Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

download Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

of 16

Transcript of Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    1/16

    1

    Foundations in Kantian Constructivism necessary and necessarily

    metaphysical

    Dr. Kerstin Budde

    Associate Lecturer

    Cardiff University, School of European Studies

    University of Sheffield, Department of PhilosophyEmail: [email protected]

    [email protected]

    Abstract:Kantian Constructivism, first developed by John Rawls, has been seen by many as a

    new and fruitful way of justifying liberal and democratic institutions. The key claim

    of Kantian constructivism as a justificatory theory is that it can convincingly argue for

    the objectivity or reasonableness of certain norms and institutions, thus avoidingrelativism, without relying on any contested foundations. Instead the claim of

    "construction" is to start from uncontested premises and to construct via a reasonable

    procedure principle all could agree on. This paper will argue that despite this aim of

    constructivism, the arguments of Kantian constructivists imply certain foundational

    premises. I argue that this is not just an unfortunate mistake of some Kantian

    Constructivists, but that foundations or foundational premises are necessarily a part of

    constructivist argument. I then further argue that the foundations used in Kantian

    constructivism are most plausibly understood as metaphysical foundations, and that

    indeed they need to be metaphysical to account for the objectivity of the norms

    'constructed'.

    1. Introduction

    Kantian Constructivism, first developed by John Rawls, has been seen by many as a

    new and fruitful way of justifying liberal and democratic institutions. The key claim

    of Kantian constructivism as a justificatory theory is that it can convincingly argue for

    the objectivity or reasonableness of certain norms and institutions, thus avoiding

    relativism, without relying on any contested foundations. Instead the claim of

    "construction" is to start from uncontested premises and to construct via a reasonable

    procedure principle all could agree on. This paper will argue that despite this aim of

    constructivism, the arguments of Kantian constructivists imply certain foundational

    premises. I argue that this is not just an unfortunate mistake of some Kantian

    Constructivists, but that foundations or foundational premises are necessarily a part ofconstructivist argument. I then further argue that the foundations used in Kantian

    constructivism are most plausibly understood as metaphysical foundations, and that

    indeed they need to be metaphysical to account for the objectivity of the norms

    'constructed'.

    It will start my analysis of Kantian constructivism, by imposing upon it a formal

    structure, which I argue captures the essence of the constructivist enterprise.1 I will

    then proceed by indicating where within this formal structure Kantian

    1Different authors have emphasised different elements or features in their characterization of Kantian

    constructivism.See for example Krasnoff 1999: 388ff, Barry 1989: 266ff, ONeill 2003: 348ff, Brink1996: 307ff and Dworkin 2004: 159ff. I would argue that my characterization captures the essential

    elements of Kantian constructivism as a non-foundational, non-relativist theory of justification.

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    2/16

    2

    constructivisms failure to provide a non-foundationalist theory of justification can be

    located, using as examples Rawlss ONeills and Scanlons constructivism. This

    failure is that each of the Kantian constructivists discussed relies upon a

    foundational conception of the person. This leads me to argue that no Kantian

    constructivism can be an anti-foundational theory of justification, if it continues to

    make strong normative claims for moral principles. I further argue that Kantianconstructivism again if it wants to retain its claim to objectivity will also have to

    provide a metaphysical argument for their favoured conception of the person. This is

    so because theoretically there are several foundational assumptions possible, and thus

    a moral theory has only conditional status unless we can give an explanation, account

    or justification of the necessity, priority, or truth of a particular foundational

    assumption. This, I argue, will however be an argument, which transcends the domain

    of both the specific moral inquiry as well as any other scientific inquiry and must

    approximate an all-encompassing explanation of the reality or our necessary

    conception of the world. That is, it must involve a metaphysical argument.

    2. Foundations in Kantian Constructivism2.1. Formal characterization

    I want to start with giving a general outline of what I have taken to be the

    constructivist enterprise and indicate where one can locate the foundational

    assumptions within this structure, using as example three constructivist theories. I will

    then go on to make the claim that these foundational assumptions are not just present

    in the three particular constructivist theories, but will be found necessarily in all

    constructivist theories, which subscribe to the general outline of (Kantian)

    constructivism and its particular ambitions.

    If one wants to characterize (Kantian) constructivism in a general or formal

    way, then, I think, one could do so as follows. Constructivism starts with certain facts

    or conceptions a, b, c which are said to be basic, weak, non-question-begging and

    uncontroversial (but obviously relevant for the construction of moral and political

    principles). A, b, cthen feed into a procedurepin a twofold fashion: they can either

    determine the build-up or structure of the procedure in the form of certain constraints

    or they can be used as data within the procedure. Pthen generates various normative

    moral or political principles n1, n2, n3

    It is important here to note that constructivism generally conceives of the basic

    facts or conceptions as being plural, trying to fend off from the very start any

    suspicions or danger of foundationalism. One will therefore rarely find a

    constructivist who sets out explicitly to use only one basic fact or conception, which

    one might illustrate as follows: a

    p

    n1, n2, n3 Instead the argument willgenerally proceed according to the following formula: a, b, cpn1, n2, n3

    Further, a, b, c are seen as basic and in one sense morally non-committal or non-

    substantive. By this I want to emphasise the crucial constructivist assumption that n1,

    n2, n3do not follow straightforwardly or directly from a, b, c; that is, the resulting

    normative principles are not assumed to be already entailed within normative starting

    assumptions. For this to hold, constructivism must claim for p a (what I will call)

    self-generating element. As Krasnoff has set out, the procedure must take us beyond

    the basic materials and must lead us to particular principles (Krasnoff 1999: 387). For

    this, the procedure in itself must do some substantial work in getting us to the specific

    principles n1, n2, n3, which we could not arrive at by an analysis of a, b, c alone.

    Foundations are then avoided when neither of the basic conceptions a, b, cgrounds or influences either n1, n2, n3or pfundamentally, and when the procedure

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    3/16

    3

    contains an independent element which enables it to generate principles that take us

    beyond what is implied or entailed in a, b, c. For foundations to be avoided, however,

    the procedure itself must also be as basic and non-controversial as possible and the

    procedural element which generates principles must be suitably influenced by and

    connected to a, b, c, so that it does not on its own determine the principles n1, n2, n3

    regardless of the specific basic conception. To illustrate, it must make a difference tothe principles n1, n2, n3if the basic material is a, b, cor if it isx,y,z.

    Constructivism then asserts that it is the (systematic) coming, connecting and

    working together of several elements, all of which are as much as possible basic,

    convincing and uncontroversial, so that they cannot reasonably be doubted or

    contested, which leads to normative principles, and which avoids relying on a single

    foundation. Thus, as we are simultaneously said to (have to) accept the starting

    assumptions and procedure, once we are shown, how when considered all together,

    we reach the particular normative principles, we cannot but accept them too, without

    however, thereby, being committed to one foundational fact, value or moral principle.

    Given that the starting assumptions and the (nature or build-up of the) procedure are

    said to be in an uncontroversial sense right or correct, so are the resulting normativeprinciples.

    2.2. Foundations

    Thus foundationalism is only possible within Kantian constructivism if certain things

    they claim do hold, in fact dont hold. The first of these possibilities concerns the

    plurality and independence of starting assumptions. If instead of several, markedly

    different and to a suitable degree independent2facts or conceptions, only one fact or

    conception influences the set-up or decision within the procedure, a suspicion of

    foundationalism arises. The same suspicion still holds, I would argue, if a

    constructivists had several starting material, but where one starting material is clearly

    dominant in influencing the procedure and decision within the procedure and the

    other facts at best only marginally influential. But this suspicion can only be

    confirmed if the constructive procedure, instead of adding something substantial and

    new to the starting conception, doesnt. If we only have one starting conception and

    fact, and the procedure, instead of adding something substantial in the generation of

    principles, just helps us to see better which moral principles are entailed or required

    by our starting conception, then we dont seem to have constructivism but

    foundationalism. The second possibility of foundationalism in Kantian constructivism

    is then contained in the possible failure of the constructivist procedure to get us

    beyond the starting material to specific principles. Both of these possibilities of failure

    seem to have to be fulfilled before we could definitely accuse Kantian constructivismof foundationalism.

    In the following I would like to briefly show how the three most prominent

    Kantian constructivists, ONeill, Rawls, and Scanlon compare when assessed with

    those criteria in mind. This can be only a very sketchy argument,3but hopefully will

    2The independence condition need not be a strong one, but it rules out, I think, mascerading as several

    facts or conceptions, those which are in fact contained in one. Thus when ONeill talks about the factof plurality and the fact that this plurality is not naturally coordinated, she seems to speek of two facts.But ONeill also states that a plurality which is coordinated naturally is not a genuine pluality (ONeill2000: 212). That is, ONeill here implies that the fact or concept of plurality entails the fact that no pre-established coordination exists. In my characterization this would violate the independence condition.

    These are not several facts, but only one (If ONeills claim that plurality entail non-coordination istrue).3I undertake a more detailed analysis in my PhD thesis Foundationalism in Kantian Constructivism.

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    4/16

    4

    suffice to make my point. Rawls admits in his Kantian constructivism openly to a

    conception of the person (as free, equal, reasonable and rational) as one of the starting

    material of his constructivism. The other starting material (model-conception) is the

    conception of society as well-ordered (Rawls 1980: 520, 530). The conception of

    society as well-ordered does not add anything new or fundamentally important to the

    design or decision within the procedure of construction (the original position) apartfrom the thought that we dont just have a singular instance of the conception of the

    person, but a plurality of such persons (Rawls 1980: 521; Galston 1982: 494) and that

    a well-ordered society would be regulated by a public conception of justice (Rawls

    1980: 521). However, the conception of the person already endowed people with a

    sense of justice, that is, the capacity to understand and act from a conception of justice

    paired with the highest-order interest to exercise and promote this capacity (Rawls

    1980: 525). It thus follows that any society of such people would aim to be regulated

    by a public conception of justice. Thus the conception of the person is Rawlss

    fundamental and most significant starting material. His procedure, the original

    position, does not seem to do any independent work. The original position itself and

    the decision within are characterized almost exclusively according to the conceptionof the person. The veil of ignorance is put into place to make sure we conceive

    ourselves solely as free and equal people (Rawls 1980: 523, 550), and do not

    unreasonably try to advantage ourselves, the rationality of the parties within the

    original position reflect that we are rational and have a conception of the good (Rawls

    1980: 520,521, 528) and the primary goods are those we need to maintain, use and

    further our two moral powers (Rawls 1980: 548). The only principles that can come

    out of the selection process are then those most congruent to the Rawlsian conception

    of the person. The conception of the person as both free and equal, reasonable and

    rational is then the foundation of Rawlss Kantian constructivism.

    ONeill avoids talking of a conception of the person altogether. Indeed it is one

    of her criticisms of Rawls that he illegitimately uses an ideal of the person. Instead

    ONeill aims to use only meagre facts about human agency and the world (ONeill

    2002: 7, 48, 179, 210). Those facts include the fact of plurality, the fact that there is

    no natural coordination between this plurality of agents, the fact that we need

    principles of coordination and the limited capacities and vulnerabilities of human

    beings. From these ONeill tries to construct the fundamental principle of

    followability as the necessary principle of coordination and derives at the first

    principle of justice, the rejection of principles of injury. Because we are faced with a

    plurality of agents and have no inborn standard which could guide interaction with

    each other, we have to adopt as principle to guide our action the principle of

    followability (any maxim of action must be such that it could be followed by allrelevant others) the only principle which includes the possibility of universal

    coordination (ONeill 2002: 60). However, as I have argued elsewhere,4 what is

    crucially underlying this construction are not facts, but the value-commitment to non-

    violent coordination, which is ultimately grounded in the respect and value of rational

    agency. This underlying conception of the person also determines in ONeill which

    principles are followable and thus which principles are constructed. When ONeill

    argues that a principle of injury could not be followed by all, because it would leave

    some peoples capacity for action injured (ONeill 2002: 163), it is not so much

    conceptual followability which does the work here, but a commitment to maintain the

    4Constructivism all the way down: Can ONeill succeed where Rawls failed under submission with

    Contemporary Political Theory.

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    5/16

    5

    (most extensive) capacities for rational agency. While all people could indeed follow

    a principle of injury if they were not committed to value rational agency and its

    expression as such, it could not conceived to be followable by those who have such a

    value commitment.

    Scanlon seems to avoid all those difficulties, by using as a procedure of

    construction the idea of reasonable rejectability (Scanlon 2000: 4) and as startingmaterial various generic reasons (adopting a view which characterises the nature of

    these reasons as or primitive (Scanlon 2000: 17)). The reasons, which could feed

    into the procedure, are unlimited and Scanlon thus seems to the fullest extend to fulfil

    the criteria of plural starting points. When we ask whether a principle could

    reasonably be rejected we can take recourse to the generic reasons connected with the

    relevant standpoints connected to the principle (Scanlon 2000: 204, Scanlon 2002:

    519). These are the materials, which the reasonable rejectability procedure has at its

    disposal. Within the procedure the materials (reasons) are then weighted and

    considered until a decision about the reasonable rejectability of a principle can be

    reached. No conception of the person seems to be lurking around in Scanlons

    constructivism. But this impression is deceptive. Scanlons justification of thereasonable rejectability formula is that this is the only formula, which expresses the

    value of human life as rational autonomous agents (Scanlon 2000: 13, 106, 143, 181,

    231, 268). And further the criteria or standard according to which the various reasons

    are assessed within the procedure is the value of rational autonomous agency

    (Scanlon 2000: 218). In fact, it is to a certain degree irrelevant which reasons are

    brought forward into the procedure, as it is clear that only those reasons that can be

    derived or connected to the value of rational autonomous agency can have any weight

    in determining whether a principle can or cannot be reasonably be rejected.

    Each of the constructivist theories, I then argue, relies on a foundational

    conception of the person. This foundational conception of the person is contained in

    some cases in one of the basic facts, which thereby also proved to be more than a

    pure fact (for example in the case of ONeills Constructivism the need for non-

    violent coordination). In some cases it is straightforwardly assumed as one element of

    the starting material (for example in Rawlss Constructivism). These foundational

    starting conceptions a determine the structure, nature or build-up of the procedure

    fundamentally, and also the decisions or workings within the procedure and

    subsequently the construction of normative principles. The other basic material b, c

    are either derived from a, or indeed peripheral or non-influential to the argument.

    Where the foundational conception of the person is not one of the starting materials

    stated (for example in the case of Scanlons theory) it turns out to be the underlying

    conception v, which determines and structures the procedure exclusively. Here a, b, c(basic reasons) have only indirect influence on the resulting principles, as only those

    facts which are congruent, or can be subsumed under or derived from vhave decisive

    influence on n1, n2, n3 Facts a, b, c have no influence in their own right on

    principles, but are discounted withinpif they do not accord with v.

    Structurally, then, we find foundations in Kantian constructivism either in one

    of the starting materials, structuring p fundamentally, or in the (hidden) conception

    underlying and structuring p. Normative principles n1, n2, n3 are then

    straightforwardly connected to the foundational conception of the person, which takes

    on such a fundamental role and has such substantive content that from an analysis of

    it alone one could have deduced the resulting principles.

    One can thus also see that the procedure in all the constructivist theories lookedat does not fulfil its promise to get us beyond the starting material, constructing out of

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    6/16

    6

    its own with the help of the material, principles which are not already entailed in the

    starting material. Why is this the case? The element or candidate for the productive or

    self-generating nature of the procedure is the idea of agreement, choice or

    (reasonable) rejection employed within the procedure. However, the only way to

    release the potential of this element to add something significant to the starting

    material, I would argue, is to rely on actual choice, agreement or rejection and thus tomake the procedure totally self-generating and independent with little or no

    connections to a, b, c. If actual choice, agreement or rejection is required from the

    procedure then the outcome is open and not pre-determined by a, b or c. But this

    would be so exactly because actual persons or choosers would bring to the choice or

    agreement much more starting material as those specified by constructivism and

    their decision on what is to count as reason for agreement or choice would also be

    guided by different standards and principles. Actual choosers would bring their

    different facts, conceptions or reasons to the table and these could in various ways

    alter or add to the (procedural) situation and thus to the principles decided. The self-

    generating element here comes with the danger of cutting ties with the starting

    material. This is so because the procedure which relies on actual agreement or choiceis unable to guarantee that the starting material specified by constructivists as the

    most important for moral argument can have a meaningful influence on the resulting

    principle.5

    In the same way as one would not be able to predict the influence of the starting

    material a, b, con principles n1, n2, n3, one would also be unable to predict principles

    n1, n2, n3or say anything meaningful about their potential content. Actual agreement

    or choice has to be awaited and there is no guarantee that we will get the same result

    at different times or with different people. Here, however, the reason why we are to

    accept the resulting principles n1, n2, n3 and take them to be objective and

    authoritative, according to the constructivist rationale, no longer applies. We could

    not theoretically comprehend any more how acceptance or correctness of the basic

    starting material and procedure would compel us in a meaningful way to accept the

    resulting principles n1, n2, n3. The link between starting material and resulting

    principles is broken. This is so because the self-generating aspect of the procedure

    has in an important way introduced additional and unrestricted (and I argue morally

    arbitrary) elements into the procedure, which has contaminated the resulting

    principles. In the case of actual agreement or choice someone will always be able to

    challenge the resulting principle as morally arbitrary because nothing prevents them

    from being contingent on the different and uncontrolled reasons and preferences

    brought into the agreement or choice situation. One has not necessarily accepted or

    seen as morally obliging all of the facts and reasons determining the outcome and itcan therefore not be inferred that the outcome is morally obliging because one has to

    accept the starting material.6The only obligation resulting here is the one (implicit in

    5Could the actual choice or agreement situation not be kept open and actual but non-arbitrary in, forexample, requiring actual discussants only to put forward reasons or principles all could accept or find

    un-contestable? I do not think that this will work, as either one would have to specify in advance whatis un-contestable or reasonable for all to accept, in which case one could theoretically specify theprinciples capable of acceptance in advance. Then however, the procedure would no longer really beopen nor need it be actual any more. The other possibility is to wait and see what turns out to beacceptable or un-contestable, which again might depend upon and be contingent upon all kinds of

    reasons, and thus is again arbitrary.6While this is of course even more the case if one has not participated in the initial choice or

    agreement situation, it holds also when one has participated. Actual choice and agreement cannot

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    7/16

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    8/16

    8

    be the case due to the specific nature and structure of the constructivist enterprise, and

    also due to the general structure and nature in normative moral and political

    justification.

    Let me turn to the specific structure of constructivism first and why it will

    always entail a foundational commitment. Two aspects here are crucial. The first

    concerns the basic material that constructivism wants to use. The aim is to use onlybasic uncontroversial and weak premises, which do not have the potential to claim to

    be or to provide a (thick) foundation. The prime candidates for constructivists here are

    basic facts, whether those concerning the human condition, or general sociological,

    psychological or economic facts. Facts would seem to have the advantage of not

    being subject to reasonable rejection or contestation and of not being morally or

    metaphysically loaded, that is of being neutral and therefore an acceptable starting

    point for all regardless of their more particular value commitments.

    However, as Cohen has observed no facts can take on the task of grounding

    normative principles or procedures without presupposing a more ultimate normative

    principle, which explains why the facts would ground that principle or procedure.

    Alternatively one could say that no principle or procedure can be derived purely fromfacts without presupposing a more ultimate or foundational normative principle.

    Cohen states his main thesis as follows:

    In my view and this is my thesis a principle can reflect or respond to a fact

    only because it is also a response to a principle that isnot a response to a fact.

    To put the same point differently, principles that reflect facts must, in order to

    reflect facts, reflect principles that dont reflect facts (Cohen 2003: 214).

    Cohen calls these fact-insensitive principles basic principles (Cohen 2003: 214n4).

    What is important to Cohen is that we need an explanation of why a given fact F

    grounds a principle p (Cohen 2003: 218). So any sequence of arguments for certain

    principles thought to be based on or grounded in facts presupposes a logically prior

    normative principle, which explains why the facts support the given principle. This

    prior principle is valid whether or not the facts hold (Cohen 2003 215, 215/6, 216). It

    is also the foundation of all following principles. Cohen states:

    all principles that reflect facts reflect facts only because they also reflect

    principles that do not reflect facts, and that the latter principles form the ultimate

    foundation of all principles, fact-reflecting principles included (Cohen 2003:

    231, my italics).

    Take, for example, ONeills constructivism, which explicitly aimed to use not just

    basic (empirical) facts but also to ground the constructive procedure in those facts.

    The fact of plurality and the fact that there is no pre-established coordination was said

    to do all the work here. However my analysis showed that what made these facts

    into decisive ones supporting the universality principle was a normative commitment

    to non-violent coordination. This could be expressed for example as principlep1: we

    should seek coordination and communication, which is non-violent. Now, our

    commitment to p1 might be supported by the fact that we are creatures with the

    capacity for reason and communication and therefore can establish non-violent

    coordination. However this fact only supports the principle p1if we believe an even

    more basic principle p2, namely that we should respect and use our rationalcapacities, that is, that we should respect rational creatures. This seems to be an

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    9/16

    9

    ultimate principle which itself is based on no facts and which would also survive the

    denial of the facts. Principles are fact-independent in the sense that they are logically

    prior to and would survive the denial of, the facts they explain. So, for example, we

    would still (have to) be committed to p1, that we should seek non-violent

    coordination, even if we came to believe that there is a pre-conditioned harmony

    among human beings. We would still have to be committed to the goal of non-violentcoordination in cases where it would apply. It is only because we are committed to

    (the truth of) these normative principles that when we are confronted with the fact of

    non-coordination, it can be used to ground a moral principle or procedure. ONeill

    could not ground her normative principles solely on empirical facts without relying on

    a more ultimate and foundational normative principle, which explained why those

    facts support her normative conclusions.

    I think that we can see clearly in ONeill that a more ultimate normative

    principle is presupposed in order to make certain facts relevant for normative

    principles, and that this principle or commitment to this principle is logically prior to

    the facts and is thus also more fundamental than the facts. This expresses nothing

    other than that it is the foundation of ONeills respective theories. Therefore my firstargument against any successful anti-foundational constructivism bases itself on the

    truth of Cohens argument and states that there is no way that constructivism could

    ever get started or get off the ground by basing itself or using solely non-controversial

    facts. They will always be committed one way or another to a more ultimate

    normative principle which then takes on a foundational role.

    My second argument against the success of a non-foundational constructivism is

    even more specific in arguing that no constructivist theory can be put forward without

    a foundational conception of the person. This is related not to the idea of facts as

    adequate starting material, but to the procedure of construction. This procedure is said

    to be in one sense obvious and innocuous, but also to be to a certain extent adding

    something to the basic material and generating specific principles. The most likely

    candidate here is a procedure, which involves (hypothetical) agreement or choice of

    human beings or agents.8If we rule out on good reasons, as I argued actual choice

    or agreement (as normatively authoritative) we are left with a procedure which asks

    what all could or would agree to or reject.

    In one way or another, this can be seen as an expression, interpretation or

    modification of the Kantian universality test, the Categorical imperative. Now, I argue

    that if we do not believe any more that the universality test, as supreme principle of

    practical reason, can undoubtedly and decisively identify moral principles by its pure

    formal operation (contradiction in conception and contradiction in the will), because

    the transcendentally valid criteria of reason would force us all to converge onprinciples which pass this formal test, then any form of this procedure presupposes a

    particular and substantive conception of the person which determines what a person

    can, or must, will, agree or choose.

    For this claim it will be useful to look at Korsgaards argument. Korsgaard, who

    herself puts forward a neo-Kantian theory, argues that what kind of reasons we accept

    or adopt depends on the practical identity we hold (Korsgaard 1996: 101). Without

    such a practical identity we could determine no reasons as relevant and thus have no

    reason to act (Korsgaard 1996: 120). If a constructive procedure asks what we could

    8If anyone is to do the agreeing or choosing, that is, the constructing, then it would have to be human

    beings or agents, as one of constructivisms basic premises is the rejection of both the existence ofsome transcendental being who could construct moral principles and the existence of a natural order

    which could generate or construct moral principles.

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    10/16

    10

    all agree on or choose, and the reasons for choice and agreement depend on our

    conception of ourselves or our practical identity, then what we would agree or

    choose would depend on the particular practical identity we presuppose. And as

    Korsgaard observes, there are numerous possible conceptions of practical identity

    (Korsgaard 1996: 101, 116/7), which consequently would lead to different principles

    being agreed to or chosen. The constructivist theorist has then to argue for herfavoured conception of the person or practical identity and why we all universally

    or within a given community should have or accept this particular identity.

    It is not enough here to argue that we do actually share some particular identity,

    as some practical identities can be shed and are thus contingent (Korsgaard 1996: 102,

    120, 129). An argument has to be made why a particular conception of the person or a

    particular practical identity is the one which we all should or necessarily have to

    accept.9 And once we do accept it, then it will also be clear what kind of reasons,

    given our fundamental practical identity or conception of the person, we will take as

    relevant for us. And only then can we make an argument for what we all (should

    morally) accept or choose.

    I have argued then that the nature of the constructive procedure (combined withtheir fundamental belief that there is no a-historical transcendental reason which

    determines what is rational to do or agree to), forces constructivists to rely on a

    substantial conception of the person or practical identity which makes it intelligible to

    talk about what all people could accept, agree or choose. As it is by no means

    uncontroversial, uncontested or obvious which conception of the person we should

    hold, that is which is the most fundamental one on which then to base morality,

    constructivists will always have to defend and justify their adherence to a particular

    (foundational) conception of the person. The question or procedure that asks what we

    all could agree or choose is not and cannot be an innocuous one, exactly because of

    the fact of pluralism and the rejection of a transcendental reason or nature which

    necessitates us to converge on the same reasons, principles or conceptions of the

    person. By asking what we all could agree, choose or reject constructivists are

    fundamentally asking which conception of the person we should have or have to

    accept as fundamental. And as I have argued before, once we have decided upon this

    9Korsgaards argument proceeds by claiming that our reflective nature necessitates us to have apractical identity which determines our reasons for action. But while most identities are contingent, thefact that we are reflective creatures who need a practical identity is not contingent and cannot be shed

    (Korsgaard 1996: 121/2). This amounts to, as Korsgaard phrases it, the necessary recognition of ourhumanity (Korsgaard 1996: 121) as our fundamental practical identity (although it only becomes

    morally authoritative for us when we endorse it (Korsgaard 1996: 254)). However, Korsgaard alsoadmits that what specific normative obligations we accept depends on our understanding of humanity.Korsgaard says that Citizen of the Kingdom of Ends, participant in a common happiness, speciesbeing, one among others who are equally real, are different conceptions of the human-being- as- suchamong which further sorting would have to be done (Korsgaard 1996: 118). Needless to say, I wouldcontend that Korsgaard is involved in a foundational and metaphysical argument concerning the

    nature of human beings, namely an argument that it is our nature to construct practical identities(Korsgaard 1996: 150) and that she will also need a metaphysical argument regarding the choice ofhow we are to interpret our humanity more concretely. Indeed when Korsgaard states something likethe following, one cannot but help thinking that she is making a metaphysical claim: You areananimal of the sort I have just described. And that is not merely a contingentconceptionof your identity,which you have constructedor chosen for yourself, or could conceivably reject.It is simply the truth

    (Korsgaard 1996: 123, my italics). Interestingly in this statement Korsgaard also seems to equate

    construction with contingency. It is clear, however, that Korsgaard accepts the need for a fundamentalconception of the person as foundation for a moral theory and goes to some lengths to argue for thenecessity of this particular one.

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    11/16

    11

    question it is in a sense a technical (or theoretical) exercise to ask what those persons

    would agree to or choose.

    Kantian Constructivists then have to come clean about the particular

    conception of the person they use as foundational and provide us with a justification

    for it. And given the many possible conceptions of the persons available they have to

    provide us with a justification for it, if the resulting normative principles are notarbitrary and can fulfil their role as normative principles that is telling us what we

    ought to do. This justification cannot itself be constructivist as the question of what

    conception of the person we all could or would accept or choose already presupposes

    (on the constructivist reading) the conception of the person. Thus, constructivists also

    have to face up to the fact that their conception of the person isa non-constructive

    foundation, and that their theory therefore cannot be constructivist. What kind of

    theory they really do provide will then depend on the particular account or

    justification they provide for their conception of the person.

    3. A Note of Foundations

    This said, however, my argument so far has said very little about the nature of andstatus of those foundations (the concept of the person) and how we (can) come to

    know them. I take my argument to be largely neutral in regard to the question of the

    substantive content and status of foundations with two exceptions, which I will

    address, in a short while. For my argument regarding the foundational structure of

    Kantian Constructivism, it is important to point out that I have been using a very

    broad notion of foundation, similar to the one that Andrew Vincent suggests. He

    states:

    The term foundation is used in a very broad sense. It is taken to imply some

    class of statements or propositions, which are favoured absolutely over others.

    To be foundational, this class of statements is regarded as fundamental

    fundamental implying that its possessors cannot avoid deferring or referring

    back to it. This class of statements is, in other words, always presupposed by a

    diversity of other statements. Insofar as this class of statements is fundamental,

    it can be considered near inescapable or near unavoidable in any theorizing

    (Vincent 2004: 3).10

    His definition of foundations as having fundamental status favoured absolutely over

    others accords with my use of foundations. Vincent argues that through this

    fundamental status these foundations can be seen as inescapable or unavoidable,

    echoing here more traditional definitions of foundations, which, for example, claim

    that foundational beliefs have to be undeniable and immune to revision (Herzog1985: 20).11While Vincent has weakened this assumed requirement considerably, it

    seems to be important for my use of foundations to clarify it further. On my reading

    foundational assumptions are inescapable or unavoidable or non-revisablewith regard

    toa given theory. That is, while I want to allow the possibility to revise, question and

    doubt the foundational assumptions of the justification of a particular theory, I want to

    argue that this doubt or revision will alter the justified theory fundamentally. We can,

    for example, doubt in a Kantian theory whether property rights are a necessary

    10For other more specific or narrow definitions of foundationalism see Seery 1999: 466, Herzog, 1985:

    20, Timmons 2004: 226, 234/5, Brink 1996: 102, Ripstein 1987: 115, Heath 1997: 460.11

    Brink similarly argues that what is essential to foundational beliefs, according to foundationalism, istheir relative incorrigibility (subjective conceptions) or their relative reliability (objective conceptions)

    (Brink 1996: 110).

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    12/16

    12

    precondition for practical reason to be effective in the world and thus adjust the

    theory accordingly, yet we could still, I would suggest, maintain that the overall

    nature of the theory (and the account of the authoritative status of moral obligation) is

    Kantian, because this element is not the foundational element of a Kantian theory.

    However, we could not change or doubt the belief in human beings freedom without

    altering the theory fundamentally. My point is therefore that foundational assumptionsare fundamental for any moral theory and have to be favoured above all others, as

    doubting or altering these foundational assumptions would result in the destruction or

    alteration of the whole theory.

    This avoids in my mind one of the frequent attacks against foundationalism,

    namely that there is no presupposition or assumption, which could not theoretically be

    doubted or imagined to be different, and that it is unclear what would make such a

    foundational assumption self-justifying or self-evident. Foundations on my reading

    then do not have to be self-justifying or self-evident (although of course they could

    be). Instead, foundations are only self-evident, necessary, un-doubtable, and immune

    to revision in relation to a particular theory. We then need another argument for these

    foundations.

    I have said that my argument is so far neutral with regard to the nature and

    content of possible foundations, but I now want to argue for two restrictions regarding

    the nature of these foundations, which indeed follow partly from what I have argued

    so far. The first restriction concerns the content of foundations and follows from my

    acceptance of Cohens argument, namely that no facts can ground normative

    principles alone. From this it follows that the absolute or fundamental assumptions of

    a moral theory cannot be facts.

    The second restriction concerns the status of these foundational assumptions and

    is connected to the specific task of justifying normative, moral and political

    principles, which are obliging or necessitating. In regard to this, I claim that no

    foundational assumptions for justifying moral or political norms can be adequate or

    convincing or fulfil their role, when it has to be conceded that we have just posited

    them without further explanation, account or justification of their special status or

    importance for morality.12To do so would fulfil the necessary formal structure of all

    moral and political justification but it would not succeed in giving a convincing

    normative justification. The reason for this is that normative (moral) principles are

    said to have a certain hold over us; they are thought to oblige or necessitate us to

    action even if we would rather do something else. Korsgaard has given a good

    account of the peculiar nature of normative principles. Ethical standards, according to

    Korsgaard, are normative in that they do not merely describea way in which we infact regulate our conduct. They make claims on us; they command, oblige,

    recommend, or guide. Or at least, when we invoke them, we make claims on one

    another (Korsgaard 1996: 8). Korsgaard then argues that When we seek a

    philosophical foundation for morality we are not looking merely for an explanation of

    moral practices. We are asking what justifies the claims that morality makes on us.

    This is what I am calling the normative question(Korsgaard 1996: 9/10). Thus, one

    of the criteria that any moral theory must answer to is one she calls normative or

    justificatory adequacy. This criteria denotes the fact that when we do moral

    philosophy, we also want to know whether we are justifiedin according this kind of

    12

    Note here, that an explanation that we could all agree on them is only insofar adequate as it issupported by an account of the normative authority or significance or truth conveying nature of

    (shared) agreement.

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    13/16

    13

    importance to morality [] We want to know what, if anything, we really ought to

    do (Korsgaard 1996: 13).

    Thus a justification, which has to admit that its foundational assumption is

    (purely) contingent, cannot account for the importance of moral principles and why

    we should see them as obliging. Some account of the importance, priority or

    worthiness or inevitable nature of the particular foundational assumption has to begiven for the justificatory theory to at least be a genuine attempt to justify normative

    principles, which reallydo oblige. Otherwise we are not really involved in justifying

    moral norms at all, but only involved in a sceptical exercise. That is, we would

    formally show that there are certain presuppositions for our moral principles, but

    these can have no special hold on us or any importance, and we would thus defeat the

    point of justification. We would then have to be sceptics with regard to moral

    obligation. Korsgaard defines the moral sceptic as someone who thinks that the

    explanation of moral concepts will be one that does not support the claims that

    morality makes on us (Korsgaard 1996: 13). This would be precisely the case if we

    had to concede that we could give no meaningful account of whywe use the particular

    foundations we use in our justificatory argument and why they are the adequatefoundations for a moral theory. Any person engaged in genuine moral and political

    justification that is any one who really does want to show or argue why we should

    direct our actions according to some principle has not only some foundational

    assumption, but must give an account, explanation or justification of their priority or

    adequacy as moral and political foundations. This need is even more obvious if we

    consider that the option to claim that our foundational assumptions are facts, which

    can just be pointed out and therefore do not seem in need of any explanation or

    justification, does not exist.

    These conclusions, although they leave much of the content and nature of

    possible foundations open,13lead me to make a further (tentative) claim about Kantian

    constructivism. This is that Kantian constructivism cannot avoid making metaphysical

    claims and thus must also be involved in metaphysical arguments.

    4. Necessity of Metaphysics

    Metaphysics has acquired a bit of a bad reputation in moral and political philosophy.

    Because of its alleged non-empirical character and thus its elusiveness with regard to

    conclusive (empirical) proof, validation or argument, many are tempted to see it as

    nonsense to be dismissed. Even if they would not go that far, it is implied by many

    liberal and Kantian Constructivists that agreement on metaphysical questions could

    never be attained, as they are always and inherently open to contestation, and thattherefore in conditions of pluralism we should avoid talking about or involving

    metaphysical presuppositions or arguments altogether.14

    13Here it might be helpful to point out that my claim is also relatively neutral regarding the question ofhow thick or weak the foundations are to be. A weak foundationalist theory would still have a

    foundation which could be contested and needs a (metaphysical) justification. The thinness orweakness of the foundation in question cannot translate itself directly into acceptability or normativeauthority for the so developed theory. The argument for thinness or weakness of foundation is, so Iwould probably suggest, itself based on a substantive normative and metaphysical claim about thenature of morality or moral theorizing.14

    Hampton, when asking herself what definition of metaphysics Rawls is referring to when he rejectsit, states that from context it doesnt seem that he can mean it in the positivists sense as nonsense to

    be dismissed but, rather, in a more Hobbesian sense as doctrines for which an incontrovertible

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    14/16

    14

    It is often not altogether clear what exactly, for example, constructivists

    understand under metaphysics, when they assert that they want to and do avoid it in

    their arguments. I will in the following assume metaphysics to either be concerned, as

    traditionally understood, with claims about the fundamental nature of reality, which

    could not be substantiated solely by the methods of any special science or intellectual

    discipline, such as anthropology or history or sociology (Lowe 2002: 4, my italics) orwith the necessary or fundamental structure of our understandingof and acting in the

    world (Kant 1996: A 841/2; B869/70, Lowe 2002:7, Loux 1998: 1,6; Williams 1999:

    2-3). Regardless of whether one adopts the traditional definition of metaphysics or a

    more Kantian one, they both capture what I take constructivists as wanting to avoid,

    namely an attempted explanation or account of the nature of the world or the

    necessary conditions of our experience or understanding of and action in the world,

    which goes beyond the remit of the specialised sciences and therefore cannot be

    proven or shown by any one of them. This, in a sense, represents the danger of

    metaphysics as it slips through the nets of the explanatory or conceptual tools of the

    more specialised (and, as we feel, more validated or sound) sciences.15 Because it so

    slips through the nets of the acceptable tools we have to show it as undeniable oruncontestable true, it is generally assumed that metaphysical arguments cannot be

    used to argue for principles we all could agree to. Even though this is an inherent

    problem of metaphysics and carries with it the possibility of irresolvable dispute, I

    will nevertheless (tentatively) suggest that it is inevitable (even and maybe exactly

    because we live in a plural world).

    I have argued that Kantian constructivism relies on a foundational conception of

    the person and thus has a foundational structure and that different foundational

    assumptions will lead us to different moral and political principles. Living in a

    pluralistic world we know of the possibility of different substantial conceptions of the

    person.16 It might seem that this kind of argument should lead me in exactly the

    opposite direction from assuming the necessity of metaphysics. It seems that I have

    shown that foundations are inevitable but that also several or a manifold of

    foundations are possible. One, maybe obvious, conclusion or reaction to such a

    demonstration may be to assume or postulate that one foundation is in principle as

    good as the other and that we should either choose among them as we please and

    prefer or just accept the one foundational assumption we happen on introspection to

    hold.

    Now, firstly I would like to argue that this in itself constitutes or would entail a

    metaphysical argument about the fundamental nature of reality, namely that there is

    no (ultimate) true, better or necessary foundational assumption from or on which true

    moral or political theories could be developed. This post-modern conclusion impliesa thesis that goes beyond the valid or established conclusions or claims of other

    demonstration is not possible. Such doctrines have the potential to arouse controversy and provokeconflict in the community (Hampton 1989: 794/5).15However, the impossibility of or extravagant nature of, metaphysics is often exaggerated. Vincentrefers to Peirce in defence of metaphysical argument, stating that the complaint that the study of

    metaphysical foundations is too abstract, is in itself ridiculous, since all the natural sciences (and manysocial sciences for that matter) are fare moreabstract and remote than metaphysics. Equally, it isnonsensical to say that the objects of foundational metaphysics are not observable or easily studied.Most objects in the sciences (and social sciences) cannot be directly or easily observed (Vincent 2004:6). For example, Energy, gravitation, or supply and demand curves [] cannot actually be seen

    (Vincent 2004: 7).16Successful is used here not to denote something like maximally flourishing or the like, as this is itself

    a substantive criteria, but just the fact that people could live by it.

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    15/16

    15

    sciences and also beyond the claim that different foundations are possible. It makes a

    very fundamental claim about the reality of (moral) knowledge. Only the

    metaphysical thesis of the impossibility of true foundational assumptions (for

    morality) leads or directs us from the statement about different possible foundations

    to the normative claim that we should not try and could not find a true foundation,

    but should instead either make the best of what we have or choose as we please. Inthat sense I argue with Lowe who states that the attempt to undermine or eliminate

    the metaphysical dimension of our thinking is self-defeating, because the very attempt

    necessarily constitutes a piece of metaphysical thinking itself (Lowe 2002: 4). Even

    those who want to deny that moral or political principles are capable of universal truth

    claims or of being objective must in the end make a universal metaphysical claim

    about the nature of reality or about our possible understanding of it.

    While I therefore argue that even the post-modern or radical relativist

    conclusions that one could try to draw from my argument would involve a

    metaphysical claim, I would also like to argue that these conclusions cannot be drawn

    by anyone who wants to engage in genuine justification. If we really did hold the

    metaphysical view that no foundational assumption can even possibly be true orcorrect or necessary17and that we therefore would not be wrong, or would be equally

    justified in espousing any of the foundational assumptions, we would have turned

    once more into the sceptic. Here moral theory would not survive metaphysical

    explanation. We could not account for the demands and importance of a particular

    moral obligation, and would have to concede that we are deceiving ourselves about

    the status of morality. To attempt any genuine justification at all of moral or political

    norms we need to at least entertain or allow for the possibility that a foundational

    assumption could be true, correct or necessary.

    In the case of Kantian Constructivists, with their reliance on various principles

    of respect for rational and free human beings, this metaphysical argument would, for

    example, have to take the form of providing an explanation of why we (necessarily)

    have to conceive of ourselves as free, and why rationality and freedom express our

    real or fundamental nature, so that they can demand respect and can thus demand to

    be valued by us.

    Bibliography

    Barry, B. (1989): Theories of Justice. A Treatise on Social Justice, Volume I.

    Harvester-Wheatsheaf, Hertfordshire.

    17

    Here it is important that one only need to state the possibility of foundations to be true or correct andthat one is not committed to saying that we have found an (undeniable) true foundation or that there is

    an easy way to do so.

    Copyright PSA 2008

  • 8/12/2019 Foundations in Kantian Constructivism

    16/16