Information-structure driven word order variation in the ...€¦ · van Kemenade 2011) • This...

30
Information-structure driven word order variation in the history of English: a phase-based approach Tara Struik & Ans van Kemenade Radboud University Nijmegen DiGS20 19-06-2018

Transcript of Information-structure driven word order variation in the ...€¦ · van Kemenade 2011) • This...

  • Information-structure driven word order variation in the history of English: a

    phase-based approach

    Tara Struik & Ans van Kemenade Radboud University Nijmegen

    DiGS20 19-06-2018

  • Roadmap

    (re)Examination of Old English (OE) and early Middle English (eME) OV/VO Variation

    New insights –  Old English (OE) and early Middle English (eME) OV word order (both AuxV and VAux) with

    referential objects is characterised by givenness of the object –  There is no evidence that quantified and negated objects are syntactically different from

    referential objects

    Unified syntactic analysis –  Phase-based approach ! all preverbal objects are the result of movement to spec,v –  Some types of objects (referential/quantified/negated) have an extra feature layer which needs

    to be valued –  Movement is triggered by an Edge Feature (EF) on v causing movement to value that extra

    feature –  The feature layer for quantified and negated objects is different; this is what is responsible for

    the different rates of change in the change from OV to VO.

  • A long-standing debate: three analyses

    I.  Basic OV with optional rightward movement (van Kemenade, 1987; Koopman, 1990; Lightfoot, 1991;Stockwell & Minkova, 1991)

    II.  The Double Base Hypothesis; basic OV ánd basic VO, with rightward and leftward movement whenever relevant (Pintzuk, 1999; Pintzuk, 2005; Taylor & Pintzuk, 2012a, 2012b)

    III.  Basic VO analysis with optional leftward movement (Fischer et. al, 2000; Biberauer & Roberts, 2005, 2006)

  • 2 (movement) possibilities

    If either one of these scenarios is true and if we assume that there is a factor which triggers movement, we can make the following predictions: a.  A homogeneous set of OV objects (i.e. objects that are triggered) b.  A homogeneous set of VO objects (i.e. objects that are triggered)

    ! Information Structure (for referential objects)

  • Materials & Method

    •  OE: York-Toronto-Helsinki Parsed Corpus of Old English Prose (YCOE) (Taylor et al. 2003) -  Selection of texts from the O2 and O23 period (850-1050)

    •  eME: Penn-Helsinki Parsed Corpus of Middle English, 2nd edition (PPCME2) (Kroch & Taylor 2000) -  Selection of texts from the M1 period (1150 – 1250)

    •  Non-translated texts; Cichosz et al,. (2017) show that the Latin original text influences OV/VO behaviour. More especially, quantified and negated objects (cf. Gianollo 2016 on preverbal negative in Late Latin).

    •  Subclauses with a finite verb, a non-finite verb and a direct object

    •  Annotated for information structure (using a simplified version of the Pentaset (Komen 2013))

  • IS annotation

    Given (1) Þæt anlipige Godes tempel wæs wundorlice gecræft. þurh gastlicum gerynum; Dauid se mæra

    cyning hæfde gemynt þæt he wolde þæt tempel aræran đam ælmihtigan Gode to wurđmynte. ‘that single temple of God was wondrously contrived through ghostly mysteries. David, the great king, had designed that he would rear that temple to the honour of the almighty God.’

    [+ACHom_II,_45:335.10.7522-23]

    (2) We magan ongytan þæt he forþon us gesette þæt we hine biddan sceoldan, þy we sceolan þonne eac, in þa tid þæs gebedes, ure heortan geclænsian from oþrum geþohtum. ‘We may perceive that he has formed us that we should pray to him, so we must during our time of prayer cleanse our hearts from wayward desires.

    [HomS_8_[BlHom_2]:21106.266]

    (3) þæt se awergda gast ongan Godes bec trahtian ‘…. that the accursed spirit began to expound God’s books’

    [HomS_10_[BlHom_3]:29.59.398]

  • IS annotation

    New (4) Nu segđ se wyrdwritere þæt seo wicce sceolde aræran þa of deaþe þone Drihtnes witegan

    Samuhel gehaten, haliges lifes mann, ‘… now says the historian that the witch should then raise from the dead the Lord’s prophet, named Samuel, a man of holy life.’

    [+AHom_30:45.4103] (5) … cwæđ đæt he wolde genealæcan his hulce gif he mihte.

    ‘… [the leper] said that he wished to reach his hut, if he could’ [+ACHom_I,_23:369.136.4634]

  • A (re)examination of OE OV/VO variation

    AUXOV AUXVO OAUXV OVAUX VAUXO TOTAL

    GIVEN 293 (97.7%) 125 (51.0%) 42 (97.7%) 143 (98.0%) 23 (67.7%) 626

    NEW 7 (2.3%) 120 (49.0%) 1 (2.3%) 3 (2.1%) 11 (32.4%) 142

    TOTAL 300 247 43 146 34 768

    •  OV word order is reserved for given objects; there are virtually no new preverbal objects

    •  VO word order is a mix of given and new objects

    Struik & van Kemenade (in press):

  • A (re)examination of eME OV/VO variation

    •  VAux orders have largely disappeared

    •  OV orders have been reduced

    •  What OV that is left is reserved for given objects (confirming the data of Elenbaas & van Kemenade 2014)

    AUXOV AUXVO OAUXV OVAUX VAUXO TOTAL

    GIVEN 96 (100%) 100 (64.9%) 9 (100%) 4 (100%) 5 (62.5%) 214

    NEW 0 (0%) 54 (35.1%) 0 (0%) 0 (0%) 3 (37.5%) 57

    TOTAL 96 154 9 4 8 271

  • From OE to eME

    •  Stripping the data of structural assumptions leads to new insights in the nature of OV/VO variation and the change to a strict VO language

    •  OV is reserved for given objects, and for quantified and negated objects •  There is a stepwise decline in the number of OV objects, but the trigger remains the same •  The VO orders are mixed in terms of IS (also when leaving aside the effect of weight)

  • Quantified and negated objects

    The position of quantified and negated has been assumed, from a Double Base perspective, to be different (Pintzuk & Taylor 2004, 2006), but these objects occur in exactly the same positions as referential objects:

  • Quantified and negated objects (6) a. AuxOV

    for þan đe he sceolde ærest menine mann mid his micclum wisdome Gode gestrynan ‘for he had first to gain many a man to God by his great wisdom’

    +ACHom_I,_27:403.94.5322 b. AuxVO swa þæt eall þæt folc mihte geseon swyđe mycel fyr ofer ealne þone munt mid egeslicum lige, ‘such that all the people could see a lot of fire over all the hill with aweful flames’

    +AHom_21:27.3091 c. OAuxV and þu mycelne wurđmynt miht swa begitan. ‘and thou mayest so obtain great honour

    +ALS_[George]:120.3145 d. OVAux þæt hi ealle eorđlice đing sæmninga forlætan magon ‘that they must suddenly leave all earthly things

    +ACHom_II,_29:232.78.5167 e. VAuxO for đan đe he habban wile micel werod mid him ‘because he wants to have many men with him’

    +AHom_11:545.1770

  • Quantified and negated objects

    •  The position of quantified and negated has been assumed’, from a Double Base perspective to be different (Pintzuk & Taylor 2004, 2006), but these objects occur in exactly the same positions as referential objects:

    •  Once a scenario in which OV is derived from VO has been established, we can extend this to quantified and negated objects

  • Quantified and negated objects in OE

    •  The distribution of quantified and negated objects closely parallels that of referential objects •  The number of AuxVO is higher with referential objects, but this is because new objects are allowed only in

    postverbal position

    AUXOV AUXVO OAUXV OVAUX VAUXO TOTAL

    QUANTNP 46 (44.7%) 27 (26.2%) 6 (5.83%) 19 (18.45%) 5 (4.9%) 103

    NEGP 12 (38.7%) 7 (22.6%) 2 (6.45%) 9 (29.03%) 1 (3.2%) 31

    TOTAL 58 (43.3%) 34 (25.4%) 8 (6.0%) 28 (20.9%) 6 (4.5%) 134

    REF 300 (39.1%) 247 (32.2%) 43 (5.6%) 146 (19.0%) 34 (4.2%) 768

  • Quantified and negated objects in eME

    •  The distribution of quantified and negated objects closely parallels that of referential objects •  The number of AuxVO is higher with referential objects, but this is because new objects are allowed

    only in postverbal position

    AUXOV AUXVO OAUXV OVAUX VAUXO TOTAL

    QUANTNP 22 (33.8%) 36 (55.4%) 5 (7.7%) 1 (1.5%) 1 (1.5%) 65

    NEGP 3 (30.0%) 6 (60.0%) 0 (0%) 0 (0%) 1 (10.0%) 10

    TOTAL 25 (33.3%) 42 (56.0%) 5 (6.7%) 1 (1.3%) 2 (2.7%) 75

    REF 96 (35.2%) 154 (56.8%) 9 (3.3%) 4 (1.5%) 8 (3%) 271

  • Quantified and negated objects

    •  The distribution of quantified and negated objects does not differ from the distribution of referential objects.

    •  Conclusion: a scenario in which OV is derived from VO is to be preferred for referential objects as well as quantified and negated objects.

  • Fit the data to the theory

    •  Our data analysis highlights three elements that a syntactic theory needs to account for:

    -  OV order as the result of givenness -  OV order as the result of quantification/negation -  The step-wise change from OV to VO from OE and eME, starting with VAux clauses

    •  We show that a phase-based analysis of OE/eME word order derivations (building on Biberauer and Roberts (2005, 2006 et seq.) can derive all word orders in a unified way

  • Assumptions •  Pre-Auxiliaries trigger

    restructuring

    •  VR allows defective T as its complement

    •  We assume that V moves, via v, to T on the lower cycle.

    •  The Aux in the higher cycle can be in either T or V

    •  O is base-generated as the complement of V in post-verbal position

    •  The subject is merged in spec,v

    CP

    C’

    C TP

    T’

    Aux vP

    v’

    v VR

    V’

    Aux TP

    T’

    T vP

    S v’

    v VP

    V’

    V O

  • What triggers movement?

    •  Aboh (2010: 14): A numeration N pre-determines the Information Structure of a linguistic expression

    •  This predetermination comes in the form of an extra feature-layer on the object (cf. also Biberauer & van Kemenade 2011)

    •  This means that there is an extra feature that needs to be checked/ valued before the derivation can converge

    •  This leads to an unbalanced phase (in the sense of Müller 2011); we are left with a feature that cannot be checked/valued in the current phase.

    •  We need something like an Edge Feature to complete the phase, which attracts the DP (which can have interpretive consequences) and which makes the feature visible to higher phases.

    n*P

    DP

    D NP

  • Edge Features

    •  Edge Feature Condition (EFC) (cf. Chomsky 2005): The head X of phase XP may be assigned an edge feature after the phase XP is otherwise complete, but only if that has an effect on outcome.

    •  Müller (2011) Edge Feature Condition (EFC, new version)(Müller 2011): An edge feature [•X•] can be assigned to the head γ of a phase only if (a), (b), and (c) hold: a. The phase headed by γ is not otherwise balanced. b. γ has not yet discharged all its structure-building or probe features. c. [•X•] ends up on top of γ’s list of structure-building features.

    ! Spec,v is the place where interaction with PF and LF interfaces takes place and we assume that this is the location where IS is formally encoded (i.e. Chomsky (2005)’s D-effect; cf. López 2009 for a similar proposal) ! This gives the object the opportunity to check its features in a higher phase; the phase edge thus serves as an escape hatch; this is especially relevant for quantifiers, negated objects, and pronouns

  • Quantified and negated objects

    •  We follow Christensen (2004)’s analysis of derivation of quantifiers by phase, assuming a [uQuant/Neg] feature on T (following the general assumption of QR as adjunction to IP in standard GB analysis).

    •  The quantified and negated objects have an extra feature layer marking them [Quant/Neg].

    •  The [uQuant/Neg] feature will not be able to see [Quant/Neg], as it is in the lower vP phase, which has already been sent to spell-out. The [Quant/Neg] object will thus have to make itself visible at the vP edge.

    •  The derivation will thus insert an Edge Feature, which allows movement to spec,v.

  • AuxVO: derived

    •  Obligatory V-to-v-to-T movement

    •  Object has three options -  It pied-pipes the VP to spec,v -  It moves to Spec,v by itself

    -  It stays in its basic position and is sent to spell-out once vP is completed (as the result of PIC)

    •  The subject moves to the higher cycle (see Biberauer & van Kemenade (2011)) for a similar IS-driven account of subject positions)

    Given objects Quantified/negated objects

    New/heavy objects

  • AuxOV

    •  Obligatory V-to-v-to-T movement

    •  Object moves/pied-pipes to Spec,v

    •  No new objects because of the Phase Impenetrability Condition:

    Once a phase is completed, material inside it becomes inaccessible for further syntactic operations. Only materials in the edge are available

    •  If the object were to stay in the VP, it would be spelled out with VO as a result.

    CP

    C’

    C TP

    T’

    Aux vP

    v’

    v VR

    V’

    Aux TP

    T’

    V-v-T vP

    S v’

    O VP

    V’

    O

    Given objects Quantified and negated objects

  • OAuxV

    •  Obligatory V-to-v-to-V movement

    •  Movement of O to spec,v

    •  No movement of new objects

    •  vP is pied-piped to the higher clause as a result of features of S

    CP

    C’

    C TP

    T’

    Aux vP

    v’

    v VR

    V’

    Aux TP

    T’

    V-v-T vP

    S v’

    O VP

    V’

    O

    Given objects Quantified and negated objects

  • OVAux + VAuxO •  Obligatory V-to-v-to-T movement

    •  Movement of O to spec,v

    •  Spell-out of O in VP leads to VAuxO

    Given objects Quantified and negated objects CP

    C’

    C TP

    T’

    Aux vP

    v’

    v VR

    V’

    TP

    T’

    V-v-T vP

    S v’

    O VP

    V’

    O

  • A note on diachrony

    There is step-wise disappearance of object checking

    a. Loss of pied-piping to value v’s features; this was restricted to DP-movement with referential objects (including pronouns); pronouns can still move to higher positions

    b. Referential objects lose their extra feature layer (presumably as a result of the grammaticalization of the determiner); loss of DP-movement and loss of high object pronouns. Retention of an Edge Features with quantified/negated objects

    c. Movement of quantified and negated objects becomes covert

    A sketch of further changes (cf. Biberauer & Roberts 2008: 27); subject to further research

    d. Loss of pied-piping to value T’s features e. (Matrix) C loses feature triggering T-movement f. Modal features of T realised by Merge g. v loses feature triggering V-movement h. T loses obligatory feature triggering v-movement

  • Conclusion

    (re)Examination of Old English (OE) and early Middle English (eME) OV/VO Variation

    New insights –  Old English (OE) and early Middle English (eME) OV word order (both AuxV and VAux) with

    referential objects is characterised by givenness of the object –  There is no evidence that quantified and negated objects are syntactically different from

    referential objects

    Unified syntactic analysis –  Phase-based approach ! all preverbal objects are the result of movement to spec,v –  Some types of objects (referential/quantified/negated) have an extra feature layer which needs

    to be valued –  Movement is triggered by an Edge Feature (EF) on v causing movement to value that extra

    feature –  The feature layer for quantified and negated objects is different; this is what is responsible for

    the different rates of change in the change from OV to VO.

  • References

    Aboh, E. (2010). Information structuring begins with the Numeration. Iberia, 2(1), 12-42. Biberauer, T., & van Kemenade, A. (2011). Subject Positions and Information-Structural Diversification in

    the History of English. Catalan Journal of Linguistics(10), 17-69. Biberauer, T., & Roberts, I. (2005). Changing EPP-parameters in the history of English: accounting for

    variation and change. English Language and Linguistics, 9(1), 5-46. Biberauer, T., & Roberts, I. (2008). Cascading paramter changes: Internally-driven change in Middle and

    Early Modern English. In T. Eythórsson (Ed.), Grammatical Change and Linguistic Theory: The Rosendal papers (pp. 79-113): John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Biberauer, T., & Roberts, I. (2006). The loss of residual “head-final” orders and remnant fronting in Late Middle English: causes and consequences. In J. Hartmann and L. Molnárfi (Eds.), Comparative Studies in Germanic Syntax: From Afrikaans to Zurich German, 263 – 297.

    Chomsky, Noam (2005): Three Factors in Language Design, Linguistic Inquiry 36, 1– 22. Christensen, K. (2004) Quantifier Movement and Derivation by Phase Now You See It, Now You Don’t.

    Paper presented at the Workshop on Comparative and Theoretical Linguistics: “When and why do constituents move?”, University of Aarhus.

    Cichosz, A., Gaszewski, J., & Pęzik, P. (2017). Element Order in Old English and Old High German Translations. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

  • References

    Elenbaas, M., & van Kemenade, A. (2014). Verb particles and OV/VO in the histoy of English. Studio Linguistics, 68(1), 140-167.

    Fischer, O., Kemenade, A. v., Koopman, W., & van der Wurff, W. (2000). The Syntax of Early English. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Gianollo, Chiara. (2016). Negation and indefinites in Late Latin. Pallas, 102. 277 – 286. van Kemenade, A. (1987). Syntactic case and morphological case in the history of English. Dordrecht:

    Foris. Komen, E. (2013). Finding focus: a study of the historical development of focus in English. (PhD), LOT,

    Utrecht. Koopman, W. (1990). Word order in Old English; with special reference to the verb phrase. (PhD),

    University of Amsterdam, Kroch, A., and A. Taylor. (2000). The Penn-Helsinki Parsed Corpus of Middle English (PPCME2). Lightfoot, D. (1991). How to set parameters: Arguments from language change. Cambridge, MA: MIT

    Press. López, L. (2009). A Derivational Syntax for Information Structure. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Müller, G. 2011. Constraints on displacement. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

  • References

    Pintzuk, S. (1999). Phrase structures in competition: Variation and change in Old English word order: Garland Publishing.

    Pintzuk, S. (2005). Arguments against a universal base: evidence from Old English. English Language and Linguistics, 9(1), 115-138.

    Pintzuk, S., & Taylor, A. (2004). Objects in Old English: Why and how Early English is not Icelandic. York Papers In Linguistics (YPL2), 2(1), 137-150.

    Pintzuk, S., & Taylor, A. (2006). The loss of OV in the History of English. In A. v. Kemenade & B. Los (Eds.), The Handbook of the History of English (pp. 249-278). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

    Stockwell, R. P., & Minkova, D. (1991). Subordination and word order change in the history of English. In D. Kastovsky (Ed.), Historical English Syntax (pp. 367-408). New York: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Taylor, A., & Pintzuk, S. (2012a). Rethinking the OV/VO alternation in Old English: The effect of complexity, grammatical weight and information status. In T. Nevalainen & E. C. Traugott (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of the History of English. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Taylor, A., & Pintzuk, S. (2012b). Verb order, object position and information status in Old English. York Papers in Linguistics Series, 2(12a), 29-52.

    Taylor, A., Warner, A., Pintzuk, S., & Beths, F. (2003). The York-Toronto-Helsinki Parsed Corpus of Old English Prose.