Constitutional Ism in India

download Constitutional Ism in India

of 24

Transcript of Constitutional Ism in India

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    1/24Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1006621

    LOCATING POST-MODERN

    CONSTITUTIONALISM IN INDIA: THE BASIC

    STRUCTURE DOCTRINE

    I refuse to be intimidated by reality anymore. After all, what is reality anyway?

    Nothin' but a collective hunch.

    - Jane Wagner

    ANIRUDH BURMAN

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    2/24Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1006621

    TABLE OF CONTENTS

    INTRODUCTION ............................................................................................... 3

    AN EXERCISE IN LOCATING POSTMODERN ELEMENTS:TEAGUE V.LANE .... 7The judgment: ................................................................................................................. 8The postmodern analysis: ................................................................................................ 9

    THE BASIC STRUCTURE DOCTRINE. ............................................................ 12The evolution towards a Basic Structure....................................................................... 12

    The Keshavananda Judgment. ....................................................................................... 15

    THE BASIC STRUCTURE CRITIQUE:ACONCLUSION .................................... 16Applying Hermeneutics................................................................................................. 18

    The Courts Institutional Power. ................................................................................... 19

    BIBLIOGRAPHY ....................................................................................... 22Statutes and related Documents: ................................................................................... 22Articles and Reviews:.................................................................................................... 22

    Books and related works: .............................................................................................. 23

    TABLE OF CASES........................................................................................................... 23Foreign Judgments .................................................................................................... 23

    Indian Judgments....................................................................................................... 24

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    3/24Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1006621

    INTRODUCTION

    The one non-debatable, non contradicted, inescapable truth we cannot deny is that the

    world has changed drastically and maybe too rapidly to be made sense of, since the

    Second World War. The glory of territorial power has been shorn of its halo by the onset

    of economic power and the rise of the MNC, the cry of one nation one people by the

    mantra of globalization, and at the same time the recognition of multicultural values.

    Classical music has lost its followers to pop, and oratory has lost its voice to the

    television and the media. In this scenario, it would be futile to sit in value judgment over

    the changes that envelop us thick and fast, and instead accord recognition to what is

    happening all around us.

    I do not seek to trumpet the dawn of post-modernity, to analyse the existence of post-

    structuralist behaviour, or to undertake exercises in deconstruction. My endeavour here is

    to merely presume the existence of social and cultural ethos that are very different from

    those that existed five decades ago, of the slow but gradual rise of forces that are all

    around us while we struggle to grapple with them with tools handed down to us who

    lived in a world that was suited to what they propounded.

    To come to the question at hand, what is Post-modernism? To quote very succinctly,

    Knowledge and truth are fantasies. Objectivity is unattainable. Foundationalism is

    dead. We are limited to our historically situated, subjective perspectives.1

    But this is not

    all. To go beyond this theoretical diatribe, postmodernism can also be defined, if rather

    simplistically as the cultural era in which we are living in.2

    As such, it is something

    which has already happened, and needs to be understood as it exists, not as it should be.

    We do not seek to live in a world where no universal truth exists, but to recognize that no

    1 Ken Kress,MODERN JURISPRUDENCE,POSTMODERN JURISPRUDENCE,AND TRUTH,95 Mich. L. Rev.

    1871,at 18712 See David Harvey, The Condition Of Postmodernity: An Enquiry Into The Origins Of Cultural Change

    (1989); Fredric Jameson, Postmodernism, Or, The Cultural Logic Of Late Capitalism (1991); Jean-Francois

    Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report On Knowledge (Geoff Bennington & Brian Massumi trans.,

    1984). As given in J.M. Balkin, What Is A Postmodern Constitutionalism?, 90 Mich. L. Rev. 1966

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    4/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 4

    truth is universal, that there is another truth which might be in the nature of an alternative,

    or in the nature of a contradiction.

    In legal scholarship it has been used consistently in the sense conveyed by those basic

    concepts. Stated in somewhat different terms, the postmodern school of thought

    conceives of knowledge as always mediated by our social, cultural, linguistic, and

    historical circumstances, and it will thus vary as those circumstances change. The truth,

    consequently, can never be transparent to us; it is and must always be a social

    construction, one made even more opaque by the mediation of language, a system of

    communication inherently incapable of capturing reality. This includes the "truth" about

    legal doctrines, legal principles, and legal interpretations:All are social constructions.

    Both in commonsense, everyday understanding and in Western philosophy, including

    traditional jurisprudence,3

    the bedrock assumption has been that we are capable of

    representing reality more or less precisely and that some knowledge transcends particular

    perspectives and contexts. This is exactly what postmodern thought rejects. Because, in

    the view of postmodernists, knowledge of the world is filtered through the structures of

    the socially and culturally derived assumptions that each of us has accumulated as human

    beings, and because each of us is differently situated, there are different perspectives on

    objects and events and thus differing content to our knowledge of them. Knowledge is

    thus conceived by postmodernists as always contingent, always dependent on context,

    and always "local" rather than "universal," as it is so often assumed to be. This results in

    the charge that postmodernists are relativists--that is, that postmodernists hold that the

    content of knowledge varies according to the framework, perspective, and circumstances

    of the observer.4

    3 This includes the basic jurisprudential schools of legal positivism, natural law, and legal process, but not

    legal realism, which was in vogue in the 1920s and '30s and which has a close affinity with postmodern

    jurisprudence, as taken from Peter C. Schanck, Understanding Postmodern Thought And Its Implications

    For Statutory Interpretation, 65 S. Cal. L. Rev. 2505 (The theoretical bases of postmodernism have been

    borrowed from this article, and relevant sections have been footnoted accordingly)4 Pauline M. Rosenau, Postmodernism And The Social Sciences: Insights, Inroads, And Intrusions, as cited

    in Peter C. Schanck, supra n. 3

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    5/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 5

    Postmodern theory may be divided into two major strains: poststructuralism and

    neopragmatism. The first tends to emphasize the role of language and language's

    underlying structures in shaping our understandings of reality and texts, and it is

    represented principally by such French theorists as Roland Barthes, Jean Baudrillard,

    Jacques Derrida, Jacques Lacan, and Jean-Franois Lyotard, although Baudrillard and

    Lyotard can also be considered neopragmatists.5

    The second strain, neopragmatism,

    agrees with poststructuralism that language mediates our understanding of the world and

    that we lack the ability to grasp reality "as it really is,"6

    but neopragmatism emphasizes

    the social construction of knowledge and language. Its leading figures are Richard Rorty

    and Stanley Fish.7

    There is another conception of postmodernism, which is referred to variously as thepostmodern condition, the postmodern age, or postmodernity,and forms the basis of the

    researchers endeavour to locate a postmodern jurisprudence. It is used to convey the idea

    that the present world is fundamentally different from previous historical periods, that life

    today-- compared with the modern era--is seriously uncertain, fragmented, disjointed,

    incoherent, uncentered, pluralistic,8

    and that the master narratives that once structured our

    lives are absent9

    or, that postmodern society is in thrall to multinational capitalism in

    contrast to the monopoly capitalism of the modern age.10

    It is here that the question of justice arises. For, if there is no universal truth, can there

    indeed be a universally true and objective justice? If there is, is it accessible to all? Does

    5 Christopher Norris, for one, lumps Baudrillard and Lyotard in with pragmatists Rorty and Fish.

    CHRISTOPHER NORRIS, Introduction to What's Wrong With Postmodernism: Critical Theory And The

    Ends Of Philosophy , as cited in supra n. 36

    Supra n. 37 Id.8 Walter Truett Anderson, Reality Isn't What It Used To Be: Theatrical Politics, Ready-To-Wear Religion,

    Global Myths, Primitive Chic, And Other Wonders Of The Postmodern World (1990), as cited in supra n. 39 Jean-Francois Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report On Knowledge (Geoff Bennington & Brian

    Massumi trans., 1984)10 Fredric Jameson, Postmodernism, Or The Cultural Logic Of Late Capitalism, 35-36 (1991). In Jameson's

    view postmodernism is the unfortunate cultural manifestation of multinational capitalism, as cited in supra

    n. 3

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    6/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 6

    a constitutional guarantee and a judiciarys affirmation of the same necessarily do justice

    to all concerned?

    It is while searching for these questions that one first stumbles upon the issue of judicial

    activism. Is not judicial activism a universally recognized method of legal enunciation, of

    stepping beyond legislative limits and constitutional provisions that seem inscribed upon

    stone? Does it not seek to keep the constitutional process fluid, to hone legal provisions

    according to changing standards? Where then is the notion of a universal concept of

    liberty if it was a paramount consideration in the minds of the judges while deciding

    cases in the 1950s, but is now subject to economic development of the country at large?

    It is easy to discern that judicial activism is not to ensure compliance with objective,

    universal truths, but to mould such truths according to changing morays. And if such aneffort is conscious, then it is also necessarily subjective, for such an effort can only be

    made if one actively perceives the need to remodel old conceptions of such universal

    truths, if one is aware that a different generation requires a different conception of liberty,

    equality and fairness.

    In India, the zenith of judicial activism was witnessed in the enunciation of the basic

    structure doctrine. The judiciary for the first time violated the basic principle of

    separation of powers to decide to what extent the constitution could be amended, and

    specifically whether any of the fundamental rights could be done away with. In doing so,

    it decided the question of the parliaments power of constitutional amendment. It was an

    approach that strikes at a well established, modernist principle of legislative supremacy in

    the legislative sphere, and clear delimitation between judicial and legislative spheres. It

    was based on a perception of the political instability of the period in which it was

    enunciated, and was thus far from objective.

    Yet, ironically, the doctrine itself is essentially modernist in character. It sets out a grand

    narrative based on the overriding perpetuity of the principles they proposed. It

    presupposes that certain principles are universal to human existence and dignity, and may

    not be challenged. And yet, there are spaces where gaps may be filled in. If equality

    under Article 14 of the Constitution is part of the Basic Structure, well and good. But the

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    7/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 7

    precise content of such equality is always open to change, to discourse and to judicial

    opinion.

    There is thus an intermingling of both elements of modernity and post-modernity within

    the Indian judicial scenario. How they have evolved and where exactly they stand is what

    needs to be understood.

    AN EXERCISE IN LOCATING POSTMODERN ELEMENTS:TEAGUE V.LANE11

    Teague v. Lane was an American case in which the Supreme Court has focused on the

    issue of whether constitutional rules should apply retroactively in habeas cases.12

    As

    argued by Stephen M Feldman13

    , the deconstruction of the Teague rule demonstrates,

    therefore, how a postmodern approach can disturb the assumptions and reveal the

    instabilities hidden within a Court's modernist reasoning. Furthermore, this

    deconstruction concludes with a typical postmodern theme: a focus on the relation

    between power and language.14

    Teague v. Lane, decided in 1989, arose from a state prosecution of an African-American

    defendant. The defendant, Teague, petitioned for habeas relief, arguing that the all-white

    jury which had convicted him did not represent a fair cross section of the community. In

    1975, Taylor v. Louisiana15 had held that the Sixth Amendment required a jury venire to

    be drawn from a fair cross section, and Teague maintained that the Sixth Amendment

    should be held to require the same of a petit jury. In rejecting Teague's habeas petition,

    the Court held that it should not even reach the merits of his constitutional claim.

    11Teague v. Lane 489 U.S. 288 (1989)12

    Wright v. West, 112 S. Ct. 2482 (1992); Stringer v. Black, 112 S. Ct. 1130 (1992); Sawyer v. Smith, 497U.S. 227 (1990); Saffle v. Parks, 494 U.S. 484 (1990); Butler v. McKellar, 494 U.S. 407 (1990); Penry v.

    Lynaugh, 492 U.S. 302 (1989)13 Professor of Law, University of Tulsa, in Diagnosing Power: Postmodernism In Legal Scholarship And

    Judicial Practice (With An Emphasis On The Teague Rule Against New Rules In Habeas Corpus Cases),

    88 Nw. U. L. Rev. 104614 Feldman S. M, The Persistence of Power and the Struggle for Dialogic Standards in Postmodern

    Constitutional Jurisprudence: Michelman, Habermas, and Civic Republicanism, 81 GEO. L.J. 2243 (1993)15Taylor v. Louisiana 419 U.S. 522 (1975)

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    8/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 8

    The judgment16

    :

    The Teague plurality opinion articulated two important points. First, it stated that

    the question of retroactivity should be the threshold issue in any case which mightrequire the Court to announce or apply a new rule of constitutional law. The plurality

    justified this approach by reasoning that "once a new rule is applied to the defendant in

    the case announcing the rule, evenhanded justice requires that it be applied retroactivelyto all who are similarly situated." Since the announcement of a new rule would lead,

    according to this reasoning, to the supposedly drastic consequence of retroactive

    application to anyone seeking either direct or habeas relief, the plurality insisted that theissue of retroactivity should be resolved first.

    Second, the plurality, following Justice Harlan, pronounced a general rule: " New

    constitutional rules of criminal procedure will not be applicable to those cases which

    have become final before the new rules are announced." And the Teague pluralityidentified two exceptions to this general rule. First, "a new rule should be applied

    retroactively if it places 'certain kinds of primary, private individual conduct beyond thepower of the criminal law-making authority."' Second, retroactive application should be

    allowed for new "watershed rules of criminal procedure," or in other words, for "those

    new procedures without which the likelihood of an accurate conviction is seriouslydiminished." While the Teague plurality and Harlan shared identical first exceptions,

    their second exceptions differed-the plurality's second exception was significantly

    narrower.

    Teague effectively created a rule against new rules in habeas cases. As the plurality

    stated:

    We therefore hold that, implicit in the retroactivity approach we adopt today, is the

    principle that habeas corpus cannot be used as a vehicle to create new constitutional

    rules of criminal procedure unless those rules would be applied retroactively to all

    defendants on collateral review through one of the two exceptions we have articulated.

    What this essentially implies is that wherever the petitioner demands that a new rule17

    in constitutional law be considered by the court, the court is under no obligation to

    consider it if the judgment in the instant case is already final, provided the case does not

    fall under any of the exceptions mentioned above. As a further example, in Butler v.

    16 As quoted from Feldman S.M, supra n. 1317 [I]n general, a case announces a "new rule" when it breaks new ground or imposes a new obligation on

    the States or the Federal Government. Put differently, and, indeed, more meaningfully for the majority of

    cases, a decision announces a new rule "'if the result was not dictated by precedent existing at the time the

    defendant's conviction became final.",Butler v. McKellar 494 U.S. 407 (1990)

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    9/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 9

    McKellar18

    , decided in 1990, the Court interpreted broadly the ambiguous Teague

    guidelines for the identification of new rules. In a state prosecution, Butler had been

    convicted of murder and sentenced to death. He had appealed to the highest state court

    and then had petitioned the United States Supreme Court for certiorari. When the Court

    denied certiorari, Butler's conviction became final. Butler subsequently filed a habeas

    petition in federal district court, claiming that he had been unconstitutionally questioned

    about the murder after retaining counsel for an unrelated charge of assault and battery.

    After Butler had filed his habeas petition, the Court decided a different case, Arizona v.

    Roberson, which "held ... that the Fifth Amendment bars police-initiated interrogation

    following a suspect's request for counsel in the context of a separate investigation." Thus,

    Roberson effectively vindicated the exact constitutional claim that Butler raised in hishabeas petition. Nonetheless, the Court held that to apply the Roberson holding to Butler

    would amount to the application of a new rule of constitutional law after Butler's

    conviction already had become final on direct review. Thus, following the Teague rule

    against new rules, the Court refused to reach the merits of Butler's habeas claim.19

    The postmodern analysis:

    This portion has been adapted from Feldmans work as cited above, and consequently the

    approach adopted in deconstructing the above case is the same as that of the learned

    scholar, namely, philosophical hermeneutics. Philosophical hermeneutics basically states

    that there is no objective mechanical interpretation of a given text, and even that text in

    itself is not merely an object ready to be interpreted. The text is merely what we interpret

    it to be. It has no independent existence, save the interpretation of the reader. However,

    such interpretation in itself may not be subjective or arbitrary. The reader (or interpreter)

    is never an independent and autonomous subject who freely or arbitrarily imposes

    meaning on a text.20

    One's life within a community and its traditions necessarily limits

    18Butler v. McKellar 494 U.S. 407 (1990).19 Supra n. 1320 Id, as taken from Jacques Derrida, Positions (Alan Bass trans., 1981), given in n. 6 of the cited article in

    note 13

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    10/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 10

    one's range of vision-what one can possibly see or understand in a text. As Gadamer

    says, the traditions of one's community help to shape the interpreter's horizon: the

    range of vision that includes everything that can be seen from a particular vantage

    point.21 Therefore, a judge constantly, while consciously bound by rules of precedent, is

    actually bound by principles of tradition of legal maxims and his own morays and those

    of his community. The interpretative process is not merely objective and rule-bound. The

    objectivity flows from the relativity of the text to the subjectivity of community-rules and

    standards, and social and political contexts.

    A crucial element of philosophical hermeneutics is the recognition that although

    communal traditions and the concomitant prejudices constrain our possibilities for

    understanding, they simultaneously enable us to communicate and to understand. Ourtraditions, prejudices, and interests actually open us to meaning, understanding, and

    truth.22

    Moving on, the Teague ratio implies that the retrospective application of a constitutional

    rule should depend on whether that rule is new or old. However, on an application of

    hermeneutic philosophy, it is easily concluded that every rule is both simultaneously old

    and new. Every rule is new because each time we apply it, we must interpret and thus

    reconstruct it (as well as tradition), yet simultaneously every rule is old because each rule

    emerges only from our already existing prejudices and traditions.23

    The rule in Teague v.

    Lane, as laid down is strikingly modern, strikingly foundationalist i.e. it clearly states that

    there are old rules in existence, which must be given effect to without thought or

    meditation, and then there are new rules, products of judicial creativity and constitutional

    interpretation. A legal rule, from this modernist perspective, is a normative guide

    expressed in a text, such as a case precedent, that mandates or influences judicial action.

    Teague assumes that such a rule has a fixed and stable meaning that firmly grounds

    understanding. Thus, a court, at least sometimes, is able to implement some technique or

    21 Gadamer, Hermeneutics, Tradition, And Reason (1987), as cited in Feldman, supra n. 1322 Stanley Fish, Dennis Martinez and the Uses of Theory, 96 YALE L.J. 1773, 1795 (1987) , as cited in

    supra n. 1323 Supra n. 13

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    11/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 11

    method whereby it mechanically and objectively understands and applies the rule to a

    new case.24

    Hermeneutics disputes this foundationalist reasoning. It argues that experience,

    perception, and understanding are interpretive, and not original or new and thus no

    mechanical technique or method can directly access the meaning of a rule. Legal rules

    therefore have no independent meaning which stands crystal clear and is understood

    objectively, or rather mechanically. Rather, all legal texts are understood through a sum

    of experience, understanding, and interpretation based on the previous two. Moreover,

    the meaning of a legal rule comes into being only because communal traditions and our

    derived prejudices and interests open us to the truth or meaning of the rule.25

    For example, the word mantra was used very differently say, even a century ago. Now itimplies a chant, a formula, more synonymous with the western concept of a formula for

    invoking success as distinguished from its perhaps original use as a word for an

    invocation or a sacred rite. These different interpretations do not symbolize two different

    interpretations, one new and one old. They are merely two different interpretations based

    on usage, intermingling of different cultures and of different lifestyles.

    Hence, every legal rule is, in an important sense, always old. Each time we apply a legal

    rule, we necessarily draw upon and extend our communal traditions. Every legal rule

    emerges as a manifestation of tradition, of what came before, of the old. Simultaneously,

    however, every legal rule also is, in an important sense, always new. The meaning of a

    legal rule comes into being anew each time we understand, interpret, and apply it. No

    legal rule exists apart from the social practices that constantly create and recreate it.

    In the Teabing case, the old rules of retrospective application and habeas corpus have

    been interpreted differently, drawing upon existing rules and combined with it a

    deference towards, in this case, the decision of the lower courts. On a simple application

    of hermeneutics, the judgment seems to appear in an entirely different light. Once the

    judgment is deconstructed the ratio, the new law laid down by the U.S Supreme Court

    24 Id.25 Id.

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    12/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 12

    does not seem to be the new aspect of the case.26

    What was new was the Supreme

    Courts deference to a lower courts judgment save the two exceptions they noted above.

    THE BASIC STRUCTURE DOCTRINE.

    In a watershed decision in Keshavananda Bharati v. State of Kerala27

    , the Indian

    Supreme Court decided in a thirteen bench judgment that the sovereign legislature, who

    were otherwise possessed of otherwise plenary power to amend the Constitution, could

    not alter the basic structure of the Constitution.28

    The case represents the high point of

    judicial innovation and alters the very basis on which constitutional power is divided

    between the plenary amendatory bodies and the judiciary.29

    The evolution towards a Basic Structure.

    26Brown v. Board of Education 347 U.S. 483 (1954)., decided in 1954, illustrates the instability of the

    Teague Court's claimed distinction between new and old rules of constitutional law. Brown is renowned for

    overturning the rule of Plessy v. Ferguson that "separate but equal" public facilities for whites and African-

    Americans were constitutional under the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. A

    unanimous Court in Brown wrote: "Separate educational facilities are inherently unequal." Thus, many

    commentators would agree, Brown stands as a prototypical example of a case that announces a new rule of

    constitutional law.

    Brown should be understood as the culmination of a long social and legal crusade to destroy the "separate

    but equal" doctrine. Indeed, some have insisted that by 1954, the Brown decision was nearly inevitable and

    thus quite unremarkable in terms of legal doctrine. The NAACP orchestrated a sustained (though perhaps

    unsystematic) campaign that built slowly but steadily on the already existing tradition of equal protection

    until the "separate but equal" doctrine appeared facially indefensible. In particular, the NAACP initially

    accepted the existence of separate facilities, but challenged the inequalities between the black and white

    institutions. A series of cases following this tactic eventually revealed the incoherence of the "separate but

    equal" doctrine: separate facilities never could be fully equal.

    The Court's first important step was to question seriously whether separate state institutions were equal, and

    its second step was to consider intangible factors when determining equality. In the context of the

    pervasive racism of America, the reputation and prestige of separate black and white facilities never could

    be equal. Thus, even Brown-the prototype of a Supreme Court case announcing a new rule of

    constitutional law-can be fairly characterized as merely articulating or even rephrasing an obvious, alreadyexisting, or old rule.

    As taken from Diagnosing Power: Postmodernism In Legal Scholarship And Judicial Practice (With An

    Emphasis On The Teague Rule Against New Rules In Habeas Corpus Cases), 88 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1046.

    27Keshavananda Bharati v. State of Kerala AIR 1973 SC 146128 Ramachandran, R., The Supreme Court and the Basic Structure Doctrine, Supreme But not Infallible, Ed.By BN Kirpal, AH Desai, Gopal Subramaniam et al, Oxford India Paperbacks, Delhi, 200629 Id.

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    13/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 13

    The first goal while trying to reconstruct the basic structure doctrine would be to take a

    brief view on the constitutional history that led to the doctrine itself.

    In Shankari Prasad v. Union of India30, the Supreme Court considered whether an

    amendment is law under Article 13(2) of the Constitution. The Court held that there

    was a clear distinction between ordinary law and an amendment made in the exercise of

    constituent power. Thereafter, the Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964

    came to be challenged in the Sajjan Singh31

    case. The majority affirmed the judgment of

    Shankari Prasad, with two notable dissenting decisions. Justice Hidayatullah in his

    dissenting judgment said, in an ominous tone that while restricting fundamental rights

    under the restrictions imposed in Article 19 was one thing, removing them from theConstitution itself was totally different.

    32

    Justice Mudholkar, while agreeing with the majority on the validity of the Seventeenth

    Amendment, said that the law laid down in Shankari Prasadwas not the last word on the

    parliaments amending power. He said:

    The Constituent Assembly..formulated a solemn and dignified preamble which

    appears to be an epitome of the basic features of the Constitution. Can it not be said that

    these [written constitution, executive responsibility to Parliament, federal structure, clear

    distribution of powers, fundamental rights etc.] are indica of the intention of the

    Constitution framers to give a permanency to the basic features of the Constitution?33

    The first indication of the judiciarys wariness with the political milieu of that time came

    with the Golaknath34

    judgment. Nehru had died in 1964, two months prior to the decision

    in Sajjan Singh. Indira Gandhi had already been installed as the Prime Minister. Though

    those were the early days of her leadership, not yet characterized by the authoritative

    30Shankari Prasad v. Union of India (1952) SCR 8931Sajjan Singh v. State of Rajasthan (1965) 1 SCR 93332 Supra n. 2833 Supra n. 31, at para 57, as taken from The Supreme Court and the Basic Structure Doctrine, infra n. 2834IC Golaknath v. State of Punjab Air 1967 SC 1643

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    14/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 14

    streak that characterized her leadership later on, the fact that she was Nehrus daughter,

    and that there was a dynasty in the making, must have troubled the judiciary.35

    The court considered the validity of the Seventeenth Amendment, therefore necessarily

    the First and the Fourth, and held them to be invalid, though with prospective

    application.36

    The Court held that Article 368 of the Constitution did not confer the

    power to amend the Constitution. It merely prescribed the procedure to do so. An

    amendment was therefore a legislative process and was therefore law within the meaning

    of Article 13. An amendment would therefore be void if it took away or abridged

    fundamental rights.

    Soon however, Mrs. Gandhi came into her own. The end of the Nehru years and theascendancy of Indira Gandhi brought about a new power dynamic between the executive

    and the judiciary: one of open confrontationalism, and one in which the judiciary

    increasingly had the upper hand. None would illustrate this point better than the

    Golaknath37

    Case, followed by the Bharti case. Of course, important issues of

    constitutional governance underlay this attitude of confrontation, namely, individual

    rights against the increasing societal need for a social revolution. To achieve these goals,

    central authority became more concentrated, and more autocratic. In the end, it attacked

    the judiciary for greater power and unlimited authority to bring about its proposed

    objective of social revolution.

    Pursuant to the Bank Nationalization case38

    and the Privy Purses Case39

    , in 1971 the

    Constitution (Twenty Fourth) Amendment Act was passed which brought about the

    necessary changes in both Article 13 and Article 368.40

    Article 13(4) now said that an amendment was not law for the purpose of Article 13(2) of

    the Constitution. Article 368 now provided, Notwithstanding anything in this

    35 Supra n. 28. Also see Granville Austin, The Indian Constitution: Cornerstone of a Nation, Clarendon

    Press, Oxford, 1966, and The Working of a Democratic Constitution by the same author.36 Id.37 Supra Note 11

    38RC Cooper v. Union of India (1970) 1 SCC 24839Madhavrao Scindia v. Union of India (1971) 1 SCC 8540 Supra n. 35

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    15/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 15

    Constitution, Parliament may, in exercise of its constituent power amend by way of

    addition, variation or repeal any provision of this Constitution in accordance with the

    procedure laid down in this article.41

    The Keshavananda Judgment.

    The judgment in Keshavananda was delivered by a narrow majority of seven is to six,

    Justice Khannas judgment tilting the balance in favour of the majority. Only nine out of

    the thirteen judges signed what has since been accepted as the Courts view. The Court

    dealt with the Twenty Fourth amendment, and also two others. The Following has been

    accepted as the courts judgment:

    1. Golak Naths case is overruled;

    2. Article 368 does not enable the Parliament to alter the basic structure or the

    framework of the Constitution;

    3. The Twenty Fourth Amendment Act is valid42

    Though the judgment overruled Golaknath, it ensured once and for all that the final say

    with respect to the validity of an amendment to the constitution rested with the judiciary.

    While the judgment in Golaknath was specific to abridgment of fundamental rights, the

    Keshavananda judgment declared that the court now had the power to scrutinize any

    amendment43

    to see if it violated the basic structure.

    Most judges had differing perceptions of what the basic structure constituted. Chief

    Justice Sikri spoke about the supremacy of the Constitution, republican and democratic

    41 Supra n. 2842 Id.43 Id.

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    16/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 16

    form of government, separation of powers, federal character, based on the dignity and

    freedom of the individual. CJ Sikri however, did not mention that his list was

    illustrative.44

    Justice Shelat did mention that the list was illustrative, while additionally

    mentioning sovereignty, unity and integrity of the nation and Part III of the Constitution

    to be parts of the Basic Structure.45

    Justice Jagamohan Reddy basically concurred with CJ

    Sikris judgment.

    Justice Khannas views were slightly different. He stated that the Parliaments power of

    amendment did not extend to abrogating the very Constitution and replacing it with a new

    one. He therefore observed that the basic structure or framework of the Constitution

    could not be destroyed.46

    Since the formulation of the doctrine of the Basic structure, the Indian Supreme Court has

    repeatedly struck down amendments on the premise that they violate the basic structure

    of the Constitution.47

    Though the Basic Structure was initially meant to scrutinize

    amendments to the Constitution, the Court has lately started holding even ordinary

    legislations invalid when measured by the yardstick of the Basic Structure doctrine.48

    Even other countries in South Asia have relied on the doctrine to hold amendments and

    legislations invalid.49

    THE BASIC STRUCTURE CRITIQUE:ACONCLUSION

    For the purposes of this portion, the researcher seeks to draw an analogy between the old

    rule- new rule proposition analyzed in the previous portions of this paper. It is argued

    that the Basic Structure doctrine was not a brand new grand narrative based on

    44 Id.45 Id.46

    Id.47 SeeIndira Nehru Gandhi v. Raj Narain (1975) 1 Supp SCC 1, Minerva Mills v. Union of India (1980) 3

    SCC 85, Waman Rao v. Union of India (1981) 2 SCC 36248Ismail Faruqui v. Union of India (1994) 6 SCC 360, G.C Kanungo v. State of Orissa (1995) 5 SCC 9649 Bangladesh Supreme Court inAnwar Hussain Chowdhary v Bangladesh 1989 Bangladesh Law

    Documents (Spl) 1; in Pakistan,Darwesh Arbey v Federation of Pakistan All Pakistan Law Decisions(1908) Lahore 206 and Suleiman v. President, Special Military CourtAll Pakistan Law Decisions (1996)Supreme Court 367; in Sri Lanka inIn Re the Thirteenth Amendment to the Constitution (1987) 2 Sri Lanka

    Law Reports 312.

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    17/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 17

    foundationalist notions of constitutional theory, but a culmination of the traditional and

    legal patterns that had emerged from the very inception of our constitution. The first step

    towards such an understanding is to identify what the basic structure doctrine essentially

    states.

    The doctrine puts certain limitations on the constituent power of amendment, based on

    the premise that there is an essential, non-derogable, inalienable framework to our

    constitution. The doctrine states that there are certain features present in our constitution,

    essential to its framework, and they therefore cannot be eroded or abridged, even through

    the constituent power of the Parliament. Among other reasons, one reason put forward is

    that the constitution framers intended that there be certain inalienable features whichform the basic framework of our constitution, and to amend such features would be akin

    to tampering with the socio-political set up the constitution framers sought to create. But

    what are these basic features?

    CJ Sikri spoke about the supremacy of the Constitution. But what constitutes the

    supremacy of the Constitution is what the judiciary interprets it to be. It is not a static

    element. Then again, before, during or after, supremacy over the constitution was never

    sought to be asserted. What was asserted was the power to amend the constitution. He

    also talked about a democratic form of government, of the scheme of separation of

    powers as being the bedrock of our constitution. His observation is essentially

    foundationalist, setting out a grand, objective scheme which cannot be amended.

    Additionally, sovereignty, a secular polity, federal, democratic and republican in

    character was held to be a part of the basic structure.

    With respect to sovereignty specifically, it is humbly stated that it need not be stated that

    sovereignty is a basic feature of the Constitution. A constitution cannot exist without a

    nation or the will of its people being sovereign. Upendra Baxi argues that there are

    certain facets of a constitution which are never the subject of constitutional discourse, one

    of them being territorial sovereignty, others being the will to defend a nations political

    existence with coercive power, the institutions and apparatuses of governance etc. These

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    18/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 18

    are outside the scheme of constitutional discourse. The subject matter of

    constitutionalism is therefore the substantive rights, duties and obligations of state

    organizations, individuals etc. Even a discourse based on these has to be confined within

    the limits of the wider boundary of such apparatuses.50 Therefore, to say that sovereignty

    is a basic structure of the constitution seems to the researcher, superfluous.

    The other features within the ambit of the doctrine, it is argued, were not given their

    precise content and definition prior to the basic structure doctrine, but instead after it.

    Indeed the content of the basic features of the Constitution have been so greatly enlarged,

    hardly anything is left outside the scope of the doctrine.51

    Applying Hermeneutics.

    The first problem to be considered while applying philosophical hermeneutics to the

    Basic Structure doctrine, is that the most ardent critics of the judgment have consistently

    argued that there was never any indication during the framing of the Constitution of a

    basic structure nor of the consequent limitations put on the Parliaments amending power.

    The Supreme Court on the other hand argued that its judgment did in fact have firm roots

    in the constitutional process of the country. Therefore, while the judges said that the

    doctrine is not a new rule, its critics argued that it is, in direct opposition to the Teague

    case.

    The Court was however, only seeking to justify its decision from precedent, and from the

    historical processes that formed the Constitution. Its aim in doing so was to set a static,

    unchangeable rule of a basic structure. In doing so, it was a foundationalist to the core.

    On a closer look however, the basic structure is nothing without the constituent features

    making it up. It is nothing but a restatement of the constitutional set up already existing; a

    50 Baxi, U, The (Im)possibility of Constitutional Justice, Indias Living Constitution, Ed. By Zoya Hasan,E. Sridarshan, R. Sudarshan, Permanent Black, Delhi, 200251 Supra n. 48 & 49

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    19/24

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    20/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 20

    objective reasoning and interpretation, but because the Supreme Court had the power

    over the Government of the day to do so.

    In the Teague case, Judge William Rehnquist did not necessarily exercise his

    extraordinary power over Butler because of the former's judicial expertise, his clever use

    of legal rhetoric, or his ability (or inability) to distinguish new from old rules. Rather,

    Rehnquist exercised power because he performed his role within judicial practice. That

    is, Rehnquist performed as Chief Justice of the Supreme Court, which is a relatively

    embedded and ongoing social position situated within an institutional framework and

    web of social relationships (which in part constitute the role of Chief Justice as a

    dominant position imbued with an exceptional amount of power). When Rehnquist

    concludes that Butler had sought the application of a new rule, Rehnquist's written wordsimplement power.

    54

    In the same way, the words of the seven majority judges are not expressions of a

    foundationalist doctrine, but of the assertion of its institutional power. The judges merely

    exercised and asserted their position of dominance to ensure that the judiciary remains

    the final and sole authority to interpret the Constitution.

    Observed from this perspective, different textures are added on to the doctrine of Basic

    Structure. It may be a grand foundationalist doctrine, but the reason and the processes

    that formed it are very postmodern. Even the way the doctrine has been used and

    interpreted, remains essentially postmodern. The Court held in Keshavananda that

    secularism was a basic feature of our constitution. However, in S.R. Bommai v. State of

    Karnataka55, while holding secularism to be a basic feature of the constitution, the court

    held it to justify the imposition of emergency under Article 356.

    So the Basic structure doctrine may have set out to give the Constitution an element of

    rigidity or permanence. What it has achieved in doing is making Constitutional

    provisions more dynamic, more open to differing interpretations with a change in time,

    54 Id.55

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    21/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 21

    and of course ensuring that the task of such interpretation rests with the Supreme Court.

    That is, to sum up, the only permanent aspect of the Basic Structure doctrine.

    You will find that many of our truths depend on our point of view.

    - Yoda in Return of the Jedi56

    56 RETURN OF THE JEDI (Twentieth Century Fox 1983)

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    22/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 22

    BIBLIOGRAPHY

    Statutes and related Documents:

    1. The Constitution of India, 1950

    Articles and Reviews:

    1. S.M. Feldman, Diagnosing Power: Postmodernism In Legal Scholarship AndJudicial Practice (With An Emphasis On The Teague Rule Against New Rules

    In Habeas Corpus Cases), 88 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1046 .......................................... 6

    2. S. M Feldman, The Persistence of Power and the Struggle for DialogicStandards in Postmodern Constitutional Jurisprudence: Michelman,Habermas, and Civic Republicanism, 81 GEO. L.J. 2243 (1993) .................... 6

    3. J.M. Balkin, What Is A Postmodern Constitutionalism?, 90 Mich. L. Rev.1966 ................................................................................................................... 2

    4. Ken Kress,MODERN JURISPRUDENCE,POSTMODERN JURISPRUDENCE,ANDTRUTH,95 Mich. L. Rev. 1871 .......................................................................... 2

    5. Peter C. Schanck, Understanding Postmodern Thought And Its ImplicationsFor Statutory Interpretation, 65 S. Cal. L. Rev. 2505 ....................................... 36. Stanley Fish, Dennis Martinez and the Uses of Theory, 96 YALE L.J. 1773,

    1795 (1987......................................................................................................... 9

    7. G. Alan Tarr, Understanding State Constitutions, 65 Temp. L. Rev. 11698. Ruti Teitel, Comparative Constitutional Law In A Global Age, 117 Harv. L.

    Rev. 2570

    9.

    Linda R. Hirshman, Postmodern Jurisprudence And The Problem OfAdministrative Discretion, 82 Nw. U. L. Rev. 646

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    23/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 23

    Books and related works:

    Indias Living Constitution, Ed. By Zoya Hasan, E. Sridarshan, R. Sudarshan,Permanent Black, Delhi, 2002............................................................................... 17

    David Harvey, The Condition Of Postmodernity: An Enquiry Into The OriginsOf Cultural Change (1989) ...................................................................................... 2

    Fredric Jameson, Postmodernism, Or The Cultural Logic Of Late Capitalism, 35-36 (1991) ................................................................................................................. 4

    Fredric Jameson, Postmodernism, Or, The Cultural Logic Of Late Capitalism(1991........................................................................................................................ 2

    Gadamer, Hermeneutics, Tradition, And Reason (1987) ........................................ 9 Granville Austin, The Indian Constitution: Cornerstone of a Nation, Clarendon

    Press, Oxford, 1966 ............................................................................................... 13

    Jacques Derrida, Positions (Alan Bass trans., 1981) ............................................... 9 Jean-Francois Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report On Knowledge

    (Geoff Bennington & Brian Massumi trans., 1984) ............................................ 2, 4

    Supreme But not Infallible, Ed. By BN Kirpal, AH Desai, Gopal Subramaniam etal, Oxford India Paperbacks, Delhi, 2006 ............................................................. 11

    Walter Truett Anderson, Reality Isn't What It Used To Be: Theatrical Politics,Ready-To-Wear Religion, Global Myths, Primitive Chic, And Other Wonders OfThe Postmodern World (1990) ................................................................................ 4

    TABLE OF

    CASES

    Foreign Judgments

    1. Anwar Hussain Chowdhary v Bangladesh 1989 Bangladesh Law Documents(Spl) 1 .................................................................................................................... 15

    2. Brown v. Board of Education 347 U.S. 483 (1954) .............................................. 113. Butler v. McKellar 494 U.S. 407 (1990) ............................................................ 7, 84. Butler v. McKellar, 494 U.S. 407 (1990) ................................................................ 65. Darwesh Arbey v Federation of Pakistan All Pakistan Law Decisions (1908)

    Lahore 206............................................................................................................. 16

    6. In Re the Thirteenth Amendment to the Constitution (1987) 2 Sri Lanka LawReports 312. .......................................................................................................... 16

    7. Penry v. Lynaugh, 492 U.S. 302 (1989) .................................................................. 68. Saffle v. Parks, 494 U.S. 484 (1990) ....................................................................... 69. Sawyer v. Smith, 497 U.S. 227 (1990).................................................................... 610.Stringer v. Black, 112 S. Ct. 1130 (1992) ............................................................... 6

  • 8/4/2019 Constitutional Ism in India

    24/24

    -Postmodern Constitutionalism in India- 24

    11.Suleiman v. President, Special Military CourtAll Pakistan Law Decisions (1996)Supreme Court 367................................................................................................ 16

    12.Taylor v. Louisiana 419 U.S. 522 (1975) ................................................................ 613.Teague v. Lane 489 U.S. 288 (1989) ...................................................................... 614.

    Wright v. West, 112 S. Ct. 2482 (1992) .................................................................. 6

    Indian Judgments

    1. G.C Kanungo v. State of Orissa (1995) 5 SCC 96 ................................................ 152. IC Golaknath v. State of Punjab Air 1967 SC 1643 ............................................. 133. Indira Nehru Gandhi v. Raj Narain (1975) 1 Supp SCC 1 ................................... 154. Ismail Faruqui v. Union of India (1994) 6 SCC 360 ............................................ 155. Keshavananda Bharati v. State of Kerala AIR 1973 SC 1461 ............................. 116. Madhavrao Scindia v. Union of India (1971) 1 SCC 85 ....................................... 147.

    Minerva Mills v. Union of India (1980) 3 SCC 85 ............................................... 158. RC Cooper v. Union of India (1970) 1 SCC 248 .................................................. 14

    9. Sajjan Singh v. State of Rajasthan (1965) 1 SCR 933 .......................................... 1210.Shankari Prasad v. Union of India (1952) SCR 89 .............................................. 1211.Waman Rao v. Union of India (1981) 2 SCC 362 ................................................. 15