McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

download McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

of 23

Transcript of McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    1/23

    Wesleyan niversity

    Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective?Author(s): C. Behan McCullaghSource: History and Theory, Vol. 30, No. 3 (Oct., 1991), pp. 302-323Published by: Wileyfor Wesleyan University

    Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2505560.Accessed: 29/10/2014 11:06

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Wileyand Wesleyan Universityare collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access toHistory

    and Theory.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=blackhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=wesleyanhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2505560?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2505560?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=wesleyanhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    2/23

    CAN

    OUR UNDERSTANDING

    OF

    OLD

    TEXTS

    BE

    OBJECTIVE?

    C.

    BEHAN

    MCCULLAGH

    I. INTRODUCTION

    Some

    people

    today

    would

    deny

    the

    possibility

    of

    achieving

    an

    objective

    under-

    standing

    of a

    contemporary

    ext,

    and

    thenargue

    hat there

    s even less

    chance

    of achieving

    such an

    understanding

    f a

    text from

    the

    past.

    Such

    wholesale

    skepticism

    needs to

    be

    rejected,

    I

    shall

    argue,

    as

    quite

    often

    objective

    under-

    standing

    of

    historical

    exts is

    possible. By

    an

    objective

    understanding

    f a

    text

    I

    mean both

    one which

    is rationally

    ustifiable

    and

    one

    whichwould

    generally

    be acceptedas correct.

    Sometimes

    here

    s

    no rational

    way

    of

    choosing

    between

    two or

    morealternative

    nterpretations,

    ut

    this

    is by no means

    always

    he

    case.

    First let

    me explain

    my use

    of a

    few keyterms.

    We understand

    text when

    we can say

    what

    it means. I

    have no

    comprehensive

    heory

    of meaning

    o

    de-

    fend

    here, but will generally

    assumethat

    the

    meaning of

    sentences

    ncludes

    their llocutionary

    orce

    together

    withthe

    conditions

    which

    makethem trueor

    correct.

    There

    are often several

    different

    ways

    of expressing

    one's

    understanding

    f

    the meaning

    of a sentenceor

    text.

    Any statement

    by

    a

    person

    of

    his or

    her

    understanding

    f its meaning

    is what

    I

    call his

    or her

    interpretation

    of

    its

    meaning.

    If

    there

    are several

    ways of

    understanding

    he

    meaning

    of a text,

    then

    each of

    those

    ways

    of

    understanding

    t is

    an

    interpretation

    f

    its

    meaning

    as

    well. So an

    interpretation

    f a text

    can be

    eitherone

    of several

    different

    ways

    of

    understanding

    text, and/or

    one of several

    differentways

    of

    expressing

    ne's

    understanding

    f

    a

    text. Generally,

    however,

    when

    I

    refer

    to

    an

    interpretation

    of a text

    I

    refer

    to

    a

    statement

    of its meaning.

    It is my

    belief

    that

    there

    are conventionally

    accepted

    criteria

    by which an

    interpretation

    f a textcan be

    justified

    as correct.

    Those

    who

    are

    skeptical

    about

    the

    objectivity

    f

    understanding

    ometimes

    gnore

    he existence

    f these

    criteria,

    focussingupon

    the subjective

    determinants

    f an interpretation

    lone. But a

    glance

    at any debate

    over the

    correct nterpretation

    f

    a

    text

    soon

    revealsboth

    the

    presence

    and the importance

    of these criteria.

    Examples

    of them

    will

    be

    given

    below.

    If

    an

    interpretation

    atisfies

    the relevant

    criteria,

    t

    is

    not only

    justified

    but

    also

    correct.

    I

    prefer

    o

    use the

    word true

    ust

    of statements

    which

    correspond

    o

    some

    reality. nterpretations

    f

    the

    meaning

    of

    a

    text

    are

    generally

    not

    true

    in

    this sense.

    They

    do

    not

    necessarily

    correspond

    o

    any

    particular

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    3/23

    CAN OUR UNDERSTANDING OF OLD TEXTS BE OBJECTIVE? 303

    reality. To call an interpretation f a text correct s to say that it would be

    acceptedas the meaningof the text by the majorityof educated peakers

    of

    the

    language n which it is written, were they to know the literaryand historical

    contexts relevantto its subject matter and the intentionsof its author. No

    individualmight have such an understanding f the text, because ndividuals

    are occasionally mistaken about

    the

    conventional meaning

    of words and

    phrases,and may be ignorantof the contextof the text and of the intention

    of

    its author.Nor is the author's ntendedmeaning he correctmeaning,as authors

    sometimes

    ail

    to say

    what

    they

    intend.

    Before considering he possibility

    of

    objective understanding

    f old

    texts,

    let me addressJacquesDerrida'sattack upon the possibility

    of

    an objective

    understanding f any text, old or new. Following Saussure,Derrida nsists

    that the meaningof

    words is to be found in their role in a

    language,

    n their

    implications, ssociations,and contrasts. He goes beyondSaussure

    n

    allowing

    that the

    meanings

    which

    words have for

    any

    readerare also

    to

    be

    found in

    whatever iteraryand logical significance hey may

    have

    for

    that reader. So

    Derrida

    inds a profusion

    of

    meanings

    or the texts he

    analyzes,

    a

    profusion

    which he

    says

    is without

    limits. For

    him,

    a text is henceforthno

    longer

    a

    finished orpus

    of

    writing, omecontent

    enclosed

    n

    a book or its

    margins,

    but a

    differential etwork,a fabricof tracesreferring ndlessly o somethingother

    than

    itself,

    to other differential

    races.

    Thus the text overrunsall the

    limits

    assigned

    o it so

    far. 2

    He

    dismisses he suggestion hat the meaningof a text corresponds o the

    author's ntention

    by pointing

    out that texts exist

    independent

    f their

    authors,

    anddo not

    dependupon

    a

    knowledge

    f

    theirauthor o be meaningful.Similarly

    he denies hattheymustbe understoodby reference o the context

    n

    which hey

    were

    written,

    or

    they

    can

    normallybe

    understoodwithout

    any reference

    o

    that

    context.3Theonly thingwhichhe admitsas determininghemeaningof a text

    is thelanguage

    n

    whichit is written,togetherwiththe literaturen whichthat

    languageappears.

    Derrida's

    heory

    of

    meaning

    s of some

    value,

    but it is far from

    adequate.

    He

    rightly

    describes he

    meaning

    of

    words as

    a

    function

    of

    their relation

    o

    other

    words

    associated

    with

    them

    in

    one way

    or

    another, hough

    he

    shouldalso have

    recognized

    he

    importance

    f theirassociation

    with

    other

    hings,

    suchas

    objects

    in

    the

    world,experiences eoplehave, and changespeoplewantto bringabout.

    The fact that manytexts can be understoodwithoutknowledgeof the circum-

    stancesof

    their

    composition

    does not mean that the words

    they

    use

    have no

    association

    with

    the world.

    Many

    wordsare

    commonly

    and

    regularly

    ssociated

    1. See the essay Differance

    in

    Jacques

    Derrida, Margins of Philosophy,

    transl.

    Alan Bass

    (Brighton, Eng.,

    1982).

    2.

    Jacques

    Derrida,

    Living On,

    in Deconstruction and

    Criticism,

    ed.

    Harold

    Bloom et

    al.

    (London,

    1979), 84.

    3. Jacques Derrida, Semiology and Grammatology: Interview with Julia Kristeva, in Posi-

    tions,

    transl.

    Alan

    Bass (London, 1972).

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    4/23

    304 C. BEHAN MCCULLAGH

    with things in the world, things to which they refer or bring about. However,

    even

    if

    Derrida's heorywere augmented o include

    associations uch as these,

    it still would not be adequate.For surelya theory

    of meaningshould explain

    how we know the meaningof texts. Derrida's heoryfails to explainhow we use

    language

    o

    communicateas clearlyand precisely

    as we do. It simply gnores

    the conventions

    by

    whichwe

    decidewhich,among

    he variouspossiblemeanings

    wordscan have, we shouldunderstand hem to

    have in the case of a given text

    or utterance.

    It is difficult o formulate hese conventionsprecisely.Generally peaking,

    the correct

    nterpretation

    f

    a

    text is that which (1) does not violate any of the

    semantic

    and

    syntactic

    rulesof the

    language

    n which t is

    written; 2)

    resolves

    any obscuritiesof referenceand ambiguitiesof meaning arising from these

    rules;(3) provides

    a coherent

    body

    of

    information; 4) performs he first hree

    functions o a muchgreaterdegree han any other

    nterpretationwhich he text

    warrants; nd perhaps 5) convincingly xplains

    away any failures o perform

    the first

    hree

    functions

    (that is, any

    inconsistencies etween he

    interpretation

    and the rules of the

    language,any remaining

    obscuritiesand

    ambiguities,

    and

    any

    inconsistencieswithin he information t

    provides).

    f

    an interpreter annot

    meet these requirements

    rom

    a study

    of

    the

    text alone, then he or she may

    examine he context n whichthe text wasproduced.This willoften locate the

    text

    in

    a widerframe of discourseand

    in

    an historicalcontext

    which

    will clear

    up uncertainties

    f

    reference

    and

    meaning.

    If an

    adequate nterpretation

    s still

    not

    available, he interpretermay then try

    to reconstruct he author's

    ntention

    in

    order to resolve

    remaining

    uncertainties.

    Sometimeseven

    recourse

    o

    the

    author's ntentions

    will

    not remove

    all

    uncertainties, mbiguities

    nd

    inconsis-

    tencies romone's

    nterpretation

    f a text. These

    may

    n

    fact havebeen

    ntended,

    as

    in

    the case of some

    diplomatic etters,

    and

    in

    some

    poems.

    Or

    they may

    not

    havebeen noticedbythe author.In cases suchas these,the readerappreciates

    an

    explanation

    of

    remaining nadequacies

    n

    the

    interpretation

    whichaccounts

    for

    theirpresence

    here. The

    interpretation

    f

    a text

    which s

    arrived

    at

    in

    this

    way,

    and whichsatisfies

    he five criteria isted

    above,

    is

    generally

    deemed

    o

    be

    the

    correct

    nterpretation

    f the text.

    If

    the language

    of

    the text

    is not

    very

    well

    known

    by

    the

    interpreter,

    nd the

    text

    provides

    a

    significantlyargepart

    of

    the evidence

    of that

    language,

    hen the

    criteria

    are

    a bit different.The

    interpreter

    till

    wants

    to find

    an

    interpretation

    of the text which s as unambiguous ndcoherentas possible.But it must also

    be

    consistent

    with

    the rules

    of

    language

    which

    he

    or she

    judges

    to make

    best

    sense

    of all

    the evidence

    of

    that

    language

    available.

    Thus,

    for

    example,

    if

    a

    scholar

    wereunfamiliar

    with

    Plato's

    Greek,

    he or

    she

    would ook

    for

    interpreta-

    tions

    of the Platonic

    dialogues

    onsistent

    with he besttheoriesof Plato's

    general

    semantics

    and

    syntax,

    as well as

    interpretations

    which

    are

    as

    unambiguous

    nd

    coherent

    as

    possible.

    Derrida

    mightargue

    hat

    any suchconventions

    annotbe justifiedas yielding

    a correctunderstandingf a text withoutviciouscircularity. f wewereto say

    thattheseconventions re

    appropriate

    ecause

    n

    conforming

    o them

    we

    always

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    5/23

    CAN OUR UNDERSTANDING

    OF OLD TEXTS BE OBJECTIVE? 305

    arrive at a correct understanding of texts, that would

    indeed be circular, as-

    suming that there is no independent check of their

    correctness. But if we say

    that

    in

    our community conformity to these conventions

    is what we mean by

    calling an interpretation of a text correct, then circularity has been avoided.

    The claim that a correct

    understanding of a text is

    one which satisfies certain

    conventional

    criteria does not

    necessarily entail any vicious circularity of rea-

    soning.

    Does it invite a

    charge

    of arbitrariness nstead? This question is more difficult

    to answer. But perhaps it is enough to say that, as Saussure

    has taught us, many

    linguistic conventions are

    arbitrary. Saussure noted

    that the relations between

    signifiers (words)

    and

    signifieds

    (things), though

    fairly regular, are usually arbi-

    trary. It would be no great surprise, then, if the relations between texts and their

    meanings

    are somewhat

    arbitrary

    too.

    They

    involve,

    at

    a

    minimum,

    rules of

    semantics and

    syntax

    which seem

    largely arbitrary,

    varying

    as

    they

    do from

    language to language.

    Whether they are arbitrary or

    not, the rules for interpre-

    ting texts generally enable

    quite effective communication

    of precise ideas, and

    that is what justifies them.

    II. BASIC

    AND

    SECONDARY

    INTERPRETATIONS

    Another common reason

    for denying the possibility of an objective under-

    standing

    of the

    meaning

    of a

    text is the observation that

    people's interpretations

    generally vary

    with

    their culture and interests. This was a major argument

    of

    Hans-Georg

    Gadamer. He noted how the interpretations

    of great historians

    such

    as

    Mommsen, Treitschke,

    and

    Sybel

    differed

    in

    accordance

    with their

    society,

    and went

    on

    to

    say:

    No one disputes he

    fact that

    controlling

    he

    prejudices

    f our own

    present

    o

    such

    an

    extent hatwedonot misunderstandhewitnesses f thepast s avalidaim,butobviously

    such

    controldoes not

    completely

    ulfill

    he

    task

    of understanding

    he

    pastand

    its trans-

    mission.

    Indeed,

    t could

    very

    well be that

    only insignificanthings

    n historical cholar-

    ship permit

    us to

    approximate

    his ideal of

    totally extinguishing

    ndividuality,

    whilethe

    greatproductive

    chievements

    f

    scholarship lwayspreserveomething

    f

    the

    splendid

    magic

    of

    immediately

    mirroring

    he

    present

    n the

    past

    and

    the

    past

    in

    the present.4

    It is not

    entirely

    clear what insignificant things

    in

    historical scholarship

    Gadamer allowed can be

    objective.

    A

    close

    look

    at

    historical

    practice, however,

    reveals that there is frequently complete agreement among historians about the

    basic

    meaning

    of

    a

    text,

    though considerable disagreement

    about

    it

    secondary

    meaning. Perhaps Gadamer meant

    that historians can

    get

    individual facts

    about

    the

    past right,

    but

    that

    their

    understanding

    of constellations

    of

    facts is

    much

    more

    subjective.

    When

    it

    comes

    to

    the

    interpretation

    of

    texts,

    what is

    certain

    is

    that the

    variety

    of

    interpretations

    of the kind Gadamer has

    noted exists

    4. Hans-Georg

    Gadamer, Philosophical

    Hermeneutics,

    transl.

    and

    ed. David

    E.

    Linge

    (Berkeley,

    1976),

    6. Compare Hans-Georg

    Gadamer,

    Truth

    and

    Method (New

    York,

    1975),

    465-466.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    6/23

    306

    C.

    BEHAN

    MCCULLAGH

    predominantly

    mong

    the interpretations

    f the secondarymeanings

    of

    texts.

    Understanding

    f the basicmeaning

    of a text

    is much essfrequently

    ontested,

    so

    there is less reason to

    doubt

    that

    it

    can

    be

    rationally

    ustified. However,

    sometimesan interpretation f the secondarymeaningof a text is so well sup-

    ported

    that

    it is undisputed

    oo, and so

    one

    may assume that it is

    rationally

    justified.

    Gadamer's

    wn essays on Plato's Lysis

    and Phaedo

    illustrate

    what

    has

    just

    been

    said quitewell.

    The

    literalmeaning

    of Plato's text is

    never

    n

    doubt,

    so

    well

    s his

    Greekunderstood.

    Any

    ambiguities re

    seen

    to havebeendeliberately

    introduced

    s a play on words.5

    What

    s uncertain

    s the point

    of thesedialogues.

    The

    Lysis, an inquiry

    nto the natureof

    friendship,

    eems o be

    entirely

    nconclu-

    sive, the discussion umpingfrompointto point, with eachsuggestedanalysis

    of friendship

    being

    shown

    to be

    quite

    unsatisfactory.

    The Phaedo

    presents

    arguments

    bout

    the

    immortality

    f the

    soul,

    but all

    of

    them

    are

    plainly

    nade-

    quate

    so that

    it

    is

    hard

    to

    see any point

    to the dialogue.

    Gadamerdiscusses

    the force of

    thesedialogues,

    and suggests

    what Plato might

    have

    intended

    n

    presenting

    hem as he did.

    To help

    fix

    the intent

    of thesedialogues,

    Gadamer

    onsiders

    heir

    genre.

    The

    Lysis,

    he concludes,

    s not

    a systematic

    nquiry

    but

    a discussion,

    a

    form of

    conversationn which wemove within the live play of riskingassertions,of

    taking back

    what we have said,

    of

    assuming

    and

    rejecting,

    all

    the while

    pro-

    ceeding

    on our

    way

    to

    reaching

    an

    understanding. 6

    ince Socrates'discussion

    in

    the Lysis

    is

    with two boys, Lysis

    and

    Menexenos,

    Gadamer uggests hat

    it

    is appropriate

    o

    find t

    inconclusive,

    forchildren

    do

    not

    yet

    knowwhat

    friend-

    ship

    is

    and how

    complex

    a relationship

    n

    enduring riendship

    reates

    between

    the

    friends. IThe inconclusive

    arguments

    have

    a

    point though.

    When

    Menex-

    enos

    cannot tell

    whether

    a lover becomes

    a friend

    of

    the beloved

    or vice

    versa,

    Gadamer aysthatPlato certainlywants us to sensethat in actualfriendship

    it

    is impossible

    o distinguishhe

    lover

    from

    the

    beloved

    n

    this

    way

    and

    to

    say

    who

    is the lover

    andwho the beloved. 8 his,

    in Gadamer's yes,

    is

    characteristic

    of the force

    of the

    discussion,

    and

    he

    goes

    on to

    find

    similar

    ignificance

    n

    other

    apparently

    nconclusivearguments.

    Gadamer

    also detects implicit

    significance

    n

    the Phaedo.

    For

    example:

    WhenPlato

    has

    Socrates,

    n

    the

    hour

    of

    death,

    enter

    into conversation

    with

    'Pythagorean'

    epresentatives

    f contemporary

    cience,

    hat

    is

    obviouslymeant

    to showthatPlato sawit as his own task to unite the moralintrospection or

    which

    Socrates

    tood

    with

    the scientificknowledge epresented

    y

    the

    Pythagor-

    eans. 9

    Gadamer's

    entral hesis

    s

    that

    the

    Phaedo's

    poetic

    power

    to

    convince

    5.

    For examples,

    Hans-Georg

    Gadamer,

    Dialogueand Dialectic:

    EightHermeneutical

    tudies

    on Plato

    (New Haven,

    1980),

    9, 11.

    6.

    Logos

    and Ergon in Plato's Lysis,

    bid.,

    5.

    7. Ibid.,

    6.

    8.

    Ibid.,

    10.

    9. Ibid., 32.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    7/23

    CAN OUR UNDERSTANDING OF OLD

    TEXTS BE OBJECTIVE?

    307

    is stronger than

    its arguments'

    logical power to prove. '0He

    sums up his discus-

    sion

    with

    these words:

    Plato certainlydoes

    not

    want

    to say that he has proved

    he same mmortality f the soul

    which sbasic o thereligious radition.Butwhathe doeswant o say s thatthe spreading

    skepticism esulting

    rom

    the scientific

    nlightenment

    oes not at allaffect he sphere

    of

    our

    human ife andour

    understanding

    f

    it. The

    growing

    cientificnsight

    nto the

    causes

    of coming-into-being

    ndpassing-away,

    nto the

    courseof natural

    processes,doesnot

    obviate

    the need

    for

    thinkingbeyond

    the

    reality

    of

    this world,

    and it has no authority

    to

    contest

    religious

    convictions.

    Thus

    the pointof the demonstrations,

    t

    seems to

    me,

    is

    that

    they

    refute doubts and

    not that

    they justifybelief.

    For proof

    of the uncertaintyof secondary

    interpretations

    of the Lysis and the

    Phaedo one need only glance at books about them. David Bolotin has given a

    detailed

    account

    of the

    long dispute

    between

    Max Pohlenz and Hans

    von

    Arnim

    about

    the

    significance

    of

    the

    Lysis.

    12

    Pohlenz

    argued

    that it was meant to

    show

    that friendship

    is related to

    erotic love

    in

    that it

    always

    includes an element

    of

    desire;

    whereas

    Arnim

    produced

    reasons

    for

    thinking

    Plato

    regarded

    true

    friendship as

    existing only between good people

    who

    are

    quite

    self-sufficient,

    possessing the

    good already and so not desiring

    it. It

    is

    interesting

    to see

    how

    texts can be

    found

    to

    support

    both

    interpretations.

    As for the Phaedo, compare the following fairly recent interpretations:

    The

    subject

    of the discussion s the desirability

    f death.'3

    It willbe wellto askwhat s thefundamental urpose

    f the dialogue.

    It is

    not,

    of

    course,

    to

    prove

    that the

    humansoul

    is

    immortal,

    houghmuch of

    it is

    devoted

    to

    arguments

    for thatthesis; t

    is

    not to pay

    a

    tribute

    of

    admiration

    o a

    beloved

    friendand

    master,

    though

    hattribute s

    undoubtedly aid;

    t is not to

    expound

    or

    propagate

    metaphysical

    doctrine,

    hough

    the

    doctrine

    of

    Forms

    (Ideas)

    bulks

    arge;

    t

    is,

    I

    would

    say,

    to

    extend

    and

    deepenthrough

    the mouth

    of

    a

    consciously

    Platonized

    Socrates,

    the essential

    teaching

    of

    Socrates

    himself,

    namely

    hat man's

    upreme

    oncern

    s

    the

    tendance f his

    soul,

    or

    (in

    more

    modern anguage)

    he furthering

    f his

    insight

    nto moraland

    spiritual

    values and the

    application

    of that

    insight

    n

    all

    his conduct.'4

    The

    Pythagoreans,Aristotleargues,

    differfrom Plato only

    in

    denyingany separation

    between

    irst

    principles

    which hey dentify

    withnumbers ather

    han

    ideas -and

    the

    things

    said to be their

    imitations;

    he

    Pythagorean eaching

    on

    reincarnation,

    n

    the

    other

    hand,

    presupposes

    he separability

    f the

    psyche

    from

    the

    body.

    The

    attempt

    o

    reinterpret

    he

    meaning

    of

    separation,

    nd

    in

    so

    doing

    to reverse

    he

    Pythagorean

    position, is,

    one might say, the

    fundamental ntention

    of

    the Phaedo.'5

    With such a variety of secondary interpretationsit is tempting to suppose that

    each

    represents

    a

    subjective

    viewpoint

    and

    that none can

    be

    judged

    to be

    superior

    to

    any

    other.

    But that is not

    what the commentators

    believe,

    as the

    quotation

    10. Ibid.,

    22.

    11.

    Ibid.,

    37.

    12. David Bolotin,

    Plato's

    Dialogue on Friendship

    (Ithaca, N.Y.,

    1979).

    13.

    R. S.

    Bluck, Plato's Phaedo

    (London,

    1955),

    1.

    14. R. Hackforth, Plato's Phaedo (Cambridge, Eng., 1955), 3.

    15.

    Rome Burger,

    The Phaedo:

    A Platonic

    Labyrinth

    (New Haven,

    1984),

    7.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    8/23

    308 C. BEHAN MCCULLAGH

    from Hackforth ndicates. CertainlyGadamerdefends his

    interpretations y

    suggesting

    hat

    they

    accountfor more featuresof the

    dialogues

    han

    previous

    interpretations id.

    In

    particularhe believes they account for the inconclu-

    sivenessof the Lysis, and the obvious inadequacyof the arguments n the

    Phaedo.

    The distinction havejust madebetween he basic

    meaningof a text and the

    text's

    secondarymeaningneeds

    to be

    explained.The secondarymeaningof a

    text

    dependsupon its basic meaning,but the basic

    meaning

    of a text

    depends

    on no other

    meaning

    t

    has.

    The

    basic meaningdoes,

    of

    course, dependupon

    the

    meaning

    of

    the wordsand phrasesused

    in

    the text, but not upon anyother

    meaning

    of the text

    as

    a

    whole.

    It is not

    quite

    the same

    as

    the literal

    meaning

    of the text, for the latter is sometimes aken to be a functionsimplyof the

    semantics

    and

    syntax

    of the

    language

    used

    in

    the

    text,

    and not of the context

    in

    whichthe text appears.The basic meaningof a text is sometimes

    a

    function

    of its context.

    In

    discussions f the meaning

    of

    texts,

    t

    is

    common

    o

    distinguish

    he

    meaning

    of

    the

    sentences,according

    o the rulesof

    language;

    he

    meaning

    of the utter-

    ance, taking

    nto accountthe

    context

    n

    which

    the

    text was

    produced;

    and

    the

    meaningof the utterer, hat is the meaningwhich he author

    ntended o convey

    in writing he text. How does the basic meaningof a textrelate o these alterna-

    tives?

    From what

    I

    have

    observed,

    our

    practice

    s to decide

    the

    basic

    meaning

    of

    a

    text

    by following

    the

    procedure

    described

    above. First we

    considerthe

    meaningof the sentences,drawing olely upon our

    knowledgeof the language;

    if

    this is

    unambiguous,we go no further.

    If

    it is ambiguous,however,we refer

    to the context

    in

    the

    hope

    of

    clearingup

    the

    ambiguity.

    The

    sentence There

    are

    bats

    in

    the

    belfry meansonething

    f

    addressed

    o the local

    pest controller,

    and another

    f

    spoken

    to the

    churchcricket

    eam

    looking

    for

    their

    equipment.

    If a

    careful

    study

    of

    the contextfails

    to

    resolve

    he

    ambiguity,

    we then turn

    our

    attention

    o the

    speaker,

    and

    try

    to

    discover

    what he

    or she

    probably

    ntended

    in

    saying

    what he or

    she did. Thus the meaningof a text

    may dependupon

    the

    meaning

    of the

    corresponding tterance,and even the

    meaning

    of

    the

    utterer,

    but it

    neednot do

    so.

    Indeed,

    f

    the

    meaning

    of a text is

    unambiguous ccording

    to the rules of

    the

    language,

    t

    may differ rom

    the

    meaning

    which

    the utterer

    intended o

    convey. Interestingly nough, precisely

    he

    same

    procedure

    s

    fol-

    lowed to determine

    he secondarymeaningof a

    text as well.

    I

    have

    suggested hat one can sometimes ustify one's

    understanding

    f

    the

    basic

    meaning

    of

    a text

    by

    reference

    o

    rules

    of

    semantics

    and

    syntax

    alone.

    In

    practice,however, providinga completejustification

    of an

    interpretation

    n

    terms

    of these

    rules s

    virtually mpossible,

    as

    the

    rules

    nvolved

    defy complete

    formulation.

    Competent anguageusers

    know how to

    apply

    hese

    rules,

    but not

    how to state them.

    In

    practice, therefore,

    we

    regard

    an

    interpretation

    f a

    sentence

    as

    justified

    f

    most educatedusers

    of

    the

    languageudge

    t

    to be correct.

    Sometimes he

    meaning

    of

    a

    sentence,

    taken on

    its

    own,

    is

    ambiguous.

    To

    resolve he

    ambiguity

    t

    is conventional

    o

    choose

    a

    reading

    whichbest

    fits

    the

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    9/23

    CAN

    OUR UNDERSTANDING

    OF OLD

    TEXTS

    BE OBJECTIVE?

    309

    context.

    Derrida

    asserts

    hat

    there

    are no absolutely

    determinable

    ontexts

    by

    which

    o justify

    an

    interpretation.6

    But

    once againhe overlooks

    he

    conventions

    we use

    to

    determine

    meaning.

    We

    always

    choose

    the meaningwhich

    fits

    best

    withthe surroundingext, thatis a meaningwhicheitherentailsor is entailed

    by

    what is said

    elsewhere

    n the

    text, or

    at least

    which

    s

    not incompatible

    with

    what

    is said elsewhere.

    This

    usually

    resolves

    he ambiguity

    quite

    quickly.

    If

    it

    does

    not,

    then

    we commonly

    draw

    upon

    our

    knowledge

    of the literary

    and

    historical

    ontext

    n which

    he sentence

    was uttered.

    And

    if this fails to

    resolve

    the

    issue,

    we turn

    our

    attention

    to

    the author

    and the

    circumstances

    f her

    composing

    or

    uttering

    he

    text to determine

    what she

    probably

    ntended

    t

    to

    mean.

    Derrida

    ries

    to preclude

    hese

    movesby

    denying

    that the meaning

    of

    texts depends n any way upon the presenceof a contextof utteranceor the

    presence

    of the

    author,

    but

    in that

    he

    is just

    mistaken.

    Often

    it does

    depend

    upon

    those things.

    Certainly

    we sometimes

    come

    upon

    texts

    in places far

    re-

    moved

    from

    the context

    of

    theirproduction,

    and

    that

    fact sometimes

    makes

    t

    difficult

    o be sure

    that we

    have

    understood

    them correctly.

    Historians

    are

    particularly

    onscious

    of this

    difficulty,and

    do what

    they

    can to overcome

    t.

    II. CRITERIA FOR JUDGING SECONDARY INTERPRETATIONS

    As

    has been

    shown,

    the secondary

    meaning

    of

    texts

    is much

    more frequently

    debated han

    their

    basic meaning,

    but

    that does

    not mean

    there is no

    way

    of

    justifying

    a

    secondary

    nterpretation.

    A

    secondary

    nterpretation

    f a text

    is

    often

    an act

    of

    colligation,

    n

    which various

    features

    of the basic meaning

    of

    the text are

    shown

    to have

    a certain

    significance

    when considered ogether.

    Secondary

    nterpretations

    ake

    a

    variety

    of forms. Theymay

    simply

    be

    state-

    mentsof the additionalllocutionaryorceof atext,

    and

    perhaps

    f its secondary

    field

    of

    reference.

    A

    secondary

    nterpretation

    might

    ake

    the formof a

    statement

    of

    the author'sgeneral

    ntention,

    which

    would

    help

    account

    for the features

    of

    the

    text which

    could

    be seen

    as

    helping

    to fulfillit. We

    have

    already

    seen

    an

    example

    f

    this

    kindof

    interpretation

    n

    Gadamer's

    iscussion

    f Plato's

    general

    intentions

    n

    writing

    he

    Lysis

    andthePhaedo.

    A

    secondary

    nterpretation

    might

    also consist

    of a

    general

    summary

    of the

    content

    of

    the

    text,

    or a

    summary

    of

    itsessential

    deas

    or

    thesis. It could

    even

    be a

    statement

    f someoverall

    tructure

    of the text. Thekeycriterionusedin judgingthe adequacyof suchinterpreta-

    tions

    s

    theirscope:

    we

    prefer

    nterpretations

    hich

    colligate

    he

    greatest

    number

    of facts about

    the text.

    But

    they

    must

    also be

    not

    very

    complex,

    and

    coherent.

    General ummaries

    re

    expected

    o

    satisfy

    additional

    equirements

    ppropriate

    to

    their nature:

    hey

    must

    be

    accurate,

    nformative,

    and

    comprehensive.

    Texts

    sometimes

    llustrate

    a

    number

    of

    general

    ruths,

    as

    the discussion

    of

    16.

    Jacques

    Derrida,

    Margins

    of

    Philosophy,

    310.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    10/23

    310 C. BEHAN MCCULLAGH

    the Lysis and the

    Phaedo has

    shown.

    All

    of these might be interesting, so

    the

    search

    for

    one

    reading superior to the others could appear

    pointless.

    It

    has a

    point, however, which is to

    provide

    a

    reading which somehow explains

    all

    the

    major parts of the text, if possible, and thus to representthe whole text fairly.

    That is

    why the scope of

    secondary interpretations is so important.

    It is possible for a text to have

    a significance

    for

    its

    author's contemporaries

    which the author did not intend. And it

    is possible for a

    text to have a significance

    for modern

    readers which neither the author

    nor

    the

    author's contemporaries

    would have known

    -the Freudian interpretation of

    The Turn of the Screw is

    a

    case

    in

    point.

    Whose

    secondary interpretation is the

    correct one?

    I

    believe

    that current conventions are

    captured

    by

    the

    following

    distinctions.

    I think

    we

    judge the most comprehensive interpretation to be the correct one, whether or

    not it accords

    with

    the

    author's

    intended reading, or the reading of the author's

    contemporaries.

    The

    historically

    correct

    interpretation

    is

    that

    of the

    majority

    of

    the author's educated

    contemporaries, which might well be that intended

    by

    the

    author. The intended

    interpretation

    is

    simply that

    intended by

    the author.

    1. The

    dangersof anachronism

    The best

    secondary

    interpretation of a text is usually also the historically correct

    one, because modern theories often have implications which do not apply to an

    old

    text,

    and so

    frequently misrepresent

    them.

    Indeed, the

    appropriateness

    of

    summarizing

    texts

    in

    modern terms which the

    author would never have used

    has been

    questioned. Quentin Skinner

    has

    shown

    that this

    practice, by historians

    who have

    not

    carefully

    understood the

    basic

    meaning

    of the texts first,

    can

    lead

    them to

    misrepresent them. For example, those

    who have interpreted the

    political

    views of the

    Levellers

    in

    seventeenth-century Britain as a

    philosophy

    of

    liberal

    democracy, simply because the Levellers

    were concerned

    with

    an

    extension of the right to vote, have completely mistaken their views.

    First the

    paradigmmakes it unnecessarily ifficult o

    account for some of the most

    characteristic

    eaturesof

    Leveller

    deology.

    For

    if

    we areprogrammedo

    think

    n

    terms

    of

    the

    republican

    ecularism f the

    movement,

    t

    is not

    surprising

    hat

    their

    agonizings

    over the

    Monarchy

    and

    their

    appeals

    to

    religioussentiment

    begin

    to

    look

    somewhat

    baffling.

    And

    second, the paradigmof

    democracy

    will

    tend to lead the historical

    investigation

    n

    rather

    nappropriate irections.Some anachronistic oncept

    of

    the

    welfare

    state

    has to be

    found in Leveller hought, as well

    as a belief

    in

    manhood

    suffrage,

    which

    they

    never

    n

    fact

    held.17

    To

    describe

    the

    Levellers as

    presenting

    a

    theory

    of

    liberal democracy

    is thus not

    only

    unfair,

    in

    that it

    fails to accommodate

    many

    of their

    important

    concerns

    about the crown and

    religion,

    but it is also

    misleading

    in

    that

    it

    implies

    concerns

    for a welfare state

    and manhood

    suffrage

    which

    were

    not theirs

    at

    all. Such

    17. Quentin kinner, Meaning ndUnderstandingnthe Historyof Ideas, Historyand heory

    8

    (1969),

    27.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    11/23

    CAN

    OUR

    UNDERSTANDING

    OF

    OLD TEXTS

    BE OBJECTIVE?

    311

    mistakes

    can be

    avoided,

    however,

    if the

    historian

    carefully

    checks

    whether

    the

    basic

    meaning

    of a

    text

    warrants

    the modern description

    of

    it.

    Despite

    the

    dangers

    of summarizing

    old texts

    in modern terms,

    John

    Dunn

    suggests that such summaries are useful in showing the modern relevance of

    these

    texts.

    He therefore

    applauds

    the practice,

    while

    remaining

    concerned

    about

    their accuracy:

    To present

    a

    complex

    argument

    from the

    past

    in

    terms

    of

    its significance

    for us

    may often

    seem

    mendacious

    and

    to present it

    with

    the

    greatest

    concern

    for historical

    specificity

    but without

    exploring

    its significance

    is

    likely to seem

    trivial.18

    The history

    of philosophy,

    like

    the history

    of science,

    must

    needs

    be Whig

    as

    to subject-matter

    . .

    . [and]

    .

    .

    .

    Tory

    as to

    truth. 19

    The

    process

    of

    carefully

    judging

    the

    justification

    of a

    modern

    summary

    of

    an old text is well illustratedby J. W. Gough's discussion of Willmore Kendall's

    thesis

    that

    Locke's

    theory

    was

    not

    individualist,

    as has

    been

    commonly

    thought,

    but

    that

    it gives

    an authoritarian

    and collectivist

    account

    of political

    power.20

    To judge

    the

    adequacy

    of these

    descriptions,

    Gough

    interprets

    them

    and

    then looks

    for

    evidence

    relevant to

    them

    in

    Locke's

    writing.

    An

    individu-

    alist

    theory,

    it

    seems,

    is

    one which

    presents

    government

    as severely

    limited

    by

    the

    rights

    of individuals.

    An

    authoritarian

    theory

    insists upon

    the govern-

    ment's

    authority

    over

    individuals,

    unless

    the government

    is so bad

    that

    the

    people are entitled to revolt. There are passages in Locke which support both

    views,

    so

    how does

    Gough

    decide

    the issue?

    First,

    he carefully

    examines

    the

    crucial passages

    in context

    to see

    whether they

    do

    support

    the

    interpretation

    suggested

    for them.

    He

    finds that

    some which appear

    to support

    the

    individualist

    interpretation

    do not

    really

    do

    so,

    when

    studied

    in

    their

    context.2

    Second,

    he

    points

    out

    that there

    is evidence

    for and

    against

    both readings,

    and that

    each

    can only

    be defended by ignoring

    as

    insignificant

    those

    passages

    which

    tell

    against

    it.

    As

    Gough

    puts

    it:

    Many

    critics

    have

    noticed

    features

    of

    Locke's

    theory

    which

    seem

    inconsistent

    with

    the

    usual

    individualist interpretation

    of

    him.

    The critics

    have

    varied,

    however,

    in the

    degree

    of

    emphasis

    they have

    laid

    on such discrepancies,

    and

    have

    generally

    tended to

    treat

    the

    individualism

    as fundamental,

    and

    to

    minimize

    what

    is

    inconsistent

    with this,

    either

    ignoring

    it

    in

    their

    final verdict

    or dismissing

    it as

    ill-considered

    and unrepresentative

    of

    Locke's

    real

    view.

    Mr.

    Kendall,

    in

    effect,

    reverses

    this

    tendency.

    It is

    the

    individualist

    passages

    which are

    inconsistencies

    for

    him,

    and he

    emphasizes

    instead the

    points

    -and

    they certainly

    amount

    to a

    considerable

    array-on

    the

    other

    side.22

    Finally, Gough concludes that the truth about Locke lies somewhere between

    the

    two extremes.

    His

    theory

    does

    not

    neatly

    fit either

    modern model,

    though

    it contains

    important

    elements

    of

    both.

    18.

    J. Dunn, The

    Political Thought

    of John Locke (Cambridge,

    Eng., 1969), 208.

    19.

    J. Dunn, Political

    Obligation n

    Its HistoricalContext:

    Essays

    in Political Theory Cam-

    bridge,

    Eng., 1980),

    26.

    20. J. W.

    Gough, John Locke's

    Political Philosophy (Oxford,

    1956), chap. 2.

    21. Ibid., 29-30.

    22. Ibid., 28.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    12/23

    312

    C. BEHAN

    MCCULLAGH

    WasLocke

    then,

    after all,

    an

    individualist?

    think

    we

    can sayhe

    was, but

    he

    wasnot

    a thorough-going,

    xtreme

    ndividualist....

    He standsmid-way

    between

    wo

    extreme

    positions

    n

    politics....

    Wemay

    conclude,

    hen,

    that Locke

    wasan individualist

    n

    a

    qualified

    ense.

    Hedid not

    imagine

    he

    state

    to be an

    artificially

    abricated

    ombination

    of naturally

    eparate

    ndividuals;

    e didnot championhe individual gainst hecommu-

    nity,and

    barely

    onsidered

    hepossibility

    of conflict

    between

    hem.

    Butthe

    government

    he recommended

    was in

    effect

    he parliamentary

    imited

    monarchy

    approved

    of

    by his

    Whig

    contemporaries,

    nd this

    meant hat

    it

    would

    be constitutional

    nd

    not absolute,

    and that

    it would not invade

    the

    liberties

    of

    the subject.23

    Old

    theories seldom

    fit modern paradigms

    neatly,

    but

    they

    sometimes

    have

    important

    ideas

    and

    values

    in

    common.

    These

    are

    highlighted

    by

    modern

    sum-

    maries

    of them. The

    extreme

    interpretations

    of Locke were

    neither accurate,

    comprehensive, nor fair. They implied positions contrary to those Locke

    adopted

    or

    they

    ignored

    important

    parts

    of

    his

    theory,

    thus giving

    a

    misleading

    impression

    of

    the whole.

    That

    is why they

    were

    finally rejected

    by

    Gough.

    2. The

    illocutionary

    force

    of

    texts

    The historically

    correct

    interpretation

    of a text usually

    coincides

    with

    the

    au-

    thor's

    intended

    meaning,

    as

    authors are usually

    well

    aware of how

    their

    texts

    will be

    read

    by

    their contemporaries.

    Interestingly

    enough, historians

    frequently

    take the identity of the two for granted. Skinner, for example, has shown

    that John

    Locke,

    in

    his

    Two Treatises

    of

    Government,

    was rejecting

    and

    repudiating

    one

    of

    the

    most

    widespread

    and

    prestigious

    forms

    of

    political

    argu-

    ment

    at the

    time,

    simply by

    noting

    the

    prevailing

    conventions

    of debate

    about

    political

    obligation,

    the role

    of

    the

    ancient

    English

    constitution

    in those,

    and

    Locke's

    failure

    to

    mention

    it.24

    Similarly

    he has

    shown

    that

    Machiavelli

    in

    places

    challenges

    the

    prevailing

    assumptions

    of the

    mirror-for-princes

    writers,

    by

    comparing

    what

    those

    writers

    said

    with certain

    passages

    in The

    Prince.25

    Skinner

    assumes that these implications of the texts were intended by their authors,

    which

    is

    probably

    true,

    though

    nothing

    need

    be known

    about their

    intentions

    to

    identify

    them.

    These

    are

    conventional

    secondary

    meanings

    of the texts

    justi-

    fied

    by

    the context

    of the writing together

    with

    the rules of

    language

    which

    warrant

    the statements

    reporting

    them.

    There

    are times,

    however,

    when

    the

    further

    illocutionary

    force

    of

    a

    text

    cannot

    be inferred

    from the

    context,

    and

    can

    only

    be

    known

    by

    discovering

    the

    author's

    intentions.

    For

    example,

    to decide

    whether

    Thomas

    Hobbes

    and

    Pierre

    Bayle

    meant their

    pious

    utterances to be taken ironically, historians have to

    judge

    their

    intentions,

    as there

    is

    no

    hint of

    irony

    in their

    texts.26

    23.

    Ibid.,

    51.

    24.

    Quentin

    Skinner,

    Some

    Problems

    n the

    Analysis

    of

    Political

    Thought

    and

    Action,

    Polit-

    ical

    Theory

    2

    (1974),

    286.

    25.

    Quentin

    Skinner,

    The Foundations

    of

    Modern

    Political

    Thought.

    Volume

    1:

    The

    Renais-

    sance

    (Cambridge,Eng., 1978),131.

    26. See

    Quentin

    Skinner,

    Meaning

    nd

    Understanding

    n the History

    of

    Ideas,

    33-35.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    13/23

    CAN

    OUR UNDERSTANDING

    OF OLD

    TEXTS BE OBJECTIVE?

    313

    An

    author's

    ntention

    can

    be

    stated

    n

    modern

    words,

    I think,

    so long

    as

    the

    author

    would

    have

    consented

    o an

    appropriate

    ranslation

    f

    them

    as

    accurately

    representing

    is or her

    intention.

    Skinner,

    or

    example,

    has said

    that:

    During

    theeighteenth entury, he enemiesof the rulingoligarchynEngland ought o

    legitimate

    heir

    attacks

    on

    thegovernment

    y insisting

    hat they

    were

    motivated

    entirely

    by

    reverence

    or the constitution,

    and thus

    that

    their actions

    deserved

    to

    be commended

    as patriotic

    rather

    han

    condemned

    as factious. 27

    t is very

    doubtful

    hat

    eighteenth-century

    ritishpoliticians

    would

    have

    recognized

    heir

    explanations

    s

    legitimations.

    egitimation,

    s Skinner

    himself

    has

    acknowl-

    edged,28

    s

    a Weberian erm,

    and

    derives

    ts

    modern

    meaning

    from

    Weber's

    theory

    of legitimation.

    Eighteenth-century

    oliticians

    would

    have

    said

    they

    were

    justifyingtheirattackson the government,not legitimating hem. But if the

    meaning

    of

    Weber's

    erm

    were

    explained

    o them,

    then they

    probably

    would

    agree

    hat

    n

    justifying

    heir

    attacks hey

    were ndeed

    egitimating

    hem,

    making

    them politically

    acceptable

    according

    o

    recognized

    authorities.

    Because

    the

    best

    interpretation,

    he

    historically

    correct

    nterpretation,

    nd

    the

    author's

    nterpretation

    f

    a text

    are usually

    he same,

    historians

    requently

    fail

    to distinguish

    hem. Thisis

    the case

    in the

    commonly

    accepted

    reading

    of

    Gulliver's

    Travels s

    a

    political

    atire.

    This

    s

    an

    excellent

    xample

    of

    a

    secondary

    interpretationf a text, one whichstates ts additional llocutionary orceand

    its secondary

    ield

    of reference.

    Gulliver's

    Travels

    an

    be understood

    at a

    basic

    level as

    a story

    about

    the adventures

    of

    Gulliver.

    That,

    indeed,

    is

    how

    most

    people

    understand

    t today.

    To Swift's

    contemporaries,

    owever,

    amiliar

    with

    the details

    of

    political

    ife

    in

    Britain,

    ts

    forceand

    its references

    ppeared

    quite

    different.

    They

    took

    it to

    be not

    just

    a story,

    but

    also

    a satire;

    t

    referred

    not

    just

    to Gulliverand

    the imaginary

    ands

    he

    visited,

    but

    also

    to

    political

    figures

    of his day

    with

    the intention

    of

    ridiculing

    hem.

    A. E.

    Case

    has pointed

    out,

    for example, hat whencontemporarieseadthat theEmperorwhomGulliver

    encountered

    n

    his

    firstvoyagewas

    strong

    nd

    masculine,

    with

    anAustrian

    Lip

    and

    arched

    Nose,

    his

    Complexion

    olive,

    his

    Countenance

    rect,

    his Body

    and

    Limbswell

    proportioned

    ..

    His

    Dress

    was

    very

    plainand

    simple

    ..

    His

    Voice

    wasshrill,

    but veryclear

    and

    articulate,

    hen

    they

    thought

    of George

    I's

    thick

    and ungainly

    form,

    his bad taste

    in

    dress,

    and

    his

    guttural

    and unintelligible

    pronunciation

    f

    the

    little

    English

    he knew. 29

    The

    interpretation

    f

    Gulliver's

    Travels s

    a political

    satire

    has

    the strongest

    possiblesupport.Itaccounts or a very argenumberof thedetailsof thestory.

    (The

    third essay

    in

    Case's

    book

    explains

    he political

    allegories

    n detail.)

    It

    is

    an

    example

    of

    a

    genre

    amiliar

    o Swift's

    contemporaries,

    nd so readily

    denti-

    fied

    by

    them.

    And

    the

    interpretation

    s

    consistent

    with what s

    known

    of

    Swift's

    intentions

    n

    writing.

    Similarustification

    an

    be provided

    or the interpretation

    27.

    Quentin

    Skinner,

    The

    Idea

    of a

    Cultural

    Lexicon,

    Essays

    in

    Criticism

    29

    (1979),

    216.

    28. Quentin Skinner, Some Problems in the Analysis of Political Thought and Action, 292.

    29.

    Arthur

    E. Case,

    Four

    Essays

    in

    Gulliver's

    Travels

    (Gloucester,

    Mass., 1958),

    71.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    14/23

    314

    C. BEHAN

    MCCULLAGH

    of Cervantes'

    Don Quixote

    as

    a

    parody

    of both the

    aims and

    means

    of knightly

    chivalry.

    A. J.

    Close,

    in

    defending

    his

    reading

    of

    the

    story,

    wrote: The

    aims,

    like the

    acts, are

    a

    madly literal

    mimicry

    of

    the stereotype

    behaviour

    of

    the

    heroesof chivalric omance, ndwouldhavebeenimmediately ecognizedas

    such by contemporary

    eaders.30

    Sometimes

    he

    further force

    of a text

    is not to

    be identified

    with a

    genre

    such

    as satire

    or

    parody,

    but

    with a

    conventional

    mplication

    of the text in

    its

    particular

    ontext.

    For example,

    when

    a piano

    teacher

    tells

    a

    pupil that

    she

    played

    a piece

    beautifully,

    she is

    not only

    describing

    he

    playing,

    but by

    doing

    so

    she is

    praising

    he

    student,

    and by

    doing

    that she is encouraging

    her.

    These

    further

    descriptions

    are warranted

    by

    the

    rules

    of

    language

    andthe

    context.

    3. Summaries

    f

    the basic meaningof

    a

    text

    A

    very

    common

    form

    of

    higher

    understanding

    f the meaning

    of

    a text is

    that

    achieved

    by

    producing

    n

    adequate

    ummary

    f

    what t says,

    that

    s,

    of

    itsbasic

    meaning.

    A

    common

    reason

    for

    summarizing

    n author's

    views

    is to compare

    them

    with those

    of others.

    J. G.

    A. Pocock

    has

    made a

    special

    study

    of

    the

    writing

    of

    James

    Harrington.

    n

    an essay

    entitled Machiavelli,

    Harrington

    nd English

    EighteenthCentury deologies, he produceda summary f Harrington's olit-

    icalthought,quoting

    him

    only

    for the

    sakeof

    illustration.

    His summary

    s often

    quite

    terse: Harrington's

    ntire

    theory

    of

    monarchy

    can

    be

    reducedto two

    propositions:

    irst,that

    theKing's

    agents

    and servants

    must

    be

    supported

    ither

    upon

    the land, as a

    feudal

    aristocracy,

    or about

    his person

    as praetorians

    or

    janissaries; econd,

    that whichever

    of these

    methods

    s

    adopted,

    relationsbe-

    tween hemilitary lass

    and

    theKing

    will be so prone

    o

    tensions

    hat

    monarchy

    can

    neverbe a

    stable

    form

    of

    government. '

    ocock

    provided

    his

    summary

    of Harrington'sheory in order to compare t with that of the first Earl of

    Shaftesbury.

    This

    practice

    s

    repeated

    hroughout

    he

    essay.

    For

    example

    he

    used summaries

    o

    compare

    what

    he

    called

    the 'County'

    vision

    of

    English

    politics

    with

    Harrington's

    iew:

    If we

    now summarize

    he

    main outlines of

    the 'County'

    vision

    of

    Englishpolitics

    as

    it

    appears

    n a

    multitude

    of

    writings

    in

    the

    century

    hat

    follows 1675, we

    may

    attempt

    o see

    what

    is Harrington,

    or

    rather

    neo-Harrington,

    bout

    it. 32

    Historians

    aim

    to

    produce

    summaries

    which

    are

    accurate,

    nformative,

    and

    comprehensive.A summarys accuratef the statementsn the text instantiate

    it and are not

    inconsistent

    with

    it. Informativeness

    ecreases

    as

    generality

    n-

    creases,

    as a

    very general

    summary

    ould

    be instantiated

    by

    a

    large

    number

    of

    diverse

    exts.

    So

    historians

    prefer

    a

    summary

    which

    is

    no

    more

    general

    than

    30. A.

    J. Close,

    Don Quixote

    and 'The Intentionalist Fallacy, '

    British

    Journal

    of

    Aesthetics

    12 (1972),

    13.

    31. J.

    G. A.

    Pocock, Politics,

    Language

    and Time:Essays

    on

    Political

    Thought

    and

    History

    (London,

    1972),

    116-117.

    32.

    Ibid.,

    124.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    15/23

    CAN

    OUR UNDERSTANDING

    OF OLD

    TEXTS BE OBJECTIVE?

    315

    they require.

    The level

    of generality

    s that

    atwhichcomparisons

    f interest

    an

    be

    mademost

    clearly.

    A summary

    hould

    be comprehensive

    nthatit covers

    he

    variousaspects

    of the

    basicmeaning

    of the text

    in

    question,

    so that each

    signifi-

    cant partof the basictext instantiatespartof the summary.Let me illustrate.

    C.

    B.

    Macpherson's

    Marxist

    nterpretation

    f Locke

    in ThePolitical

    Theory

    of

    Possessive

    Individualism

    as earned

    much

    respectbut

    also some

    criticism.

    Alan Ryan

    has

    argued hat

    it is

    not accurate.

    For example,

    Macpherson aid

    that Locke

    denied

    that laborers

    without

    property

    could

    be

    full citizens,

    as

    citizenshipwas

    reserved or

    those

    with

    property.

    Ryan

    objects

    hat some

    plainly

    unambiguous

    statements

    by Locke

    .

    . .

    flatly contradict

    this summary

    of

    Locke's

    views.

    Locke

    n fact maintained

    hatallrational

    adults

    couldbe

    citizens,

    and deniedcitizenshiponly to Lunaticks nd Idiots. 33Macphersonwas also

    mistaken n thinking

    hat Locke

    restricted

    property

    o

    goods, for

    Locke

    de-

    scribed

    property

    s

    that which

    othershave

    no

    right

    o take

    without he person's

    consent,

    and

    specifically

    ncluded

    such personal

    things as

    life, liberty,

    and

    health.

    Ryanconcludes

    hat

    the

    orce of Macpherson's

    ccount

    challenges

    ne

    to

    produce

    some

    alternativepicture

    hat fits

    the text better

    than this. 34

    Dunn's

    criticism

    of

    John

    Plamenatz's

    nterpretation

    f

    Locke reveals

    the

    importance

    of

    summaries

    being

    comprehensive

    f

    they are

    to be acceptable.

    Plamenatz,seeingLocke as a greatliberal philosopher,assumedthat Locke

    based

    political

    obligation

    upon

    the consent

    of

    the

    governed.

    But,

    Dunn

    points

    out,

    this

    interpretationgnores

    the

    theological

    dimension

    of Locke's

    hought.

    Referring

    o a large

    rangeof

    Locke's

    writings,

    Dunnshows

    hat

    Lockegrounded

    political

    obligation

    in

    man's

    duty

    to God

    of

    self-preservation.

    Since

    people

    cannot

    subsist

    without

    society,God,

    who

    wills them to

    subsist,

    also wills

    them

    to use their reason

    to discover

    he rules

    by

    which

    a

    society

    can be

    maintained,

    and to follow

    them.

    People

    consent to

    others

    havingauthority

    over

    them,

    so

    that consentis a necessaryconditionof politicalobligation.But what is also

    necessary,

    o drive

    them to obey,

    is duty

    to

    God.35

    By ignoring

    he theological

    dimension

    of

    Locke's

    hought,

    Plamenatz

    and

    othershad

    produced

    a

    summary

    which said

    nothing

    about

    large

    and

    important

    parts

    of

    Locke's

    writings

    on

    political

    obligation.

    Whenan

    important,

    relevant

    part

    of

    any

    author's

    work s

    ignored

    by

    a

    sum-

    mary

    description,

    he summary

    s

    prone

    to

    give

    a

    misleading

    mpression

    of

    the

    whole.

    Pocock has

    explained

    how the

    habit

    of

    commentators

    n

    ignoring

    books

    IIIandIVof Hobbes'Leviathan,whichdiscussreligioushistory,hasledpeople

    to

    believe

    that

    Hobbes'

    thought

    was

    unhistorical

    o a

    degree

    which

    it

    was

    not.36

    ndeed

    he

    practice

    has

    even

    fuelled he

    belief

    thatHobbes

    acked

    religious

    33. Alan Ryan,

    Locke

    and the Dictatorship

    of the Bourgeoisie,

    Political

    Studies

    13 (1965),

    223.

    34. Ibid., 227-228.

    35. J. Dunn, Political Obligation in Its Historical Context, 29-33.

    36. J. G.

    A. Pocock,

    Politics, Language

    and

    Time,

    149-150.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    16/23

    316

    C. BEHAN MCCULLAGH

    convictions

    and was, perhaps,

    an atheist.37

    ocock condemnssuch

    interpreta-

    tions

    of Hobbes'

    writing

    and

    of

    his convictions

    as

    seriously

    misleading.

    4. The key dea

    of a text:

    a tertiary nterpretation

    Anotherkindof

    higherunderstanding f

    the meaning

    of a text whichhistorians

    sometimes

    eek involves dentifying

    he key dea

    of an author'swork.

    A

    key

    idea, itseems, s one

    uponwhich he other

    principle deas

    o someextentdepend.

    Once a

    work

    has been

    summarized,

    t is then sometimes

    possible

    o identify ts

    key idea. For this

    reason,

    an interpretation f the

    key idea of

    a text could be

    regarded

    as a tertiary

    nterpretation f the

    meaning

    of the text, depending

    as

    it does upon a secondary

    ummaryreading

    of the text.

    In a thoughtfuldiscussionof the fundamentaldeain Harrington's olitical

    philosophy

    Pocock discusses

    C. B. Macpherson'sbelief

    that Harrington's

    system

    will not

    work

    unless

    entrepreneurial

    ehaviour

    n

    land owners

    is

    pre-

    sumed

    o be at its basis. 38

    Macpherson

    rgued

    hat

    changes

    n the

    social

    distribu-

    tion

    of

    power

    in

    seventeenth-century

    ngland

    were seen

    by

    Harrington

    o be

    the result

    of

    changes

    n

    patterns

    of wealth,particularly

    and

    ownership.

    Pocock

    thinks

    Harrington

    aw it

    as

    the result

    of

    changes

    n

    the

    legalobligations

    which

    went

    with

    land tenure.

    Feudal

    obligations

    o

    serve an overlordgave place

    to

    independent enured freeholders. Pocock arguesthat Macpherson'sunder-

    standing

    of

    the

    key

    idea

    in

    Harrington's ystem

    is

    wrong

    because

    certain

    m-

    portant

    featuresof his system

    do not

    depend

    upon

    it.

    Harrington's

    otion

    of

    the

    power

    whichthe

    man

    who

    has

    property

    exerts

    over the man

    who has

    none

    does

    not entail

    any

    particular

    escription

    f

    the economicrelations

    between he

    two men,

    or

    of

    the

    economic

    process

    n

    which

    the two are

    engaged.

    All

    that is

    necessary

    o know is

    that

    the one is independent

    and

    the other dependent

    on

    him. s39

    Inanotheressay,on Burke nd theAncientConstitution, Pocockexplains

    how Burke's onservative olitical

    heory

    s an

    expression

    f

    a

    theory

    about

    the

    nature

    of

    English

    awdevelopedby Sir

    EdwardCoke

    and

    SirMatthew

    Hale

    in

    the seventeenth

    entury.

    This

    theory

    maintained

    hat

    English

    common

    aw was

    based

    upon

    custom, interpreted

    nd

    applied

    n

    courts,

    from time

    immemorial,

    and

    that it enshrined

    he

    practical

    wisdom of

    ages

    and so deserved

    he utmost

    respect.

    This theorywas applied

    o the

    English

    constitution

    n

    what was called

    the doctrine

    of the

    ancient constitution,

    o defend the constitution

    against

    reform.That doctrinewasrespectedby many n Burke's ime,and wasusedby

    him

    in

    1782 o

    oppose

    movesto reform

    t. Instead

    of

    talking

    about

    a

    key

    dea

    Pocock

    here

    refers

    o

    a

    root

    dea :Burke

    roots

    his

    argument

    n the idea that

    the

    law is

    immemorialand

    customary. 40

    37. Ibid., 161.

    38. Ibid.,

    111.

    39. Idem.

    40. Ibid.,

    229.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    17/23

    CAN

    OUR

    UNDERSTANDING

    OF OLD TEXTS BE OBJECTIVE?

    317

    5. Cases of underdeterminationf

    a secondary

    nterpretation

    In describing

    ach kindof secondary

    meaning

    of a text I have drawnattention

    to criteria

    which historians

    espect n deciding

    whethera secondary

    nterpreta-

    tion of a text is acceptable r not. It sometimeshappens,however, hat two or

    more different econdary

    nterpretations

    meet these criteria

    equally well,

    and

    thenthere

    s no rationalground or

    saying hatone interpretation

    s morecorrect

    than another.

    For

    example,according o Christopher

    Butler,

    there are several

    differentmodern summary

    accounts of

    Emily

    Brontd's

    WutheringHeights

    whichareequallywarranted.

    He accepts

    hat theyall meet

    nternalcriteria

    of

    accuracy,

    consistency,scope,

    simplicity, and fruitfulness. 41

    erek

    Traversi,

    for

    instance,

    sees

    it

    as

    contrastingbasic human

    emotions

    with the superficial

    graces of civilized ife; TerryEagleton arguesthat Catherine tradesher au-

    thenticselfhood

    for

    social

    privilege,

    howingan ideological

    contradiction

    e-

    tween

    the

    individualand

    the family;whereas

    Patsy Stoneman

    ees

    it

    as

    demon-

    strating

    the pressures

    o conformityput upon

    women

    in

    Victoriannuclear

    families.42

    utler ays

    hat the ext aloneunderdetermines

    ur nterpretation, 43

    and

    suggests

    we should accept

    the

    diversity

    of readings

    n

    this

    case.

    Similarly

    Paul

    B.

    Armstrong as

    discusseddifferent econdary

    nterpretations

    of EdgarAllan Poe's

    The Turnof

    the Screw.EdmundWilson

    observed

    hat as

    only the governesssees the ghost of Peter Quint, the storycan be seento be

    about the

    fantasies

    of

    a

    thwarted

    Anglo-Saxonspinster -an

    interpretation

    basedupon

    Freudian

    heory.

    For

    Wayne

    Booth, on the other

    hand, the ghosts

    are

    real,

    and it is

    just

    a

    frightening host story.

    Finally, Robert

    Heilmannhas

    read it as a struggle

    f evil to possess

    the humansoul. 44

    Armstrong

    draws

    attention

    o the way

    a critic'sview

    of

    life

    informshis or her

    interpretation.

    He

    acknowledges

    hat

    minimum

    tandards

    have

    to

    be met for

    an

    interpretation

    o

    be

    acceptable.

    It must

    demonstrate

    nternal coherence

    and

    effectiveness

    n

    meetingunexpectedchallenges, 45e says, meaningthat the interpretation

    should coherewell

    with

    the

    basic

    meaning

    of

    the

    text,

    though

    even this is

    not

    alwaysunambiguous.46

    rmstrongargues hat,

    in

    this case

    at

    least,

    an

    appeal

    to the historyof

    the

    book's composition,

    to Poe's intentions,

    will

    not resolve

    the issuebecause hese

    can

    be variously nterpreted

    s

    well.47He finds

    no rational

    groundsfor preferring

    ne

    of these interpretations

    o

    another.

    It

    is

    interesting

    o

    notice

    that the

    Freudian

    nterpretation

    f

    The

    Turn

    of

    the

    Screw

    nearly

    succumbed

    o

    the

    criticism

    by

    A.

    J.

    A. Waldock that

    it

    could

    41. Christopher

    Butler, On the Rivalry of

    Norms for

    Interpretation, New Literary

    History 20

    (1988-1989),

    133.

    42. Ibid., 129-130.

    43.

    Ibid., 132.

    44. Paul B. Armstrong,

    History

    and Epistemology:

    The Example

    of the Turn of the Screw,

    New Literary History

    19

    (1987-1988),

    697-698.

    45.

    Ibid., 700.

    46. Ibid., 701-702.

    47.

    Ibid., 707-708.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 29 Oct 2014 11:06:43 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 McCullagh, Can Our Understanding of Old Texts be Objective.pdf

    18/23

    318

    C. BEHAN

    MCCULLAGH

    not

    explain

    the

    governess'saccurate

    description

    of Peter

    Quint, whose

    ghost

    according

    o this theory

    she

    had never

    seen. Armstrong

    notes

    that a

    single

    failure

    o

    fit

    may thus

    have devastating

    epercussions

    or the entire

    nterpretive

    configuration. 48s it turnedout, the Freudian heorywas saved, at least to

    some

    extent,by

    John Silver,

    who identified everalways

    n

    which

    the

    governess

    could

    have learned

    of Quint'sfeatures,

    including

    reports

    from

    people

    in the

    village

    nearby.

    IV. THE PROBLEM

    OF

    PAST

    CULTURES

    I have argued

    that there

    are

    objective

    criteria

    for

    deciding

    which

    basic

    and

    secondary nterpretations f a text are acceptable,and which are not. In the

    case

    of

    the

    basic meaning

    of a text,

    these criteriaare normally

    decisive.

    When

    it

    comes

    to secondary

    nterpretations,

    here is

    more

    room for equally

    well

    supported

    alternative

    eadings.

    Now

    I mustraise

    a

    problem

    which

    confronts

    historians

    nterpreting

    ld

    texts.

    Historians

    want

    to know

    what old

    texts

    meant

    when

    they

    were irstpublished.

    Historians

    do not

    merely

    ook for

    an

    interpreta-

    tion

    of the

    text which

    will

    fit it

    well.

    They

    look

    for

    a

    reading

    whichwill do

    that

    and

    which

    is also

    likely

    to

    have been

    historically

    correct that

    is, a

    reading

    which hemajorityof educated eaderswouldhaveacceptedat the timethetext

    was written.

    But are

    they

    ever

    justified

    n

    thinking

    hat

    their

    interpretation

    f

    an

    old

    text

    is historically

    orrect?

    Hans-Georg

    Gadamer

    has argued

    at length

    in

    his book

    Truthand

    Method

    that

    it is never reasonable

    o

    suppose

    that

    we have

    an

    accurate

    knowledge

    of

    whattextsreally

    meant

    n

    the past.

    Gadamer

    presents

    he

    process

    of

    interpreta-

    tion

    as one

    of

    trying

    o

    findan

    interpretation

    hich

    willmake he textmeaningful

    to

    oneself.

    He likens

    it to the

    process

    of

    trying

    to

    understand

    what another

    person s saying n conversation.Onebeginswith thephysical ounds,or in the

    case

    of

    texts,

    the marks

    on a

    paper,

    andtheseare

    nterpreted

    n

    accordance

    with

    the

    interpreter's

    xisting

    knowledge

    of the

    language

    and

    of the

    subject-matter.49

    If one's

    initial nterpretation

    f

    a

    text

    does

    not

    fit

    it

    exactly,

    if

    it

    is inconsistent

    withsome

    featuresof

    the

    text,

    or

    makes

    no

    sense

    of

    them,

    then

    different

    nterpre-

    tations

    are

    tried to see

    whether

    hey

    are

    more

    comprehensive.

    At

    every

    stage,

    Gadamer

    points

    out,

    the

    possible

    interpretations

    re

    drawn

    from one's

    own

    prior

    knowledge

    of likely

    meanings,

    one's prejudices,

    s

    he calls them.50t is

    no surprise,Gadamer oncludes, hat interpretationshange romtimeto time.

    They

    are inescapably

    relative

    to the knowledge

    of

    the

    interpreter.

    You,

    for

    example,

    know

    immediately

    when

    you

    read

    a

    classic

    essayby

    Mommsen

    he

    only

    time

    when it could

    have been

    written. Even

    a master

    of the

    historical

    method s

    not able to

    keep

    himself

    entirely

    ree

    from the

    prejudices

    f his

    time,

    48.

    Ibid.,

    701.

    49. Gadamer, Truth and Method, 349-352