Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition...

62
Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer 1874-1945 Thomas Kuhn 1922-1996

Transcript of Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition...

Page 1: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

OxfordNovember 25, 2015

Michael Friedman

Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn:

The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science

Ernst Cassirer1874-1945

Thomas Kuhn1922-1996

Page 2: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Zurück zu Kant!

Hermann Ludwig Ferdinand von Helmholtz

1821-1894

Hermann Cohen

1842-1918

Page 3: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.
Page 4: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.
Page 5: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.
Page 6: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.
Page 7: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cohen on the B Deduction

Kant’s Theory of Experience (1871) (18852)

But through this equation we guard against the suspicion that a form that “lies ready” could be a “completed” form. Intuition, even pure intuition, is generated. It lies “ready” but is not “complete.” Such errors are only possible if one treats transcendental aesthetic without transcendental logic, if one severs the unity of the Kantian critique, if one has not made clear to oneself the form of space as contribution and instrument of the highest principle of the transcendental unity of apperception. (1885, 156)

Page 8: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Critique of Pure Reason (B), §26

But space and time are represented a priori, not merely as forms of sensible intuition, but as intuitions themselves (which contain a manifold) and thus with the determination of the unity of this manifold (see the Transcendental Aesthetic*). Therefore, unity of the synthesis of the manifold, outside us or in us, and thus a combination with which everything that is to be represented in space or time as determined must accord, is itself already given simultaneously, with (not in) these intuitions. But this synthetic unity can be no other than that of the combination of the manifold of a given intuition in general in an original consciousness, in accordance with the categories, only applied to our sensible intuition. (B160-1)

Page 9: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cohen on the B Deduction

Kant’s Theory of Experience (1871) (18852)

But through this equation we guard against the suspicion that a form that “lies ready” could be a “completed” form. Intuition, even pure intuition, is generated. It lies “ready” but is not “complete.” Such errors are only possible if one treats transcendental aesthetic without transcendental logic, if one severs the unity of the Kantian critique, if one has not made clear to oneself the form of space as contribution and instrument of the highest principle of the transcendental unity of apperception. (1885, 156)

Page 10: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer on the B Deduction

The Problem of Knowledge in the Philosophy and Science of the Modern Age, vol. II (1907)

The pure intuitions of space and time, like the concepts of pure understanding, are only different aspects and manifestations [Entfaltungen und Ausprägungen] of the basic form of the synthetic unifying function. (Cassirer: 1907, 684)

Page 11: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer on the Genetic Conception of Knowledge

Page 12: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer and Hegel

Page 13: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer and Hegel

Page 14: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer and Hegel

Page 15: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Kuhn on Scientific Revolutions

Page 16: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Kuhn on Scientific Revolutions

Page 17: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Kuhn on Scientific Revolutions

Page 18: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Kantianism with Movable Categories

“The Road since Structure” (Presidential Address), PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. Two: Symposia and Invited Papers (1990), 3-13

The Road since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970-1993, with an Autobiographical Interview (2000)

Page 19: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Kuhn and the Relativized A Priori

Reichenbach, The Theory of Relativity and A Priori Knowledge (1920).

Carnap, The Logical Structure of Language (1934)

Kuhn, “Afterwords,” in P. Horwich (ed.), World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science (1993), 311-41

Both [of Reichenbach’s] meanings make the world in some sense mind-dependent, but the first disarms the apparent threat to objectivity by insisting on the absolute fixity of the categories, while the second relativizes the categories (and the experienced world with them) to time, place, and culture. (1993, 331)

Page 20: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

The Background to Kuhn’s Historiography

I continued to study the writings of Alexandre Koyré and first encountered those of Emile Meyerson, Hélène Metzger, and Anneliese Maier. More clearly than most other recent scholars, this group has shown what it was like to think scientifically in a period when the canons of scientific thought were very different from those current today. (1970, v-vi)

A. Koyré, Galileo Studies (1939) (1978)

Page 21: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

The Background to Kuhn’s Historiography

[The proper] attitude toward past thinkers came to the history of science from philosophy. Partly it was learned from men like Lange and Cassirer who dealt historically with people or ideas that were also important for scientific development . . . And partly it was learned from a small group of neo-Kantian epistemologists, particularly Brunschvicg and Meyerson. (1977, 107-8)

Kuhn, The Essential Tension (1977)

Page 22: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

The Background to Kuhn’s Historiography

The concept of historical reconstruction that underlies [my book] has from the start been fundamental to both my historical and my philosophical work. It is by no means original: I owe it primarily to Alexandre Koyré; its ultimate sources lie in neo-Kantian philosophy. (1987, 361)

Kuhn, Black Body Theory and the Quantum Discontinuity, 1894-1912 (19872)

Page 23: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

The Background to Kuhn’s Historiography

Page 24: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

The Background to Kuhn’s Historiography

Emile Meyerson1859-1933

Page 25: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer and Meyerson

Emile Meyerson1859-1933

Ernst Cassirer1874-1945

Page 26: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer and Meyerson

Emile Meyerson1859-1933

Vol. II

Page 27: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer and Meyerson

Page 28: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer and Meyerson

Page 29: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer and Meyerson

The identity towards which thought progressively strives is not the identity of ultimate substantial things but the identity of functional orders and coordinations. (1910, 431)

Page 30: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Koyré and Meyerson

Alexandre Koyré1892-1964

Emile Meyerson1859-1933

Page 31: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Koyré and Meyerson

Alexandre Koyré1892-1964

Page 32: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Koyré versus Cassirer

Page 33: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Koyré versus Cassirer

A. Koyré, “Die Philosophie Emile Meyersons,” Deutsch-Französische Rundschau 4 (1931): 197-217

Page 34: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Kuhn, Cassirer, and Meyerson

Page 35: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Kuhn on Scientific Revolutions

Page 36: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Kuhn on Scientific Revolutions

Page 37: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Kuhn on Scientific Revolutions

There is, I think, no theory-independent way to reconstruct phrases like ‘really there’; the notion of a match between the ontology of a theory and its ‘real’ counterpart in nature now seems to me illusive in principle. Besides, as a historian, I am impressed with the implausibility of the view. I do not doubt, for example, that Newton’s mechanics improves on Aristotle’s and that Einstein’s improves on Newton’s as instruments for puzzle-solving. But I can see in their succession no coherent direction of ontological development. (1970, 206-7)

Page 38: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Kuhn on Scientific Revolutions

There is, I think, no theory-independent way to reconstruct phrases like ‘really there’; the notion of a match between the ontology of a theory and its ‘real’ counterpart in nature now seems to me illusive in principle. Besides, as a historian, I am impressed with the implausibility of the view. I do not doubt, for example, that Newton’s mechanics improves on Aristotle’s and that Einstein’s improves on Newton’s as instruments for puzzle-solving. But I can see in their succession no coherent direction of ontological development. (1970, 206-7)

Page 39: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Kuhn on Scientific Revolutions

Page 40: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.
Page 41: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

MF on Scientific Revolutions

Page 42: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

MF on Scientific Revolutions

Page 43: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

MF on Scientific Revolutions

Page 44: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

MF on Scientific Revolutions

Page 45: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

MF on Scientific Revolutions

Page 46: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

MF on Scientific Revolutions

Page 47: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

MF on Scientific Revolutions

Page 48: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

MF on Scientific Revolutions

Page 49: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

MF on Scientific Revolutions

Page 50: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Einstein on Poincaré

Geometry (G) [according to Poincaré’s standpoint] asserts nothing about the behavior of actual things, but only geometry together with the totality (P) of physical laws. We can say, symbolically, that only the sum (G) + (P) is subject to the control of experience. So (G) can be chosen arbitrarily, and also parts of (P); all of these laws are conventions. In order to avoid contradictions it is only necessary to choose the remainder of (P) in such a way that (G) and the total (P) together do justice to experience. On this conception axiomatic geometry and the part of the laws of nature that have been elevated [erhobene] to conventions appear as epistemologically of equal status. (1921, 8)

Page 51: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

MF on Scientific Revolutions

Page 52: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

MF on Scientific Revolutions

Page 53: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer on General Relativity

Page 54: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer on General Relativity

The reality of the physicist stands opposite the reality of immediate perception as a thoroughly mediated reality: as a totality, not of existing things or properties, but rather of abstract symbols of thought that serve as the expression for determinate relations of magnitude and measure, for determinate functional coordinations and dependencies in the appearances. (1921, 14)

Page 55: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer on General Relativity

The reality of the physicist stands opposite the reality of immediate perception as a thoroughly mediated reality: as a totality, not of existing things or properties, but rather of abstract symbols of thought that serve as the expression for determinate relations of magnitude and measure, for determinate functional coordinations and dependencies in the appearances. (1921, 14)

[Einstein’s theory can be incorporated within the “critical” conception of knowledge] without difficulty, for this theory is characterized from a general epistemological point of view precisely by the circumstance that in it, more consciously and more clearly than ever before, the advance from the copy theory of knowledge to the functional theory is completed. (1921, 55)

Page 56: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer on General Relativity

Kant also had emphasized decisively [that] this form of dynamical determination does not belong any longer to intuition as such, but rather it is the ‘rule of the understanding’ alone through which the existence of appearances can acquire synthetic unity and be taken together in a determinate concept of experience. (1921, 109)

The pure intuitions of space and time, like the concepts of pure understanding, are only different aspects and manifestations [Entfaltungen und Ausprägungen] of the basic form of the synthetic unifying function. (1907, 684)

Page 57: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Kant on Regulative and Constitutive Principles

constitutive principles of understanding

regulative principles of reason

necessarily instantiated in experience via spatio-

temporal schemata

can never be instantiated in spatio-temporal

experience

system of massive bodies interacting via LUG

realizes nature in general in space and time

Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science

chemistry under the Idea of the complete systematic

unity of nature

Critique of Pure ReasonAppendix to the Dialectic:

On the Regulative Use of the Ideas of Pure Reason

Page 58: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer’s Philosophy of Symbolic Forms

First Part: Language (1923)

Second Part: Mythical Thought (1925)

Third Part: The Phenomenology of Knowledge (1929)

Page 59: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

When I speak of a “Phenomenology of Knowledge,” I do not align myself with modern usage, but I go back to the fundamental meaning of “phenomenology” as Hegel [established] it. For Hegel phenomenology becomes the fundamental presupposition of philosophical knowledge, because he requires of the latter that it comprehend the totality of spiritual forms, and because this totality, according to him, can only be made visible in the transition from one form to another. [There follows a quote from Hegel to the effect that the individual has the right to demand that science provide a “ladder” from more primitive consciousness to science.] It cannot be expressed more sharply that the end, the “telos” of spirit cannot be grasped and expressed if one takes it as something self-subsistent, if one takes it as dissolved and separated from the beginning and the middle. (1929, vi-vii)

Page 60: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer’s Philosophy of Symbolic Forms

First Part: Language (1923)

Second Part: Mythical Thought (1925)

Third Part: The Phenomenology of Knowledge (1929)

Page 61: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

Cassirer on the Logic of the Cultural Sciences

1942

Page 62: Oxford November 25, 2015 Michael Friedman Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in History and Philosophy of Science Ernst Cassirer.

“Naturalistische und humanistische Begründung der Kultur-philosophie,” Göteborg Kungl. Vetenskaps- och Vinterhets-Samhälles Handlingar. 5e Földjen, Ser. A, Band 7, No. 3, 1939

In his philosophy of history Hegel wanted to provide the definitive speculative demonstration that reason is substance and infinite power. For this, however, we must, according to him, above all attain the insight that reason is “not so powerless as to pass for a mere ideal, a mere ought.” . . . If we turn back from the Hegelian meaning of the idea to the Kantian, from the idea as “absolute power” back to the idea as “infinite problem,” we must of course give up the speculative optimism of the Hegelian view of history. But, at the same time, we thereby also avoid fatalistic pessimism with its prophecies and visions of decline. [Our] acting again has a free path to decide for itself out of its own force and responsibility, and it knows that the direction and future of culture will depend on the manner of this decision. (Cassirer: 1939, 28)