifiability (whether followed in

practice or not). as witnessed by the importance placed upon secular measures and

Page 35: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

34

policies that are born out of the idea of a “neutral” secular moral system. Thus we have

returned to Postman’s “god.”

Reason is a unique choice for a god, in that so many of its followers could have

such contradictory beliefs. This is different from differing schools of theology within

Islam, Christianity, or Judaism, because each school has a different understanding of who

God is or of who the human person is. But the philosophes all understood what reason

was, and even more, they understood in common what was required to serve reason. The

problem here was that reason itself could serve different ends. This is in fact the crux of

the matter, the reason the Enlightenment was truly revolutionary. For the first time, men

and women placed their faith in something which was not an end in itself to be served.

And because of the nature of reason, they did not perceive their own faith. They

considered themselves to have “true knowledge” requiring no leaps of faith. What the

philosophes in essence had was a faith without dogmas. With belief in rational

secularism, there’s no room for dogmas.

We would like to argue that the community of the philosophes held a common

god of rational thinking as a means to truth, and therefore had also a illusory notion that

they also believed in a common truth. In reality, and as witnessed by their many differing

personal philosophies, each had his own conception of what “truth” meant. Consider

Hume, or the mechanical philosophers, whose idea of truth was the discovery of the

causal mechanics of the universe, or Rousseau, to whom truth was what we might call the

virtuous life which individuals should strive for but which was discovered not through

mores handed down from frowning clerics but through introspection and embracing the

Page 36: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

35

“the order of nature” and “a well-regarded natural instinct.”43 Rousseau’s thought is

particularly illustrative of this Enlightenment phenomena, as so many of his ideas are so

near to traditional Church teaching. Where the Church taught of the person’s inclination

to sin as a result of separation from God, Rousseau held that people were everywhere

corrupt because of social constructs (Social Contrat: “Man is born free, and everywhere

he is in chains”; Emile: “Everything is good as it leaves the hands of the Author of things;

everything degenerates in the hands of man.”). While his ideas on moral behaviors were

grounded in both observation and his “innate sense of truth or falsehood,” the Church

included what it saw as the testimony of scripture in its empirical evidence, and held that

the “innate sense” was the indelible mark of a Creator, but that such a sense could be

dulled by sin and so create a need for an authority.44 But in Rousseau’s thought and in the

thought of the philosophes natural reason lights the way to an ideal state. However, the

vision of the ideal state was unique to each. Thus Reason was only an imagined god.

It may seem paradoxical to use Rousseau as an example of a rational paradigm,

and certainly he does not fit the strict computational mathematics of Adorno and

Horkheimer. It was Rousseau after all who said of the philosophes, “I found them vain,

dogmatical and dictatorial... Ignorant of nothing, yet proving nothing.”45 It was Rousseau

who so doggedly fought against the subtle arguments of rationality and distrusted the

philosophe’s good intentions, asking “Where is the philosopher who would not readily

deceive mankind, to increase his own reputation?”46 Nevertheless, though at odds with

43

Rousseau, Jean Jacques. Profession of Faith of a Savoyard Vicar. Vol. XXXIV, Part 4.

The Harvard Classics. New York: P.F. Collier & Son, 1909–14; Bartleby.com, 2001.

www.bartleby.com/34/4/. [accessed January 27, 2010], paragraph 3.Paragraph 3. 44

Ibid. 17. 45

Ibid. 12. 46

Ibid. 14.

Page 37: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

36

the philosophes and an opponent of soulless mechanistic philosophy, Rousseau in fact

disagreed only in detail with the Rationalist view, and still held to the god of Reason. For

to Rousseau, Nature was the great revealer of truth, and what he disdained about the

philosophes was inscrutability and distance of their thought from the reality of

experience; he faulted them for failing to take into account the experiential data of human

passions. In his Profession of a Savoyard Priest, after proclaiming that moral rules not

based on Nature will come to naught, “how strongly soever prohibited by reason,” he

then builds his own system by saying “The love of Truth comprises all my philosophy.”47

His Profession reminds one very much of Diderot’s Supplement, and taken with his ideas

of Nature, education, corruption, and proper government, we see that his thought too

takes up the belief that the human person has the wherewithal (“the simple and easy rule

of common sense”48 ) and desire to overcome the ills of life and create an ideal society.

And though he separates “reason” from his own natural common sense, he holds the

common value of enlightenment: that the application of one’s natural rational faculties

will produce a utopia.

We finish this chapter with regard given to Rousseau because he had such a

strong impact on the thought of the men and women of the French Revolution, which is

often seen as the culminating mark of the Enlightenment. His impact on Robespierre was

very marked in terms of political thought in the idea of the Republic of virtue, but also

(and perhaps more importantly) in the almost spiritual reverence for the pure, simple

virtue of the common people, whom Robespierre adored in the abstract. The illusory god

of Reason could lead a thousand persons in a thousand different directions, as in the past

47

Ibid. 3, 18. 48

Ibid. 18.

Page 38: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

37

a thousand local gods had, but now the individuals all thought they were moving in a

common direction, toward a common, true, modern state.

* * *

What come into play, then, under the god of Reason are anthropologies. Because

rational analysis or common sense can lead to different ends, what determines those ends

are the notions of the ideal and of human nature which a person brings with him or her

into analysis, the premises to which a person applies reason. Thus, given an input with

notions of human rights, common sense yields behavior in keeping with such rights.

However, in a system like that of Hobbes or Hegel, where morality is essentially

determined by the state, human rights and even the human person may subordinated

within reason toward the goal of creating a utopia. When such a step happens, the

justification of murder becomes possible, which Camus so abhorred: “…as soon as a

man, through lack of character, takes refuge in doctrine, as soon as crime reasons about

itself, it multiplies like reason itself and assumes all the aspects of the syllogism.”49 This

danger which Camus (and many others) so feared must be recognized even today, for it

has the potential for major human consequences. To observe these consequences we shall

look at the “excess” of the Terror, after which we shall consider the state of the

framework of law in the global community today, which is arguably “post-

Enlightenment” in identity and values. As rational analysis leaves room for a variety of

moral systems (witnessed by the Nuremburg investigations and the founding documents

of the UN, which emphasized the need for an accepted basic moral system) current

constitutional governments are obliged to consider this reality.

49

Camus, 3.

Page 39: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

38

Chapter 2

Robespierre and Reason

On June 8 (20 Prairial in the Revolutionary Calendar), 1794, the First Republic of

France under the National Convention held a revolutionary holy day: the Festival of the

Supreme Being, a feast in celebration of a god created in the image and likeness of the

revolutionaries. L’etre Suprême was a god of Reason, represented in the festival as a

classical goddess under the name of Wisdom - the sublime beauty of the feminine form

was a more fitting image for pure reason than the rough and wounded body of a Jewish

carpenter. In honoring a god fashioned after the taste of the Eighteenth Century, the

revolutionaries were ironically almost praising their own enlightenment more than any

being outside themselves. Robespierre called that day “fortunate,” because on that day

the French people (“the most interesting part of humanity”) gathered to “offer to the

Author of Nature the only homage worthy of him.” The Enlightenment critique had come

full circle, for the worshippers of Reason now preached as hegemonic a dogma as had

ever a religious zealot, if not more so, for by laying claim to the only worthy method of

worship Robespierre dismissed all other religious cults of worship practiced by

humankind.

Throughout the day, the French people - the “benefactors of mankind” - led by

Robespierre celebrated and honored divine Reason. Robespierre was perhaps priestly in

that he acted symbolically for the people, burning a statue of atheism to reveal Wisdom in

its place,50

but he was not a priest in the sense of acting on behalf of a fallen or powerless

50

It would perhaps be thought that the atheistic Cult of Reason of the Hebertists would pose a better

example of the moral revolution, but Robespierre’s cult serves just as well if not better, by avoiding

painting the secularization of the Revolution in simplistic terms. There was variety in the Revolution, as

there had been in the Enlightenment (as Timothy Tackett reveals in Becoming a Revolutionary, Chapter 2),

Page 40: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

39

humanity in pleading to the gods for mercy or good harvests. Here, the human person’s

release from self-imposed tutelage was central. If the human person was enlightened by

Reason, then the Supreme Being was honored. Thus the new religion was a celebration of

human enlightenment, and fittingly the new hymns were to France herself as well as to

Reason. Robespierre led the deputies then from Reason to Liberty, as they processed to a

manufactured mountain, at the top of which was a Liberty Tree. Two days later,

Robespierre led the Committee of Public Safety in passing the infamous Law of 22

Prairial, which ushered in the climax of what has come to be known as the Reign of

Terror. In the thirty-seven days following the Festival of the Supreme Being, 1,376

people were sent to the guillotine in Paris alone.

The monumental irony of these events which offer themselves as drama provides

a symbolic example of the contradictions of the Terror. To understand Robespierre

himself and the means by which he and the Jacobins brought about the Reign of Terror

we will look at biographical material (Ruth Scurr) and at Robespierre’s own speeches, as

well as the analysis of the Jacobin rational offered by Slavoj Zizek’s and Dan Edelstein’s

work on the justifications for terror. It becomes apparent that the contradictions of the

Revolution are the contradictions of the Enlightenment revolution, and thus the Reign of

Terror offers much clarity to our question of systematic violence.

***

June and July of 1794 saw the peak of the violence of the Terror, but as a whole it

took rather longer, lasting from late 1793 to July 27, 1794, when Robespierre was

arrested. To the economic historian,51

the Terror was simply another bungled attempt to

and Robespierre himself decried atheism (see Scurr, 293-296, 320-321). 51

Marx, of course, provides the classic linear historical model in which the tensions of human interaction

Page 41: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

40

solve the economic problems which had plagued Louis XVI: bankruptcy, bad harvests,

skyrocketing bread prices. To address popular unrest, Louis had attempted to institute a

tax on the nobility, and had then been pressured into calling the Estates-General to decide

the issue. Here the nobility were met with a host of young bourgeois professionals, more

educated and literate at a higher rate than ever before, and talented at argument and

debate through training in the legal courts, the clubs, lodges, and societies, as well as the

taverns--venues that formed a strong component of the “public sphere.”52

The clerical

and noble estates proved to be unprepared for such an intellectual onslaught, riding on the

momentum of more than a century of reaction to supernatural explanations of any sort

and especially to the Divine Right of kings and Divine Revelation. The political unrest of

what swiftly became a political revolution only exacerbated the economic turmoil, adding

new fear to the mob as the foreign powers arrayed themselves for war to protect the

ancien regime. And as the people who were lowest on the economic ladder perceived that

a democracy was as impotent as a monarchy when it came to putting bread on the table,

the new class of politicians found themselves between the hammer of foreign invasion

and the anvil of insurrection. In this climate the radicals such as Danton, Marat, and

Robespierre appeared to be the side willing to actually do something to save France, and

in their polemics the Jacobins did much to support this picture by presenting their

opponents as self-interested. Such self-interest was antithetical to a Republic of Virtue,

and therefore France had to be protected from her enemies with decisive force.

Robespierre had no thirst for blood, unless it be the blood of the enemies of his vision of

and use of environmental resources moves naturally towards equilibrium: to him, in the Communist state.

See also Timothy Tackett, Becoming a Revolutionary, especially Chapter 4. 52

See Jurgen Habermas classic work which examines the role of social phenomena in preparing for the

political revolution.

Page 42: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

41

France - as a young lawyer in Artois he had been repulsed by the death penalty even for

the guilty. In his mind he had no choice but to employ terror to preserve the Republic for

the good of the people.

We emphasize that Robespierre saw himself as without choice because it is

important to note that he was not choosing between Terror on the one hand and peace on

the other. Most famously, he declared, “If the mainspring of popular government in time

of peace is virtue, then the mainspring of government in time of war is virtue and terror:

terror, without which virtue has no force, and virtue, without which terror is disastrous.”

These words are unnerving to the modern ear, which has associated terror and terrorism

with evil excesses and crimes against humanity, but to Robespierre terror was a defense

against such crimes and excesses. Terror was not merely a more effective way; it was the

only way. Given Robespierre’s assumptions - his “faith” so to speak, that the happiness

and goal of humanity was to be found in the republic based on virtue (“Virtue produces

happiness as the sun produces light”53

) - we can understand how he was able to marry the

contradictory beliefs in the Declaration on the one hand and in the use of terror on the

other. As a young representative from Arras to the Estates-General, he wrote to the King

to encourage him to “to lead men to happiness through virtue, and to virtue by legislation

founded on eternal principles of justice and so framed as to restore human nature to all its

rights and all its dignity.” More importantly, he noted that this task could be achieved by

“by removing all the causes of oppression.”54

Although he probably did not yet have

revolution in mind as a means of removing such causes (in Arras he had written that “it is

53

Scurr, 47. 54

Scurr, 57.

Page 43: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

42

dangerous to look for the remedy for a specific ill in a general revolution”55

) he did

believe that laws based on eternal principles could form virtue, and that therefore those

laws were the primary function and goal of government.

Here the Enlightenment Revolution’s influence made itself felt. There was no set

of Enlightenment principles (save perhaps that of “being enlightened” - that is, thinking

for oneself, and basing one’s decisions on rational analysis); but there was an idea that

Reason would lead to such principles. With no agreed-upon moral laws, the course of the

nation was left to the competing interests of the representatives in the Convention. This

revolution left, in effect, a kind of power vacuum, in that the guiding principles of a state

would now be those of the sovereign: Cuius regio, eius religio.56

As the legislators in

power were the Jacobins, it was their primary beliefs which became the guiding beliefs.

A parallel situation in fact occurred politically in the French Revolution in that the

various legislative bodies which succeeded the Monarchy all feared an executive power

becoming another absolute tyrant, and so never legislated specifically for powers

executive. In this power vacuum, a strong Committee or a strong, driven personality

could effectively take that power.

***

Historians have often approached the Terror in one of two ways: we must either

view Robespierre as a mad fanatic (and perhaps the first modern dictator) who hijacked

the language of reason, rights, and revolution in order to pursue his own ideological ends,

or we must take Robespierre at his word and view the Terror as, in fact, an application of

natural reason. We here argue for the second view: whether or not Robespierre departed

55

Scurr, 47. 56

‘Whose realm, his religion’ The rule of the Peace of Augsburg, deciding which German states would

Page 44: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

43

from the moral norms expressed in the Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen and

in the thought of the philosophes (even that of Rousseau, who most influenced

Robespierre), he was pursuing a rational program designed to protect the people by

producing a Republic of Virtue. In fact, we may indeed say that Robespierre was

certainly striving to attain his own ideological ends, but he was doing so in a rational

legal way, through law and due process, with the approval of the legislating

representatives of the people.

From the beginning, Maximilien Robespierre pursued specific ideals in his career,

so that, while he recognized his own ambition,57

he was a uniquely sincere man, well-

deserving of his epithet “the Incorruptible.” He was ambitious, but for ideological rather

than selfish ends.58

As a lawyer in his small hometown of Arras, he took the side of the

poor and weak parties and upheld rational principles over privilege, probably in part due

to his own suffering on account of his father’s delinquency and his wish to be judged in

his own merit rather than in the shadow of his father.59

His sister Charlotte later

remembered him saying, “To defend the oppressed against their oppressors, to plead the

cause of the weak against the strong who exploit and crush them, this is the duty of all

hearts that have not been spoiled by egoism and corruption.” This aversion to corruption

(and its association with self-interest) would be present throughout his political career.

follow Lutheran or Catholic Christianity. Furet and Baker 57

Scurr, 40. 58

The purity of his own ambition was a strength of Robespierre’s, for he could and did attack his

opponents as being “devoured by passions and ambition,” as in his defense of the political clubs in

September of 1791 (Virtue and Terror, 25), whereas his own ambition was ambition for the success of the

revolution. If he ultimately needed power to defend that success , it was only as a humble servant thereof,

and his ethic and commitment attested to this. See Scurr, Fatal Purity, (335-337), for the extent to which

opponents had to go to try to paint Robespierre as a corrupt politician bent on personal power. 59

Scurr, 41

Page 45: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

44

He was ever devoted to his vision of a moral state of things,60

and he so identified himself

with the attainment of that vision that his own enemies were always oppressors,

conspirators against the moral state, and he came also to perceive himself as a victimized

martyr for the cause. This perception is apparent in a poem he wrote early in his career:

The just man’s torment, at his final hour,

The only pang he feels--and I shall feel--

Is the dark breath of calumny and blame

Breathed by a grimmer ghost than death himself:

The hate of those for whom he gives his life.61

Again, it is important to note that Robespierre equates his political ideal with justice and

virtue: he is a “just man,” giving his life up for the people. This sense takes on a semi-

religious meaning: one is reminded of the Hebrew scriptural theme of the “just man” of

the Book of Wisdom, whose suffering is incomprehensible to those who don’t follow the

law of the Lord; and the “suffering servant” of Isaiah, who suffers for following the laws

of God rather than the wickedness of men. One also recalls the ideal philosopher-king of

Plato, the follower of truth who is ultimately killed by the ignorant people who cannot

accept that truth. Robespierre takes such a mantel of moral righteousness, at least in his

own perception. Very interesting on this note is Robespierre’s literary tribute to the poet

Gresset. In his essay he touched again on the idea of the noble wounded spirit: “I have

been so bold as to insist upon his [Gresset’s] virtue, upon his respect for morality, and

upon his love of religion. This will undoubtedly expose me to the ridicule of the witty

majority; but it will win me two votes which are more than a recompense--that of my

60

His vision was not necessarily a single unchanging ideal--in a letter to the king from February 1789, he

speaks of the responsibility of the king to uphold the rights of the people, and in another letter from before

the Revolution, he wrote that “there is no need for us to change the whole system of our legislation; it is

dangerous to look for the remedy for a specific ill in a general revolution.” What is key is that his vision

was equated with moral truth, not personal gain (Scurr, Fatal Purity, 57,47). 61

Scurr, 39

Page 46: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

45

conscience and that of yours.”62

His identification with another martyr may come across

as pride (and biographer Ruth Scurr draws this connection with his model: “he was--as

Rousseau had been--exceptionally self-absorbed”),63

but most importantly, his conviction

is sincere (to the point of death) and righteous (in his eyes).

This conviction of righteousness remained a distinctive part of Robespierre as the

political upheaval unfolded in France. In a different age, when his conviction was at odds

with the currents, he perhaps would have remained in obscurity or been silenced for his

reformist beliefs, but in the French Revolution, Robespierre’s conviction became more

and more the conviction of the time: his devotion to the republic became “the order of the

day,” as it were. The moral dimension of his conviction meant that he personally was

beyond reproach, in terms of the morality of revolution, and of course this advantage

added fuel to his ambition in cyclical fashion so that more and more Robespierre’s

adamantine vision became conflated with the revolution itself.64

In the pressures of 1793-

4 (the war, counterrevolutionary insurrection, and popular unrest) the necessity of

protecting the revolution until it could finish its work became a necessity of protecting

Robespierre’s republican vision.

***

This vision was, if not connected to any particular moral argument of the

Enlightenment, only possible in the world of the Enlightenment, for Robespierre

compellingly articulated his republic as a product and goal of natural reason. As the

62

Scurr, 50 63

Scurr, 53-4 64

See Scurr, especially 101, on how Robespierre came to be identified, and to identify himself, with the

Revolution and its outcome. Scurr writes, “In short, he behaved like someone with nothing whatever to lose

outside the Revolution itself” His religion, his morality was the revolution. We have no reason to doubt his

word that he was a martyr, for his god was the republic.

Page 47: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

46

events that would ultimately earn the name “revolution” began, Robespierre argued in the

name of natural reason, which he saw as only leading to the republic of virtue. In his

famous speech, Robespierre spoke in his characteristically grandiose terms to the

convention, claiming, “In our country we want to substitute morality for egoism, honesty

for honor, principles for customs, duties for decorum, the rule of reason for the tyranny of

custom…that is to say, all the virtues and all the miracles of the Republic for all the vices

and all the absurdities of the monarchy.”65

To Robespierre, the “rule of reason” and

“morality” meant his concept of the Republic, and he continued to support the

marginalized poor by means of this natural, reasonable morality. As the Estates-general

clashed, he supported Abbe Sieyes’ influential pamphlet, confronting the archbishop of

Nimes in an early public speech and challenging the higher clergy to “convert all their

superfluous wealth into food for the poor.”66

After the mob stormed the Bastille,

Robespierre defended their questionable vigilantism as a swelling of Rousseauvean

general will: “M. Foulon was hanged yesterday by the people’s decree.”67

This defense

reveals an early endorsement of violence for political ends: as Robespierre says “the

terror inspired by this national army…determined the Revolution,” he truly justifies terror

(in the Pauline sense of the term: “to make just”)--that is, he does not merely excuse the

use of violence, but acknowledges its positive moral value as a part of the revolution, an

idea he would later aptly articulate as an “emanation of justice.”

65

Robespierre, 115. 66

From one of Robespierre’s earliest speeches to the Third Estate in Versailles, early in May, 1789, quoted

in Scurr, Fatal Purity, 89. 67

Scurr, 94. Interestingly, Robespierre was relatively atypical among the deputies in his support of the

vigilantism, as suggested by Timothy Tackett’s readings of the deputy diaries in his Becoming a

Revolutionary (1996). As Ruth Scurr notes of Robespierre, he “grasped early, rapidly, intuitively the

conflict between ends and means that was destined to blight the Revolution, cause tens of thousands of

deaths, and haunt the survivors…. He was vehemently committed to the Revolution and anything it

entailed, passing quickly over moral scruples, intellectual incoherence, and political doubts. In short, he

Page 48: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

47

In the immediate aftermath of the Terror, reactionaries on the Right claimed that

the Terror was the logical result of revolution, revolutionary philosophy, and even

Enlightenment philosophy. The Irish-born member of the English House of Commons, an

acclaimed writer and speaker in his time, Edmund Burke offered almost immediate

critique in a letter from October 1789, his famous Reflections on the Revolution in

France and on the Proceedings in Certain Societies in London relative to that Event.

Burke’s response arose out of yet another (very English) perception of what is “natural”

for society, “a constitutional policy [by which], working after the pattern of nature, we

receive, we hold, we transmit our government and our privileges, in the same manner in

which we enjoy and transmit our property and our lifes”: that is, the tradition of

inheritance.68

To Burke, innovations which attacked tradition were inherently flawed

because they undermined their own staying power. The revolution destroyed the age of

privilege and chivalry, when “ten thousand swords must have leaped from their

scabbards”69

in defense of honor, and to Burke it was only consequential that the reckless

innovations should result in disorder and violence.

However, we hardly need to rebut these perspectives, which are among the

simplistic answers of the kind Gay wished to avoid in describing the Enlightenment. The

Revolution is similarly complex, and while Burke’s pragmatic commentary on the social

turbulence of revolutions is well-made, it is at the same time perhaps too universal in its

claims and too grounded in the perspective of British Imperialism. To the notion that

terror was the unavoidable result of upsetting the “natural” tradition of the age of

behaved like someone with nothing whatever to lose outside the Revolution itself” (Fatal Purity, 101). 68

Burke, Edmund, Reflections on the Revolution in France (London: MacMillan and Company, 1890), 36. 69

Burke, Edmund, “The Age of Chivalry,” in Modern Eloquence, vol. IX (London: Modern Eloquence

Corporation, 1923), 132.

Page 49: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

48

chivalry, we still offer an alternative view: Terror may have been necessary to

Robespierre’s ideology, but a republic clearly could conceivably exist without the Terror,

to which the almost half millenia of Republican Rome gives evidence. The situation in

France seemed to prove the fears of the traditionalists and counterrevolutionaries, but

they also played into the fears of the radicals that the enemies of the revolution were

inciting counterrevolution. Thus both sides provided fuel for the arguments of the other,

without either gaining a real answer to their question. The revolutionary government did

indeed resort to violence in order to protect the new order (an order of the rights of

citizens), but this did not prove Burke right. Burke prophesied that “the popular leader is

obliged to become active in propagating doctrines, and establishing powers, that will

afterwards defeat any sober purpose at which he ultimately might have aimed.”

Robespierre became such a leader, but not through any competition for personal ambition

as Burke assumed, but in pursuit of a pure vision. He was “obliged” by the threat of his

enemies, or rather (as he saw them) the enemies of the people. But had those enemies not

been there, had the powers of Old Europe not reacted in fear, would the Reign of Terror

have been necessary? It is certainly debatable - Furet argues that the Terror emerged in

response to other internal pressures rather than the war - but it is clearly not the sound

proof of democracy’s flaws that the early founders of conservativism saw it as.

The Enlightenment did not write a program for the Terror; rather it left open the

door for those who could write such a program, just as much as it allowed for truly

uplifting enterprises which uphold human dignity.

***

“The Dust that Speaks to You”

Human Nature in the Terror

Page 50: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

49

Looking specifically at the program of the Terror, we can learn specific factors

which allowed for sanctioned violence. The three principle architects - Danton, Marat,

and Robespierre - to varying degrees were willing to place human life in the category of

“dispensable” for the sake of creating the ideal state (or even of simply preserving the

Revolution, as an alternative to slipping back into the slavery of a monarchy, until such a

time as a constitution could be written). This kind of thought must be sharply

distinguished from “Just War” or self-defense arguments, which maintain the value of

human life throughout. A person may kill in self-defense as last resort to protect an

innocent life from unjustified murder. To the proponents of Terror, human life is

subordinated to the good of the work of producing a good society. In such reasoning,

violence in support of the Republic of Virtue is not a “necessary evil,” as in the case of

self-defense. Rather, terror “is an emanation of virtue.”

This idea of terror as an emanation of virtue is extremely important for theory of

legitimate government and constitutionality. Because the historiography has focused on

different aspects through the years (no doubt due in part to changing events that made

those aspects more interesting at different times), the justice or virtue of terror has been

somewhat ignored by those not advocating its use.70

As we have seen, the Terror has

been labeled an excess of an otherwise wholesome philosophy or else mathematical

product of the factors of materialist Enlightenment morality. To Marx, it was the clash

between great dialectical forces; to Habermas, it was a lapse in true enlightenment

growth; to Furet, it was an outcome of discourses competing over political ideas and

affected by the war; to Arendt, it was a failed revolution. However, there are a few

70

Except by thinkers such as Hannah Arendt, who were principally concerned with twentieth-century

violence.

Page 51: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

50

authors who have engaged with this separation between morality and rationality, which is

cardinal to our present question. To begin with, Camus, as we have already mentioned,

saw that philosophy “can be used for any purpose.” Camus makes a resolute argument

against totalitarian murder by means of an assumption of the inadmissibility of murder in

his articulation of the Absurd, but he does not specifically deal with this idea in terms of

the Terror. Slavoj Zizek, the contemporary Slovenian philosopher, takes note of terror

and virtue in “Robespierre, or, the “Divine Violence” of Terror”. Zizek, in riveting

fashion, discusses the relationship between humanism and terror, working with a matrix

that sets up “four variations on this motif: humanism and terror, humanism or terror, each

in a ‘positive’ or in a ‘negative’ sense” for comparison. The classic Christian perspective

holds “humanism or terror,” calling for humanism as a optimal choice.71

To Zizek,

totalitarian murderers conflated humanism with Terror (humanism and terror in the

‘positive’ sense). Then there is the ‘negative’ of humanism and terror, in which terror is

perceived as the result “of the humanist project itself, of its hubris” - the idea that

humanism always leads to violence.

There is, however, a fourth variation, usually left aside: the choice ‘humanism or terror,’ but with

terror, not humanism, as a positive term…. In today’s ‘post-deconstructive’ thought…, the term

‘inhuman’ has gained new weight, especially in the work of Agamben and Badiou. The best way

to approach it is via Freud’s reluctance to endorse the injunction ‘Love thy neighbour!’-- the

temptation to be resisted here is the ethical domestication of the neightbour -- for example, what

Emmanuel Levinas did with his notion of the neighbour as the abyssal point from which the call of

ethical responsibility emanates. What Levinas thereby obfuscates is the monstrosity of the

neighbour, a monstrosity on account of which Lacan applies to the neighbor the term Thing, used

71

Zizek places this variation (humanism or terror, humanism being positive) in the camp of “the liberal-

humanist project” and the “neo-Habermassians”; we of course would disagree on the grounds of this thesis

- that the humanists fail to truly prevent terror by believing themselves to have found “the answer” in some

Page 52: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

51

by Freud to designate the ultimate object of our desires in its unbearable intensity and

impenetrability… In proper dialectical paradox, what Levinas, with all his celebration of

Otherness, fails to take into account is not some underlying Sameness of all humans but the

radically ‘inhuman’ Otherness itself: the Otherness of a human being reduced to inhumanity…72

In Zizek’s piercing analysis, Robespierre does not engage in dialogue with the Other,

with the people: “he does not claim that he has direct access to the people’s Will which

speaks through him.”73

Robespierre rather sees the necessity of creating or attaining

social order in which humanity can flourish: for this work terror is necessary, and

Robespierre may undertake it because he has in fact given himself already to the cause.

He is a man of “moral integrity and full devotion to the revolutionary cause.”74

He was

driven by a “holy love for humanity”75

to not only take part in a mere event of revolution

(such as the storming of the Bastille or the execution of a king) but to “impose on social

reality a new lasting order” in “‘fidelity’ to the Event.” “This is the properly ‘terrorist’

dimension of every authentic democratic explosion.”76

Zizek’s clarity is extremely

helpful to our present discussion, for he articulates perfectly (and even defends) the

exquisitely lucid ratio in Robespierre’s mission. His was not a cold calculus, but a

passionate martyrdom - held to its iron course by its very passion - for the sake of his

perception of humanity. “Who am I…?” asks Robespierre, near the end. “a slave of

Liberty, a living martyr of the Republic.”77

Robespierre’s perception of humanity was

remarkably important. Zizek notes that Robespierre said “The characteristic of popular

sort of ideological solution: in effect, for failing to be truly humanist with “human” as the highest priority. 72

Zizek, xii-xiv 73

Zizek, xvii 74

Zizek, xxxviii 75

Robespierre, Virtue and Terror, 129 76

Zizek, xxxv 77

Robespierre, Virtue and Terror, 131

Page 53: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

52

government is to be trustful toward the people and severe toward itself.”78

And it is so

very striking that the day before his arrest, amidst failing health and a frenetic climate in

Paris, Robespierre gave one final, dramatic oration to the Convention in which he alluded

to the Festival of the Supreme Being which had taken place just before the climax of the

Terror began:

O day forever fortunate! When the French people rose altogether to offer to the Author of Nature

the only homage worthy of him, what a touching assemblage was there of all the objects that can

fascinate the eyes or attract the hearts of men! O honored old age! O generous and ardent youth! O

pure and playful joy of childhood! O delicious tears of maternal fondness! O divine influences of

innocence and beauty! O the majesty of a great people, happy in the contemplation and enjoyment

of its own strength and glory and virtue!79

These appeals were certainly not germane to the specific points of his speech that day, yet

at the same time they speak eloquently, as though his ideals burst through the details of

the speech. Here is the vision of humanity which drove Robespierre to exert himself

almost to the point of expiration even if his end had not come prematurely. His idea of

the people and of trusting them Zizek calls a “wager that the large majority of the people

support these severe measures, see them as their own, and are ready to participate in their

enforcement.”80

The assumptions which Robespierre brought with him into Paris and the

Revolution - formed perhaps in his early hardship, in his classical education, in his

experiences as a lawyer for the marginalized in Arras - these guided his program when he

found himself in the seat of power.

Another very recent work which deals with this rationality in an important way is

Dan Edelstein’s The Terror of Natural Right: Republicanism, the Cult of Nature, and the

French Revolution. Edelstein addresses the rationality of the Terror in the light of a

particular juridical theory - natural right theory - which arose out of the particular guiding

78

Zizek, xxxvi 79

Robespierre, “Speech of 8 Thermidor,” in Scurr, Fatal Purity, 347-8. 80

Zizek, xxxvii.

Page 54: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

53

philosophy of Robespierre and his radical followers. This is a different aspect from that

addressed by Zizek81

but it also helps to emphasize the capacity for terror within an

Enlightenment system, even a system founded on natural human rights. Edelstein

pinpoints this philosophical idea of natural right theory as the particular cause of the

Reign of Terror: “Jacobin political leaders…drew on natural right to authorize and draft

the laws underpinning the terror.”82

Edelstein’s description of the Terror is insightful, as

it goes beyond the perhaps too simplistic “polemic” of Adorno and Horkheimer in

pointing to the particular values toward which Robespierre and the radical Jacobins were

working. These values were a particular vision of the Republic of Virtue, inspired in an

important way by Rousseau and others, that Edelstein terms “natural republicanism.”

Natural republicanism is a combination of the idea of a republic as the best political

system with Rousseauvian humanism, with the result that the republic is no longer merely

a good or useful construct of society, but the natural end of interpersonal relationship.

Thus it is “natural” (that is, the design of the Supreme Being) for people to form a

republic based on virtue. Edelstein ties this vision in to the myth of the Golden Age

which the revolutionaries began to embrace as a utopian reality: “By the time of the

French Revolution, the myth of the golden age no longer appeared to many as a myth; it

had become the ideal and natural template on whose basis all of society could be

reorganized.”83

Robespierre again and again appealed to this idea of the “natural” good of

the republic, noting that reason produces republican ideals: “it is reason, which will make

the republic immortal; where reason reigns, the people are sovereign, and such an empire

81

Edelstein’s analysis is more pragmatic than philosophical; he looks at the juridical foundations for

Robespierre’s political action, rather than the metaphysics of his justification. 82

Edelstein, Dan, The Terror of Natural Right (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 2009),

4.

Page 55: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

54

is indestructible.”84

To Robespierre, well-versed in Rousseauvean thought, the republic

was the hope for mankind which was on the verge of realization in the Revolution, and he

was the man to help France realize that hope.85

The thoughts of Rousseau and

Robespierre were not identical, however, for while Rousseau argued for the republic on

the grounds of its legitimacy as a form of government by the people, Robespierre went a

step further and equated the will of the people with the republican utopia itself.

Rousseau’s Contrat Social holds that “The articles of this contract are…unalterably fixed

by the nature of the act…. [O]nce the social pact is violated in any instance, all

obligations it created cease….”86

Clearly, to Rousseau the legitimacy of popular

government is grounded in the contract among the participants. Robespierre abandoned

the social contract idea, believing that the “spontaneous voice of the people” (which was

nebulous enough even in Rousseau) was the civic virtue of the republic. That is, it was

outside Robespierre’s concept of “natural” for a person to oppose the republic. It was not

a matter of majority rule favoring a republic, but of Nature favoring a republic: thus the

opponents of the republic were opponents of Nature, the Supreme Being, and good order.

Edelstein argues this very point, noting that the Jacobin vision (which was in some sense

a moral claim: to be doing things the “right” way) claimed “that the laws of nature were

also the laws of the republic” and that this claim led to “a conflation between nature and

nation that had grave consequences for anyone misfortunate enough to break (or to

83

Ibid., 14. 84

Scurr, Fatal Purity, 295 85

In the purges of the Hebertists and the Dantonists, we see how convinced Robespierre was of his own

infallibility: he trusted very few people close to him to hold the pure vision of the Republic. Even other

republican revolutionaries had to be removed as enemies to his vision of the Republic. Here we see that

Enlightenment revolution at work: “heaven on earth” was no longer a platitude, but a mission statement and

a goal that could be achieved through social change. 86

Rousseau, J.J., “The Social Contract,” in Aspects of Western Civilization, vol. II, ed Perry M. Rogers

Page 56: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

55

appear to break) the law.”87

This was indeed a move away from the legitimacy of social

contract to a legitimacy of moral rectitude based on the republican ideal. Rousseau did

allow for law enforcement within the contract (“…whoever refuses to obey the general

will, shall be compelled to it by the whole body, which is in fact only forcing him to be

free”88

), but this is clearly different from the enemy-of-nature justification. Such a model

would never have survived in a Hobbesean worldview, in which the natural state of man

is “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.”89

However, the revolutionaries embracing the

republican utopia had a warmer conception of humans in their natural state, more along

the lines of the ideas of Rousseau and Diderot, coming out of the new contact with people

in the New World. Edelstein notes that natural republicanism found its way into literature

in “works such as Fenelon’s Telemaque and Montesquieu’s Lettres persanes [which]

depicted societies … that existed in a revised state of nature, in which individuals were

social and equal, no one ruled over anyone else, and virtue came naturally.”90

Here we

have a remarkable paradox: the revolutionaries relied on the “natural goodness” idea to

support “natural republicanism” as a good state for society, but they also relied on the

natural right juridical theory which was developed as a justification for imperialist action

against the “savages” of the New World.91

Natural Right theory became very central to

Robespierre’s logic in the Terror, justifying it as an “emanation of justice.”

The concept of natural rights was largely developed by the Enlightenment

thinkers “in direct response to the pressing legal questions raised by European

(Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Education, Inc., 2008), 104. 87

Edelstein, 3. 88

Rousseau, 106. 89

Hobbes, “Leviathan,” in Political Philosophy, ed. Steven M. Cahn (New York and Oxford: Oxford

University Press, 2005), 225. 90

Edelstein, 11.

Page 57: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

56

imperialism in the New World.”92

Here, again, it cannot be emphasized enough that

anthropology is the key distinction in the praxis of any philosophy: how we see the

human person determines how we treat people. Edelstein notes that Thomistic

philosophers supported what we might today call “human rights” or the innate dignity of

the human person. But some philosophers responded with the idea of people who can

remove themselves from that natural rights category by opposing themselves to the laws

of Nature. Francis Bacon called on nations to “suppress” those who “have utterly

degenerated from the laws of nature.”93

John Locke, one of the great founders of

democratic thought, held that one who violates natural law “declares himself to live by

another Rule, than that of reason and common Equity…and so he becomes dangerous to

Mankind.”94

In Locke in particular we see the notions of reason and nature combined

here: what is natural is reasonable; what is reasonable is good. These Enlightenment

jurists produced a body of thought that included the concept of hostes humanis generis,

or enemies of the human race.95

Thus natural right theory played a key role in justifying violent action against

people who are perceived to be enemies “outside the law” so to speak -- such came to

include the king himself.96

In this knowledge, if we are to speak of the “excesses” of the

Terror, or of the Terror “going off track,” we must be very clear in specifying what

91

Edelstein, 27. 92

Edelstein, 27. 93

Bacon, Advertisement Touching a Holy War, in Edelstein, 28. 94

Locke, “Second Treatise of Government,” in Political Philosophy, 247. 95

Edelstein, 15-17. 96

Not all used the concept to attack the legitimacy of the monarchy; Jacques Benigne Bossuet went so far

as to say that disobedient subjects fit that category: “whoever refuses to obey the king cannot appeal to

some other judge, but will be condemned to death without appeal as an enemy of the public peace and of

humanity” (Bossuet, “Politque teree des propres paroles de l’Ecriture Sainte,” in Aspects of Western

Civilization, 55).

Page 58: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

57

moderate good became evil in excess, or from what good track the revolution derailed.

Likewise if we are to speak of the totalitarian logic of the Terror, we must be equally

clear in specifying which and whose premises produced that conclusion. As we have

seen, each of these paradigms has something to offer, but given Robespierre’s moral

purity and the centrality of natural right theory, none of these paradigms is precise

enough. The Terror was not an excess of Republican virtue, nor was it the republican

ideal gone off track. Neither was it inevitable in a post-Enlightenment world. Rather it

was the rational means of Robespierre and the Jacobin radicals to produce a free society

with a popular government that could be safe from tyrants, foreign attack, and internal

conspiracy. And this radical means was determined out of their anthropology: the human

person is the virtuous citizen. Any outside of that definition fall under a different

category, “enemies of the people.”

***

Robespierre said “To punish the oppressors of humanity: that is clemency; to

forgive them, that is barbarity. The rigour of tyrants has rigour as its sole principle: that

of republican government is based on beneficence.”97

Any system must ensure that

human life is never subordinated to another end, even another good end, because it is the

human experience, founded in the inner life of the person, which gives the very meaning

to life which is the basis for desiring utopia. Pure Reason does not ensure this; it must be

accepted as an assumption, rather than a deduction from empirical data. The nature of this

assumption must be recognized formally in law in order to not leave the door open to

justified killing. The French Revolution, in postponing writing a constitution until the

97

Robespierre, “On the Principles of Political Morality that should guid the National Convention in the

domestic administration of the Republic” (February 5 1794), in Virtue and Terror, 117.

Page 59: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

58

country was safe, left that door open, and the thousands who lost their lives give

testimony to that reality. Today, the strongest states have the responsibility to protect

people from their own power; in foreign and domestic policy these politically and

economically powerful states must insure against the possibility of being driven down the

path of systematic destruction of human life, the environment, and the larger human

community. The subject of the next chapter will be this necessity in the modern post-

Enlightenment state.

Page 60: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

59

Chapter 3

The Politics of Terror

The Revolution of mentality which allowed for the radical Jacobins of the French

Revolution to attempt to discover moral principles from natural reason is not a

meaningless thing of the past. The post-Enlightenment mentality has affected mass

movements in the twentieth century, and still affects our political thinking today. Many

millions of persons have been killed in the name of some ideology or other, and yet those

peoples most influenced by Enlightenment thinking (Western industrialized democracies)

continue to perceive such atrocities as flawed reasoning, rather than misplaced values.

The rationalists see such murder as the work of ignorant, rather than depraved, minds,

and approach the new challenges of our day such as the use of terrorism by radical

religious fundamentalists as stemming from people placing religious beliefs over reason.

Indeed, the term “fundamentalist” implies that what is problematic is that beliefs of faith

are fundamental - that is, foundational. If only people relied on natural reason, war,

violence, and inequality would not occur. Pure secular rationalists pay lip service to

religious beliefs, perhaps as a cultural heritage, but ultimately such beliefs must be

subordinated to reason.

This mentality is still alive today, especially in the West. Many constitutions in

democratic nations are based on the Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen, a

product of the Enlightenment paradigm, and even the charter and vision of the United

Nations is related in many ways to the French declaration. Thus as we approach new

challenges in the twenty-first century, our question becomes very pertinent. In this

chapter, I will bring the connection between the Jacobin Terror and Enlightenment

Page 61: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

60

humanism up to date in twentieth and twenty-first centuries. This connection is not a

moot topic but an important concern of any government and is tied in a basic way to the

legitimacy of law.

The first half of the twentieth century shocked the world. On a single day in 1916,

almost 60,000 men were killed or captured in the Somme region of France, and the rest of

the war “to end all wars” proved equally devastating. In the Ottoman Empire during the

same years, the world suffered one of the early appearances of genocide (a term all too

familiar in twenty-first century ears) as over half a million ethnic Armenians were

“exterminated.” The death tolls continued to rise as the already-stricken suffered the

worst epidemic to date in the Spanish Influenza, food shortages associated with a global

Great Depression, and further civil wars in the 1920s and 1930s, as well as a continuation

of “ethnic cleansing” movements which surfaced around the world throughout the

century. World War II truly saw the world mobilized in warfare, and saw also the fruits

of mankind’s energies turned towards war in fire-bombing of civilian areas, the

devastating power of nuclear weapons, and the numbers of mobilized soldiers as a

sizeable percentage of the world’s population engaged in conflict. Totalitarian dictators

from Hitler to Stalin to Mao to Pol Pot executed social restructuring plans whose costs in

human lives was heavy to the point of being meaningless by the sheer scale of the

numbers. It is said that when Oppenheimer, the director of the development of the atomic

bomb, saw the first successful testing of the bomb, he said, “Now I am become Death,

destroyer of worlds.” Truly, on a global level at least, humanity was forced to see itself in

a new way, and what it saw was of terrible aspect.

Those twentieth-century intellectuals, activists, observers and contemplators of

Page 62: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

61

the human person “become Death” responded in new ways to violence and found (or

were forced into) new paradigms with which to attempt to comprehend the “monstrosity

of the neighbor,” to use Zizek’s term.98

There were, of course, a variety of responses

ranging from cynicism (we think here of Celine’s pseudo-autobiographical Journey to the

End of the Night and certain reactions in the world of art to the apparent fatalism of the

First World War such as Wilfred Owen and Otto Dix) to a more resolute commitment to

understand and oppose the new attack. For our purposes we shall again engage with the

thought of a few commentaries in order to analyze certain facts about systematic murder

and oppression in order to come to a positive program, not a specific arrangement of

society but rather essential principles to guide such arrangements.

In response to this terrible new age of death, a group of scholars from a variety of

fields met in a conference at the American Academy of Arts and Sciences in March of

1953, to discuss specifically the topic of Totalitarianism. The goal of the scholars was a

“clarification of the issues” of totalitarianism, a phenomenon which impressed itself upon

the twentieth century as fundamentally new; in his introduction, German American

scholar Carl J. Friedrich, an important member of the conference, emphasized that

totalitarianism came “unexpected and unannounced.”99

Attending this conference (though

she did not submit a paper) was a Jewish immigrant from Germany, a political scientist

named Hannah Arendt, whose interest in the topic of totalitarianism would produce a

wealth of insight into the nature of society, politics, and the history of twentieth-century

Europe, publishing her seminal Origins of Totalitarianism five years later in 1958.

Arendt’s work on totalitarianism is extremely important for any study of modern political

98

Zizek, in Virtue and Terror, xiv. 99

Friedrich, Carl J., “The Problem of Totalitarianism - an Introduction,” in Totalitarianism (Cambridge,

Page 63: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

62

philosophy, and especially for our task in the twenty-first century of preventing

justifications for murder. Friedrich, drawing upon Aristotle’s high regard for political

science, makes an insightful remark on “the impossibility of making any science

contribute to the good life without understanding how the community is governed,”

placing the mind over the tool. Better minds have pointed out the errors of

technocracy,100

but it may be said that the necessity of responsibly and ethically handling

technology directs us to consult Arendt’s analysis of the flaws of totalitarianism in order

to avoid them in our own society.

Even at the conference in 1953, Arendt noted that totalitarian rule, while marked

certainly by the use of violence, is unique in that it utilizes ethically unsavory tactics “in

broad daylight.”101

Totalitarian regimes established themselves by using conspiratorial

methods in the open to attack an alleged conspiracy in the government or society. By

acting in “daylight,” agents of totalitarianism break off from the normal state, in which

violence belongs “in the dark,” not in the realm of daily life. “The point,” says Arendt,

“…is not the use of violence per se, not even on an unprecedented scale, but that

“totalitarian indifference” to moral consideration is actually based on an reversal of all

our legal and moral concepts….” 102

Our normal legal and moral concepts, based on the

prohibition to murder, suddenly become ineffective frameworks for analysis. This is

perhaps in part why, as a phenomenon, totalitarianism took the world by surprise.

Totalitarian rule did not excuse violence with circumstantial evidence to show why,

Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1954), 4,1. 100

For instance, Postman in Building a Bridge to the 18th

Century, esp. Chapter 1, or early 20th

century

journalist and essayist G.K. Chesterton, who in a variety of works questioned the wisdom of blind

technological progression and apathy toward history and tradition. See, for instance, The Everlasting Man

(San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1993). 101

Arendt, Totalitarianism, 77

Page 64: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

63

violence was in this case permissible; in its own legal and moral concepts, there was

simply no need to find an excuse. As Arendt notes, “The peculiarity of totalitarian crimes

is that they are committed for different reasons and in a different framework which has a

“morality” of its own.” The totalitarians were not unenlightened or ignorant; they were

working off different assumptions, to a degree without historical precedent (with the

possible exception of Machiavelli).103

This is a very important point to be made in a

secular democracy.

Arendt does note that totalitarian terror seems to kill without reason, but even this

seeming irrationality fits into the anti-moral (in the sense of anti-matter, it’s negative or

opposite) framework. She writes that while totalitarian terror ““punishes” independently

of any subjective guilt for “objective” reasons,” nevertheless this punishment is part of

the negative morality, a part of “the scientifically forecast course of history itself,

according to which certain crimes are necessary and for which therefore “criminals” must

be found.”104

The word “necessary” is extremely important here. Observers of certain

examples of justified murder in the twentieth century can be tempted to call such

atrocities “madness” and “irrational,” again linking evil to ignorance or to a social system

built upon irrational structures (as did the men of the Enlightenment and as have many

post-Enlightenment thinkers ever since). But such commentary is only possible from

within the observer’s own moral framework. In other words, the impression or

appearance of madness is only perceived from within particular viewpoints or through a

particular lens; if the observer viewed the situation through the lens of the totalitarian

ideology, he should affirm that the so-called atrocity was perfectly rational and therefore

102

Arendt, Totalitarianism, 78 103

Arendt, On Revolutions, 30-2.

Page 65: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

64

perfectly acceptable. We remember here the words of Robespierre: “To punish the

oppressors of humanity, that is clemency; to forgive them, that is barbarity.”105

Working

from within an observation point in which opponents of a particular system are in fact

enemies of humanity (hostes humanis generis), it is indeed barbarity to forgive them.

Hence, the phrase “One man’s terrorist is another man’s freedom-fighter.” One might

almost say, the observer can only call the mass murderer or the terrorist mad because of

the ignorance his own lens of perspective in a sort of cultural relativism applied to moral

actions.

Arendt continues and refines her analysis in Origins. In this voluminous study of

European politics in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, she explores more deeply the

nature of totalitarian rule’s reversal of the moral and legal concepts of the norm.

Totalitarian rationality is not nihilistic chaos or moral relativism, but a new set of moral

and legal rules, and indeed a new conception of the relation between morality and

legality: “It is the monstrous yet seemingly unanswerable claim of totalitarian rule that,

far from being “lawless,” it goes to the sources of authority from which positive laws

received their ultimate legitimation, that far from being arbitrary it is more obedient to

those superhuman forces than any government was before, and that far from wielding its

power in the interest of one man, it is quite prepared to sacrifice everybody’s vital

immediate interests to the execution of what it assumes to be the law of History or the

law of Nature.”106

The centralized nature of totalitarian rule results in that its inverted

rationality is total in its control over society. There is not room for dissent, which is an

104

Arendt, Totalitarianism, 79. 105

Robespierre, speech before the Convention, “On the Principles of Political Morality that should Guide

the National Convention in the Domestic Arbitration of the Republic,” February 5, 1794, in, Virtue and

Terror, 117.

Page 66: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

65

irrational (and even immoral) act within the totalitarian framework, because the law of

Nature and the law of History (which can become conflated into one concept, as in, say,

Marxism, which sees history as a linear evolution) point to a particular end: namely, that

touted by the ideology in question. This conflation, along the lines of what Edelstein saw

in the Jacobin use of natural republicanism - which made the laws of the republic the

laws of nature intended by Divine reason - is a very important element within totalitarian

rule and action. In the framework of the norm, “Both moral judgment and legal

punishment presuppose this basic consent; the criminal can be judged justly only because

he takes part in the consensus iuris.” People who are thought to make an oath of

agreement share a common set of principles; one who commits an action not in line with

those principles is transgressing the law, and the law holds him accountable. But

totalitarianism, conflating the principles with totalitarian action, has no need of laws (in

the normal sense) because the idea of “legality” must change in a system of movement

toward some other state. Arendt writes, ““Totalitarian policy does not replace one set of

laws with another, does not establish its own consensus iuris, does not create, by one

revolution, a new form of legality. Its defiance of all, even its own positive laws implies

that it believes it can do without any consensus iuris whatever, and still not resign itself

to the tyrannical state of lawlessness, arbitrariness, and fear…because it promises to

release the fulfillment of law from all action and will of man; and it promises justice on

earth because it claims to make mankind itself the embodiment of the law.”107

The

normal concept of law is a man-made code aimed at the preservation of society, to ensure

the security of human persons in their interactions. In totalitarian thinking, society is

106

Arendt, Origins of Totalitarianism, 461-2. 107

Arendt, Origins of Totalitarianism, 462

Page 67: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

66

moving toward some goal, the ideological utopia, and therefore the “law” becomes

human action toward that end.

This new conception of law is fully realized in the application of terror, for which

reason it is particularly pertinent to our discussion. Since the law of Nature or of History

which totalitarian thinking follows is one of total movement, society in general and the

human person in particular must also “move totally” - must ever change toward the

ideological utopia. The role of laws formerly in attempting to recreate in human society

the natural law or the laws of God are replaced by terror, which is in a similar way

“designed to translate into reality the law of movement of history or nature.”108

This new

concept of morality and legality as terror of course brings with it new conceptions of old

ideas in morality and legality. “Right” and “wrong,” “morally permissible,” “guilty” and

“innocent” take on new meanings. Because totalitarian terror is not lawless nor arbitrary,

these ideas are not dispensed with. Instead they take on new roles, reflective of the new

moral and legal framework. Right and wrong are now based on the direction of

movement of humanity; “No free action…can be permitted to interfere with the

elimination of the “objective enemy” of History or Nature.”109

Note that right and wrong

are still objective notions, but now with relation to the objective movement and the

objective enemies. We are no longer necessarily speaking of personal action, of

subjective guilt or innocence, but of objective facts: not only those who act against the

rule but also those who simply are against it by nature of their not fitting into the

ideologically perceived categories of humanity’s movement (i.e. those humans who need

to be “weeded out,” inferior races, the weak and vulnerable, “dying classes and decadent

108

Arendt, Origins of Totalitarianism, 464. 109

Arendt, Origins of Totalitarianism, 465.

Page 68: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

67

peoples”110

). As Arendt says, “Guilt and innocence become senseless notions; “guilty” is

he who stands in the way of the natural or historical process,” and, in the terror “all

concerned are subjectively innocent.” Victims are not killed because of something they

have necessarily done, and the murderers do not themselves order their deaths but rather

“execute a death sentence pronounced by some higher tribunal”: the law of the

ideology.111

Totalitarian terror was arguably new; Robespierre’s Reign of Terror was not

totalitarian by Arendt’s definitions. Robespierre had written definite laws in the

traditional legal sense, as articulations of natural law (republicanism was natural,

according to Jacobin thought). His vision of Republican utopia was not linear movement

along the lines of evolution, but rather a picture of a state to aim for. Thus Robespierre’s

terror was of course politically revolutionary, but it operated within the republican legal

framework. Nevertheless, the two are related, because both systems are marked by the

subordination of the human person (among all other concerns) to some other end -

producing a republic of virtue (in Robespierre’s case) or “the fabrication of mankind”

(the goal of the law of History and of Nature). When a philosophy or political system

takes this step (the subordination of the human person), it becomes an ideology (“isms

which…explain everything and every occurrence by deducing it from a single premise”).

Nothing matters but reaching the end - producing the republic, fabricating mankind -

ostensibly in the name of mankind itself. The problem to be noted here is the substitution

of the vague and general humanity for the neighbor in the old dictum of the Great

Commandment from Leviticus: Love thy neighbor becomes instead, Love humanity.

110

Ibid. 111

Ibid.

Page 69: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

68

Arendt, herself raised in the Jewish moral tradition, saw the flaw in this thinking. She

made very strong argument against totalitarian rule that it “destroys the space” between

individuals, destroys their “plurality” in order to create “One Man of gigantic

proportions.” In pursuit of this goal of abstract humanity, terror “eliminates individuals

for the sake of the species.”112

The flaw in this substitution of the species for the person is

that the genius of the Great Commandment lies in its praxis, in the actual work of

respecting another individual person which rises above the level of an emotional feeling

or attitude to that of an act of the will for the good of the other. This Dostoevsky

articulates perfectly in The Brothers Karamazov, with the doctor who loves humanity so

much remarking, “The more I love mankind as a whole, the less I love individual

people…The more I hate individual people, the more ardent is my general love for

mankind.”113

This is not, of course, a rule of logic, but a testament to the distinction

between programs that aim at whole societal change and working for the good of people;

the former may be necessary for the latter to be achieved, yet if such programs take on

preeminence, the systematic subordination of the person becomes dangerously possible.

This is true whether the programs be totalitarian or not, and thus this fact figures

significantly as a litmus question to be posed across a range of political, economic, and

even religious systems.

Another twentieth-century commentary to our interest in understanding the

elements of systematic murder is offered by the philosopher Isaiah Berlin. From a

philosophical perspective, rather than one of political science, Berlin offers insight into

what he describes as “the slaughter of individuals on the altars of the great historical

112

Ibid., 465,6 113

Dostoevsky, The Brothers Karamazov (New York: Bantam Dell, 2003) 71-2.

Page 70: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

69

ideals.”114

Berlin offers his own principles to guide political arrangement, which we shall

consider in due time, but first we will look into his analysis of the causal errors in

thinking, which are related to Hannah Arendt’s points, but articulate in a very specific

way the logical progression of those errors. First pointing out the flaws in practical

“monism” - the idea that all good human practices (social justice, equality, liberty,

happiness) are mutually conducive and cooperative - Berlin points out that certain goods

must be sacrificed for the attainment of others. Choosing between these objective and

subjective goods is “an inescapable characteristic of the human condition.”115

However,

when an ideology claims that one program of action will eventually provide for all those

human desires (i.e. happiness, equality, and personal freedom) it necessarily conflicts

with and subordinates those other values. Indeed, argues Berlin, this claim is the cause of

the slaughter, “the belief that somewhere, in the past or in the future, in divine revelation

or in the mind of an individual thinker, in the pronouncements of history or science, or in

the simple heart of an uncorrupted good man, there is a final solution” (emphasis

added).116

Supporting democratic values in political arrangement, Berlin notes the centrality

of liberty in the democratic system. Liberty is both a prerequisite necessity for and a goal

of democracy. However, Berlin posits that there are actually two distinct concepts of

Liberty, a “positive” and a “negative” conception, which may be distinguished simply as

“freedom from” and “freedom for.” The one notion is connected with a lack of external

coercion within an area of motion or action, while positive liberty is the power to control

114

Berlin, Isaiah, "Two Concepts of Liberty," in Social and Political Philosophy: Contemporary Readings,

eds. George Sher and Baruch A. Brody (Harcourt Brace Publishers, 1999), 8. 115

Berlin, 10. 116

Berlin, 8.

Page 71: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

70

one’s own condition, especially connected with the ability to play a role in government -

the “wish, above all, to be conscious of [one]self as a thinking, willing, active being,

bearing responsibility for [one’s] choices and able to explain them by references to

[one’s] own ideas and purposes.”117

While, infringement on either of these liberties

makes one feel “enslaved” to some degree, Berlin notes that as two separate values, they

are not necessarily mutually cooperative, and on the contrary are in “direct conflict.”

That even such an accepted good as liberty could become the cause and

justification for systematic murder is of great importance to us, particularly because it is a

democratic value (in the famous trio of liberty, equality, and fraternity). Berlin

demonstrates how such a good is transformed into a ideological end with such drastic

consequences. The value of positive liberty in conjunction with the belief that one has

found the rational final solution - the one which therefore all rational people should desire

and which Reason itself desires - can allow for one to construct a system based on his

solution, while any opponents are opposing the rational answer and therefore are acting

out of some ignorance or blindness.

“What gives such plausibility as it has to this kind of language is that we recognize that it is

possible, and at times justifiable, to coerce men in the name of some goal (let us say, justice or

public health) which they would, if they were more enlightened, themselves pursue, but do not,

because they are blind or ignorant or corrupt. This renders it easy for me to conceive of myself as

coercing others for their own sake, in their, not my, interest. I am then claiming that I know what

they truly need better than they know it themselves.”118

This is another side to the “fabricating mankind” justification in totalitarian terror that

Arendt pointed out and to the natural republicanism (along with the notion of hostes

humanis generis) that Edelstein charted in Jacobin radicalism; Berlin here reveals how

one’s assumptions can lead one to believe that one is really acting in the interests - the

true desires, in fact - of even one’s enemies.

117

Berlin, 6.

Page 72: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

71

Again, the importance of assumptions highlight the paramount importance of a

person’s or groups anthropology. Berlin sees clearly that “conceptions of freedom

directly derive from views of what constitutes a self, a person, a man.”119

What we see

emerging as a common element or formulation in systematic violence is this distortion of

the definition of the human person applied in some kind of rational program of social

arrangement. Now two clarifying points should be made with this claim. First, non-

systematic violence of course is also related to a distorted perception of the human

person; our perceptions are a basic factor in any interpersonal relations. Our focus here

on systematic murder is chiefly concerned with its justification, which seems to be a

common characteristic.120

Second, there may be objection to any talk of “the definition”

of the human person, when our perceptions are inherently subjective. “Human nature” as

a concept is prone to utilization in over-simplifications (and a subjective one at that) as

substitutes for close analysis. We will address this question in some depth when we come

to discerning (if possible) some positive principles to guide political and social relations

in order to prevent their abuse of the human person. Coming to such principles will of

course necessitate choosing some understanding, and discarding others, and this process

must be analyzed and defended. Let us only re-emphasize Berlin’s warning that “Enough

manipulation with the definition of man, and freedom can be made to mean whatever the

manipulator wishes. Recent history has made it only too clear that the issue is not merely

118

Berlin, 7. 119

Berlin, 8. 120

The justification of terror (as “an emanation of virtue” [Robespierre] or in “the reversal of our…moral

concepts” [Arendt]) is perhaps the most important challenge to us, for it is a metaphysical challenge: it

changes our categories of knowledge and language, and thus almost removes the possibility of

communication and resolution through dialogue. Thus overcoming this challenge is the most important task

for “social cooperation” as the early political philosophers like Hobbes, Mill, and Locke saw.

Page 73: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

72

academic.”121

***

In her reflections On Revolution, Arendt comments that “Theoretically, the most

far-reaching consequence of the French Revolution was the birth of the modern concept

of history in Hegel’s philosophy.”122

In Arendt’s analysis, the law of history plays an

important role in totalitarian rule in both Nazism and Communism. To our purposes, the

key element is the replacement of systems of value which uphold the human person with

systems (on either end of the political spectrum) which subordinate the human person to

some other end. Connected with Berlin’s diagnosis of the potential misuse of positive

liberty in coercing people into the rational arrangement for their own good, “those who,

throughout the nineteenth century and deep into the twentieth, followed in the footsteps

of the French Revolution, saw themselves not merely as successors of the men of the

French Revolution but as agents of history and historical necessity.”123

That the French

Revolution and the Enlightenment have had profound influence upon humanity up to and

beyond the twentieth century does not need to be argued here; we only point out that

specifically the weight given to rationality as the final measure of things has been a key

value in the moral, political, and intellectual heirs of those event, given that, “Historically

speaking, both conservative thought and reactionary movements derive not only their

most telling points and their elan but their very existence from the event of the French

Revolution.”124

Ours is an Enlightenment-guided world - even when it contradicts the

121

Berlin, 8. 122

Arendt, On Revolution, 45. 123

Arendt, On Revolution, 46. 124

Arendt, On Revolution, 287. Arendt holds that the Fr Rev departed from values, but clearly they just

applied the value of rationality as the measure of truth to different assumptions. Thus it is not quite accurate

to speak of a departure of “values,” for although the personal moral beliefs of the revolutionaries differed

Page 74: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

73

personal moral values of the philosophes, inasmuch as it seeks justification in reason -

and so long as this worldview holds, the human person is in danger.

Another term besides “totalitarianism” which came into use in the twentieth

century to describe new phenomena is “genocide,” a word now unfortunately familiar to

us. Coined by Raphael Lemkin in connection with the war crimes tribunal at Nuremburg,

genocide refers to the “destruction of a nation or of an ethnic group.”125

While this is not

the place for an in-depth analysis of that terrible phenomenon, there are some things

germane to this discussion that may be learned from it. Gregory Stanton, one of the

foremost students of genocide and the founder of Genocide Watch, an organization aimed

at preventing genocide, published a paper for the U.S. Department of State in 1996 on

preventing and responding to genocide. “The 8 Stages of Genocide” outlines a model of

genocide as a “process” that develops in logical steps. Stanton’s findings are very

revealing in light of Arendt’s and Berlin’s emphasis on the role of anthropologies.

Perceptions of the human person again play a role in the case of genocide: the most

openly violent stage of genocide according to Stanton’s model is the seventh:

Extermination, which “is “extermination” to the killers because they do not believe their

victims to be fully human.”126

Perception of the victim group as outside the category

“human” is indeed a main component right from the earliest stage, which is Classification

of the targeted group in a different class than the perceived majority. This classification

of a group of persons into a subhuman and non-person category is yet another way of

overcoming the ethical Great Command to Love thy neighbor as thyself, in this case by

and perhaps changed (see Tackett, Chapter 2), the value of the Enlightenment, the one which seemed to

provide the basis for liberty, justice, etc., was Reason. 125

,Oxford English Dictionary, “Genocide”, cf. Lemkin, Axis Rule in Occupied Europe ix. 79 126

Stanton, The 8 Stages of Genocide.

Page 75: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

74

redefining the enemy as something other than the neighbor. The concept of the “Other” is

of course a recurring theme in human interaction, manifested most often in the practice of

labeling, and this is another stage in genocide.127

The target group, after being classified

in a “outside” group, undergoes dehumanization and polarization. Dehumanizing names

such as “cockroaches” (as in the case of the term used for Tutsis in Rwanda in 1994) are

applied and the victims are actively presented as the polar opposites of the normal,

healthy, or moral majority. Most importantly, “dehumanization overcomes the normal

human revulsion against murder.”128

Along similar lines, M. Hassan Kakar, an observer

of the Soviet invasion of Afghanistan, writes that “For genocide to happen…members of

the dominant society must perceive their potential victims as less than fully human.”129

The twentieth century encounter with genocide thus reestablishes the centrality of the

human person in any moral system; terror and systematic murder when happen when

groups fail to recognize the human person as such, and when the human person is

therefore subordinated to the pursuit of some other end, whether it be equality or racial

“purity.”

***

Given the negative warnings of Arendt, Berlin, and Stanton (as well as many

other commentators), we know when programs of action are wrong - when they perceive

and use persons as objects or enemies - and we know also that the secular liberal

127

The Other is also present in various figures in literature, such as Grendel in Beowulf, who is called a

mearcstapa - a “mark-stepper” or being who inhabits the borders of the human world; or Frankenstein’s

monster, portrayed hauntingly with a human psychology and inner self, yet ostracized simply for his

appearance. The recurring figures of the witch, the monster, Quasimodo, the barbarian outside the polis all

point to a mix of fear and fascination with the Other, who has been the object of much analysis for the last

several centuries from Hegel to de Beauvoir to Levinas. 128

Stanton, The 8 Stages of Genocide 129

Kakar, M. Hassan, Afghanistan: The Soviet Invasion and the Afghan Response, 1979–1982 (Los

Angelas: University of California Press, 1997), 215.

Page 76: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

75

“project” of the Enlightenment is not enough alone to avoid the danger. This knowledge

is a sort of negative ethics: what not to do. But what positive principles should be

adopted? Stanton’s paper is itself a call for positive response, and he calls for

governments to have the “political will” to intervene in the process of genocide anywhere

in the world. Skirting discussion of national border claims, the idea of “political will” of

course goes without saying. The real question is, “who’s” will? Or, which principals shall

direct the will, political or otherwise?

Isaiah Berlin does put forward a working principle, that of “negative liberty.”

While positive liberty is more apt to be misused for systematic murder, as history has

shown, Berlin holds that negative liberty is a workable principle which is naturally

opposed to misuse. What we have here is along the lines of Mill’s harm principle, though

perhaps expanded to allow for some social benefits, which Berlin seems to deem

permissible. “Pluralism,” he writes, “with the measure of “negative” liberty that it entails,

seems to me a truer and more humane ideal than the goals of those who seek in the great

disciplined, authoritarian structures the ideal of “positive” self-mastery by classes, or peoples, or

the whole of mankind.”130

For many of the same reasons for which Mill argued against

suppression of opinion, pluralism has some practical inhibitors against mistaken idealists coercing

the people. However, as a practice even pluralism demands a grounding in principle - one needs

to value things like equality, justice, and freedom in order for pluralism to work practically. Even

those structures of social justice which infringe upon personal negative liberty would need to be

justified somehow; without a supporting principle, pluralism can slip into relativism. Even Berlin

quotes Joseph Schumpeter131

in writing, “To realize the relative validity of one’s

convictions,” said an admirable writer of our time, “and yet stand for them unflinchingly,

130

Berlin, 11.

Page 77: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

76

is what distinguishes a civilized man from a barbarian.” To demand more than this is

perhaps a deep and incurable metaphysical need; but to allow it to determine one’s

practice is a symptom of an equally deep, and more dangerous, moral and political

immaturity.”132

Unfortunately, relative validity is not sure enough ground for principles,

indeed counters the very idea of the word “conviction,” and Berlin himself should not

have crafted his argument in the first place had he not been convinced of the objective

evil of the “slaughter on the altars.” What we approach here is the very crux of the whole

matter, the “metaphysical need” which Berlin criticized as dangerous.

The systematic murderers of course do not hold that morality is relative: they

work “in a different framework which has a “morality” of its own.”133

“Right” and

“wrong” are orientations toward or away from the end of the ideology. However, it is no

very helpful response to deny the objectivity of morality, or our inability to know it

objectively. Such denial only offers a Hobbesean State of Nature which is the problem

which social cooperation seeks to overcome in the first place. Zizek addresses this

problem and the necessity of social cooperation to avoid disaster. For, he argues, without

social cooperation we live in a “dream” imagining that we can continue in our “wild

expansion,” grasping at both individual freedom and equality. Ironically, he advocates

that we take a second look at Robespierre’s claim, in order “to intervene into our pseudo-

natural development.”134

The answer to “the threat of ecological catastrophe” is to turn

again to revolutionary “institutionalization” so that people can cooperate to pursue a

“path of a contained life of balanced reproduction, focused on cultural refinement,

131

Schumpeter, Joseph, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, (Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2003), 243. 132

Berlin, 12. 133

Arendt, Totalitarianism, 78. 134

Zizek, xxxvii.

Page 78: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

77

avoiding wild expansion.”135

Zizek therefore encourages a combination of four

“moments” delineated by the philosopher Alain Badiou which support that

institutionalization of truth. These four elements are egalitarian justice, terror,

voluntarism, and trust in the people. This is ultimately a reliance on social control in

order to ensure fidelity to the people.

Here ultimately these tensions between Self and Other, Humanism and Terror

make themselves felt as the basis of any social arrangement and even of interpersonal

interaction itself. We return to those words of Robespierre which are the quintessence of

this “social control” anthropology:

If the mainspring of popular government in peacetime is virtue, the mainspring of popular

government in revolution is both virtue and terror: virtue, without which terror is disastrous;

terror, without which virtue is powerless. Terror is nothing but prompt, severe, inflexible justice; it

is therefore an emanation of virtue; it is not so much a specific principle as a consequence of the

general principle of democracy applied to our homeland’s most pressing needs.136

There is a lyrical beauty to Robespierre’s speeches, even in translation. His parallelisms

and contrasts, constructed on monumental and heroic universals, are light and graceful;

they almost carry themselves. But the meaning of the poetry is terrible and terrifying.

And we must take Robespierre at his frightening word: The “general principle,” the “sole

principle,” to which he appeals is Democracy and Republican Government. For

Robespierre, Democracy was the god; Providence, or the Supreme Being, might almost

be said to be “good” insofar as He endowed men with the Reason to be able to seek

Democracy. It seems that to Robespierre oppressing humanity is “wrong” because it is

undemocratic; or rather, what he means ultimately by oppression is non-democracy.

Oppression in the service of democracy is simply not oppression; it is “justice” and

135

Zizek, xxxvii. 136

Robespierre, speech before the Convention “On the Principles of Political Morality

that should Guide the National Convention in the Domestic Arbitration of the Republic,”

Page 79: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

78

“virtue.” Saint-Just said, “That which produces the general good is always terrible,” but

Robespierre does not agree, as can be seen in his dramatic appeals to weeping mothers

and playful children in his final speech- there is a vision, somewhere in his mind, of

idyllic utopian Republican democracy safe from the conspiring tyrants of the world, a

vision of a good unaccompanied by evil. He did not think man evil, as Zizek suggests,

but seemed to have held a Rousseauvean notion of inner goodness; like Rousseau, he

believed people were corrupted, (indeed, in a way not unlike orthodox Christian teaching

on Original Sin) - however for Robespierre corrupted man is almost no longer man. In

this Zizek’s argument applies, for the corrupted men, the schemers, the enemies and

plotters against the dream-Republic…these were “the Thing,” the “monstrous other” in

the Neighbor that we fear and loathe. And because Robespierre’s dream world could

never hold people who disagreed with him, it became necessary to seek democracy itself

in the present, and destroy those who would stand in the way: “to punish the oppressors

of humanity: that is clemency.” How? Does Robespierre simply change the definition of

clemency, which meant ever, not treating a man according to his actions, but treating him

according to one’s own mercy? No, Robespierre does not really mean to simply change a

word’s meaning to assure himself that virtue was on his side. Here, again, we take him at

his word. Punishing the oppressors of humanity is indeed mercy, for the oppressors no

longer belong to the category of humanity which is “self” but are rather exiled to the

realm of the “monstrous” Other.137

February 5, 1794, in Virtue and Terror, 115. 137

This kind of reasoning is found, for instance, in certain contemporary ethics theorists such as Judith

Thompson, who argues that self-defense or defending the innocent is permissible because the unjust

attacker relinquished the right to not be attacked, and therefore may be killed in the defense of the innocent.

But of course this idea is frightening in every aspect. One can only not attack a man because he has a right

to not be attacked? What does this say about the victim? It does not address whether one ought to attack

Page 80: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

79

Zizek’s suggestion, especially in the “trust in the people” part - “the wager that

the large majority support these sever measures, see them as their own, and are ready to

participate in their enforcement”138

- clearly falls prey to the weaknesses of positive

liberty as Berlin outlined them. And his call to take the “risk…to endorse again large-

scale collective decisions,” while addressing the dangers of unguided expansion, does not

take into account the dignity of the individual person (as Arendt said, sacrificing

“individuals for the sake of the species”).139

Reliance on social arrangement to solve the

problems of social cooperation (a key idea in so many of the “isms” offered or imposed

on humanity) is thus built on a fundamental misapprehension of the human person and of

interpersonal relation.

How then to arrive at a principle to guide such arrangement and yet remain in

keeping with the nature of the human person and of interpersonal relation. Hobbes’ great

insight was to begin with sense perception, for he saw that our convictions are tied to our

perceptions, which are inherently subjective. Locke of course countered with an appeal to

the Creator, which is the great answer of religion as a foundation for equality (i.e. that

God made us for his glory).140

But the mere appeal to the Creator is on the same level as

Robespierre’s appeal to supreme Reason, and runs the danger of providing a tautology

him or treat him well, nor does it address the obligation to protect the innocent. If one sees a man

threatening the innocent, one have the duty to protect the innocent. In the relinquishable rights view, one is

merely coincidentally present to a window of opportunity wherein the right of one of two individuals to not

be attacked has been relinquished. Furthermore, if the attacker could be incapacitated without killing him,

one is certainly not permitted to kill, even though this measure would also save the innocent. If the man had

given up his right to not be attacked, this would not be the case. Rather, it is the danger to the innocent

which must be stopped for the sake of the innocent. In the interest of the individual and of the common

good, the danger must be stopped even if it involves hurting the attacker, but not because the attacker has

given up his own dignity. 138

Zizek, xxxvii. 139

Zizek, xxxviii. 140

Locke, 247-8.

Page 81: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

80

based now upon our theology rather than our anthropology.141

But given the subjective

nature of our perception, and the clear danger of moral frameworks based on some

conviction, can we really counter the totalitarian program with another of our own with

any certainty that ours is based on the objective reality of which our perceptions differ?

Can we claim to somehow apprehend the “true” nature of the human person where so

many other projects have failed?

One way to attempt this is via our negative convictions, which are in fact accepted

with certainty by the sheer force with which crimes against the human person attack the

humanity in all of us. Indeed, the measure of any program all along has been whether it

justifies violence against the human person. Thus arising out of assurance of human

suffering, we see something of the human person emerging, as distinct from an animal in

pain, in but a few basic facts: the fact of questioning, of feeling an affront to one’s

dignity, the sense that this should not happen; the fact of an inner self capable of such

questioning; and the fact of the relational nature of that self, which finds and

comprehends meaning (of any sort, even of the questioning of suffering) through

communication with another. Mere secular pluralism does not provide for the human

person as this fundamentally relational being with an inner self, because it allows for

value to be conceived as a relative matter: truth as consensus is never acceptable for it is

not in keeping with the truth of the human person.

Arendt’s warning not to be willing to sacrifice the individual for the species is

quite in keeping with this interpersonal nature, as is Dosteovsky’s insight. Yet another

twentieth-century philosopher, statesman, and churchman has in fact argued for the pro-

141

Such flaws have clear historical precedents in pogroms and massacres during the Crusades, jihad and

holy wars in general, as well as of course in the practice of human sacrifice found in certain religio-cultural

Page 82: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

81

active principle supporting the person-as-relational idea in the principle of Love. Karol

Wojtyla, the Polish priest later to become Pope John Paul II, drew upon the psycho-social

aspects of phenomenology (which was his particular field within philosophy), combined

with his own experiences with Nazism and Soviet Communism as well as his pastoral

work with young people and families in Poland under the USSR, to produce Love and

Responsibility, which aimed to give a basis of principles for action, “a basis as definitive

as possible, relying on the most elementary truths and the most fundamental values or

goods. Such a good is the person…”142

Interestingly, the work was principally designed

to draw principles for human sexual relationships in particular, yet the reasoning applies

to human action in general, because it is still based upon the fundamental value of the

human person, which is the basis indeed for our sense of meaning, as noted in our

discussion of crimes against humanity. Wojtyla thus offers Love as the guiding moral

principle, “for love is a good peculiar to the world of persons.”143

Wojtyla first denies any validity for those systems (already dealt with here) which

subordinate the human person to some other end. As he says, “In modern times…what

we have to deal with is a conscious utilitarianism, formulated from philosophical

premises, and with scientific precision.”144

The programs decried by Berlin all valued

some form of social control over the human person; people would be free, or fully

human, only in a certain condition. The principle based on truth of the human person,

Love (which “in its “purest form” is amor benevolentae, or goodwill: willing, in motive

and action, the good of the other) can never use another person as a means to an end.

practices. 142

Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility, 16 143

ibid. 144

Wojtyla, Love and Responsibilty (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1993), 35.

Page 83: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

82

Thus those systems which allow for systematic murder by placing other values above

human life cannot be permitted.

…it becomes obvious that if the commandment to love, and the love which is the object of this

commandment, are to have any meaning, we must find a basis for them other than the utilitarian

premise and the utilitarian system of values. This can only be the personalistic principle and the

personalistic norm. This norm, in its negative aspect, states that the person is the kind of good

which does not admit of use and cannot be treated as an object of use and as such the means to an

end. In its positive form the personalistic norm confirms this: the person is a good towards which

the only proper and adequate attitude is love. This positive content of the personalistic norm is

precisely what the commandment to love teaches.145

The personalistic norm and Love are of course rooted in interpersonal relation (which is a

necessary thing in order to avoid systematic murder), but is this norm in keeping with

value of justice? The answer to this question goes back to the metaphysical nature of

love: all human values such as justice, equality, and freedom only have their very

meaning insofar as they correspond to something in the human person, namely the

dignity which demands respect. Wojtyla writes, “To be just always means giving others

what is rightly due to them. A person’s rightful due is to be treated as an object of love,

not as an object for use.”146

Love and the personalistic norm thus can never be

manipulated to subordinate the person, because their end is the person: “the general

problem of sexual relationships between man and woman [and other problems, for the

same reasons] cannot be solved in a way which contradicts the personalistic norm. we

have to do here with the value of the person, which is for all humanity the most precious

of goods - more immediate and greater than any economic good. It is therefore

impossible to subordinate the person as such to economics, since its proper sphere is that

of moral values, and they are intimately bound up with love for the person.”147

Economic

and other goods thus find their proper place in relation to the good of the human person;

145

Wojtyla, 41. 146

Wojtyla, 42.

Page 84: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

83

even the value of the species as such exists by fact of its containing persons.

Returning to the question of social arrangement, its very aim becomes clearer in

light of the personalistic norm: the end of any political or economic system must be the

good of the human community as revealed in the good of the person. Such a principle

therefore does not demand a specific arrangement, but rather that every person and every

institution recognize the inherent goodness of the person; it does not aim for a particular

utopic state, but urges society to work in an ongoing way to strive ever closer to that goal.

But at the same time, the personalistic norm provides a very concrete standard against

which to measure the validity of a course of action (i.e. war, social programs),

recognizing both the value of positive freedom as reflected in the free will which is an

essential component of that “inner self” and the value of the objective good of the person.

The objection may certainly be raised that the commandment to Love and the

personalistic norm is idealistic and abstract, no real blueprint for an political and socio-

economic arrangement. But neither does Love hold that there is one “final solution.”

Rather the ideal is necessary to provide an objective value against which to measure

systems, policies, and even individual acts. In this way Love is quite practical: within

reason, if human laws are based upon the personalistic norm, a group cannot at least

attack or subordinate the human person justifiably and systematically, “in broad

daylight,” as Arendt puts it. Within the practice of Love and the personalistic norm is

contained all the goods hoped for by even the most violent ideologies: justice, human

rights (natural and political), freedom, the fulfillment of the human person. Ironically,

perhaps Robespierre said it best: “What is the goal we are aiming for? Peaceful

enjoyment of liberty and equality; the reign of that eternal justice whose laws are

147

Wojtyla, 65.

Page 85: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

84

engraved, not in marble and stone, but in the hearts of all men, even of the slave who

forgets them, and the tyrant who denies them.”148

148

Robespierre, speech before the Convention “On the Principles of Political Morality that should Guide

the National Convention in the Domestic Arbitration of the Republic,” February 5, 1794 quoted in, Virtue

Page 86: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

85

Conclusion

On the day before his arrest, Robespierre spoke before the National Convention,

which was now largely disenchanted with the application of terror over the last several

months. Robespierre, fearing that his beloved Republic was in jeopardy, recalled the

ideals which had inspired their grand endeavor: “the French Revolution is the first to

have been founded on the theory of the rights of humanity and the principles of justice.”

This fact - for fact it was - was the material for the leading question of this project. How

indeed could a voyage announcing such a sublime destination and with such committed

members wind up in the dark reality of terror in practice? The misappropriation of such

ideals pointed us in the direction of political theory: how can the polis protect freedom

and avoid systematic terror? This question deals with the legitimization of law and

government, specifically with the notion of secular government: the idea that people can

arrive at a system which protects human rights through the application of reason.

The Age of the Enlightenment was of course the quintessential “experiment” in

reason, and was also the great influence upon the French Revolution itself, founded, as

Robespierre said, on human rights and the principles of justice. The very variety of that

period confirmed that reliance on reason was no sure means of arriving at a consensus of

law and government, let alone truth and morality. The Enlightenment served to

demonstrate that rational policies are in fact based upon the assumed premises of the

policy-makers. Nevertheless, the Enlightenment has had a lasting impact in the form of

this illusion that human beings can arrive at truth merely through the process of reason,

apart from assumptions and beliefs which are thought to be necessarily distorting.

The example of the Reign of Terror proved to be an apt example (and perhaps the

and Terror, 109-110.

Page 87: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

86

first) of how this Enlightenment illusion can have devastating results even among well-

meaning, level-headed, rational people. As Dan Edelstein helped to show, the Jacobin

republicans had as their grounding premise the idea that a very specific political

arrangement of society was necessary for the happiness and fulfillment of people. Given

this premise, there were very little lengths to which they would not go in order to achieve

that social arrangement. The prime element of the terror was its justification as a

necessary good.

The illusion of rationality which the Enlightenment engendered has held influence

even into the twentieth century and right up to our own day. The wars, revolutions,

genocides, and general disregard for human life can be summed up in Camus’ phrase,

“massacres justified by philanthropy.” The reflections and commentaries on such

phenomena from thinkers from a variety of scholarly and religious backgrounds (Hannah

Arendt was a Jewish political scientist; Gregory Stanton a Protestant in the field of law

and genocide studies; Isaiah Berlin an analytical and liberal philosopher; and Karol

Wojtyla a Catholic phenomenologist) help to reveal that one of the key flaws in the

secular illusion is the claim that social structures must be changed for people to be

fulfilled. Wojtyla’s notion of the personalistic norm and the principle of Love offer

themselves as a sound answer to the illusion rational reductionism. They are grounded in

common experience and on the premise of human value (an assumption which supports

rational inquiry and also recognizes the existential aspects of meaning), and therefore

cannot be manipulated in the way Berlin warned of because they cannot change the

definition of man without destroying their own premises.

What is perhaps the most strongest testimony of the personalistic norm is that

Page 88: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

87

while it certainly calls for social justice and structures which are in keeping with the good

of the human person, it does not admit social change at any cost. What is more, Love and

the personalistic norm are fundamentally grounded in interpersonal relation. Thus

meaning and fulfillment are not found in some future utopia, but in the present relations

of every individual; people must work toward political policies and social arrangements

which uphold human dignity, justice, and equality, but even in situations of gross

indignity, injustice, and inequality, individuals must still follow the personalistic norm

and the principle of Love. This is what was being shown in Victor Frankl’s epiphany in

the death camp at Auswitzch, when he said that “for the first time in my life I saw the

truth as it is set into song by so many poets, proclaimed as the final wisdom by so many

thinkers. The truth -- that love is the ultimate and the highest goal to which man can

aspire. Then I grasped the meaning of the greatest secret that human poetry and human

thought and belief have to impart: The salvation of man is through love and in love.”149

Today’s policy-makers must recognize in law the fundamental value of the human

person in such a way that it cannot be subordinated to any other end. This will require

overcoming finally the illusion of the Enlightenment. In this project it would perhaps be

fitting to pay heed to the words of another twentieth century thinker, one who did indeed

strive for justice, always in light of the dignity of the human person.

A just law is a man-made code that squares with the moral law or the law

of God. An unjust law is a code that is out of harmony with the moral law.

To put it in the terms of Saint Thomas Aquinas, an unjust law is a human

law that is not rooted in eternal and natural law. Any law that uplifts

human personality is just. Any law that degrades human personality is

unjust.

- Martin Luther King, Jr

Letter from a Birmingham City Jail

149

Frankl, Viktor, Man's Search for Meaning, (Nagasandra, Bangalore: Better Yourself Books, 2006), 42.

Page 89: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

88

Bibliography

Adorno, Theodor and Max Horkheimer. “The Dialectic of Enlightenment,” in The

Enlightenment: A Sourcebook and Reader, edited by Paul Hyland, Olga Gomez, and

Francesca Greensides. London and New York: Routledge, 2003.

Arendt, Hannah. On Revolution. New York: The Viking Press, 1965.

. Origins of Totalitarianism. New York: Meridian Books, Inc., 1960

. Discussion on “The Nature of Totalitarianism,” “Totalitarianism and Ideology,”

“Psychological Aspects of Totalitarianism,” and “Totalitarian Social and Economic

Organization,” in Totalitarianism: Proceedings of a Conference held at the American

Academy of Sciences March 1953, edited by Carl J. Friedrich, 75-79, 133-134, 228-

229, 336-338. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1954.

Arnold, Thomas, trans. Beowulf. London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1876.

Atomic Archive. “J. Robert Oppenheimer “Now I am become death…” Atomic Archive

Web site. http://www.atomicarchive.com/Movies/Movie8.shtml [accessed March 25,

2010].

Berlin, Isaiah. "Two Concepts of Liberty," in Social and Political Philosophy:

Contemporary Readings. Edited by George Sher and Baruch A. Brody. Harcourt

Brace Publishers, 1999.

Burke, Edmund. “Age of Chivalry,” in Modern Eloquence, Volume 9. London: Modern

Eloquence Corporation, 1923.

. Reflections on the Revolution in France. London: MacMillan and Company, 1890.

Camus, Albert. The Rebel. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1969.

Cassirer, Ernst. “The Philosophy of the Enlightenment,” in The Enlightenment: A

Sourcebook and Reader, edited by Paul Hyland, Olga Gomez, and Francesca

Greensides, 381-383. London and New York: Routledge, 2003.

Crocker III, H.W. Triumph: The Power and the Glory of the Catholic Church - a 2,000-

Year History. Roseville, California: Prima Publishing Forum, 2001.

Diderot, Denis. “Supplement to the Voyage of Bougainville,” in The Enlightenment: A

Sourcebook and Reader, edited by Paul Hyland, Olga Gomez, and Francesca

Greensides, 320-327. London and New York: Routledge, 2003.

Dostoevsky, Fyodor. The Brothers Karamazov. New York: Bantam Dell, 2003.

Edelstein, Dan. The Terror of Natural Right. Chicago and London: University of Chicago

Press, 2009.

Foucault, Michel. “What is Enlightenment?” in The Enlightenment: A Sourcebook and

Reader, edited by Paul Hyland, Olga Gomez, and Francesca Greensides, 398-400.

London and New York: Routledge, 2003.

Friedrich, Carl J., et al. Totalitarianism: Proceedings of a Conference held at the

American Academy of Sciences March 1953, edited by Carl J. Friedrich. Cambridge,

Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1954.

Frankl, Victor. Man’s Search For Meaning. Nagasandra, Bangalore: Better Yourself

Books, 2006.

Furet, Francois. Interpreting the French Revolution. New York: University of Cambridge

Press Syndicate, 1997.

Gay, Peter. The Enlightenment: an Interpretation. New York and London: W.W. Norton

and Company, 1966.

Page 90: The God of Reason: The Enlightenment Revolution And the ...

89

Habermas, Jurgen. “The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere.” In The

Enlightenment: A Sourcebook and Reader. Edited by Paul Hyland, Olga Gomez, and

Francesca Greensides. London and New York: Routledge, 2003.

Hobbes, Thomas. “Leviathan.” In Political Philosophy: the Essential Texts. Edited by

Steven M. Cahn. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.

Hyland, Paul, Olga Gomez, & Francesca Greensides, eds. The Enlightenment: A

Sourcebook and Reader. London and New York: Routledge, 2003.

Kant, Immanuel. “What is Enlightenment?” in The Enlightenment: A Sourcebook and

Reader, edited by Paul Hyland, Olga Gomez, and Francesca Greensides, 54-58.

London and New York: Routledge, 2003.

Kakar, M. Hassan. Afghanistan: The Soviet Invasion and the Afghan Response, 1979–

1982. Los Angelas: University of California Press, 1997.

Macpherson, C.B. Burke. New York: Hill and Wang, 1980.

Martin, Jean-Clement. Violence and Revolution: an Essay on the Birth of a National

Myth. Paris: Editions du Seui, 2006.

Oxford English Dictionary. Entry on “Genocide.”

http://dictionary.oed.com/cgi/entry/50093700?single=1&query_type=word&querywo

rd=genocide&first=1&max_to_show=10 (accessed February 30, 2010).

Postman, Neil. Building a Bridge to the 18th

Century. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, Inc.,

1999.

. The End of Education: Redefining the Value of School. New York: Alfred A. Knopf,

Inc., 1995.

Robespierre, Maximilien. Virtue and Terror. Edited by Slavoj Zizek and John Howe.

New York: Verso, 2007.

Rousseau, J.J. “The Social Contract,” in Aspects of Western Civilization, vol. II. Edited

by Perry M. Rogers. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Education, Inc., 2008.

. Rousseau, Jean Jacques. Profession of Faith of a Savoyard Vicar. Vol. XXXIV, Part

4. The Harvard Classics. New York: P.F. Collier & Son, 1909–14; Bartleby.com, 2001.

www.bartleby.com/34/4/. [accessed January 27, 2010].

Schumpeter, Joseph. Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy. Taylor & Francis e-Library,

2003.

Scurr, Ruth. Fatal Purity. New York: Metropolitan Books, Henry Holt and Company,

LLC, 2006.

Stanton, Gregory. “The 8 Stages of Genocide.” Genocide Watch.

http://www.genocidewatch.org/aboutgenocide/8stagesofgenocide.html [accessed

February 25, 2010].

Sutherland, D.M.G. Review of Jean-Clément Martin, “Violence et Révolution: Essai sur

la naissance d’un mythe national,” H-France Forum Vol 2, Issue 2, No. 4.

http://www.h-france.net/forum/forumvol2/SutherlandOnMartin1.html (accessed

March 20, 2010).

Tackett, Timothy. Becoming a Revolutionary. Princeton: Princeton University Press,

1996.

Wojtyla, Karol. Love and Responsibility. San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1993.