Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27,...

download Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (an 12342976)

of 25

Transcript of Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27,...

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    1/25

    Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth

    JEFFREY DOWNARD

    hen it comes to truth, most interpreters assume that Nietzsche is pri-

    marily interested in one of two questions. First, what is the nature of

    truth? Second, what is the value of truth? In this article, I want to focus on a

    third question. In his early essay, On Truth and Falsity in Their Ultramoral

    Sense, Nietzsche raises a question about the origin of our pure impulse totruth.1 I will suggest that, for Nietzsche, the third question is the central ques-

    tion and must be answered before we can attempt to answer the other two.

    I maintain that Nietzsches answer to the question about the origin of our

    pure impulse to truth can be defended using arguments from Kants ethics

    and aesthetics.2 According to Kant, both empiricist and rationalist accounts

    of morality are mistaken, and for roughly the same reason. They both attempt

    to ground morality in a principle of self-love. In a strikingly similar fashion,

    Nietzsche claims that both empiricists and rationalists attempt to ground their

    accounts of truth in vanity. The upshot of the arguments is that our commit-ment to the principles of morality must, according to Kant, be grounded upon

    a pure incentive of respect, and our commitment to inquiry must, according

    to Nietzsche, be grounded upon a pure love of the truth. For both Kant and

    Nietzsche, what is at issue is the purity of the motive.

    The similarities between Kants rejection of consequentialism in ethics and

    Nietzsches rejection of consequentialism in the pursuit of truth might help

    us better understand Nietzsches criticisms. At the same time, they do not

    explain why Nietzsche maintains that the origin of our pure impulse to the

    truth is to be found in art. In order to make better sense of Nietzsches appealto art, I begin with Kants aesthetics. For both Kant and Nietzsche, it is aes-

    thetics that teaches us to love from a pure impulse. I will lay emphasis on

    the idea that Kants aesthetic argument against consequentialism is struc-

    turally similar to his ethical argument against consequentialism. When it

    comes to certain questions about truth, however, the aesthetic argument for

    a pure impulse is the stronger of the two.

    I divide the article into four sections. First, I reconstruct Nietzsches pre-

    suppositions about the origin of the human powers of cognition. Second, I

    compare Nietzsches arguments against rival accounts of the truth to Kants

    W

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    2/25

    NIETZSCHE AND KANT ON THE PUR E IMPULSE TO TRUTH 19

    ethical argument against consequentialism. Third, I compare Nietzsches argu-

    ments against rival accounts of the truth to Kants aesthetic argument against

    consequentialism. Finally, I examine the strengths and weaknesses of an aes-

    thetic defense of Nietzsches claims and try to determine whether or not such

    an argument is successful against Kants own account of moral truth.

    1. A Reconstruction of Nietzsches Presuppositions

    In his early essay on truth, Nietzche offers an explicit answer to the ques-

    tion, What is truth? He starts by telling us what truth is not. On the one hand,

    there is no such thing as a pure truth. We have no access to things as they are

    in themselves. Truth is not a logical relation between concepts and objects.

    This amounts to a rejection of a rationalist account of truth. On the other

    hand, concepts are not true in virtue of their being grounded on perceptions

    that resemble their objects. Truth is not a causal relation between objects,

    nerve impulses, perceptions, and concepts. This amounts to a rejection of an

    empiricist conception of truth. Having told us what truth is not, Nietzsche

    turns to what truth is. Truth is a sum of effects. It is a mobile army of metaphors.

    Most interpreters agree that Nietzsche challenges a traditional account of

    truth. If most interpreters are right, then how should we understand his rec-

    ommendations for rethinking the nature of truth? On the one hand, inter-

    preters such as A. C. Danto, Jacques Derrida, and Sara Kofman maintain that

    Nietzsche denies there is any such thing as truth.3 According to Danto,

    Nietzsche is offering something similar to a pragmatist account of truth. On

    such a line of interpretation, a belief is true if it is useful. If, by acting in

    accordance with the belief, we are able to satisfy our desires, then we have

    sufficient reason to treat the belief as the truth. But it is a mistake to suppose

    that beliefs correspond to the way things really are. On the other hand, inter-

    preters such as Alexander Nehemas, John Wilcox, and Maudemarie Clark

    suggest that Nietzsche accepts some parts of the common-sense account of

    truth. They insist that he is at pains to deny a metaphysical understanding of

    truth.4 They maintain that he is offering a perspectival account of truth. Such

    a reading admits that there may be many interpretations of the truth, but main-

    tains that some interpretations are better than others. According to readings

    such as these, theories of truth fall on a spectrum from those that are strongly

    noncognitivist to those that are strongly cognitivist. The debate is over where

    Nietzsche falls in this spectrum.

    Depending upon whether one thinks Nietzsche is a cognitivist or a noncog-

    nitivist determines, to some extent, the kind of value one believes he ascribes

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    3/25

    20 JEFFREY DOWNARD

    particular truth will depend on ones individual interests. If truth is relative

    to perspective, but some interpretations are more correct than others, then

    one has reason to attribute a higher value to the truth. On this question, I

    agree with Maudemarie Clark that Nietzsches mature account is neo-Kantian

    in spirit.5 The relative value of truth is determined by its place within a larger

    ideal of life. Like Kant, he denies that truth should be the single highest organ-

    izing end in our ideal. Part of Nietzsches larger project is to examine vari-

    ous ideals and argue that many, such as the ascetic ideal, are mistaken because

    they are life denying. He will praise only those philosophical expressions of

    ideals that are life affirming. Unlike Clark, however, I believe that Nietzsche

    affirmed this position in his early essay on truth. Furthermore, I believe that

    Nietzsches primary mode for evaluating the relative worth of ideals is aes-

    thetic, and it is this move to art that he announces in On Truth and Falsity

    in Their Ultramoral Sense. Having briefly sketched the interpretative ter-

    rain, let us turn to a reconstruction of this early essay on truth.

    I want to suggest that many readings of Nietzsche neglect the possibility

    that he was primarily interested in a different kind of question. Nietzsche

    suggests that it is not possible to determine whether or not our representa-

    tions correspond to the essence of things without ending up in dogmatism

    at least at the outset (TF, 180). As such, the general nature of the truth is

    probably one of the last things we will be able to determine. Over the course

    of this early essay, I believe that Nietzsche turns from the traditional ques-

    tion, What is Truth? to the question, Why ought I engage in the pursuit of the

    truth? The traditional question about the nature of truth seems to require some

    theory of the objective standards that enable us to determine the truth.

    Nietzsches question, on the other hand, seems to require an account of the

    subjective impulses that lead human beings to commit themselves (or fail to

    commit themselves) to the pursuit of the truth.

    At the very beginning of On Truth and Falsity in Their Ultramoral Sense,

    Nietzsche recites a fable in which animals living in a remote corner of the

    universe invented cognition. One reason Nietzsche calls this story a fable and

    provides a remote setting is to stress the status of the ideas contained within

    the story. The ideas are offered only as a metaphorical expression of what is

    possible. It is at least possible that animals lacking the power of cognition,

    at some specific point in time, came to possess the ability to reason.

    Furthermore, it is possible that such animals might lose the powers of cog-

    nition. It is much easier to establish the evolution of the powers of cognition

    as one possibility among others, than it is to establish the claim as a histor-

    ical fact for the world in which we live.

    Consider what is implied in the possibility that animals might have invented

    cognition. In calling these beings animals, Nietzsche does not want to set

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    4/25

    NIETZSCHE AND KANT ON THE PUR E IMPULSE TO TRUTH 21

    they lack the capacity that, according to philosophers ranging from Aristotle

    to Kant, makes us must most humanthat is, the capacity to reason. In order

    for an animal to become a rational animal, that being must gain an ability to

    think in terms of the concepts and principles of reason. In telling this fable,

    Nietzsche raises the following question. How is it possible for an animal that

    is not rational to gain the ability to reason? More specifically, how did the

    powers of cognition evolve from what were originally just natural impulses?

    Nietzsche frames this line of questioning in terms that are familiar to us

    from Rousseaus discussion of the evolution of human rationality. In the first

    and secondDiscourses, Rousseau challenges the assumption that human

    beings are essentially rational. In his hypothetical reconstruction of the state

    of nature, human beings lack both reason and language.6 In order to explain

    the evolution of reason, Rousseau insists that human beings first developed

    the capacity to use language. Reason grew out of this capacity. How did lan-

    guage ever come about? It isnt clear. Part of the answer, however, is that it

    occurred as a matter of chance. Because the development of language was

    contingent, and reason grew from the capacity to use language, the ability of

    human beings to reason is contingent as well.

    Nietzsche expresses agreement with the idea that the evolution of both lan-

    guage and reason are merely contingent both in his early essay on truth and

    in his later works. InZarathustra, for example, Nietzsche makes similar

    claims about the role of chance in the evolution of values. He asserts that

    chance is the most ancient nobility of the world (Z, 2728). Zarathustras

    goal is to free us from servitude under Purpose. What we need is an under-

    standing of how it is possible for purposes (including the ends of reason) to

    grow from what was once merely a matter of chance.

    Nietzsche claims that the moment in which the clever animals invented

    their power of cognition was the moment of their greatest deceit and arro-

    gance. Why might Nietzsche criticize these animals for their haughtiness and

    mendaciousness at the very moment that most historical philosophers would

    think is their greatest achievement? While these philosophers think of the

    cognitive powers as the source of our greatest dignity, some offer a more

    qualified assessment of the role of reason in the development of human cul-

    ture. For instance, Rousseau argues that the theoretical use of reason has not

    necessarily improved the lives of human beings. Rather, it has corrupted their

    capacity for virtue and caused them to be more self-interested and prone to

    conflict.

    As human beings gained the capacity to reason, they learned to use their

    new powers primarily as a means to attain their self-interest. Very quickly,

    human beings began to realize that their interests are better served living in

    the society of others. According to Nietzsche, the basis of society is a peace

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    5/25

    22 JEFFREY DOWNARD

    conventions (TF, 176). These conventions established the first laws of truth.

    In such a society, the only difference between the liar and the honest man is

    that the liar breaks the established conventions in the pursuit of his own self-

    ish purposes. The honest man, on the other hand, believes it is in his interest

    to obey the established conventions.

    Rousseau claims that the only characteristics essential to all human beings

    are the capacities for reflection and free choice. Much of the reason for exam-

    ining man in the state of nature is to discover what human beings would need

    to do in order to retain, and perhaps improve, their capacity to exercise free-

    dom. Part of what a philosopher should do is to uncover hidden biases and

    prejudices in the way that we employ various conceptsincluding those con-

    cepts that we hold highest such as truth, virtue, justice, honesty, and even

    freedom.

    It is here that we find Nietzsche raising questions about the evolution of

    language and the realization of freedom. He seems to think that we need a

    better account of how human beings gained the capacity to use language. His

    suggestion is that all of the concepts embodied in a language have their ori-

    gin in metaphor. It is through the activity of the artist that new ideas come

    to be expressed in language for the first time. At the same time, we cannot

    simply assume that human beings possess the capacity for freedom as part

    of their essence. Like language, we need some account of how the capacity

    for freedom evolved.

    This, I believe, is Nietzsches key point in the early essay on truth: In man

    . . . deception, flattery, falsehood and fraud, slander, display, pretentiousness,

    disguise, cloaking convention, and acting to others and to himself in short,

    the continual fluttering to and fro around the one flameVanity: all these

    things are so much the rule, and the law, that few things are more incom-

    prehensible than the way in which an honest and pure impulse to truth could

    have arisen among men (TF, 175). Our thinking can only express our sta-

    tus as free beings if the impulse to truth, or to any end for that matter, is a

    pure impulse. In order for us to explain how it is possible that human free-

    dom might arise, we need to understand how a pure impulse might evolve

    from natural inclinations.

    One might be tempted to suppose that I am misreading Nietzsches point.

    Contrary to what I have suggested, it is possible to read Nietzsche in such a

    way that he is denying the very possibility of a pure impulse. In several places,

    Nietzsche reminds us that our pursuit of ends such as truth, equality, and jus-

    tice are nothing more than the expression of personal interests. He might be

    claiming that all human actions are entirely governed by personal interests.

    The main difficulty with such a reading is that it is hard to square such

    assumptions with Nietzsches emphasis on freedom. This early essay on truth

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    6/25

    NIETZSCHE AND KANT ON THE PUR E IMPULSE TO TRUTH 23

    philosophical accounts of truth that attempt to ground inquiry on a vain

    impulse. In the second section, Nietzsche is concerned with the prerequisites

    for restoring harmony between the intuitive and rational parts of our intel-

    lect. Only where such harmony has been achieved is the intellect released

    from its former slavery. As members of the modern period, the character of

    our intellect has become fragmented and out of proportion. In particular, our

    reason has come to dominate over the intuitive part of our soul. This lack of

    harmony is not our only problem. Reason finds itself just a servant to our

    self-interest. We use it only as a tool for selecting the best means for the sat-

    isfaction of our desires. Nietzsche claims that only art can restore harmony

    between the intuitive and rational parts of our character, and only the artis-

    tic imagination can restore freedom to our intellect (TF, 19092).

    Another reason for reading Nietzsche in this manner is that it preserves the

    consistency between this early essay on truth and his later works. InZarathustra,

    for example, he tells us that the lion is the powerful spirit that prepares to do

    battle with the great dragon. The lion wants to fight this last master so that he

    can gain the freedom to be his own master. He does not possess the freedom

    to create new values. For that, the innocence and the beauty of a child is nec-

    essary. But the power of a lion is sufficient for the creation of freedom for

    oneself for new creation (Z, 2728). As in his early essay on truth, Nietzsche

    stresses the need for purity: Cast your eyes into the well of my pleasure,

    friends! . . . It shall laugh back at you in its own purity (Z, 98). Zarathustra

    tells us that even the liberated spirit must still purify himself. . . . his eyes

    must still become pure (Z, 4344). Often, this requirement of purity is referred

    to as innocence, solitude, honesty, or forgetfulness. Our experience must be

    a new beginning, an immaculate perception.

    On my reading of the essay, other interpreters were likely led into a mis-

    understanding of Nietzsches point about the purity of our impulse to truth

    by his comparison of the state of nature and modern society. In the state of

    nature, human beings lack the ability to act from a pure impulse. In modern

    society, it is difficult to determine whether or not human beings act from pure

    impulses because the motives for their actions are cloaked by social con-

    ventions. For all we know, human beings might act from selfish motives most,

    if not all, of the time. Other interpreters have made the mistake of confusing

    Nietzsches observations of modern society with the position he wants to

    advocate. Regardless of whether or not we actually do possess the capacity

    to act from pure impulses, Nietzsche wants to examine what we ought to do

    to gain or improve such a capacity. His reason for inquiring into the origins

    of our pure impulse is to determine what we would need to do to gain or

    improve such a capacity for freedom. In The Birth of Tragedy, Nietzsche

    makes the point quite clearly: Poetry does not lie outside the world as a

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    7/25

    24 JEFFREY DOWNARD

    opposite, an unvarnished expression of truth, and for this reason must cast

    away the trumpery garments worn by the supposed reality of civilized man.

    The contrast between this truth of nature and the pretentious lie of civiliza-

    tion is quite similar to that between the eternal core of things and the entire

    phenomenal world (BT, 53).

    In his early essay, the suggestion that artistic freedom is the basis of the

    harmony of our intellect is not as fully explored as it will be in his later works.7

    In The Birth of Tragedy, for instance, Nietzsche searches for the basis of artis-

    tic freedom in the experience of the beautiful and the sublime. He suggests

    that the sublimity of the Dionysian spirit has priority over the beauty of the

    Apollonian spirit (BT, 3639). InZarathustra, Nietzsche attempts to ground

    the creation of all valuesincluding such values as truth, justice, and virtue

    in the artistic imagination. I believe the upshot of his argument is a defense

    of the freedom of the artistic imagination. Contrary to Maudemarie Clarks

    suggestion that Nietzsches early essay on truth is inconsistent with his later

    essays, I want to suggest that this early essay sets up a larger philosophical

    project that he continues to develop in his later works.

    2. An Ethical Argument for a Pure Impulse to Truth

    In the first section of the early essay on truth, Nietzsche presents a series of

    objections against various philosophical accounts of the truth. What is trou-

    bling for interpreters is that the objections appear to be a mere collection of

    points without any underlying theme, much less the structure of an argument.

    Despite appearances to the contrary, I hope to show that it is possible to

    defend Nietzsches criticisms of various philosophical theories of truth using

    Kants argument against rival theories of morality.

    If Nietzsches criticisms can be defended in this manner, then we will

    secure for Nietzsche the advantages of Kants argument. The main argu-

    mentative advantage that I hope to confer on Nietzsches criticisms is that

    they are not directed against a mere collection of views. Kants argument has

    the effect of placing all philosophical accounts in a table that exhausts all of

    the possibilities. The point of the argument is to show that, despite the dif-

    ferences between the views, they are all based on the same fundamental mis-

    take. According to Kant, all rival theories of morality are grounded on a

    principle of self-love. The point of Nietzsches criticism is that all prior philo-

    sophical accounts of truth are grounded in an impulse of vanity. Let us begin

    by reconstructing Kants argument in the second Critique and Groundwork

    and then determine whether or not Nietzsches criticisms can be defended

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    8/25

    NIETZSCHE AND KANT ON THE PUR E IMPULSE TO TRUTH 25

    In the Analytic of Principles section of the second Critique, Kant argues

    that the possible material grounds of the will can be divided along two axes:

    the grounds can be either subjective or objective; and they can be either inter-

    nal or external.8 Simplifying matters, I think the argument consists of a series

    of three mutually exclusive and exhaustive dichotomies that progress along

    the following lines. First, a putative moral principle can have only one of two

    possible forms: either it is a categorical imperative or a hypothetical imper-

    ative. Second, the highest end of the fundamental principle can be one of two

    possible things: either it is an end that is determined by a principle of rea-

    son, or it is an end that is determined by the faculty of desire. Third, the incen-

    tive that connects the fundamental principle to an action can be related to the

    principle in one of two ways: either the incentive is a pure feeling of respect

    that follows from the fundamental principle, or the incentive is a feeling of

    pleasure that precedes the principle. The analytic is a series of arguments

    designed to show that only an account of moral judgment that affirms the

    first option contained in each of these three dichotomies will be able to legit-

    imate our common moral knowledge. That is, the fundamental principle must

    have the form of a categorical imperative, the end of autonomy, and a pure

    incentive of respect that follows from a formal principle. His argument is a

    regress on the conditions that a moral judgment would have to satisfy in order

    to legitimate our common understanding of morality.

    As moral agents, we must abstract from all personal inclinations and every

    contingent end when duty calls. Our will must be determined objectively by

    a principle having the form of a categorical imperative and the end of auton-

    omy. At the same time, our will must be determined subjectively by an incen-

    tive of pure respect.9 The objective conditions establish the requirements that

    any putative principle must satisfy to be a principle of morality. The subjec-

    tive conditions establish the requirements that we must meet as moral sub-

    jects for our actions to be properly determined by the moral law.

    Kant argues that all previous moral philosophers have made roughly the

    same mistake. Their mistake was to assume that the basis of our duties could

    be a material practical principle. Given the range of different moral theories,

    how is it possible that they could all be based on the same mistake? According

    to Kant, a practical principle is material and not formal if it presupposes some

    contingent end. Ultimately, the choice of any contingent end is made on the

    basis of a principle of self-love. Epicurus and Hobbes would have little dif-

    ficulty admitting that their moral theories are grounded on a principle of self-

    love. After all, they believe it is a strength and not a weakness that their

    theories are based on an account of motivation that is as psychologically plau-

    sible as self-interest. But why does Kant believe that philosophers ranging

    from Plato to Hume and Wolff have made a similar mistake? It is hard to see

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    9/25

    26 JEFFREY DOWNARD

    and a rational principle of perfection might fall prey to such an objection.

    Kants argument takes the following form. One reason that a material prin-

    ciple cannot be the basis of our duties is that such a principle has the wrong

    form. Material practical principles have the form of a hypothetical imperative

    and not a categorical imperative. Kant argues that all rational agents are under

    a practical principle that is hypothetical in its form: if an agent has adopted

    an end, then she should either adopt the necessary means to the end or forgo

    the end.10 But a principle having the form of a hypothetical imperative cannot

    be the primary principle of morality because it leaves the choice of end open.

    As a rational agent, one always has the option of choosing to forgo the end if

    one decides there is something else one would rather pursue. The only thing

    that one ought to do under a hypothetical imperative is pursue the means that

    are necessary for ones ends. Under hypothetical imperatives, there is no sense

    in which a rational agent ought to pursue any given end, except insofar as it

    is a means to some further end that the agent has adopted.

    Any attempt to justify actions by appeal to hypothetical imperatives threat-

    ens an infinite regress. If we justify an action by saying that it was a neces-

    sary means to the pursuit of a given end, we have a further question of what

    justifies the choice of the end. The only way to justify the choice of the end

    under a hypothetical imperative is if the end is a necessary means to some

    further end, and so on ad infinitum. Practically speaking, the threat of an infi-

    nite regress is not a real threat. After all, we often ground our choice of ends

    by appeal to some given inclination. The point of Kants discussion is that

    such a move does not justify the choice of the end. There is no sense in which

    we ought to choose ends that satisfy our given inclinations. We often do make

    such choices, but the choices are merely expressions of personal inclinations.

    Kant maintains that any attempt to justify a choice of an end on the basis

    of given inclinations is grounded on a principle of self-love. He calls it a prin-

    ciple of self-love for the following reason. When an agent asks the practical

    question Why should I pursue this end? and answers the question by say-

    ing The fact that I desire it is good enough reason for me, the agent is tak-

    ing this fact to be a sufficient basis for making the choice. It is a principle of

    self-love because the fact that the individual desires it is good enough rea-

    son for that individual to pursue the end. The agent has taken a merely sub-

    jective inclination and treated it as if it justified the choice. But, according

    to Kant, the only way to justify a choice in terms of determining whether or

    not it is something that one ought to do, is on the basis of a rational princi-

    ple. Practical principles can have only one of two forms: hypothetical imper-

    atives and categorical imperatives. Setting to the side imperatives that are

    categorical in their form, the only remaining type of principle that can jus-

    tify a choice is a hypothetical imperative. But the decision to pursue an end

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    10/25

    NIETZSCHE AND KANT ON THE PUR E IMPULSE TO TRUTH 27

    tion at allat least not a justification that is sufficient to establish an imper-

    ative for action. Lacking any rational justification, the choice is a mere expres-

    sion of personal interest.

    The upshot of Kants argument against philosophical theories that appeal

    to subjective inclinations is that they might offer an empirical explanation of

    our behavior, but they do not justify our choices of action in terms of any

    imperative. While such a charge might hold against empiricists such as Hobbes,

    Hutcheson, and Montaigne, how does it work against rationalists such as

    Crusius and Wolff? On both of their accounts, our choices are ultimately

    grounded on a principle of perfection.

    Theological moralists such as Crusius maintain that our choices ought to

    be guided by the pursuit of external perfection. As human beings, it is our

    place to contribute to the greater perfection of all of Gods creation. But,

    when asked why we ought to pursue such perfection, Crusuiss answer is that

    God gives us the end. Whether such an end is implanted in our natural desires,

    or the end is natural to our reason, Kant objects on grounds that such a move

    does not justify the choice of end. It does not show that we ought to pursue

    the greater perfection of all things. All that Crusius and the other theologi-

    cal moralists can establish is that we actually do pursue such an end.

    Kants objection against moral theories that posit an internal objective end

    takes a similar form. Rationalists such as Wolff claim that the principle is

    innate in our capacity for reason. It is clear that, among the four types of

    moral theories listed in Kants table, his own theory bears the closest resem-

    blance to Wolffs. Wolff asserts that the principle of perfection is innate in

    our capacity for reason, while Kant asserts that the categorical imperative is

    innate in our capacity for reason. Kant holds, however, that there is a signif-

    icant difference between a categorical imperative and a principle of perfec-

    tion. As a rational principle, a principle of perfection is a merely logical

    requirement. For any set of beliefs, or desires, or ends, we ought to attempt

    to bring them into greater harmony and completeness as a system. The prob-

    lem is that a principle of perfection does not, on its own, establish that we

    ought to pursue any particular end. As a logical principle, it is a purely for-

    mal requirement. The only way Wolff can treat the principle of perfection as

    the primary principle of morality is if he can find some way to sneak in a

    determinate end. Whether that end is virtue, knowledge, or some other end,

    Wolff has given us no reason for thinking that we ought to pursue such an

    end. His only recourse is to assert that we do pursue such ends because they

    are a natural part of our reason.

    All four types of moral theories fall prey to the same objection. The prin-

    ciples that they hold up as the primary principle of morality all have the form

    of a hypothetical imperative. Hypothetical imperatives establish only that a

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    11/25

    28 JEFFREY DOWNARD

    pursuing, all of these moral theorists simply assert that we are inclined toward

    such an end either because it is something that we desire, or because we have

    rational impulses that move us in such a direction. According to Kant, all

    such incentives, regardless of whether they are empirical or rational in char-

    acter, are impure. As such, they fail to express our freedom as moral agents.

    Only an incentive of respect that is generated by an awareness of the cate-

    gorical imperative is pure. The reason is that only a principle of this form

    expresses our autonomy as moral agents. The difference is a matter of pri-

    ority. The feeling of respect is pure because it follows from the moral law.

    All other moral theories use a form of justification that puts the incentive

    first and the principle second.

    At this point, let us turn to Nietzsches argument against both rationalist

    and empiricist accounts of truth. I hope to show that Nietzsches criticisms

    can be defended using Kants moral argument against consequentialism. If

    Nietzsches criticisms can be defended in this manner, then his criticisms will

    work against any philosophical account of truth that is grounded on a prin-

    ciple of self-love. The targets of Nietzsches criticisms in his early essay on

    truth can be divided, according to Kants table, along the axes of subjective

    and objective accounts. Taking them in reverse order from Kants argument,

    let us first examine rationalist accounts of truth.

    According to Nietzsche, such theories posit the following kinds of claims.

    Rational beings control their behavior entirely by abstractions. Their aim is

    to avoid being carried away by a disorderly array of perceptual impressions.

    Abstract concepts can be put into a pyramidal order of genus and species,

    with the unruly impressions residing at the bottom. Standing back, looking

    at the pyramid that we have constructed, we are impressed by those concepts

    that are more fixed, general, known, human of the two and therefore the reg-

    ulating and imperative one (TF, 181). In creating such a world of concepts,

    our conduct is regulated by imperatives. These imperatives guide the con-

    duct of our inquiry and determine how we ought to form concepts and dis-

    tinguish between those assertions that are worthy of being believed and those

    that ought to be treated as false. The target of Nietzsches criticism is, first

    and foremost, the imperatives that rationalists think should guide the con-

    duct of our inquiry, and only secondly the beliefs that are held to be true at

    any given time as a result of following those imperatives.

    Nietzsche makes his criticism of rationalist accounts of truth in the fol-

    lowing terms.

    When someone hides something behind a bush and looks for it again in the

    same place and finds it there as well, there is not much to praise in such seek-

    ing and finding. Yet this is how matters stand regarding seeking and finding

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    12/25

    NIETZSCHE AND KANT ON THE PUR E IMPULSE TO TRUTH 29

    Nietzsches criticism has the same structure as Kants criticism of Wolffs

    moral theory. On both accounts, the mistake of the rationalists was to assume

    that merely logical principles could establish how we ought to conduct our-

    selveseither morally or in scientific inquiry. Logical principles cannot

    establish what we ought to hold as true any more than they can establish

    ends that are morally worthy of our pursuit. In order to hide this flaw, ratio-

    nalists try to sneak in a given end or belief. But the question remains, is that

    end really worth pursuing and is that assertion really worth believing? We

    should note that Nietzsche does not assert that the belief adopted on the basis

    of such a procedure is false. Rather, he says that it has limited value as a

    truth. The reason is that the belief is, to some extent, improved by follow-

    ing the rationalists method. It is rendered more consistent and harmonious

    with all the other assertions that are held to be true. But the rationalists have

    failed to use a method that honestly asks whether or not the belief itself is

    worthy of being believed.

    By way of contrast, empiricists explain the origins of our beliefs in the

    following kinds of terms. A habitual relation between a word and certain

    images is caused by mere repetition. A nerve stimulus causes an image to

    appear in our consciousness as a sound or a sight. Objects external to us

    cause the stimulation of our nerves. Nietzsches first point against an empiri-

    cist account is that the appeal to an object outside of us is the result of a

    wrong and unjustifiable application of the concept of causality (TF, 177).

    This concept has led empiricists to formulate a chain of causes, each one

    explaining what follows it in the series. Empiricists such as Hobbes and

    Hume openly assume that all objects have the same basic nature (material

    objects for Hobbes and conscious impressions for Hume), and all relations

    between things must be understood in terms ofde facto causes. But insuf-

    ficient justification is given for the presumption that words, images, nerve

    impulses, and objects external to us all have the same nature and can all

    stand in causal relations to one another.

    Empiricists believe that these kinds of philosophical assumptions should

    guide our inquiry. Nietzsche takes issue first and foremost with the impera-

    tives that they think should regulate our conduct. What is the basis of these

    imperatives? Why not think that there is a difference in kind between nerve

    impulses and conscious images? Why not think that the relation between the

    two is fundamentally an aesthetic relation and not a merely de facto causal

    relation? The question that Nietzsche puts to the empiricists is at root the

    same as the question he puts to the rationalists.

    The point of Nietzsches criticism of both rationalists and empiricists can

    be understood by considering his account of our move from the state of nature

    to the state of society. In order to end the war of all against all, human beings

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    13/25

    30 JEFFREY DOWNARD

    honest person follows the fixed conventions, the liar uses the fixed conven-

    tions to make things that are unreal appear to be real (TF, 2). He reverses

    the fixed conventions and says, for example, I am honest, when the correct

    word for his actions is dishonest. The liar misuses the proper designations

    for his own selfish purposes and causes harm to others. The majority of peo-

    ple follow the established conventions, but are their actions any less fraudu-

    lent? What the majority of people hate is not being deceived, but the harmful

    consequences of being deceived.

    Once again, Nietzsche does not assert that there is no value to such a grade

    of truth. Rather, he wants to question whether there is a higher grade of truth

    that we ought to pursue. The point of his criticism of both rationalists and

    empiricists is to question whether or not the imperatives that they recom-

    mend for the conduct of our inquiry can lift us out of the this state. In this

    state, we can establish a certain peace. We can rest in confidence that the

    fixed conventions have the status of accepted certainties. But we lack free-

    dom. Nietzsche does not believe that either account can improve our free-

    dom. The reason is that neither teaches us to act from a pure impulse to truth.

    Rather, they encourage us to seek the pleasant consequences of preserving

    the fixed conventions.

    3. An Aesthetic Argument for a Pure Impulse to Truth

    Nietzsche maintains that art and not morality is the origin of our pure impulse

    to truth. I believe that Nietzsches purpose in appealing to art is to find a basis

    for establishing and perhaps improving our freedom as inquirers. According

    to both Nietzsche and Kant, aesthetic judgments express a special kind of

    freedom. Kant maintains that this freedom surpasses even the autonomy of

    our moral agency.11 Like moral judgments, aesthetic judgments must be free

    from any given inclination or contingent purpose. Unlike moral judgments,

    aesthetic judgments must be free from any given concept or principle, includ-

    ing the ends and principles of reason. Given Nietzsches larger philosophi-

    cal project, this fact makes it easy to see why he would appeal to art. His

    question is one of how the capacity to act from a pure impulse ever evolved

    from natural inclinations. Furthermore, he wants to give an account of how

    this capacity evolved that does not make an appeal to either language or rea-

    son. It is the independence of art from both the concepts embodied in lan-

    guage and the principles of reason that makes art an especially appealing

    candidate.

    At this point, I would like to review the general features of Kants account

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    14/25

    NIETZSCHE AND KANT ON THE PUR E IMPULSE TO TRUTH 31

    for thinking that there are substantial agreements between Kant and Nietzsche

    about the nature of aesthetic judgments. In his early essay on truth, Nietzsche

    does not offer an account of aesthetic judgment. As such, I would like to start

    by briefly reviewing the agreements that Nietzsche expresses in both The Birth

    of Tragedy andZarathustra with Kants aesthetics. According to both Kant and

    Nietzsche, there are two types of aesthetic judgments. We experience the sub-

    lime when we confront the infinitude of abysses, mountains, and storms. We

    experience the beautiful when we hear the harmony of a piano sonata or see

    the unity in a painting. Setting to the side the differences between these two

    types of judgments, let us focus on the points that are common to both.

    Kants analytic is an attempt to make sense of three conflicting intuitions

    that we share about aesthetics.12 On the one hand, matters of art are a matter

    of personal taste. Aesthetic estimations are subjective judgments. Because

    they are subjective, there are no objective proofs to which we could appeal

    to settle disputes. At the same time, we do quarrel about matters of beauty

    and sublimity. If I find a painting beautiful and you think it is ugly, we take

    ourselves to be engaged in a real disagreement even if there are no objective

    grounds to settle the dispute. In order to help settle our quarrel, I might point

    to the harmony of shapes, while you might point to the unattractive colors.

    Nietzsche maintains that the distinction between the subjective and the

    objective cannot be used in aesthetics to do any philosophical work.

    Nietzsches main point, like Kants, is that aesthetic judgments are not merely

    subjective. They are not expressions of what is merely agreeable for an indi-

    vidual. A judgment of taste cannot be based on the satisfaction of personal

    preferences: the striving individual bent on furthering his egoistic pur-

    posescan be thought of only as an enemy to art, never as its source (BT,

    41). At the same time, aesthetic judgments are not determinative judgments,

    for there are no objective grounds for matters of taste. Nietzsche challenges

    the idea that aesthetics is grounded on standards of reason (Z, 166). He wants

    to suggest that the aesthetics must be independent of such determinate con-

    cepts and principles.

    Nietzsche recognizes that there can be quarrels over matters of taste. In

    fact, he elevates the idea to a crucial position in his argument inZarathustra

    when he challenges those who would maintain that judgments of taste are

    merely subjective expressions of personal preference: [t]astethat is at the

    same time weight and scales and weigher; and woe unto all the living that

    would live without disputes over weight and scales and weighers! (Z, 117).

    The fundamental prerequisite to being a self-conqueror is that one over-

    come ones personal biases and prejudices. According to Kants transcen-

    dental analysis, judgments of taste must be grounded on a disinterested

    pleasure. In order for the pleasure that we take in an aesthetic experience to

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    15/25

    32 JEFFREY DOWNARD

    cising his judgment, Zarathustra tells us that he had to fly to the highest

    spheres that (he) might find the fount of pleasure again (Z, 98). Not only do

    we need to set aside our interest in what we find agreeable and what we find

    to be consistent with our prudential interests, but we must also set aside our

    interest in satisfying the requirements of morality (BT, 142).

    According to Kants analysis, aesthetic judgments must be purposive with-

    out any given purpose. Zarathustra teaches us to live without any depend-

    ence upon given ends. He urges us to renounce any servitude under given

    purposes. Often, Nietzsche refers to such a condition as a matter of chance

    or accident. It is through the purposiveness of art that purposes grow from

    mere accidents (Z, 62). Purposiveness is realized where harmony and unity

    are restored to what was merely fragmentary.

    Under the last two moments of Kants analysis, aesthetic judgments must

    make claims of subjective universality and subjective necessity. When we

    estimate the beauty or sublimity of an object, we make claims to the effect

    that all other human beings ought to agree with our judgment. 13 The judg-

    ment is universal insofar as it makes a claim on all others. According to

    Nietzsche, judgments of taste help us to become reconciled to one another

    by teaching the gospel of universal harmony (BT, 1924). A judgment of

    taste is necessary insofar as it makes a claim on how others oughtto estimate

    the object. According to Nietzsche, in the Apollonian state we experience

    dreams with a sense of real necessity. For Zarathustra, the Thou shalt is

    higher than to command for those that are sublime (Z, 48). Nietzsche rec-

    ognizes that it is possible to make such claims of necessity only where you

    have set aside personal biases and prejudices. As such, you can only make

    such claims where you call this cessation of all need necessity (Z, 77, 222).

    So far, we have reviewed the agreements between Kant and Nietzsche on

    aesthetic judgments and have found them to be in substantial agreement on

    major points. The fact that the agreements are found in both The Birth of

    Tragedy and Zarathustra is evidence that Nietzsche did not dramatically

    alter his position on these points in aesthetics between his early and later

    periods.14 Furthermore, the fact that Truth and Falsity in Their Ultramoral

    Sense and The Birth of Tragedy were published at about the same time indi-

    cates that Nietzsche was likely working with such ideas in his early essay

    on truth.

    Kant tells us that the key to the critique of taste is in the solution to the

    following problem. The question is whether the feeling of pleasure that we

    take in an aesthetic judgment follows from the judgment, or whether the feel-

    ing of pleasure precedes the judgment.15 Only if the feeling of pleasure fol-

    lows from the judgment is the judgment free from determination by external

    causes. Only if the judgment is free from such causes can we presume to

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    16/25

    NIETZSCHE AND KANT ON THE PUR E IMPULSE TO TRUTH 33

    ment, the basis for the correctness of the judgment is the complete freedom

    of the subject.

    Here we find what may be the key to understanding Nietzsches account of

    aesthetic judgments. In Nietzsches terms, the purely perspectival character

    of aesthetic judgments is the key to their legislative authority. For Kant, one

    who is engaged in an act of aesthetic judgment can tell us how we ought to

    judge because only a subjective necessity is presupposed by such judgments.

    Taste claims a special kind of autonomy. Only where we have overcome all

    of the external causes of bias in judgment, including the tyranny of our feel-

    ings, the tyranny of reason (scientific, prudential, and moral) and even the

    tyranny of the object and the truth of its existence, does our judgment have

    autonomy. Only where autonomy has been realized can we presume to tell

    others how they ought to judge, assuming that they have adopted an aesthetic

    perspective and distanced themselves from their own biases and prejudices.

    The structural similarities between Kants two arguments against conse-

    quentialism are striking. In both Kants ethics and his aesthetics, the issue is

    one of the purity of the judgment. Because of the structural similarities between

    the two arguments, we can make the same kinds of arguments against ratio-

    nalist and empiricist accounts of truth from the perspective of art as can be

    made from the perspective of ethics. On Kants account, aesthetic reflective

    judgments share some of the same features as determinative moral judgments.

    Most important, aesthetic reflective judgments are categorical in their form

    even though they are singular judgments and are not determined by an objec-

    tive principle of reason. Because they are categorical and not hypothetical,

    aesthetic judgments must be grounded in a pure impulse. Kant claims that

    the experience of the sublime teaches us to esteem in opposition to our inter-

    ests and that the experience of the beautiful teaches us to love. In a similar

    fashion, Nietzsche claims that the experience of the sublime gives us a height

    above our vanity and the experience of the beautiful teaches how to love

    something, such as the truth, from a pure impulse (Z, 11618).

    4. Defending Nietzsches Appeal to Art Against Kant

    In this last section, I want to argue that Nietzsches appeal to art as a basis

    for our pure impulse to the truth can be defended using arguments from Kants

    aesthetics. In fact, I will suggest that the aesthetic argument for a pure impulse

    can be used to show that Kants own account of moral truth is grounded on

    an impulse of self-love. That is, on certain questions, Kant has fallen prey to

    his own objections against consequentialism. This point is easiest to see if

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    17/25

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    18/25

    NIETZSCHE AND KANT ON THE PUR E IMPULSE TO TRUTH 35

    we infer general laws in order to explain the individual pieces of data.

    Nietzsche draws an analogy between the concept of honesty and the concept

    of a leaf to make this point. In botany, we start with many different individ-

    ual images of leaves. Only later, by a process of abstraction, do we infer the

    general concept of a leaf. For us, the general property that all leaves have in

    common in virtue of which they are all leaves is an occult property. To claim

    that a property is occult is to maintain that it is, for us, hidden from view and

    mysterious. The reason is that we have no direct acquaintance with such gen-

    eral properties. We always perceive leaves as individual images. We never

    directly perceive general properties.

    Famously, Kant makes a similar point about the epistemology of the nat-

    ural sciences in the first Critique. All of our perceptions are given as indi-

    vidual intuitions. The application of general concepts to objects as they exist

    is always grounded in individual intuitions. His main reason for insisting that

    ethics is different and must start from an awareness of the principles of rea-

    son is that ethics is not an inquiry into how we in fact do act, but how we

    ought to act. In this respect, ethics is like logic, which does not merely explain

    how we in fact do think, but teaches how we ought to think.16 The require-

    ments for how we ought to act, like the requirements for how we ought to

    think, must be grounded upon timeless principles of reason; otherwise the

    requirements could not be absolutely necessary. An ethics or logic that was

    grounded on individual cases could never be anything more than an empiri-

    cal description of how we in fact do act or think.

    It is in response to this objection that we find another advantage of turn-

    ing to aesthetics. Namely, it gives us a model of singular judgments in which

    the estimations are fundamentally normative. When we estimate the beauty

    or the sublimity of a work of art, we make a judgment of the worth of an

    individual example. The estimation is one of good or bad or, perhaps more

    accurately, better or worse. Using aesthetics as the model for such judgments,

    Nietzsche can avoid the charge that the individual pieces of data are merely

    empirical observations.

    Kant might object that an epistemology built on inferences from individ-

    ual cases can give no account of the overriding character of our obligation

    to be honest. One response to such an objection is that there is no need to

    explain the overriding character of such obligations. Kant mistakenly assumes

    that we have knowledge of what duty requires. Based on such an assump-

    tion, he argues that our obligations must be grounded on absolutely neces-

    sary principles of reason. Furthermore, he had to assume that all minimally

    rational agents are quite aware of these principles, even if they cannot fully

    articulate their form. Living in the twenty-first century, we are a bit more

    sanguine about our understanding of the requirements of morality. Faced with

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    19/25

    36 JEFFREY DOWNARD

    assumptions about certainty in the moral realm. Nietzsche, living in an age

    much closer to our own than Kant, was willing to challenge such assump-

    tions about moral certainty.

    Perhaps a better response to the objection starts by pointing out that aes-

    thetic judgments, on Kants own account, do carry a certain kind of necessity.

    While they dont carry the objective necessity that is implied in Kants account

    of moral judgment, they do make a claim to subjective necessity. The open

    question is whether subjective necessity is sufficient when it comes to truth.

    I believe the shift from objective standards of reason to subjective impulses

    makes all the difference in the world. If it is not possible to determine at the

    outset what the principles of reason really are, or how we ought to use those

    principles to determine what the truth really is (without ending in dogma-

    tism), then it is an open question why any individual person ought to pursue

    the truth. Nietzsches task is to show that we may have sufficient subjective

    grounds to pursue the truth, even if we do not have any clear idea what it

    might turn out to be. If we do not know at the outset what we might find if

    we search for the truth, we run the risk of finding something that is contrary

    to our desires, disrupts the peace, and even threatens our lives. Given such a

    possibility, the task is to show that we have sufficient subjective grounds to

    pursue the truth, even if it turns out to be something that is contrary to our

    personal interests.

    In order to determine whether or not subjective necessities are sufficient

    for matters of truth, we need to focus more closely on Nietzsches point of

    attack. Nietzsche questions the metaphysical assumptions that are often made

    about truth. As scientists, we seek to convince ourselves of the eternal rigid-

    ity, omnipresence, and infallibility of natures laws and that everything is

    quite secure, complete, infinite, determined, and continuous (TF, 185). The

    metaphysical principles behind such assumptions include the principles of

    sufficient reason and continuity. According to Kant, we have no right to

    assume that nature corresponds to such principles. Rather, such principles

    are merely regulative for our inquiry. Regulative principles are only subjec-

    tively sufficient for us as inquirers.17 We ought to act as if nature was entirely

    complete, determined, and continuous, even if it turns out that nature is, in

    at least some respects, incomplete, indeterminate, and discontinuous. Kant

    tells us that such regulative principles have the status of transcendental hypothe-

    ses. They are not objectively sufficient to establish what must be the case,

    but they are subjectively sufficient to serve as a belief or as a hope for how

    we ought to act.

    It is at this level of the debate that Nietzsche can engage with Kant. In a

    number of places, Nietzsche forwards some of his most importantand most

    contestedideas as hypotheses, conjectures, and guesses (BT, 32). Nietzsche

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    20/25

    NIETZSCHE AND KANT ON THE PUR E IMPULSE TO TRUTH 37

    dictory (GM, 156). But the kinds of contradictions that we ought to reject are

    not limited only to logical contradictions. There is no logical contradiction

    in assuming that we know what honesty is. Nietzsche is attempting to warn

    us against making grand assumptions that contradict the purposes of making

    a hypothesis in the first place. Such hypotheses are counterproductive to the

    purposes of experimental inquiry. In key places inZarathustra, for example,

    Nietzsche addresses himself solely to those experimenters that are willing to

    hazard a daring guess.18 He does so to point out that the claims made will be

    legitimate only as conjectures and only from the perspective of those that are

    engaged in experimental inquiry.

    According to Kant, truth and falsity are but one species of the more gen-

    eral standards of correctness and incorrectness of judgments.19 Certain aspects

    of the standards of correctness may vary from one area of inquiry to the next.

    What makes a judgment true in mathematics is different in some respects

    from what makes a judgment true in the natural sciences. Furthermore, the

    standards of correctness in ethics are not primarily a matter of truth and fal-

    sity, but that of right and wrong. In aesthetics, we have no need for a simple

    dichotomy when it comes to the correctness of the judgments. Rather, dif-

    ferences in terms of degrees of better and worse are more appropriate.

    What I find especially insightful about Nietzsches early essay is that he

    thought to raise questions about the standards of correctness for claims about

    truth. Rationalists say that truth is a logical relation between concepts and

    objects. Empiricists say that truth is a causal relation between objects, nerve

    impulses, and perceptions. Nietzsche seems to be asking, What is the stan-

    dard for judging the correctness or incorrectness of such claims about truth

    generally? Given that there are a number of different standards of correct-

    ness, what should be the model for the core set of standards that all areas of

    inquiry share? (GM, 28689). When it comes to claims about truth itself,

    should the standard of correctness be modeled on judgments in mathematics

    or natural science? Or, should the standard be modeled on judgments of right

    and wrong in ethics? Nietzsche suggests that the standards of correctness

    should be modeled on aesthetic estimations of better and worse. Art is the

    proper model for understanding the origin of our pure impulse to truth because

    art is the origin of our pure impulse generally. If aesthetics is the origin of

    the general standards of correctness for judgments, then we have reason to

    question whether or not we need a set of objective standards at the core.

    Why should we think that Nietzsche is right to claim that art is the origin

    of our pure impulse to truth? Why shouldnt we agree with Kant that a pure

    impulse to the truth can and should be grounded in practical reason? I believe

    that Nietzsche can make the same criticism of Kant that he has made of empiri-

    cist and especially rationalist accounts of truth. Namely, that on certain ques-

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    21/25

    38 JEFFREY DOWNARD

    reason Kant falls prey to such an objection is that there are a whole host of

    questions Kant is unable or unwilling to admit are real questions.

    Let us start with Nietzsches example of honesty. According to Kant, why

    should we be honest? The answer is that any minimally rational agent rec-

    ognizes a duty to be honest. Rational agents need no further reason to do their

    duty because the principles of morality give them overriding reasons to be

    moral. On Kants account, can a moral agent honestly question what it is to

    be honest? What I mean is, supposing the circumstances are perfectly clear,

    and supposing that there are no apparent conflicts of duty, can a moral agent

    honestly raise the question, what ought I to do? Kant maintains that any min-

    imally rational agent already knows the answer. Such an agent may feel a

    temptation to violate the duty to be honest, but the agent recognizes that the

    duty to be honest should always be given the highest respect.

    Nietzsche seems to think that we can raise honest questions about our val-

    ues. On the one hand, the requirements of conscience do appear to impose

    necessary obligations for our conscience. On the other hand, we can raise

    questions about what, in particular, is required by an obligation. Furthermore,

    we can raise questions about the legitimacy of an obligation itself. As moral

    agents, we realize that social traditions and personal biases may unduly affect

    our conception of the requirements of morality. Even those requirements of

    conscience that seem the clearest and the strongest may, in a manner great

    or small, be infected by certain biases and prejudices.

    Kant insists that all minimally rational agents know what duty requires

    and, as such, are aware of the principles of morality. When a question about

    the requirements of morality arises, all we need to do is carefully abstract

    from our personal biases and prejudices and focus our attention on the prin-

    ciples that are innate to our power of practical reason. In effect, the answers

    to any moral questions that might arise are already contained in the princi-

    ples embedded in our conscience. We can rest assured that the principles are

    absolutely universal and necessary. As a system of principles, the set is com-

    plete, consistent, and unchanging. Why does Kant believe that the system of

    moral principles has these general features? In ethics, he takes a stronger

    stand than he does in natural science. The ideas of freedom, immortality, and

    God are regulative ideas that are justified only as practical postulates. But

    the ideas that the requirements of morality are absolutely universal, neces-

    sary, complete, consistent, and unchanging are constitutive of the very idea

    of a categorical imperative. In ethics, we know with significantly more cer-

    tainty that the requirements of morality really do have these general features.20

    Nietzsche is free to question Kants assumptions on such general points.

    How do we know the truth about honesty with such certainty? Kants response

    is that we just know the principles of morality. Nietzsches point is that such

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    22/25

    NIETZSCHE AND KANT ON THE PUR E IMPULSE TO TRUTH 39

    to avoid the question. Why does Kant seek to avoid the question? His reason

    seems to be that the question leads us to skepticism about the requirements

    of morality. A natural response to Kants worry is that such questions may

    lead us to be skeptical about claims to certainty in ethics, but it is an open

    question as to whether or not we need such certainty in ethics.

    Kants mistake was to turn his back on questions that we ought not ignore.

    He closes the door to inquiry by setting to the side questions to which we

    ought to seek answers. That is a bad habit to inculcate. Nietzsches criticism

    works equally well against both the rationalists and Kant (GM, 28992). The

    attempt to avoid real questions by saying that the question has no answer, or

    by simply assuming an answer, is ultimately grounded on vanity. The fact

    that you happen not to like the consequences that follow from the question

    is not sufficient reason to set the question to the side.

    Kant would have been better off to forward such claims as regulative prin-

    ciples. He could have made his claims about the absolute necessity and uni-

    versality of the principles of duty as transcendental hypotheses. While such

    a move would have avoided premature claims to certainty, it would not remove

    Nietzsches objection. As a hypothesis, the claim that the principles of prac-

    tical reason are absolutely universal and necessary is not a good hypothesis.

    The problem is not that it is false. For all we know, the principles of moral-

    ity may be absolutely necessary and universal. The problem is that, as a

    hypothesis, it does not answer real questions. How can I be so sure that my

    understanding of my moral duties is correct? I have a clear understanding of

    the principles of morality and it is plausible to suppose that those principles

    are absolute. Simply asserting that the principles of morality are absolutely

    universal and necessary does not answer the question, regardless of whether

    the assertions are forwarded with certainty or only as hypotheses.

    Having made what I take to be the main point of Nietzsches criticism in

    his early essay on truth, and having turned the criticism toward Kants ethics,

    let us step back and consider how he might have obtained the upper hand in

    the debate. The main question is, When engaged in inquiry, why ought I to

    commit myself to standards of correctness in general? Kant and Nietzsche

    agree that the pursuit of truth must be grounded on a free impulse. The advan-

    tage of modeling the standards of correctness on aesthetic judgments and not

    moral judgments of duty is the following. The former but not the latter are

    free from determination by any given purpose or rule. As such, Nietzsche

    does not need to make nearly as many presumptions about the nature of truth

    as Kant. The fact that aesthetic judgments are not determined by objective

    principles was thought to be their greatest weakness. But Nietzsche seeks to

    turn a weakness into a source of strength. The greatest strength of aesthetic

    judgments is their superior freedom from such presumptions. Aesthetic judg-

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    23/25

    40 JEFFREY DOWNARD

    to truth. When we forward a hypothesis, we say that it would explain a cer-

    tain phenomenon if it were truth. We think it is a plausible conjecture, but

    we do not (at least yet) claim that it is true. Similarly, the freedom of an aes-

    thetic judgment is predicated upon its independence from any claims to truth.

    Nietzsche wants to raise further questions. What is the origin of our pure

    impulse to the truth? How can beings that were once governed entirely by

    self-interest ever gain the capacity for freedom? In order to gain the upper

    hand on these questions, Nietzsche does not need to assume that the capac-

    ity to act from pure impulses did in fact evolve from natural inclinations. The

    main advantage to his position is not merely that he can give answers to ques-

    tions that Kant cannot. Rather, the main advantage to his position is that he

    can raise the questions in the first place. Because he does not need to pre-

    suppose the status of any rules or ends, he is free to pursue any line of inquiry

    whatsoever, let the consequences of what he discovers be damned.

    Once we have decided to address such questions in the terms of art, we

    have new resources available to us. Instead of having to ignore certain diffi-

    culties, we can stare them in the face. For Nietzsche, overcoming our servi-

    tude to vanity is the greatest hurdle: Nature threw away the key; and woe

    to the fatal curiosity which might be able for a moment to look out and down

    through a crevice in the chamber of consciousness, and discover that man is

    indifferent to his own ignorance, is resting on the pitiless, the greedy, the

    insatiable, the murderous, and, as it were, hanging in dreams on the back of

    a tiger (TF, 177). Ultimately, the way in which we need to face such chal-

    lenges is to let the sublimity of the task remind us of the sublimity in our-

    selves.

    Northern Arizona University

    NOTES1. References to Nietzsches works are cited in the text with the following abbreviations:

    TF: On Truth and Falsity in Their Ultramoral Sense, inEarly Greek Philosophy and Other

    Essays, ed. Oscar Levy (New York: Russell & Russell, 1964), 17192.

    BTand GM: The Birth of Tragedy and The Geneology of Morals, trans. Francis Golffing

    (New York: Doubleday, 1956).

    Z: Thus Spoke Zarathustra, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Penguin, 1966).

    BGE: Beyond Good and Evil, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (New York: Penguin, 1990).

    2. My purpose in comparing Nietzsches and Kants arguments is to show that there are

    points of agreement between the two and that Kants arguments can be used to defend some

    of Nietzsches claims. I do not attempt to show that Nietzsches views are based on his read-

    ing of Kants texts. My assumption is that there are at least enough points of agreement between

    Kant and Nietzsche about the nature of aesthetic judgment to get a debate between the two

    off the ground.

    3. Arthur Danto,Nietzsche as Philosopher(New York: Macmillan, 1965); Jacques Derrida,

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    24/25

    NIETZSCHE AND KANT ON THE PUR E IMPULSE TO TRUTH 41

    4. Alexander Nehemas,Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,

    1985); John Wilcox, Truth and Value in Nietzsche (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press,

    1974); Maudemarie Clark,Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge, 1990).

    5. See Matthew Rampley inNietzsche, Aesthetics, and Modernity (Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press, 2000); David Cartwright, Nietzsches Kantian Critique of Pity,Journal of

    the History of Ideas 45:1 (1984).

    6. Rousseau, The Basic Political Writings, trans. Donald Cress and Peter Gay (Indianapolis:

    Hackett, 1987).

    7. I believe Nietzsches points in the second section of the essay express his general agree-

    ment with Friedrich Schillers argument in The Letters on the Aesthetic Education of Man about

    both the fragmentation of the modern character and the need to appeal to art to restore harmony.

    8. Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, trans. Lewis Beck (New York: Macmillan, 1956), 41

    [40].

    9. Kant, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. James Ellington (Indianapolis:

    Hackett, 1981), 13, [400401].10. See Tom Hill Jr., The Hypothetical Imperative, inDignity and Practical Reason, 1737.

    11. Kant refers to the special freedom expressed in our aesthetic reflective judgments as

    heautonomy to distinguish it from the rational autonomy of our moral judgments. Heautonomy

    is a special kind of freedom in part because the imagination is not determined by a given

    principle.

    12. Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. Werner Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987), 20919

    [33747].

    13. Ibid., 5364 [21119], 8595 [23644].

    14. In this claim, I agree with J. Porter, The Invention of Dionysus (Stanford: Stanford

    University Press, 2000).

    15. Kant, Critique of Judgment, 6164 [21619].

    16. Kant,Logic, trans. Robert Hartman and Wolfgang Schwarz (New York: Dover Publications,

    1974), 16.

    17. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Werner Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1996), 61738

    [B 67097].

    18. For example, Nietzsche employs the hypothesis of the primordial one in The Birth of

    Tragedy, the conjecture of eternal return inZarathustra, and hypothesis of the Will to Power in

    theNachlass.

    19. Kant,Logic, 5563.

    20. Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, 71 [69].

  • 8/6/2019 Nietzsche and Kant on the Pure Impulse to Truth. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Spring2004, Issue 27, p18-41, 24p; (

    25/25