Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

69
Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson

Transcript of Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

Page 1: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

Existence by DefinitionTom Donaldson

Page 2: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

2

Section 1. Introduction

Page 3: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

3

Existence by Definition: Some Examples• (Some versions of) the ontological argument• Analytic phenomenalism• Thomasson on ‘ordinary objects’.

Wherever there are some particles arranged table-wise, there is a table.

Page 4: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

4

Existence by Definition: Some Examples• (Some versions of) the ontological argument• Analytic phenomenalism• Thomasson on ‘ordinary objects’• Schiffer on properties and propositions

If Palo Alto is a town, then Palo Alto has the property of being a town.

Page 5: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

5

Existence by Definition: Some Examples• (Some versions of) the ontological argument• Analytic phenomenalism• Thomasson on ‘ordinary objects’• Schiffer on properties and propositions• Neofregeanism• Postulationism

Page 6: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

6

Existence by Definition: Some Examples• (Some versions of) the ontological argument• Analytic phenomenalism• Thomasson on ‘ordinary objects’• Schiffer on properties and propositions• Neofregeanism• Postulationism

Page 7: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

7

ReactionariesDavid Lewis mocks those who deny the existence of classes:

I’m moved to laughter at the thought of how presumptuous it would be to reject mathematics for philosophical reasons. How would you like the job of telling the mathematicians that they must change their ways … now that philosophy has discovered that there are no classes? ...

Page 8: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

8

Reactionaries…If they challenge your credentials, will you boast of philosophy’s other great discoveries: that motion is impossible, ... that it is unthinkable that anything exists outside the mind, that time is unreal, ... ad nauseam? Not me!

David Lewis

Page 9: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

9

ReactionariesReactionaries are (typically) platonists, in the sense that (1) they believe that abstract mathematical objects exist, and (2) they believe that these objects are (setting aside the odd mistake) accurately described by current mathematical theories.

Page 10: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

10

Section 2. Postulationism

Page 11: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

11

Reichenbach’s PostulationismThe axiomatic method has most frequently been applied in mathematics. It has become customary to reduce a controversy about the logical status of mathematics to a controversy about the logical status of the axioms. Nowadays one can hardly speak of a controversy any longer. The problem of the logical status of the axioms of mathematics was solved by the discovery that they are definitions, that is, arbitrary stipulations …Reichenbach (1924)

Page 12: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

12

Postulationism: The Basic IdeaOne can learn mathematical truths by deducing them from stipulative definitions: both explicit definitions, and implicit definitions (which are more usually called ‘axioms’). For example, one might learn number theory by stipulating that the Peano axioms are implicit definitions of ‘number’, ‘plus’, ‘times’, ‘successor’ and ‘zero’, and then deducing theorems from these axioms, introducing additional terms by explicit definition as necessary. This is the ‘definitions and deductions method’.

Page 13: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

13

Some Points of Clarification• Most postulationists think that mathematical knowledge is a priori.

Page 14: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

14

Some Points of Clarification• Most postulationists think that mathematical knowledge is a priori.

Page 15: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

15

Some Points of Clarification• Most postulationists think that mathematical knowledge is a priori.• The postulationists’ view is that the definitions and deductions method can be used to acquire mathematical knowledge ab initio.• Postulationism is an answer to the ‘How possibly?’ question, not the ‘How actually?’ question.• I’ll focus on the definitions of words rather than concepts.

Page 16: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

16

Objections to postulationism• The historical objection

Page 17: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

17

Objections to postulationism• The historical objection [Postponed]• The infinity objection• The coherence objection

Page 18: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

18

Goals for the talkI want to…• …solve the infinity problem, on behalf of the postulationist.• …convince you that the coherence objection is fatal to traditional postulationism.• …suggest a new answer to the ‘How possibly?’ question, which incorporates postulationist insights while escaping the coherence problem.

Page 19: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

19

Section 3. The Infinity Problem

Page 20: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

20

A simple example• Clare sets out to learn some number theory…• …having no previous mathematical knowledge.• Her axioms might be the Peano axioms, or something similar.• She uses a ‘many-sorted’ language.• She works in isolation.• Her language (initially) is free from ambiguity and vagueness/open-texture.

Page 21: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

21

Success conditionsA definition.D: Goliath is a horse at least 10cm taller than any other horse.Its success condition.There exists a horse at least 10cm taller than any other horse.

Page 22: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

22

Clare, againThe function of a definition is to assign referents to the newly introduced words. A definition will succeed just in case suitable referents exist.Clare’s terms include:0, 0′, 0′′, 0′′′, 0′′′′, …Plausible conclusion: the success condition of Clare’s definition is at least that there exist infinitely many things.

Page 23: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

23

How could Clare show that there exist infinitely many things?• Empirical arguments?• Appeal to existing mathematical theories?• A priori, but non-mathematical arguments?

Page 24: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

24

The infinity objection(P1) In order to learn a priori that her definitions are true, Clare must establish independently and a priori that their success condition is met.(P2) The success condition of Clare’s definition is at least that there exist infinitely many things.(P3) Clare cannot establish independently and a priori that there exist infinitely many things.(C) Clare cannot learn a priori that her definitions are true.

Page 25: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

25

Section 4. Solving The Infinity Problem

Page 26: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

26

Another way of thinking aboutsuccess conditionsThe function of a definition is to assign referents to the newly introduced words. A definition will succeed just in case suitable referents exist.

Page 27: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

27

Another way of thinking aboutsuccess conditionsThe function of a definition is to assign referents to the newly introduced words. A definition will succeed just in case suitable referents exist.The function of a definition is to assign truth conditions to sentences in the agent’s newly extended language. A definition will succeed just in case a suitable assignment of truth conditions exists.

Page 28: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

28

Some notation• L is the agent’s ‘old’ language.• L+ is the agent’s newly extended language.• The definitions are δ1, …, δn.• J is a function which assigns truth conditions to the sentences in L.• We are looking for conditions on the suitability of a function J+ which assigns truth conditions to the sentences in the agent’s newly extended language.

Page 29: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

29

Conditions on suitability(C1) For each definition δi, J+(δi) is the set of all possible worlds.(C2) For any ‘old’ sentence φ, J(φ)=J+(φ).(C3) J+ should ‘respect logical necessitation’ in the following sense. If Γ is a set of sentences, and possible world wJ+(γ) for each γΓ, and if Γ logically necessitates φ, then wJ+(φ).

Page 30: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

30

Conditions on suitability(C1) For each definition δi, J+(δi) is the set of all possible worlds.(C2) For any ‘old’ sentence φ, J(φ)=J+(φ).(C3) J+ should ‘respect logical necessitation’ in the following sense. If Γ is a set of sentences, and possible world wJ+(γ) for each γΓ, and if Γ logically necessitates φ, then wJ+(φ).

Page 31: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

31

The application to Clare’s definitionsAn assignment function that meets conditions (C1)-(C3) will exist provided that the following condition is met:The Modal Conservativeness ConditionFor any possible world w, {δ1, … , δn}∪{α∊L:w∊J(α)} is coherent.

Page 32: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

32

The application to Clare’s definitionsAn assignment function that meets conditions (C1)-(C3) will exist provided that the following condition is met:The Modal Conservativeness ConditionFor any possible world w, {δ1, … , δn}∪{α∊L:w∊J(α)} is coherent.

Page 33: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

33

The application to Clare’s definitions[I]f the arbitrarily given axioms do not contradict one another with all their consequences, then they are true and the things defined by the axioms exist. This is for me the criterion of truth and existence. Hilbert

Page 34: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

34

The infinity objection(P1) In order to learn a priori that her definitions are true, Clare must establish independently and a priori that their success condition is met.(P2) The success condition of Clare’s definition is at least that there exist infinitely many things.(P3) Clare cannot establish independently and a priori that there exist infinitely many things.(C) Clare cannot learn a priori that her definitions are true.

Page 35: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

35

Aside for metaphysicians: Do numbers exist in the perfectly natural sense?“There exists a hole in every bagel.”

Page 36: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

36

Goals for the talkI want to…• …solve the infinity problem, on behalf of the postulationist. • …convince you that the coherence problem is fatal to traditional postulationism.• …suggest a new answer to the ‘How possibly?’ question, which incorporates postulationist insights while escaping the coherence problem.

Page 37: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

37

Section 5. The coherence problem

Page 38: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

38

The infinity objection(P1) In order to learn a priori that her definitions are true, Clare must establish independently and a priori that their success condition is met.(P2) The success condition of Clare’s definition is at least that there exist infinitely many things.(P3) Clare cannot establish independently and a priori that there exist infinitely many things.(C) Clare cannot learn a priori that her definitions are true.

Page 39: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

39

ExternalismGoliath is a horse at least 10cm taller than any other horse.(Strong Externalism) If an agent uses a definition , and if the success condition of is met, then the agent is in a position to know a priori that is true, in the absence of a defeater.

Page 40: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

40

Externalism(Weak Externalism) If an agent uses a definition , and if the success condition of is met, and if the definition meets constraint C, then the agent is in a position to know a priori that is true, in the absence of a defeater.Case (i) Clare uses as her definitions the Peano axioms.Case (ii) Clare uses as her definitions the Peano axioms, together with some difficult number-theoretic result, such as Fermat’s Last Theorem.

Page 41: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

41

What is coherence?First thesis: It is possible for Clare, who has no pre-existing mathematical knowledge, to establish a priori that (say) the Peano axioms are coherent.Second thesis: Whenever Clare’s definitions are coherent, there will exist a ‘suitable’ assignment of truth conditions to the sentences in her newly extended language.

Page 42: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

42

What is coherence?1. Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiabilityFirst thesis: It is possible for Clare, who has no pre-existing mathematical knowledge, to establish a priori that (say) the Peano axioms are coherent.

Page 43: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

43

What is coherence?1. Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability2. Coherence as proof-theoretic consistencySecond thesis: Whenever Clare’s definitions are coherent, there will exist a ‘suitable’ assignment of truth conditions to the sentences in her newly extended language.

Page 44: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

44

What is coherence?1. Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability2. Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency

α1, …, αn ⊢T β

Page 45: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

45

What is coherence?1. Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability2. Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency(i) PA2 ⊢T φ(n) (for each numeral n).(ii) PA2 ⊬T ∀x φ(x).

Page 46: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

46

What is coherence?1. Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability2. Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency(i) PA2 ⊢T φ(n) (for each numeral n).(ii) PA2 ⊬T ∀x φ(x).

PA* = PA2∪{⌜¬∀xφ(x)⌝}

Page 47: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

47

What is coherence?1. Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability2. Coherence as proof-theoretic consistencyJ+(⌜¬∀xφ(x)⌝) = the set of possible worlds

Page 48: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

48

What is coherence?1. Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability2. Coherence as proof-theoretic consistencyJ+(⌜∀xφ(x)⌝) = ∅J+(φ(n)) = the set of possible worldsThe Generalization Constraint:J+(⌜∀x α(x)⌝) = J+( α(o)) ∩ J+( α(1)) ∩ J+(α(2)) ∩ …

Page 49: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

49

What is coherence?1. Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability2. Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency3. Coherence as informal deductive consistencyFirst thesis: It is possible for Clare, who has no pre-existing mathematical knowledge, to establish a priori that (say) the Peano axioms are coherent.

Page 50: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

50

What is coherence?1. Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability2. Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency3. Coherence as informal deductive consistencySecond thesis: Whenever Clare’s definitions are coherent, there will exist a ‘suitable’ assignment of truth conditions to the sentences in her newly extended language.

Page 51: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

51

What is coherence?1. Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability2. Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency3. Coherence as informal deductive consistency4. Coherence as informal satisfiability

∀x Rxx ∀x∀y∀z[(RxyRyz) Rxz]

Page 52: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

52

What is coherence?1. Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability2. Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency3. Coherence as informal deductive consistency4. Coherence as informal satisfiability5. Field’s primitivism

Page 53: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

53

The vicious circleMathematicalKnowledge

Knowledge ofCoherence

Page 54: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

54

Goals for the talkI want to…• …solve the infinity problem, on behalf of the postulationist. • …convince you that the coherence problem is fatal to traditional postulationism. • …suggest a new answer to the ‘How possibly?’ question, which incorporates postulationist insights while escaping the coherence problem.

Page 55: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

55

Section 6. A solution (?)

Page 56: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

56

The vicious circle: A Solution?Method 1: Suppose that some set of mathematical terms are entirely defined by definitions δ1,…, δn, and that no other non-logical terms occur in δ1,…, δn. Then if you can show that δ1,…, δn are coherent, you may infer that they are all true.Method 2: Suppose that S is a set of sentences, and that T is a mathematical theory you know to be true. Then if you can interpret S in T, you may infer that S is coherent.

Page 57: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

57

The vicious circle: A Solution?Method 3: Suppose that S is a set of sentences, and T is an empirically well-confirmed scientific theory. Then if you can interpret S in T, you have good reason to believe that S is coherent.Method 4: If a mathematical theory T plays an indispensable role in an empirically well-confirmed scientific theory, one has good reason for believing that T is true. (See: Quine)

Page 58: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

58

The vicious circle: A Solution?Method 4: Suppose that S is a set of sentences. Then if you can deduce ⊥ from S, you may conclude that S is incoherent.Method 5: Changes to one’s overall system of logico-mathematical beliefs can be justified on grounds of simplicity, elegance etc.. (See: Penelope Maddy)

Page 59: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

59

Section 7. Postscript:Is there a ‘reliability problem’ for logic?

Page 60: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

60

Field’s Challenge• Platonists believe that ‘we’ are ‘reliable’ in what we believe about mathematics. • How can this ‘reliability’ be explained?A parallel (?) challenge: How can we explain the reliability of our beliefs about which collections of sentences are coherent?

Page 61: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

61

Field’s Argument(1) Were the mathematical facts different, the our mathematical beliefs would be exactly the same. (Premise)(2) It could only be a huge coincidence if our mathematical beliefs are true. (From 1)(3) “Our belief in a theory should be undermined if the theory requires that it would be a huge coincidence if what we believed about its subject matter were correct.” (Premise)(4) Our belief in current mathematical theories is undermined. (From 2, 3)

Page 62: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

62

Field’s Argument(1) Were the mathematical facts different, our mathematical beliefs would be exactly the same. (Premise)(1*) Were the mathematical logical facts different, our mathematical logical beliefs would be exactly the same. (Premise)

Page 63: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

63

Response to Field(1) Were the mathematical facts different, our mathematical beliefs would be exactly the same. (Premise)(2) It could only be a huge coincidence if our mathematical beliefs are right. (From 1)

Page 64: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

64

A lottery caseThe people in Dave’s department organize a lottery syndicate. They buy 100 tickets from the national lottery. Dave understands that each ticket has only a tiny chance of winning the jackpot, and he is a pessimist. So he forms the belief that the first ticket will not win, and the belief that the second ticket will not win, and the belief that the third ticket will not win, … and so on. As it happens, Dave is right: none of the tickets will win. There is thus a perfect correlation between his beliefs of the form [ticket n will not win] and the facts.

Page 65: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

65

Response to Field(1) Were the mathematical facts different, our mathematical beliefs would be exactly the same. (Premise)(2) It could only be a huge coincidence if our mathematical beliefs are right. (From 1)

Page 66: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

66

Section 8. Closing thoughts

Page 67: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

67

Conclusion: My take on postulationism• The postulationist is right that mathematical knowledge can be achieved using the definitions and deductions method. • However, this is of limited value, in the absence of some account of how one might establish the coherence of systems of mathematical definitions.• In order to obtain a satisfactory answer to the ‘How possibly?” question, we must add further methods of obtaining logico-mathematical knowledge.

Page 68: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

68

Some other possible applications• Compound objects• Social objects• Propositions(etc.)

Page 69: Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

69

The End!