Whose Metaphysics of Presence - Heidegger's Interpretation of Energeia and Dunamis in Aristotle

download Whose Metaphysics of Presence - Heidegger's Interpretation of Energeia and Dunamis in Aristotle

of 36

Transcript of Whose Metaphysics of Presence - Heidegger's Interpretation of Energeia and Dunamis in Aristotle

  • The Southern Journal of Philosophy (2006) Vol. XLIV

    Whose Metaphysics of Presence? Heideggers Interpretation of Energeia and Dunamis in Aristotle Francisco J. Gonzalez Skidmore College

    Abstract

    In t h e recently published 1924 course, Grundbegri f fe der aris totel ischen Phi losophie , Mart in Heidegger offers a detai led interpretation of Aristotles definition of kinesis in the Physics. This in te rpre ta t ion identifies entelecheia with what is finished and present-at-an-end and energeia with being-at-work toward this end. In arguing against this interpretation, the present paper attempts to show t h a t Aristotle interpreted being from the perspective of praxis r a t h e r t h a n poiesis and therefore did not identify i t wi th s ta t ic presence. The paper also challenges la ter variations of Heideggers interpretat ion, i n par t icular his account of d u n a m i s in t h e 1931 course on Metaphysics Theta, which insists tha t its mode of being is presence-at-hand. By arguing tha t this reading too is untenable, the paper concludes tha t Aristotles metaphysics is not a metaphysics of presence and t h a t h i s texts instead point toward a possibility of metaphysics ignored by t h e a t tempts of Heidegger and others to overcome it.

    j e trouve chez Aristote ... de quoi reengendrer la metaphysique. Celle-ci ne me parai t donc pas close, je dirais plut8t quelle me parait inexploree.. . .

    -Paul Ricoeur

    Central to Martin Heideggers interpretation of the Greeks, and therefore to his account of the whole history of metaphysics, is the thesis that for the Greeks being meant presence. This interpretation has been extremely influential, provoking many and diverse attempts to overcome what has come to be called

    Francisco J. Gonzalez i s associate professor a n d chair of t he Department of Philosophy a t Skidmore College. He i s the author of :Dialectic and Dialogue: Platos Practice of Philosophical Inquiry (Northwestern University Press, 1998) and has recently completed a book entitled A Question o f Dialogue: Heidegger and Plato.

    533

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    the metaphysics of presence. Yet I have elsewhere attempted to show that this thesis is untenable in the case of Plato,2 and my aim in the present paper is to show tha t i t is equally untenable in the case of Aristotle. The crucial text is Heideggers recently published SS 1924 course, Grundbegriffe der aristotelischen P h i l o ~ o p h i e . ~ I t is here tha t Heidegger provides the most thorough argument and textual exegesis in support of his thesis that being in Aristotle means presence. This thesis then underlies, and is further defended in, Heideggers reading of Aristotle in later texts, most notably in the 1931 course Aristoteles, Metaphysik 0 1-3: Vom Wesen und Wirklichkeit der K r ~ f t , ~ and in the essay, Vom Wesen und Begriff der @>6ois, written in 1939.5 A critical reading of these texts promises nothing less than the recovery of possibilities for metaphysics that the Heideggerian history of Being must ignore and exclude.6

    1.

    Heidegger often cites the ordinary, pre-philosophical meaning of the Greek word for being, oiroia, as an indication tha t the Greeks understood being as presence. Heidegger expresses this meaning in the 1924 course as follows: means [Vermogenl, possessions and goods [Hub und G u t ] , the household [der Hausstand], the estate [das Anwesen] (GA 18, 345). Heidegger emphasizes that the ordinary meaning thus not only intends a specific being as the genuine or exemplary being, that is, ones own goods or possessions, but also expresses the how of this beings being: i t s being available (uerfiigbar), usable (brauchbar), and in this way there for us. Therefore, if we take the ordinary meaning of oiroia as a clue to what being meant for the Greeks, as Heidegger suggests (24), then we can infer that the Greeks understood being as being-there, being-at-hand, being-present. Furthermore, if this ordinary meaning is preserved in the philosophical meaning, if the philosophical meaning only makes explicit and thematic what is connoted (mitgemeint) in the ordinary meaning (25-7, 3461, then we can conclude that Aristotle too in using the word oiroia understood thereby presence.

    But can we legitimately read a philosophical conception of being into the ordinary use of the word oiroia? Can we assume that this ordinary meaning is retained in the otherwise very different, technical philosophical meaning? After all, when Aristotle analyzes the different meanings of oiroia in Metaphysics Z, goods or possessions is not among them. Though Heidegger in later texts sometimes invokes the pre- philosophical meaning of oiroia as if i t were some kind of evidence for his thesis concerning the conception of being in Greek philosophy, in 1924 he is much more careful. Thus in

    534

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    Heideggers manuscript for the course we find the following important warning regarding the interpretation of oiroia: The ordinary meaning as guideline. Beware! I t could have disappeared. Only when there is a comprehensive examination of these indications. Otherwise easily dilettante. Mere sem- blance of depth. Precisely here one must take into consideration the fate and historicity of every language (GA 18, 345). Heidegger thus makes it very clear that the technical meaning of oiroia cannot be simply deduced from the ordinary meaning, that the latter can at most serve as a guideline Weitfaden) (345; see also 24 and 26). Heidegger therefore recognizes the need to demonstrate that moments of the ordinary meaning of oiroia, in particular the connotations of Hab and Anwesen, are still present in Aristotles technical use of the term (26).

    One way in which Heidegger attempts to demonstrate this is by showing that the different forms of being (Seinscharaktere), or rather the different ways of being (Wie des Seins) Aristotle presents in Metaphysics A 8 all signify, with greater or lesser transparency, a there of beings [Da des Seiendenl (350; see 348-50 and 29-34). For the purpose of the present paper, however, I will focus on the sense of being I take to pose the greatest challenge to what Heidegger wishes to demonstrate: the sense of being that cuts through the senses discussed at Metaphysics A 8, a sense of being expressed in two words that Heidegger himself will come to consider the most fundamental words for being in Ari~tot le :~ CvTE)\&Eia and C v i p y E i a .

    That Heidegger in the 1924 course translates 6vTEhEXEia when i t first makes i ts appearance as Gegenwart, Gegenwartigsein eines Seienden als Ende (296) should not surprise us, since this is precisely the translation he needs to maintain the identification of h T E ? d x E i a with presence. Yet the context is precisely the one best suited to show the untenability of this translation. This context is the account of motion ( K ~ V ~ O I S ) in the first three chapters of Physics r, an account to which Heidegger devotes the last part of the 1924 course. He turns t o this account because he believes tha t K ~ V T ) C S I S constitutes the genuine there-character o f being (287). What this means will become apparent if we turn to Heideggers translatiodinterpretation of the definition of motion Aristotle offers in the first chapter of Physics r, 201a10-11: fi TOG adopting the translation of h T E h & E i a already mentioned, initially translates the whole sentence thus: motion is the being-present [Gegenwart] of what is capable of being-there as such (313; see also 315). An immediately apparent problem with this translation lies precisely in the word Gegenwart. A piece of wood can be present as something capable of being, for example, capable of being made into a table, without thereby being in motion. Yet Heidegger oddly insists that such presence

    6VVapEI dVTO5 h T E h i X E I U , Ifi TOIOGTOV, KiVQOiS h T I V . Heidegger,

    535

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    is motion. Insofar as it is there, the piece of wood is in motion. Insofar as it is genuinely there as capable-of-being-a-box, it is in motion (313). Essential t o understanding this very strange claim is Heideggers identification of K ~ V ~ C J I S with significance or Bedeutsamkeit. This is made especially clear in Heideggers manuscript, where we read: Kivqois is the There of the from ... to ... as such (ist das Da des von ... zu ... als solchen, 376). The piece of wood is there as significant, that is, as something to be used for a house or as something from which a box can be made: this is its Bedeutsamkeit. But this is also the K ~ V ~ C J I S that Heidegger sees as constituting the genuine being-there of being. The piece of wood sitting there is in motion in the sense of referring beyond itself, signifying something, and this is the K ~ V ~ C J I S that Aristotle is making manifest in his definition.

    One could of course object tha t what is significant in Heideggers sense, such as the piece of wood in his example, is a t res t , while what Aristotle is trying t o define is not res t (ipEDia), which he characterizes as the aKivqoia of what is capable of being moved (202a4-5), but rather the opposite of rest (229b23-26; 264a27-28): K ~ V ~ O I S in the sense of alteration, growth and decay, generation and destruction, and movement in place (201all-15). Furthermore, K ~ V ~ O I S in this sense is not simply the being-present of the capable as capable, but the actual exercise, ac t iva t ion , of the capable as capable; for example, it is not simply the presence of the wood as buildable, but the actual exercise of this potential in the activity of building. Heidegger acknowledges this possible objection (314) but dismisses i t as a n illusion (Tuuschung) by drawing our attention to the phenomenon of rest. When the carpenter goes to lunch and leaves what he is building uncompleted, the wood is at rest. But rest is something that can characterize only what is capable of being in motion: rest thus preserves, rather than eliminates, a things motion as its way of being: Rest is only a Zimit-case of motion (314). The way in which this answers the objection Heidegger faces is apparently this: Bedeutsamkeit can indeed characterize something at rest, something not presently being put to work, but what is thus at rest still has motion as its way of being. Thus the identification of Bedeutsamkeit and K ~ V ~ C S I S is preserved by way of an identification of both with rest. Thus in Heideggers manuscript we read the following: Rest as the way of being-there [Da-Weisel of what is in motion as an object of concern in the world [des Besorgten der Welt]. Only thus is significance [Bedeutsamkeitl fully determined (379).8

    One can now understand why Heidegger gives such impor- tance to the discovery of the phenomenon of rest as the way of being of most of the beings we encounter and deal with in the world: As far as I know, no one has ever brought into consider- ation this moment of rest (314). But even if we admit the unity of motion and rest to which Heidegger draws our attention, is it

    536

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    not still important to explain the difference? While the explicit purpose of Aristotles definition of K ~ V ~ U I S is to explain this difference, Heideggers interpretation prevents it from doing so. Specifically-and this is what is crucial-in translating iv-rEhEXEia as Gegenwart and thereby making K ~ V ~ U I S a kind of being-present, Heidegger blocks access to the phenomenon of K ~ V ~ U I S as distinct from rest.

    Heideggers interpretation is strikingly similar to that of the philosophers whom Aristotle describes as explaining K ~ V ~ U I S in terms of otherness ( i ~ ~ p 6 - r ~ ~ ) . Heidegger himself suggests the possibility t ha t these philosophers saw ~ T E P ~ T ~ S as a characteristic a being has in itself in the sense that a being in itself has the possibility of being from ... t o ..., of being charac- terized with regard to a certain determination by the absence of this determination. Does not i - r ~ p 6 - r ~ ) ~ then in this case determine the being of being-in-motion? (3 17). The problem, of course, is that Aristotle rejects this interpretation of K ~ V ~ U I S because, in Heideggers own paraphrase, Wood can be a box and is there as wood-determined in itself through ~ T E ~ ~ T Q S - and yet not determined as moving (384). I t is as if Heidegger in proceeding through the text has suddenly encountered a resurrected Aristotle telling him his interpretation will not stand.

    Heidegger nevertheless refuses to see defeat here and instead joins Aristotle in rejecting the explanation of motion as C T E P ~ T ~ S . However, he can do so only by suggesting tha t the problem with this explanation is i t s failure to include the moment of being-present (Gegenwartigsein) (318, 384). I t is not enough for something to be characterized by otherness or differ- ence in order for it to be in motion: this otherness or difference must be present. Heideggers interpretation is thus saved because i t included presence along with Bedeutsamkeit as essential dimensions of K ~ V ~ U I S . Yet the distance here between Heidegger and Aristotle is made clear by the fact that Aristotles objection to the thesis that K ~ V ~ U I S is ~ T E P ~ T ~ S has nothing to do with its failure to take presence into account. Instead, his objections are that what is other is not necessarily moved and that movement occurs not from and to what is other, but rather between con- traries (Physics 201b21-24). In other words, Aristotle appeals not to the phenomenon of presence, but to the phenomenon of motion itself. This again shows tha t i t is Heidegger who is reading presence into the text. Furthermore, Aristotles objection explicitly rejects as a characteristic of K ~ V ~ U I S precisely what Heidegger wants to identify it with: the structure of being f rodto what is other. In other words, what characterizes K ~ V ~ U I S is the relation of contraries and not Bedeutsamkeit.

    A little later in the course Heidegger again appears to undermine his own interpretation of K ~ V ~ U I S when he insists: One should not simply say: Kivquis is simply the ivfpyEia of

    537

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    what is capable. What is capable is not as such moved (320). Yet Heidegger now appears to move towards a different account of motion: What is in possibility comes t o i ts proper end in being put to work [In-Arbeit-Sein], it is then genuinely what it is, namely, being-capable. In relation to the Epyov of noiqai~, however, it is not finished [nicht fertig] (321). Why this shift now in Heideggers account from defining motion in terms of Gegenwart t o defining it in terms of In-Arbeit-Sein? The main reason is that Heidegger by this point in the course has come to Aristotles characterization of K ~ V ~ O I S as incomplete (aTiAq$). This is clearly a characteristic of K ~ V ~ O I S that Heideggers earlier interpretation cannot account for: what is at res t and gegenwurtig in its significance need not be ax-riAqs but, on the contrary, can be finished and complete. If we saw t h a t Heideggers earlier characterization of K ~ V ~ C S I S was unable t o capture what is distinctive of K ~ V ~ C J I S as opposed to rest, we can now say that this is incompleteness, the state of being neither fully potential nor fully actual: and this is precisely the difficult indeterminacy of K ~ V ~ O I S that Aristotle is trying to explain.

    But how can Heidegger feel justified in now changing his interpretation, specifically, in replacing Gegenwart with In- Arbei t -Sein? The reason is tha t he thinks he finds such a distinction in Aristotle himself, a s he makes clear in the following remark: Insofar as Being ultimately means Being-at- its-end, Holding-itself-in-its-end in a final sense, ivTEhiXEia, Aristotle, when he speaks with care, must characterize the being [Daseinl of being-in-motion as i v i p y ~ i a (321).9 What Heidegger is assuming here is a distinction between ivTE AiXEia as being-present-at-an-end and i v i p y E i a as being-at-work- towards-an-end. This distinction then allows him to grant that the definition of motion as ivTEAiXEia is not fully adequate, since motion is C X T E A ~ S , and that Aristotle would be more careful if he were to characterize motion as iv ipyEia in the sense of an incomplete being-at-work. But what grounds are there for this sharp distinction between 2vipyEia and iv-rEAiXEia?O And is In- Arbeit-Sein an adequate translation of the ivipyEia that defines motion?

    Let us consider the second question first. This translation of i v ipyEia is of course suggested by the etymology of the term. Yet, as Heidegger well knows, etymology by itself can prove nothing. Furthermore, Heideggers etymological account is questionable on two main points. (1) He takes the word Epyov t o mean work, whether in the sense of working, as here, or in the sense of the work, the finished product, which, as we will see, is how Heidegger interprets the word in later texts (these two related meanings, for example, are the only ones recognized in the 1931 course [GA 33, 501). But are either or both of these interpretations fully adequate interpretations of Zpyov? To see that they are not, one need only recall the use of

    538

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    the word in the first book of the Nicomachean Ethics: to say that the Epyov of man is the souls i v ipye ia in accordance with reason [KaTa A6yovI (1098a7) is not t o say tha t this is the work man does nor that it is something produced by man; this is why the translation of function is sometimes chosen. Note also how in this part of the Nicomachean Ethics the Epyov is argued to be an 6vdpyEia with no sense of redundancy. (2) Therefore, the other problem with Heideggers reading is that it tends to reduce ivdpyEia to Epyov: as being-at-work it is work; as standing in the work produced, it is the work produced.12

    Heideggers translation has indeed more than etymology to recommend it: it is certainly better to characterize motion as a putting-to-work of a capability than i t is to characterize it as the mere being-present of this capability. Yet this translation confronts a serious philosophical problem: i t collapses the distinction between ivipyEia and Kivqois. Being-at-work towards an unachieved end is itself a motion, so that to define i v i p y a a thus is necessarily to turn it into a motion. Heidegger indeed characterizes i v i p y E i a , in distinction from ivTEAiXEia, as U n fe r t ig s e in ( 3 8 1 ) , d a s No c h - n i c h t - fe r t i g ( 3 8 2 ) , thereby identifying it with motion not only implicitly but at one point in the course explicitly: iv ipyEia is KivqoiS, but not ivTEhiXEia (296).13 Yet such an identification is untenable for two reasons. (1) Aristotles definition of motion would become viciously circular, since it would amount to saying: motion is the putting-in-motion of what is capable qua capable. Of course, as Heidegger would be quick to point out, in philosophy, circles are not always vicious. But while some circular reasoning can be illuminating, a definition of motion as the putting-into- motion of what is capable of motion illuminates o r reveals nothing at all.14 (2) The second problem is that, in a well-known text from the Metaphysics (0 6, 1048b18-35), Aristotle sharply distinguishes between i v i p y a a and K ~ V ~ O I S precisely because the latter is ~ I T E A I ~ S while the former is And it is impor- tant to emphasize that the definition of K ~ V ~ O I S as an 6vipyEia does not at all contradict their distinction. The iv ipyEia that defines motion is not itself an incomplete process towards some end but, rather, the ful l actuality and completion of what is capable insofar as it is capable. It is the qualification insofar as it is capable that explains the incompleteness of motion and not anything in i v i p y E i a itself, as Aristotle explicitly says: K~VTJCJIS, though a kind of ivipyEia, is incomplete [ ~ T E A I ~ S ] . The cause of i ts being incomplete is the capable [ ~ b 6 u v a ~ 6 v l of .which it is the ivipyEia (Phys. 2, 201b31-33).16 This is why the definition is not circular: iv ipyEia in itself is not motion17 nor is the capable qua capable in itself motion: only the ivipyEia of the capable qua capable is motion. This is also why Aristotle a t one point can even, with no hint of paradox, characterize motion a s a n ivTEAiXEia ~ I T E A I j s (257b8-9), a

    539

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    characterization tha t of course defeats the whole point of Heideggers distinction between ivTEAiXEia and i v i p y a a .

    We can now draw an important conclusion: the key term in the definition of K ~ V Q C J I T , whether it be ivTEAiXEia or iv ipyEia , can mean neither Gegenwartigsein nor an unfertiges im-Arbeit- Sein: the former interpretation eliminates the phenomenon of K ~ V Q O I S altogether by substituting for it the mere presence of a capability, while the latter interpretation leaves it completely unexplained by simply defining it as itself. But these inade- quate interpretations of ivTEAiXEia or ivipyEia rest on the sharp distinction Heidegger makes between them. Only by being sharply distinguished from ivipyEia can ivTEAiXEia be rid of any connotation of activity and be identified with Gegenwart, Gegenwartigsein eines Seienden als Ende and Fertigsein (296); only by being sharply distinguished from ivTEAiXEia can i v i p y a a be characterized as an incomplete movement towards a T ~ A O S . It is therefore this distinction that fails to make sense of Aristotles account of motion, an account in which the terms ivTEAiXEia and ivipyEia are used interchangeably. What justi- fication, then, does Heidegger provide for making such a distinction?

    Before looking at this justification we need to reflect on why Heidegger needs a sharp distinction between ivTEAiXEia and ivipyeia . As already noted, one of Heideggers principle aims in this discussion is to demonstrate that for Aristotle, and for the Greeks in general, Being was understood as presence and, more specifically, as a static presence. To support this interpretation he must argue tha t Aristotles word for being in the fullest sense, that is, ivTEAiXEia, means being-present-once-and-for-all, being-at-an-end, being-finished. But the only way in which he can interpret ivTEAiXEia in this way is to sharply distinguish it from i v i p y a a and interpret the latter in a way that completely subordinates it t o the former: as movement towards being-at- an-end, being-finished. The conclusion tha t Heidegger thus wishes t o arrive a t is clearly stated in the following passage from his manuscript for the course:

    The How of t h e There (Da) of something: how does being-at- work [In-Arbeit-sein] arrive at this ontological-hermeneutical precedence? Because being=being-produced [ Sein=Hergestelltsein] , There=being-present [Da=Anwesendsein], being-finished [Fertigsein], having-come-into t h e Now [Hersein in J e t z t ] , in to presence [Gegenwart] ; in being-present-before [Gegenwartigsein] , being-in- possession-of-the-there [Da-Habendsein], remaining-there with [Sichaufhalten bei]. . . . (381)

    But what becomes of this conclusion if ivTEAiXEia and ivipyEia a re synonyms? I t simply collapses. If i v n A i X E i a means the same as i v i p y E i a , then as activity i t cannot mean what is

    540

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    simply present (schlechthin gegenwart ig) , what is f in ished , much less what is produced. If i v ipyEia means the same as iv-rEhiXEia, then as an end-in-itself i t cannot be a process nor therefore work or production. The synonymous pair iv-rEhiXEia/ iv ipyEia would then name a conception of Being that evades and transcends the conception to which Heidegger tr ies t o confine Aristotle and the Greeks.

    But it is now time to look at the textual evidence Heidegger provides for the distinction on which his present reading of Aristotles ontology, and Greek ontology in general, depends. The evidence provided on p. 295 is Metaphysics 0 3 1047a30. Here Aristotle, according t o most editions of the text, refers to 4 i v ipyEia Toi jvopa as G n p o s T ~ V ivTEhiXEiav ouvTi8Evivq: i v i p y E i a (as a name) is set down in relation to, o r for, ivTEAiXEia. However, this is not the text Heidegger reads: he follows Diels in substituting O U V T E I V O ~ ~ V ~ for ouv-riBEvivq so that he can interpret the text as meaning that ivipyEia spannt sich aus zum Ende, stretches itself towards the end (296). This of course is the interpretation Heidegger needs in order to distin- guish between i v i p y a a as an unfinished movement towards an end and ivTEhiXEia as a being-finished-at-an-end. Unfortunately, W. D. Ross already showed in 1924 that the substitution of O U V T E I V O ~ ~ V ~ for mv-ri8Epivq is neither possible nor necessq.

    But it is only in the active voice tha t Aristotle uses U W V T E ~ V E W in this sense. [In other words, there is no parallel for the middle voice U U V T E I V O ~ ~ V I ~ meaning what Heidegger takes it to mean here]. ouvTiOEpivq implies t h a t Aristotle was i n t h e habi t of connecting t h e words iv ipyEia a n d ivTEhiXEia together i n his lectures, and such phrases as EIS Tab-rbv Pauihia K a i Tbpavvov uwviOEpEv [we have set down the words PaaiAia and Tljpavvov as meaning the same] (Pl. Pol. 2763, cf. 259d) form a close enough parallel.18

    In short, there is a more plausible reading of the text tha t makes it mean the exact opposite of what Heidegger needs it to mean: the word i v i p y E i a is set down in relation to iv-rEhiXEia in the sense tha t Aristotle normally uses the two together, and perhaps even-this is perfectly compatible with the text on this reading-interchangeably. And this of course is Aristotles practice. We have already seen that the two terms appear to be used interchangeably in the account of motion (see especially 201a27-2919 and 202a15-18) and there a re many more examples of this synonymy in Aristotles texts. Therefore, we can conclude t h a t both the most plausible reading of 1047a30 and Aristotles general practice rule out Heideggers interpretation.

    However, Heidegger does offer a textual parallel for his substitution of O U V T E I V O ~ ~ V ~ for ouv-ri8Epivq at 1047a30. He

    541

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    cites Metaphysics 0 8, 1050a21-23 where Aristotle writes: For the Epyov is T ~ A O S and i v i p y E i a is the Epyov; therefore, the name ivipyEia is also said according to the Epyov and stretches towards ( (SVVTE~VEI mpbs) iv-rEAiXEia. So in this text Heidegger has the word he wants, ( S U V T E ~ V E I , in order to interpret the relation between i v ipyEia and iv-rEAiXEia as a movement from one to the other. But two objections can be made here. First, the present text does not support Heideggers reading of 1047a30 since the word ( S U V T E ~ V E I here is in the active voice, not the middle voice (Heidegger must attribute the same meaning to both voices, which is not plausible). Secondly, here as in the earlier text it is the word 6vipyEia that is the subject: it is not 6v ipyEia itself tha t stretches towards iv-rEAiXEia, but the word. What can i t mean to say tha t a word tends towards another word? What else besides tha t i t tends towards the meaning of the other word, tends to mean something similar or the same? And this is the interpretation clearly suggested by the context of the entire sentence. Here we do well to cite Ross again, this time on 1050a21-23: Because the Epyov is the T ~ A o ~ (1. 21), the word iv ipyEia , which is derived from Epyov, tends to mean the same as iv-rEAiXEia (264). In short, ra ther t han saying that i v fpyEia itself is a movement towards iv-rEAfXEia, what the sentence says is that the word iv ipyEia tends to have the meaning of ivTEAiXEia. This reading would bring the passage in line with the most plausible reading of the earlier passage a t 1047a30: Aristotle sets down the word i v i p y E i a together with 6vTEAiXEia. This reading would not only fail t o support but would even contradict Heideggers interpretation of the relation between the two terms.

    Given i ts slim, or only apparent, textual basis and, more importantly, its inability to make sense of Aristotles account of motion, Heideggers distinction between iv-rEAiXEia and ivipyEia must be rejected. But to reject this distinction is, as I have already suggested, to reject Heideggers thesis that being for the Greeks meant being-present and being-produced. To think ivTEAixEia and i v ipyEia in their synonymy, as Aristotles text demands , is to recognize, on the one hand, that ivTEAiXEia is activity, being-active, and not some static presence, that it is in its T ~ A O S by being an activity with its aim in itself and not by being f in i shed o r a t a n e n d ; and, on the other hand, t ha t iv ipyEia is activity but not Arbeit, not something unfinished. In other words, i t is to recognize tha t the distinction between Fertigsein and Unfertigsein is completely incapable of capturing what is meant by either ivTEAiXEia or i v ipyEia . What emerges from such reflection as the central characteristic of Being is not presence and not being-produced, but rather act.

    As is clear from the passage cited above, with its character- ization of Being as Hergestelltsein, Heidegger insists on making m o i q a i ~ and T ~ X V ~ the guiding and determining perspective in

    542

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    Aristotles account of Being. What reflection on the synonymy of ivTEhiXEia and 6vipyEia shows, however, is that it is -rrp6

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    trates the temporal difference between iv ipyEia and Kivqois in Metaphysics 0 6, 1048b18-35:24 while in the case of a K ~ V ~ C T I S such as building I cannot say simultaneously ( a p a , Met. 1048b23) that I have built the house and that I am building the house, in the case of an ivipyEia such as seeing, I can say simultaneously that I am seeing and that I have seen. In short, in a K ~ V ~ O I ~ , the present tense excludes the past perfect tense and vice versa:25 that something cannot be what it is becoming, this opposition between being and becoming, is precisely what it means to exist in time. But how then can ivEpyEia simultaneously admit both the past perfect and the present tense, how can i t overcome their opposition and thereby not exist in time?

    Through careful reflection on what Aristotle says here we can avoid the mistake mentioned above: to see i v i p y E i a as differing from KivqaiS only in being finished, completed in the present moment would be t o identify i t with the past perfect tense, thus locating i t , like the house that has been built, in time (and, we could add, in mot ion, as the completion or finishing of motion). In this case, i v ipyEia would differ from K ~ V ~ O I ~ in that, while K ~ V T ~ I S can admit only the present active tense, i v i p y E i a would admit only the past perfect: i v i p y E i a would, like the house that has been built, exclude the present active tense.26 But this of course is not what Aristotle says. To claim, as he does, that ivipyEia admits simultaneously both the present and the past perfect tenses is to put i t completely outside the distinction between being-unfinished and being- finished, a distinction that, after all, has meaning only in time. If the same thing can simultaneously be seeing and have seen (aHa ~b a h 6 , 1048b33-44),27 this is because seeing is always complete without ever being f in ished . I can of course stop seeing, but this is not to finish seeing.28 To describe my seeing, or another iv ipyEia , as in itself finished or unfinished, makes no sense at all.

    To say that seeing, and i v ipyEia as such, does not exist in time and transcends the opposition between the past perfect and the present tense is to say that it cannot be located in any present , not even in an eternal present. I have seen and a m seeing cannot be reduced t o I am seeing, I am seeing, I am seeing, ad infinitum. We have here neither a stat ic eternal repetition o f the same nor a process: we have a n activity, an ivipyEia, which as such is not in time in the sense that it exists neither in a series of moments nor in one moment of this series; if this iv ipyEia that simultaneously is and has been exists as a whole in the now, this now cannot be a point, but must rather be a n uncountable stretch, a time outside of time under- stood as the counting of motion. In short, iv ipyEia differs from K ~ V ~ O I S in being complete; but i v i p y E i a also differs from the product of K ~ V I - ~ I ~ (e.g., the built house) in never being finished; I have seen but am also s i m ~ l t a n e o u s l y ~ ~ still seeing. This is

    544

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    precisely the mystery of ivipyEia that puts it completely beyond the realm of K ~ V ~ O I ~ and I T O I ~ ~ I ~ : i t is active without being in motion; it is complete without being finished; it is now and not now, present and not present; temporal and yet outside of time.30

    What is arguably the key example Aristotle uses in Meta- physics 0 6 is life itself.31 While it is not possible simultaneously to be moving and have moved, since these are different ( ~ T E ~ O V , 1048b32-33), i t is the same to be l iv ing and have lived (1048b27). Though life is complete, it is never completed; in its very completeness, in i t s very having lived, i t is always a present tense verb: living. Life of course can cease with death, but as Aristotle explicitly says, it can never come to a stop (TOTE TraLjEoOai, 1048b26-27). Also, a dead person cannot strictly be described as having lived (perfect tense), but only as someone who once lived (imperfect tense). Having lived is possible only in living and living is possible only in having lived. In this way life itself is not in time, that is, cannot be located anywhere on the continuum of counted time, neither in any present now nor in any sequence of present nows. As thus characterized, the iv-rE?dXEia of life can be identified neither with being-at-work, which implies working-towards-a-goal and thus not having yet l i ved , nor with being-at-an-end and being-at-hand, which implies no longer living. In other words, life that is at work has not yet lived, while life that is at hand is dead.

    These brief reflections on Aristotles fundamental concepts of iv-rEhiXEia and ivipyEia should suffice to show that Heideggers interpretation of these concepts is not only wrong but disas- trously wrong.32 In being sharply distinguished from each other, both concepts are distorted beyond recognition. I t is at this cost that Heidegger reads into Aristotle a conception of Being as Being-present. I t is at this cost tha t he transforms into an ontology of Vorhandenheit what is an ontology of npLi,is in which the highest and most genuine being is, despite being unmoved, or rather because unmoved, characterized as life (

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    [Bewegtheitl (321). In a course from SS 1926 a different, and even opposed, solution is suggested: No a-rihqs, no ~ i v q o i s , but pure i v i p y E i a , pure energy [reine Energiel, that is, pure self- standing constant presence from out of itself [reine eigenstandige standige Anwesenheit uon i h m selbst her] (GA 22, 178; see also 328). The above analysis and critique has shown tha t every- thing is lost in the move signaled by the seemingly innocent and inconspicuous that is. Just a little later in the same text iv ipyEia is characterized as the highest form of being-at-hand (hochste Art des Vorhandenseins) (180), which would make the unmoved mover something a t hand in the highest sense because eternally-at-hand. The being of the unmoved mover would thus not essentially differ from the being of an eternal, indestructible rock. In this reduction of the being of the first being to Vorhandenheit, the life and activity that are both the heart and head of Aristotles ontology are completely lost.33

    2.

    We can turn now to a consideration of two important later texts on Aristotle already cited above: the 1931 course on Metaphysics 0 1-3 and the 1939 essay Vom Wesen und Begriff der Q3ois. While Heidegger in these texts builds on and further carries out his reading of ivTEAiXEia and i v i p y E i a , we will see tha t his interpretation undergoes no fundamental transformation. These la ter interpretations will instead make even clearer the limitations of Heideggers interpretative framework and thus the need to free Aristotles ontology from this framework. As the above reflections have already suggested, what is at issue here is not primarily the reliability of Heidegger as an interpreter of Greek texts nor even the correct reading of Aristotle; what is a t issue is i v i p y E i a itself, as the word for a possibility of thinking that is arguably still unexplored and that, while still alive in Aristotles texts, is suppressed by Heideggers reading of these texts.

    The 1931 course is primarily devoted to Aristotles concept of 6 3 v a H I S . However, in Heideggers interpretation of chapter three of Metaphysics 0, the chapter in which Aristotle critiques the Megarian identification of 63vapiS with i v i p y E i a , the latter notion is necessarily at issue. Furthermore, a brief considera- tion of this par t of the course will show tha t Heideggers reading does as much violence to the notion of Grjvapis as it does t o the notion of i v i p y E i a , and again with the aim of identifying the Greek conception of being with presence-at- hand. That this is indeed Heideggers aim can be shown through a brief summary of his overall interpretation of 0 3. The central question at issue in this chapter, according to Heidegger, is how 60vapiS is at-hand (vorhanden). The thesis of the Megarians is that a 66vapis is present at-hand only when it

    546

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    is being exercised, that is, only in 6vipyEia. Heidegger insists repeatedly that this Megarian thesis is to be taken very seriously and is even a pinnacle of Greek thought. Its powerful justification is that only in 6vipyEia does a WvaviS show itself, offer a look (Anblick), announce its presence (GA 33, 179-80; see also 183). In other words, the Megarians claim that 66vavis is a t hand only in M p y E i a because it is only in the process of production, and especially in the final product, that a G6vaviS comes into full presence. But then the conception of being that comes to expression in the Megarian thesis is the Greek concep- tion of being as Hergestelltheit and Anwesenheit. Thus the Megarian thesis, Heidegger asserts, is conceived in a good Greek manner [gut griechisch gedachtl; indeed, not only that, but i t is-right up t o the new step Aristotle takes-the only possible interpretation of the being-at-hand of a capability (180).

    If the Megarians are only giving voice, with great consis- tency and insight, to the Greek conception of being, then isnt Aristotle, through his critique of the Megarians, bringing this conception into question? As the passage just cited indicates, Heidegger grants Aristotle a modification of this conception of being as presence, but not a radical departure. Indeed, Heidegger asserts emphatically that Aristotle and the Megarians are in complete agreement (sich ganz daruber einig) in understanding being as presence (179). Thus Heidegger even suggests that the Megarian thesis might have been provoked by Aristotles failure to explain the being-at-hand of 60vaviS (169) or his dogmatic assumption that this question was already resolved (175). What Aristotle does achieve in chapter 3 is to show a way in which G6vavis can be present without being 6vipyEia: namely, by being had. The having of 66vayiS is still a certain kind of presence of 66vapis. Whether or not Heidegger thought Aristotles response to the Megarians was adequate-the Megarians could, after all, insist that the GrjvapiS is really had only in actual exercise, in WpyEia-is not clear since the course comes to an abrupt end before Heideggers reading of Metaphysics 0 3 is completed. We can presume, however, that he would not consider fully adequate any response that was still locked within a conception of being as presence, as Aristotles supposedly was. Heidegger can thus maintain that the Megarians, despite the injustice history has done them, were of an equal stature with Plato and Aristotle (hatten ... den gleichen Rang, 163); they were, after all, more consistently Greek!

    It is not possible here to go into all the details of Heideggers reading of Metaphysics 0 3, a reading that without question offers some rich philosophical rewards. Instead, only one funda- mental question will be posed to this reading: is it really indisputable (unbestreitbar, 170-711, as Heidegger asserts, that the question a t issue in 0 3 is how 6 6 v a v i s can be

    547

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    vorhanden and therefore, given the supposedly Greek concep- tion of Being, how it can be present? First, it needs to be noted that Heideggers thesis that Aristotle and the Megarians shared the same conception of being as presence and therefore could disagree only about how 6 3 v a p i s is present is asserted categorically towards the beginning of the reading and is never demonstra ted . In other words, i t is a presupposit ion of the reading, not its result. However, Heidegger does a number of things to make the text fit this assumption. It is by showing the arbitrariness and untenability of these interpretative moves tha t I hope t o show tha t 0 3 has nothing t o do with the Vorhandenheit or Anwesenheit of Girvapis, and for the simple reason that for Aristotle a 63vapiS is not something present or at hand.

    The view Aristotle attributes to the Megarians in the very first line of the chapter, and the view that he spends the rest of the chapter challenging, is: o-rav h p y i j p6vov 6 3 v a d a i : when something is active only then is i t capable. I t seems from this tha t the Megarians are making a claim about the capability of capability: a capability is a capability only in i ts exercise; t o be capable is actively to be capable, that is, t o be acting. Yet consider Heideggers translation of the Greek: When a power is at work, only then is the having-power-for at hand [vorhandenl (167). With this translation the question becomes not how a capability is a capability, not how what is capable is capable, but how a capability is vorhanden. But there is in the Greek nothing corresponding to vorhanden! Heidegger takes care of this problem by adding to the text some new Greek, some Greek of his own making. After citing the Greek tha t is actually in the text, Heidegger adds: that is, 6 3 v a p i v \ jnapxEiv (167). I t is now this added Greek tha t Heidegger can translate as 66vapis is vorhanden.

    But does this really make an important difference? Is not (the being-at-hand of capability just a different way of saying being-capable ( 6 3 v a o e a i ) ? Most certainly not. To substitute the being-at-hand of capability for being-capable is t o subordinate and even reduce being-capable t o a different sense of being: being vorhanden, which is then later trans- formed, through the alchemy of Heideggers undefended thesis concerning the Greek conception of being, into being present. Heidegger would of course claim that the Greeks are the ones who reduce all senses of being, including being-capable, t o presence. But the irony is tha t Heidegger can maintain this thesis only by himself introducing presence and being-at- hand into the text. Neither a t the beginning of Metaphysics 0 3, nor anywhere in the course of 0 3, is the presence or being-at- hand of 63vapiS at issue, or even mentioned.

    Furthermore, the dispute between the Megarians and Aristotle can be naturally interpreted with no reference t o

    548

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    Vorhandenheit or Anwesenhei t . What the Megarians and Aristotle do agree on is that GhapiS is not mere possibility, but a positive capability, a power (Kraft in Heideggers defensible translation). The Megarian objection is that power is power only in being exercised and tha t therefore 66vapiS and i v i p y E i a cannot be distinguished. That this is a sensible objection-the Megarians, as Heidegger insists, were no fools-is shown by the fact that Aristotle himself in De Anima characterizes knowledge that is possessed without being exercised both as an 6vTEAiXEia (412a21-27) and as a GhapiS (417a26-28): it is an 6v-rEhiXEia in contrast to the mere potential for acquiring knowledge possessed by a certain genus or matter; i t is a GhapiS in contrast t o the actual exercise of knowledge. Thus, even for Aristotle, G6vapiS in the strongest sense of the word, that is, when understood not as a mere potent ial (as in a human embryo having the potential to learn mathematics) but as a positive capability, is i v i p y ~ i a . ~ ~ However, what he must argue in 0 3 is that despite this unity of GrjvapiS and ivipyEia, their distinctness must be preserved if what only their distinctness can explain is to be preserved: namely, not only motion, but even the independence of the external world in its relation to us (since this requires a distinction between what is perceived and what is perceivable). The argument, thus plausibly interpreted, has nothing to do with the being-at-hand or presence of GitvapiS; what is at issue is only GhapiS as 6 3 v a p i ~ . ~ ~

    As already noted, Heidegger argues that Aristotle explains the presence-at-hand of 60vapiS by interpreting the being of 63vapiS as being-had. Aristotle sees the presence of 63vapis as such in EXEIV; what is had, is in possession and as possessed usable, at hand (183). One sees clearly in this sentence why Heidegger is insisting that Aristotle understood the being of GdvapiS as being-had: i t is in this way that Aristotle can be made to conform to the supposedly Greek conception of being as what is produced and thus present for use, a t hand. But what is the evidence that Aristotle understood the being of 66vapis in this way? Heidegger can appeal only to Aristotles habit, in this text and elsewhere, of using the phrase G h a p i v EXEIV as a synonym for the verb GhaoBai . But does Aristotles use of the common Greek idiom of having a G h a p i ~ really show that he located the being of 66vapiS in h ~ v i n g ? ~ ~ T o believe this one must a t least already be convinced tha t in 0 3 Aristotle is seeking to explain how GhapiS is present and at hand-how else than a s had?-and even then one should pause before reading so much into one word. In any case, we have seen that there is no reason to believe this is Aristotles goal in the text.

    We also need t o note how philosophically questionable Heideggers method of proceeding here is. He is reducing GirvaoBai to Girvapiv EXEIV and then reading out of the verb EXEIV, instead of the verb GhaoBai, the meaning of being that is

    549

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    operative here. Aristotle, who knows better, insists that being- capable and having are two fundamentally distinct senses of being: the latter is one of the categories (Cat . lb27, 2a3), while the former is distinct from all being in the sense of the categories (Met. E 2 1026a33-b2; Met. 0 1 1045b27-35).37 And Aristotle in the present text has been seen to be faithful to his principle: he discusses being-capable in terms of being-capable and not in terms of any other sense of being. 61jvapiv E X E W must be interpreted as another and looser way of saying 81jvaoOa1, not vice versa.38

    If Heideggers reading can so far be said to have forced the text, this is nothing compared to what he does to the sentence a t 1047a20-24. Here Aristotle, defending the distinctness of b 1 j v a ~ t S and i v i p y E i a , says what anyone except Heidegger would translate as follows: So it can happen that something is capable of being something (61jvaT6v T I Eivai) without being i t , and capable of not being something (bvva-rbv pi Eivai) while being i t . . . . This is how Heidegger translates: So it can happen tha t something a s capable of something indeed really i s [wirklich istl and a t the same time is yet not really tha t of which this real capability as such is capable, and i t can also happen tha t something capable as a capability is not really [nicht wirklich ist] and yet precisely is really that of which it is capable (215). Why the tortuous and even painful circum- locution? What Heidegger is trying to do is transform the capability of being at issue in the text into the being of capa- bility; even more bizarrely, he is paraphrasing the capability of not being as the not-being of a capability as a capability. Here refutation seems superfluous, for why point out what any beginning student of Greek knows: tha t 63vaT6v TI Eivai means capable of being something and not something capable really is; that bvva-rov p i Eivai means capable of not being and not something capable is not really? The important question is why Heidegger, who certainly knows his Greek well enough t o see that , would willfully so distort the text. The answer is simple: only through such a distortion can Heidegger force through his thesis that what is at issue in the text is the Vorhandenheit and Anwesenheit of capability. Aristotle speaks of being-capable, but Heidegger needs him t o speak of the being-present o r being-at-hand of capability. The violence tha t this requires is especially evident in Heideggers trans- lation of Aristotles example: Being capable of walking and not walking (bvva-rbv PaGiSEiv o v p i PabiSEiv) becomes what is capable-of-walking is really a being (at-hand) and yet does not walk in reality (215)! That Heidegger must resort here to such impossible readings of the Greek only confirms what has been clear from the beginning: there is in Metaphysics 0 3 no ta lk of the being-present or being-at-hand of a capa- bility, but only of being-capable (of being x) where this is not

    550

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    reduced, and cannot be reduced, to any kind of being-present or being-at-hand.

    Yet Heidegger tries again when he turns to the definition or characterization of being-capable Aristotle provides at 1047a24- 26. The meaning of this sentence is unclear and disputed, but the Greek itself is not especially difficult and can be translated thus: Something is capable [EOTI 86 8uvaTbv TOGTO] if, when the iv ipyEia of which it is said to have the GGvaviS occurs in it, there will be nothing incapable [obOiv EoTai aGirva~ov1 . The problem this sentence poses for interpretation is its apparent circularity: it appears to be saying that something is capable when it is not incapable. One common expedient for remedying this problem is t o give the defining phrase not aG\jvaTov a completely different meaning from that of the word GuvaTbv tha t is being defined: GuvaTbv is taken to mean capable, while not aG\jva-rov is taken to mean not logically impossible. The sense would then be that something is capable when there is no logical impossibility in its having the corresponding i v i p y ~ i a . ~ ~ Yet this expedient, which involves giving two occur- rences of the same word in the same sentence two radically different meanings, is highly questionable and Heidegger is right to reject it.

    Furthermore, the expedient is not necessary since sense can be made of the sentence without it, especially when i t is not seen as representing a strict definition. Given the context, the task of the sentence can be taken to be this: to show the insep- arability of G h a p i c from iv ipyEia , and thus acknowledge what t ruth there is in the Megarian objection, while nevertheless showing their distinctness and preserving the autonomy and irreducibility of being-capable. We can identify something as capable only when in exercise o r activity i t proves not incapable. For example, someone cannot be said to be capable of playing chess unless an actual chess game finds him not incapable of playing chess. This means that a Girvavis indeed cannot be identified o r defined without the corresponding i v i p y E i a . So far the Megarians have a point. But Aristotles statement also maintains the distinctness of 6 3 v a p i S and i v i p y E i a . I t does not say simply tha t something is GuvaTov when it is in ivipyEia, but rather when in ivipyEia it proves not aGirva-rov. i v i p y E i a is not G h a v i S , but rather the site where 6 6 v a p i 5 shows itself as GirvapiS. Here being-capable still remains distinct from that in which i t shows itself not incap- able. Whatever circularity there is in Aristotles statement is intentional and unavoidable: being-capable can ultimately be explained only in terms of being-capable (or not being incap- able) because it cannot be reduced to any other kind of being: neither being in ivipyEia nor, much less, being in any other sense.

    What has been sketched out here is of course not Heideggers reading. This is because, in order to make the sentence fit his

    551

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    interpretation of 0 3, he must insist that it is not about being- capable, but rather about the being-present or being-at-hand of capability. To push through this reading, Heidegger must again read the Greek in his own inimitable manner. The word EOTI in the opening phrase Z O T I 86 8 u v a - h TOGTO ... does not mean, Heidegger insists, being-capable Vermogendsein (220). He insists on this because he needs the EOTI to mean is present at hand. Thus, on his reading, ZOTI 86 8uvaTov TOGTO ... means not this is capable, but rather: this capable is present at hand. Heidegger actually expresses surprise that his reading is in all interpretations and translations-as far as I know- completely missed, and continues tha t as a result every prospect of understanding the definition is from the very beginning pushed aside (220). The phrase EOTI 8i 8uvaTbv must be understood as the capable is present at hand because the task of the entire chapter is to determine in what the being of the capable, its reality-the Eivai of the immediately preceding sentence-consists (220). That this is the task of the chapter, however, has been seen to be Heideggers own invention and one sustained only at the cost of the kind of rewriting and mis- reading of the text which we see again here and saw at its most outlandish in the reading of Eivai at 1047a20-24 to which Heidegger now refers.

    I t is perhaps precisely in order t o preempt such criticism that Heidegger states the following a little earlier in the course.

    When we in the process go beyond what Aristotle says, this is not in order to make what is said there better and the like, but a t first only in order to understand it a t all; here, the manner and form of expression in which Aristotle on his side may have carried out the considerations tha t a re necessary here is a mat ter of complete indifference [ganzlich gleichgiiltig] . (192)

    One can certainly agree tha t an interpretation needs to go beyond what is said while yet strongly objecting to the sugges- tion that Aristotles own manner and form of expression are a matter of complete indifference! The la t ter a re especially important when what is at issue is Aristotles implicit under- standing of being. What has been seen again and again is that while Aristotle speaks only of being-capable in terms of being- capable, Heidegger repeatedly ignores, changes, o r distorts Aristotles form of expression in order to make him speak of being-present and being-at-hand.

    The last part of the 1931 course that needs to be considered in the present context is Heideggers return, immediately before the course abruptly ends, to 1047a30-32, and thus to the ques- tion of the relation between iv ipyEia and ivTEhiXEia. One departure from the reading in 1924 is that Heidegger now does not emend the text but reads auv-riBEpivq, perhaps because he

    552

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    had by this point consulted Rosss ~ o m m e n t a r y . ~ ~ However, his view concerning the distinction between i v i p y a a and ivTEhiXEia does not appear to change. He translates even the unemended text as follows: Being-at-work [Am-Werke-seinl , a meaning that is in itself directed at [ausgerichtet is t aufl ivTEAiXEia. Furthermore, Heideggers comments explain the meaning of ivTEhiXEia thus: the end, possessing perfection as something carried out, holding itself in it-most precisely: being-produced [Hergestelltseinl (224). What remains the same here is therefore the interpretation of i v ipye ia and ivTEhiXEia from the perspective of Herstellen, and therefore from the perspective of ~roiqois ra ther than ~rpac is , with the result tha t the one becomes being-at-work ( A m - W e r l ~ e - S e i n ) ~ ~ and the other becomes being-produced (Hergestelltheit). What has already been shown to be the main problem with such an interpretation is made clear when Heidegger in this course, after making the perhaps acceptable claim that Girvapis and iv ipyEia are essen- tially related to ~ i v q o i ~ , goes further and claims that they are ways of being-in-motion (Weisen des In-Bewegung-seins, 216). This is the fundamental mistake: as argued above, Gfivapis and i v i p y E i a are not ways of being in motion42 and therefore a fortiori certainly cannot be interpreted in terms of producing and being-produced.

    Aristotle himself makes this clear when at the very beginning of Metaphysics 0 he tells us that, while he will begin with the most common sense of 6irvavis, which is 6fivapiS in relation to motion, this sense is not what he needs for his present aim (oir piv xpqo ipq y i o ~ i mpbs 6 pouh6pEBa v h , 1045b36-1046a1). Why? Because Gfivavis and i v i p y E i a go beyond, o r are more than ( h i ~ l h i o v ) , the GirvapiS and i v i p y E i a said according to motion ( K a T a ~ i v q o i v , 1046a1-2). Predictably, Heideggers reading of this passage does everything possible to reinstate motion as the essential and unsurpassable guiding perspective, despite what Aristotle says. Thus Heidegger asserts: When accordingly in our treatise the theme of investigation should become 6irvapis and i v i p y e i a h i mhiov this does not rule out that ~ i v q o i s nevertheless remains in view; on the contrary: i t must remain in view, but not K a T a ~ i v q o i v (54). Therefore Heidegger resorts to the extraordinary expedient, grounded on nothing in the text, of characterizing 6irvapiS and iv ipyEia i d I T ~ ~ O V as KaTa K I V ~ ~ E O S , that is, he simply changes the accusa- tive to the genitive and thus retains motion as the determining perspective for even 6irvapis and iv ipyEia h i ~ r h i o v (53). This opens the door to characterizing later in the course the 66vapiS ,and iv ipyEia that go beyond what is said according to motion .as nevertheless ways of motion and moments of production, in flagrant contradiction to what Aristotle himself claims to U ~ a n t . 4 3 In short, what we see in the 1931 course is a n un- warranted and violent reduction not only of i v i p y E i a and

    553

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    iv-rEhiXEia, but now also of Girvapis, to a conception of being as presence and being-produced which, judging from all the evidence, is not Aristotles, but Heidegger~.~~

    3.

    The interpretation of ivipyEia and ivTEhiXEia in the 1939 essay, Vom Wesen und Begriff der Q)iro~s, departs from the earlier interpretations of 1924 and 1931 in no longer making a sharp distinction between the two concepts. Is this because Heidegger is now closer to understanding them both together as a kind of activity or act distinct both from motion and from what is produced, at-an-end, completed? That this is not the case is evident from the fact that his characterization of iv-rEAiXEia has not changed: i t is still Sich-im-Ende-Haben (354). What has happened is only that iv ipyEia has now been brought into line with this interpretation, being no longer interpreted as being- at-work (In-Arbei t -Sein or Am- Werke-Sein) but rather as standing-in-the-work: Im-Werk-Stehen; das Werk als das, was voll im Ende steht, where das Werk is also understood in the sense of what is to be produced and is produced [im Sinne des Herzustellenden und Her-gestellten] (354). We thus see that nothing essential has changed in Heideggers interpre- tation: we have the same interpretation of i v i p y E i a and ivTEhiXEia in terms of production (Herstellen) and thus the same ignoring of the fundamental distinction between kvipyeia and K ~ V ~ O I S ; the only change is that now both i v i p y E i a and iv-rEhiXEia are identified with the product, the result, the end or completion of this process of production. In other words, the only change is an even greater eclipse of i v i p y E i a as

    In an important passage of the Nicomachean Ethics , Aristotle asserts in no ambiguous terms: It is evident that i v i p y E i a becomes [ y i v ~ ~ a i l and is not a t hand like some possession [oirx ir-rrapx~i Bo.r r~p ~ ~ i j p 6 TI] (NE 1169b29-30). It is as if Aristotle were here anticipating Heideggers misinter- pretation and objecting to it. While Aristotle insists that i v i p y E i a is activity, even a t the cost of giving the equally erroneous impression that it is becoming in the sense in which motion is, Heidegger is determined to reduce its way of being to that of something produced and possessed.

    We can therefore expect that the interpretation Heidegger proceeds to give of Aristotles definition of motion in the 1939 essay, like the account he initially gave in the SS 1924 course, will turn it into a definition of rest. This is indeed not only what happens, but Heidegger makes this consequence of his interpre- tation quite explicit. So many momentous and questionable moves take place in his brief interpretation of 1939 that , without the preparation provided by a reading of the SS 1924

    554

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    course discussed above, it must leave one completely bewildered. Consider first his translation of Aristotles definition of motion :as stated at Physics 201134-5: The having-itself-in-its-end [Das 1Sich-im-Ende-Habenl by that which is apt [geeignetl insofar as i t is ap t ( tha t is, in i t s aptness) is clearly ( the essence of) rnovedness [Bewegtheitl (355). The obvious objection to this translatiodinterpretation is that an ability that has reached its end, that has itself in its end, is no longer in motion, but rather i3t rest. The unprepared reader must assume tha t Heidegger cannot possibly mean what he says. How could he be defining motion as an abilitys fulfillment in i ts final end o r product when this would instead be the end (in both senses of the word) of motion?

    That this, however, is exactly what Heidegger is doing is shown not only by the preceding interpretation of iv ipyaa cited above, but by the example with which he grounds and prepares his interpretation of Aristotles definition of motion.

    The transformation [Umschlagenl of the apt wood into a table consists in this: that the aptness of the apt emerges more and more fully, fulfilling itself in the look [Aussehen] of the table and thus coming to a stand in the table produced, i.e., brought-into- the-unconcealed. In the resting of this stand (of what has come to a s tand) the emerging aptness (63vavis ) of the apt ( 6 u v a ~ ~ i ) gathers and has itself as in its end. (355)

    It is thus clear that Heidegger means exactly what one other- wise would think he could not mean: t ha t what Aristotles definition of motion is describing is how the apt or capable has-itself-as-in-its-end in the sense of having-come-to-a-stand und being-at-rest in what is produced. But this is not motion. As Aristotle insists, motion, far from standing-at-its-end, is essentially ~ T E A ~ s .

    Indeed, but this is why Heidegger is careful to remove motion as the object of Aristotles definition; on his interpretation1 paraphrase, what is being defined is not motion, but movedness. On the preceding page Heidegger has distinguished between motion (Bewegung) and movedness (Bewegtheit), characterizing the la t ter as the essence (Wesen) of the former (354). Heideggers paraphrase removes Aristotles definition even further from the sphere of motion by making its object not only movedness, but the essence of movedness. Of course, the essence of motion, and a fortiori the essence of the essence of motion, is not motion. Indeed, Heidegger argues, the essence of motion, movedness in the highest and most genuine sense, is rest (Ruhigkeit, 354). And it is precisely this rest, as the essence olf movedness, that Aristotles ostensible definition of motion is dlefining. Therefore, when Heidegger does mention the kind of K ~ V ~ O I S tha t is ~ T E A ~ S and tha t is distinct from rest , he

    555

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    describes it as a narrower sense of K ~ V T ~ I S , that is, narrower than, and distinct from, the K ~ V ~ O I S defined by Aristotle a t 201b4.

    This interpretation of Aristotles definition is, unfortunately for Heidegger and fortunately for the future of philosophy, completely untenable. The motion that Aristotles definition attempts to define is beyond question the motion that is ~ I T E A ~ s and that is distinct from rest. To show this one need only cite a passage which has already been partly quoted above; it is also a passage out of which Heidegger in the 1939 text cites only one sentence, since citing the context would spell disaster for his interpretation. The passage reads:

    Its appearing indefinite [ ~ ~ ~ I O T O V ] is the reason why motion can be classed among beings neither as GirvaHiS nor as ivfpyEia. For nei ther t ha t which is capable of being of a certain quant i ty [rroaov] nor tha t which is in actuality of a certain quantity is necessarily moved. And K ~ V T ~ C S I ~ seems on the one hand to be a kind of ivfpyEia and on the other to be ~ T E A I ~ ~ ; the cause of its being ~ T E A I ~ ~ is the capable of which it is the ivCpyEia. And this is the reason why i t is hard t o grasp what motion is .... What remains is the way suggested above, i.e., that it [motion] is a kind of i v f p y a a , but the kind we said it was [i.e., the ivipyEia of what is capable qua capable], one indeed hard to see, but nevertheless capable of being. (Phys. 201b27-202a3)

    This passage makes clear that the aim of Aristotles definition of K ~ V Q O I S is precisely to explain i ts ~ I T E A ~ ~ and indefinite character, that is, that which prevents i t from being defined either as simply GirvapiS or as simply 6vipyEia. This problem is of course left completely unresolved if Aristotles definition is interpreted as being a definition not of ~ I T E A ~ s K ~ V ~ O I S at all, but rather of a rest and standing-in-the-end that are supposed to be the essence of motion.

    Why does Heidegger misinterpret Aristotles definition of ~ I T E A ~ ~ K ~ V ~ O I S as a definition of rest in the sense of having- come-to-a-stand-in-the-work (or product)? He must do so because only a t this price can his characterizations of ivTEAiXEia as das Sich-im-Ende-Haben and of 6vipyEia as Im- WerkStehen be upheld. In other words, only at this price can he persist in denying 6vipyEia and iv-rEAiXEia the meaning of act or activity as distinct from K ~ V I - ~ I S . And note the significant lesson here: it is precisely the failure t o distinguish i v ipyEia and 6vTEhiXEia from K ~ V ~ O I S and the product of K ~ V ~ O I S that renders K ~ V Q O I S undefinable and inexplicable. But there is a further question: why does Heidegger persist in his funda- mentally inadequate interpretation of ivipyEia and ivTEAiXEia? The answer has already become apparent: only in this way can Heidegger maintain his thesis that for the Greeks being meant

    556

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    producedness (Hergestelltheit) and presence. And it is indeed this thesis that Heidegger pulls out of his interpretation of the definition of motion, in a move that has become as stale and as predictable as the trick of pulling a rabbit out of a hat: The having-itself-in-its-end (ivTEhiXEia) is, however, the essence of movedness (that is, the being of what is moved) because this rest [Ruhigkeit] satisfies most purely the essence of oGcsia, of the self-standing presencing in the look [der in sich standigen Anwesung im Aussehen] (356) . Because Aristotle must a priori have had a conception of being a s visible presence (Aussehen) , the object of Aristotles definition must be transformed from ~ X T E ~ T ~ S K ~ V T J O I S into rest46 and from some- thing hard to see into a stable and unchanging object of vision.47 But tha t this thesis regarding the Greek interpre- tation of Being can once again be maintained only a t the cost of misinterpretation and even inversion of what Aristotle says should be sufficient reason to reject it once and for all in favor of liberating the very different direction in which the texts can guide our thinking.

    Heidegger could still be correct in maintaining that ordinary Greeks had an interpretation of being as constant presence born of the anxiety that what is would cease to be present (see GA 18, 289-90, 297, 367; also 353). Since this fear, however, can probably with equal justice be attributed to the ancient Egyptians and Chinese, as well as modern day Americans and Russians, rather than speak of a metaphysics of presence as a historical phenomenon beginning with the Greeks, we should probably instead see such a metaphysics as characterizing any immediate, unreflective experience of the world: a fear of insecurity and instability that leads to an identification of what is with what is had in such a way that it cannot be taken away, .what is possessed securely. In contrast, i t may belong to the essence of all philosophy, including tha t of the Greeks, to destroy this security and challenge all naive metaphysics of ,presence, to expose the indeterminate, potential, and kinetic character of being. I t is perhaps only in the modern period that ]philosophy ceases t o do that, and then because its essence is determined from without itself, t ha t is, by mathematical science. But whatever interpretation we wish to put in its place, the conclusion remains tha t Heideggers interpretation of ,4ristotle cannot stand.

    This critique in no way means to deny the great importance of Heidegger for an understanding of the Greeks: in carrying out a continuous and intense dialogue with the Greeks, IHeidegger has enabled them to speak to us to today with extra- ordinary power, relevance, and immediacy. Through Heidegger we learn to engage the Greek thinkers, not with the self-com- placency of the historian who charts their primitive antici- pations of contemporary wisdom, but rather with the respect

    557

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    of philosophers convinced t h a t we can never escape the immense shadow of the Greek beginning and that philosophy can have no future outside of a constant dialogue with this beginning. Yet it is no denial of this debt owed Heidegger to suggest tha t some, and perhaps the most important, possi- bilities for future thought locked in the ancient Greek texts can be liberated only against Heidegger; on the contrary, those who simply repeat Heideggers reading of the Greeks are doing both Heidegger and the Greeks the greatest disservice. Since Heideggers interpretation of the Greeks is inseparable from his own path of thinking, we must ask if his misinterpretation of Aristotles fundamental concepts turned him aside too soon from a barely explored road at the beginning of the metaphysi- cal tradition. What possibilities were missed in Heideggers insistent reduction of the Greek conception of being to presence, a reduction that required interpreting Greek ontology from the perspective of noiqois, instead of from the perspective of np&E,is and ivkpyEia? What is lost in reducing K ~ V ~ C S I S to rest, in failing to preserve its ontological distinctness in contrast to rest?48 The present critique of Heideggers reading of Aristotle gives a special urgency to a question posed by Paul Ricceur: One can in the end ask oneself if Heidegger perceived the hidden resources of a philosophy of being that would replace the transcendental of substance with that of act, as a phenom- enology of acting and suffering demands.49 I t is difficult at this point to resist the conclusion that this is precisely what Heidegger failed to perceive.50

    Notes

    Cited i n Dominique Jan icaud , Heidegger en France 1. Recit (Paris: Albin Michel, 20011, 470-1.

    Confronting Heidegger on Logos and Being in Platos Sophist, in Platon und Aristoteles - sub ratione veritatis: Festschrift fur Wolfgang Wieland zum 70. Geburtstag, ed. by Gregor Damschen, Rainer Enskat, and Alejandro G. Vigo (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, 20031,

    Gesamtausgabe 18 (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 2002); hereafter, cited in t h e text a s G A 18, followed by t h e page number.

    Gesamtausgabe 33, 2nd ed. ( F r a n k f u r t a m Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1990); hereafter, cited in the text as GA 33, followed by the page number.

    Wegmarken (Frankfurt a m Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 19671,

    A discussion of these texts , with t h e exception of t h e 1924 course then unavailable, is to be found in Franco Volpi, Heidegger e Aristotele (Padova: Daphne Editrice, 1984), 172-203. Volpis quick run-through, however, goes little beyond paraphrase and quotation a n d cer ta inly makes no a t t e m p t to judge crit ically Heideggers interpretations.

    102-33.

    309-71.

    558

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    Heidegger is reported in the Brocker Nachschrift of the SS 1926 course, Die Grundbegriffe der antiken Philosophie, as saying: Die ivipyEia stellt die hochste Art des Seins dar, die der oiraia zukommt (Gesamtausgabe 22 [Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 19931, 331; hereafter, cited in the text as G A 22, followed by the page number). Jean Beaufret attributes to Heidegger a t Cerisy in 1955 the claim tha t i v i p y E i a is la plus haute nomination de l&tre quait jamais Osee la philosophie des Anciens (Dialogue auec Heidegger - Philosophie Grecque [Paris: gditions de Minuit, 19731, 120).

    See also Ruhe konstitutiv fur dieses Da, d.h. Bedeutsamkeit (380); and 387 where Heidegger calls rest uneigentliche Bewegung because it conceals the T I P ~ T E ~ O V - G O T E ~ O V in the Now.

    Yet Heidegger later in the course returns to a characterization of K ~ V I ~ I S as Gegenwart. In Aristotles account of motion from the perspective of ~ ~ o i r p i s and TraOrpis in Physics r 3, Heidegger finds expressed the TIP& T I character of being-in-the-world and therefore the genuine definition of K ~ V Q O I S (clearly understood again a s Bedeutsamkeit) (327). The characterization of K ~ V I ~ S that Heidegger is working towards is made clear in the Handschrift: Kivqoir die Gegenwart des Seienden, das ist in dem genannten Mitdasein des einen zum anderen (392). Heidegger therefore now paraphrases Aristotles first definition of motion thus: das Gegenwartigsein eines Seienden in bestimmtem Bezug zu einem anderen, so zwar, daB das erste ist als Seinkonnendes durch das zweite (394). This para- phrase is open t o the same objection tha t was made against Heideggers initial interpretation as well as to the objections that follow.

    lo This distinction appears already suggested in the Phanomenologische Interpretationen zu Aristoteles (Anzeige der hermeneutischen Situation) of 1922: W v a p i s , das je bestimmte Verfugenkonnen uber, i v i p y a a , das in gen[uine] Verwendung Nehmen der Verfugbarkeit, und ivrEhiXEia, das verwendende in Verwahrung Halten dieser Verfugbarkeit (Gesamtausgabe 6 2 [Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 20051, 396; hereafter cited in the text as GA 62, followed by page number).

    l1 In the SS 1926 course, and again in the context of the account of motion, Heidegger defends the definition of i v i p y E i a as Wirklichkeit ( G A 22, 172, 3221, which he interprets a s Vorhandensein als I m - Werke-Sein (173). An interesting change, however, is his occasional translation of i v i p y a a as Zuhandenheit, so that the definition of motion can be stated as: Zuhandenheit des Bereiten in seiner Bereitheit (173). However, since he can a t the same time interpret the definition as Anwesenheit des Vorhandenen in seiner Bereitheit und hinsichtlich dieser (1741, Zuhandenheit is clearly being treated as a mode of Anwesenheit and Vorhandenheit (see also 320-21). Walter Brocker, on whose Nachschriften of the SS 1924 and SS 1926 courses the Gesamtausgabe editions of these courses partly rely, betrays the influence of Heidegger in his own book on Aristotle when, in explaining the account of motion, he .writes: Aber wirklich, gegenwartig anwesend [my emphasis], i s t nicht nur das Rotsein des Seienden, sondern wirklich ist auch das Anders-Sein-Konnen des Seienden. Dies Seinkonnen dessen, was das ISeiende j e gerade nicht ist, gehort mit zu dem was es j e gerade wirklich is t (Ar is to te les , 3rd. ed. [Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio

    559

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    Klostermann, 19641, 80). l2 Heidegger can be seen making these quest ionable inter-

    pretative moves in the following texts: Vom Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit, Gesamtausgabe 3 1 (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Kloster- m a n n , 1982), 69; Die Metaphysik a l s Geschichte des Seins, i n Gesamtausgabe 6.2 (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1997), 368-9, 375; Wissenschaft und Besinnung, in Vortrage und Aufsatze, Gesamtausgabe 7 (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, ZOOO), 43-4. At t h e s t a r t of t h e Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle makes a n explicit dist inction between i v i p y E i a a n d Epyov a s one between activit ies a n d products exis t ing a p a r t from t h e act ivi t ies t h a t produce them (1094a4-5).

    l3 In t h e SS 1922 course, Phanomenologische Znterpretationen Ausgewahlter Abhandlungen des Aristoteles zur Ontologie und Logik, Heidegger identifies i v ipyEia with reinste Bewegtheit and reine Zeitigung, apparently making no distinction between i v ipyEia and ivTEhiXEia ( G A 62, 102-08). At one point Heidegger i n cit ing t h e definition of t h e soul i n De A n i m a as t h e f i rs t ivTEhiXEIa simply inser ts K I V ~ O I ~ in brackets after ~V-rEhgXEia, t h u s suggesting their equivalence (229; see also 336).

    l4 Heidegger r ight ly defends aga ins t c i rcular i ty Aristotles definition of motion as ivTEhiXEia TOG K I V ~ T O G , fi K I V ~ T O V [of what is movable insofar as it is movable] (328). B u t h e here t r a n s l a t e s hrrEAgXEia as Gegenwart, a translation that , though creating other problems, at least avoids making the definition circular. If, on the other hand, Aristotle used the word i v ipyEia instead, as Heidegger earlier claims he should to be more precise, and we were to follow Heidegger in characterizing i v i p y a a as KivqaiS, then we would have a circular definition indeed: the motion of what is capable of being moved insofar as it is capable of being moved.

    l5 The same distinction is implied by the argument in the Nico- machean Ethics that j S o v i is not a K ~ V ~ O I S (1173a31-1174b14).

    W. D. Ross comments on 201a10-11: ivTEAiXEia m u s t here mean actualization, not actuality: it is t h e passage from potentiality to actuality tha t is K ~ v I ~ ( (Aristotles Physics [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 19361, 537). But if actualization as t h e passage from potentiality to actuali ty is K ~ V ~ O I S , then this cannot be what iv-rEhiXEia means. In this case, the qualification, of what is capable insofar as capable, would be superfluous, since ivTEhiXEia would a s such be K ~ V ~ O I ~ , and the definition would be viciously circular. The problem with Rosss reading is therefore much greater t h a n t h a t Such a sense of entelecheia is ... unparalleled in Aristotle: this is the objection of Edward Hussey, who himself t ranslates actuality (Aristotles Physics Books ZZZ and ZV [Oxford: Clarendon, 19831, 60). See also RBmi Brague: Lacte qui intervient dans l a definition du mouvement est actualit6 e t non actualisation (Aristote et la question d u monde [Par is : PUF, 19881, 500), a n d Pier re Aubenque: Le mouvement est moins lactualisation de la puissance, quil nest lacte de la puissance, la puissance en tan t quacte, cest-a-dire en tan t que son acte est d6tre en puissance (Le probleme de ICtre chez Aristote [Paris: Quadrige/PUF, 20021, 454). B u t Aubenque nevertheless immediately proceeds to make the fatal mistake: Le mouvement, dit ailleurs Aristote, est un acte imparfait, iv ipyEia ~ X T E ~ ~ S , cest-u-dire dont lacte m@me est de nCtre j a m a i s tout a fai t en acte (454, my

    560

  • Whose Metaphysics of Presence?

    emphasis) . Brague, on t h e other hand , avoids th i s error: I1 lest I a ~ ~ h i r ] moins, precise ailleurs Aristote, parce quil serait lui-m6me u n acte imparfai t , que parce quil e s t lacte (e t , en tant que tel, parfait) de quelque chose dimparfait (Ame 111, 7, 431a6 s.) (502, my emphasis). Yet the error remains persistent and widespread. In a recent book we find the following: in welchem Sinne Heidegger und Gadamer energeia auffassen: als Sein, das nur im Werden sein Sein h a t . [This is more Gadamer t h a n Heidegger] Hingegen mein t tinergeia bei Aristoteles Werden zum Sein, genesis eis on (Thomas Gutschker, Aristotelische Diskurse: Aristoteles in der politischen Philosophie des 20. Jahrhundert [Stuttgart: J . B. Metzler, 20021, 222).

    l7 At Rhet. 1412a9 Aristotle does describe CvipyEia as a ~ i v ~ p i s , b u t i n t h e context Aristotle is clearly not using t h e word i n its strictest sense. The passage therefore does not support W. D. Rosss conclusion tha t K ~ V I - ~ I S and CvipyEia are species of something wider for which Aristotle h a s no name, and for which he uses now t h e n a m e of one species, and now t h a t of t h e o ther (Aristotles Metaphysics, vol. 2 [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 19241, 251).

    Ross, Aristotles Metaphysics, vol. 2, 248. l9 In this passage the definition of motion includes both terms:

    whenever something Cv-reAEXeia dv i v ~ p y f l not insofar as it is itself but insofar as it is movable, that is motion.

    2o Heidegger presumably found support for his interpretation in Hermann Bonitzs 1849 commentary on the Metaphysics. Bonitz also finds at 1048a30 and 1050a21-23 a distinction between ivipyEia and iVTEh6XEIa, claiming tha t while the two are very closely related and therefore often not dis t inguished, nevertheless t h e former most properly signifies viam while t h e la te r most properly signifies finem viae (Metaphysicu Commenturius [Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 3.9601, 387-88). Yet Bonitz can maintain such a distinction only by making the same mistake Heidegger makes: collapsing the distinc- tion between CvipyEia and Kivrpis. Thus he sees ivEpyEiv as signifying eam actionem e t mutat ionem, qua qui ex mera possibil i tate a d plenam perducitur essentiam (387). This is obviously a definition of ~ i v q a i ~ and not of iv ipyeia. Yet this insistence on a sharp distinction between iv6pyEia and hrrEhfXEia and the mistake it presupposes have undoubtedly a n impressive pedigree since they can be traced back at least to Simplicius. After reporting t h a t Alexander, Porphyry and Themistios converted evfpyeia into iv-rEhixEia in t h e definition of motion, as if they were the same for Aristotle (Simplicii in Aristotelis Ihysicorum libros quattuor priores commentaria, ed. H. Diels [Berlin: 18821, 414, 20-211, Simplicius objects t h a t if Aristotle does some- times use the word ~vTEh&Eia for ivipyEia, he does not mean just any kvipyEia but only the complete kind (TEhEia). The name ivTEhiXeia signifies TGV TOG ~ v T E ) \ o ~ ~ . s auviXEiav (414, 37), so t h a t it cannot properly be applied to the incomplete iv6pyEia tha t Simplicius sees a s characterizing motion. Simplicius thus insists on reading the word CvipyEia in the defintion of motion at 201a9-11: Motion being of the incomplete, however, it is not i n vain t h a t he [Aristotle] directly called it iv ipyeia and not CvTeAiXeia (414, 28-9). Behind this distinc- t ion is t h e same er ror made by t h e contemporary commentators criticized above (note 16): against Porphyrys suggestion tha t ~ i v ~ p i ~ is a n CVTEhiXEia ~ I T E ~ ~ S and a n CvipyEia TEhEia, Simplicius objects: But if it is the CvipyEia of what exists potentially (TOO WvaMEi) and

    56 1

  • Francisco J. Gonzalez

    what exists potentially is incomplete ( h ~ ~ h f s ) , then how could the kvipyEia of something incomplete (TOG ~ T E A o G ) be a complete ivfpyEia

    21 I show elsewhere how Heideggers interpretation of Aristotles account of the good in this course assimilates np&Ci< to noiqois: see my Without Good and Evil: Heideggers Purification of Aristotles Ethics, in Heidegger and the Greeks: Interpretative Essays , ed. by Drew A. Hyland a n d J o h n Panteleimon Manoussakis ( Indiana University Press, 2006), 127-56. Especially significant here is t h e following passage in which Heidegger, asserting tha t noiqoi~ is the resource for t h e quest ion What is being?, does not dis t inguish between noiqois a n d np&Cis: Die Frage nach dem ~i ~b dv ist geschopft aus den Bestimmungen der noiqai~ und des Gegenwurtig- Daseins-noiqois als primare In-der-Welt-Sein, IT~&,IS (GA 18, 329). Robert Bernasconi has observed tha t Heidegger focuses explicitly on praxis only rarely and his sights a re clearly set on poiesis. Futher- more, t h i s is not always t h e broad conception of po ies i s which includes praxis ... (The Fate of the Distinction between Praxis and Poiesis, in Heidegger in Question: The Art of Existing [New Jersey: Humani t ies Press , 19931, 12). If Heidegger does not sharp ly dis t inguish prax i s from po ies i s , t h i s is because, according to Bernasconi, the characterization of praxis in terms of its distinction from poiesis still amounts to a technical interpretation of praxis (21; see also 22). Yet Aristotles definition of motion shows, I suggest, t h a t h e understands poiesislkinesis in the light of energeia lpraxis rather than vice versa. Bernasconi sees at Nic. Eth. VI ii 5 , 1139a35- b4 a characterization of praxis a s t h e goal of poies i s , a character- ization which he sees as subordinating praxis to poiesis (8). But this passage can be in te rpre ted wi th at leas t equal plausibi l i ty as showing t h a t Aristotle interprets making from t h e perspective of praxis as an unfulfilled praxis.

    22 See Paul Ricceur, Negativite e t affirmation originaire, i n Aspects de la dialectique (Paris: Desclee de Brouwer, 19561, 101-24; and Soi-m&me comme un autre (Paris: fiditions de Seuil, 1990), 364. In t h e former important essay, af ter a cri t ique of modern philos- ophies t h a t privilege negation and the nothing, like t h a t of Sar t re , for presupposing a limited and impoverished conception of being a s thinghood and essence (120), Riccleur concludes: Sous la pression du negatif, des experiences en negatif, nous avons a reconquerir une notion de letre qui soit acte plutBt que forme, affirmation vivante, puissance dexister e t de fa i re exis ter (124) . See Dominique Janicauds description of Ricceur as proposing une ontologie de lagir qui a pour fin le bien vivre au sens dhri