Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

download Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

of 150

Transcript of Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    1/150

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    2/150

    H E G E L S A B S O L U T E

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    3/150

    SUNY series in Hegelian StudiesWilliam Desmond, editor

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    4/150

    H E G E L S A B S O L U T E

    An Introduction to Reading the

    Phenomenology of Spirit

    Donald Phillip Verene

    State University of New York Press

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    5/150

    Published byState University of New York Press, Albany

    2007 State University of New York

    All rights reserved

    Printed in the United States of America

    No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoeverwithout written permission. No part of this book may be stored in aretrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means includingelectronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying,recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of thepublisher.

    For information, address State University of New York Press,194 Washington Avenue, Suite 305, Albany, NY 12210-2384

    Production by Diane GanelesMarketing by Anne M. Valentine

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    Verene, Donald Phillip, 1937Hegel's absolute : an introduction to reading The phenomenology of

    spirit / Donald Phillip Verene.p. cm. (SUNY series in Hegelian studies)

    Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index.ISBN-13: 978-0-7914-6963-7 (hardcover : alk. paper)

    ISBN-13: 978-0-7914-6964-4 (pbk. : alk. paper)1. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 17701831. Phnomenologie desGeistes. 2. Spirit. 3. Consciousness. 4. Truth. 5. Phenomenology. I. Title.II. Series.

    B2929.V46 2007193dc22

    2006003850

    10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    6/150

    A quite special, though purely negativescience, general phenomenology(phaenomenologia generalis), seems to bepresupposed by metaphysics.

    Kant to Lambert, September 2, 1770

    Hegel had the stuff of one of the greatesthumorists among philosophers; Socratesis the only other one who had a similarmethod.

    Bertolt Brecht, Flchtlingsgesprche, 1941

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    7/150

    This page intentionally left blank.

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    8/150

    Preface ix

    1. Hegels Preface: Reflection versus Speculation 1

    2. Hegels Introduction: The Double Ansich 13

    3. Hegels Reason: A Digression 25

    4. Hegels System: Dialectic of Andness 31

    5. The Beginning of the Phenomenology 41

    6. Force, Understanding, and the Inverted World 49

    7. Self-Consciousness of Masterhood and Servitude 55

    8. Unhappy Consciousness 63

    9. On Reading the Second Half of thePhenomenology: An Overview of Reason and Spirit 71

    10. Absolute Knowing 91

    Appendix. Hegels Terminology 99

    Works Cited 123

    Index 129

    vii

    Contents

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    9/150

    This page intentionally left blank.

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    10/150

    Hegels texts make unusual demands on the reader. This is espe-cially true of the Phenomenology of Spirit, commonly regardedas the most difficult text in the history of philosophy. WhatHegel intends cannot be presented as a summary of the resultsof his investigations. The course of spirits development in all itsforms is re-created as a whole in Hegels exposition, and this fullpath must be traveled by the reader. Hegel says: The length ofthis path has to be endured, because, for one thing, eachmoment is necessary; and further, each moment has to be lin-geredover, because each is itself a complete individual shape,and one is only viewed in absolute perspective when its deter-minateness is regarded as a concrete whole, or the whole isregarded as uniquely qualified by that determination (par. 29).

    Spirit has had the patience to pass through these shapesover the long passage of time, and to take upon itself the enor-mous labour of world-history (ibid.). Hegel has had thepatience to bring these shapes together in his book and thereader must have the patience to comprehend them page bypage. It is not sufficient for the reader to study the text from anexternal point of view. One must make its science for oneself.Hegel says: What, therefore, is important in the study of sci-ence, is that one should take on oneself the strenuous effort of

    the notion [Begriff] (par. 58). The reader must strive not sim-ply to pass from one shape of spirit to the next but to aim toknow each one, to think through each one, in the manner ofthe Begriffand grasp the process as a whole. This requires thereader to acquire the mentality of speculative philosophy.

    The greatest stumbling block to comprehending Hegelswork and studying his science is propensity to argumentation(raisonnement). Hegel says: Such reasoning adopts a negative

    ix

    Preface

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    11/150

    attitude towards the content it apprehends; it knows how torefute it and destroy it. That something is not the case, is amerely negative insight, a dead end which does not lead to anew content beyond itself (par. 59). Argumentation has thefurther problem of the passivity of the subject. The passive sub-ject or self that is at the center of argumentation has no essen-tial connection to the object of thought and can offer noadvance in knowing. In speculative thinking the subject isactively engaged in altering itself in relation to the object. Whatit thinks alters what it is. Philosophical texts that portray thisself-altering process of knowing, rather than just offering argu-

    ments or reflections of common sense, try the readers ability tothe limit.

    Hegel says: This abnormal inhibition of thought is inlarge measure the source of the complaints regarding the unin-telligibility of philosophical writings from individuals who oth-erwise possess the educational requirements for understandingthem. Here we see the reason behind one particular complaintso often made against them: that so much has to be read overand over before it can be understooda complaint whose bur-

    den is presumed to be quite outrageous, and, if justified, toadmit of no defence (par. 63). The reading of a philosophicalwork is never in principle a single act. Philosophical reading isa repetitive act. Hegel says, further: We learn by experiencethat we meant something other than we meant to mean; and thiscorrection of our meaning compels our knowing to go back tothe proposition, and understand it in some other way (ibid.).

    What might be added to Hegels advice of a practicalnature for the reader who is to begin the reading of the Phe-nomenology? I have three suggestions: the first derives fromprinciples of rhetoric, the second from Hegels conception oflanguage, and the third from what I believe to be the generalnature of philosophical texts.

    1. Each section of the work should be read three times:first to grasp the meaning of the section as a whole, second tograsp the transitions from point to point within its thought, andthird to grasp the particular phrases or modes of expressionused to make its central ideas comprehensible and memorable.

    x Preface

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    12/150

    These three readings correspond to the three classicalprinciples of composition in rhetoric as found in the Romantextbook on rhetoric of Quintilian: inventio, the discovery ofmaterials; dispositio, their arrangement; elocutio, their formu-lation in language (III.3). Any work is composed in this way,whether or not its author is conscious of these principles. Theyare natural aspects of composition. No work can be completethat does not have these elements. Thus any work can be readso as to grasp each of them as a level within it. A readerapproaching a work in this manner will come away from itwith a good comprehension of its contents. This does not

    mean, as Hegel points out, that one does not need to go backmany times to an important philosophical work. Philosophicalworks are like songs; their meaning is revealed in repetition.They must be heard over and over again.

    2. Hegels language has been thought to be dense, obscure,and full of special terms. Hegel wrote to Johann Heinrich Voss(May 1805) that Voss had made Homer speak German, Mar-tin Luther had made the Bible, and now he, Hegel, intended tomake philosophy speak German. Immanuel Kant writes a

    Latinized German. Hegel intends to write in German the wayDante chose to write in Florentine Italian instead of Latin.None of Hegels famous termsGeist, aufheben, Begriffis atechnical term. They all are words of ordinary German. Someof them happen to be terms deeply grounded in the Weltan-schauung of the German language and cannot be easily ren-dered into English.

    There is a decision every philosophy must make: whetherto ground its basic concepts in terms of its own invention or toextract its meanings from common speech. The father of thosephilosophers who chose the latter is Socrates, who speaks thelanguage of the agora and who is accused of using the languageof tradesmen and craftsmen. Hegels approach to philosophicalspeech is Socratic. Like Socrates, he takes words of ordinarylanguage and begins to press their meanings toward furthermeanings by developing them into new contexts, all the whileusing the words any German speaker knows. How Hegelaccomplishes this transformation of meanings can be seen by

    xiPreface

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    13/150

    consulting the remarks on Hegels terms in the appendix. Hegelalways speaks in the agora, although what he is speakingabout, as he says, will cause common sense to walk on its head.

    3. Hegel, like most great philosophers, says everythingthree ways. First he will make a point in purely intellectual ordiscursive terms, perhaps using terms such as in-itself andfor-itself, or assertions such as Substance becomes Sub-ject. Second, he will often use a common-sense example oranalogy, such as saying that zoology is not the same as all ani-mals. Third, he will use metaphor and irony, such as thenight in which all cows are black, the Bacchanalian revel,

    or the Golgotha of the Spirit. His modes of expression willpass back and forth among discursive, commonsensical, andtropic.

    In his Autobiography R. G. Collingwood says that philos-ophy is essentially questions and answers. Hans-GeorgGadamer in Truth and Method is one of the few who havenoticed the importance of Collingwoods observation. Colling-wood was a Hegelian thinker, and the emphasis on a dialecticof questions and answers over and against argumentation fits

    well with Hegels view of argumentation as an obstacle toachieving speculative thinking. A question always requires astarting point. The archai in Hegels text are always expressedin images: the image of the master-servant, the inverted world,the unhappy consciousness, the beautiful soul, and so forth.Any philosophical text depends upon images; they are alwayspresent. The reader can look first not for arguments in thework but for these root images. Once found, the reader canlook for the questions that can be drawn forth from the images.The reader will then see how the image is directing and pro-viding support for the question, which carries the reasoningprocess of the text forward. What are the images? What are thequestions embedded in them?

    The aim of this introduction is not to make a series ofsummaries of all the parts of the Phenomenology but to offerthe reader a way to approach parts A and B of Hegels workhis doctrine of consciousness and self-consciousness. My thesisis that once the dialectic of these two primary parts of Hegels

    xii Preface

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    14/150

    work is grasped, nothing of what Hegel says, at least in princi-ple, is closed to the reader. In his preface, introduction, andparts A and B of the work, Hegel brings forth the essentials ofhis whole form of thought.

    This method of approaching Hegels work is supple-mented in chapters 9 and 10, by an overview of Hegels stagesof reason and spirit, and by a view of the dialectic between reli-gion and absolute knowing that occurs at the end of the Phe-nomenology. The reader may find these last two chapters use-ful, as they offer a place to stand when taking on the oftencomplicated details of the second half of the work. They

    offer a way to keep the forest in sight while confronting thetrees of each of Hegels stages.

    My remarks on the various features of the Phenomenol-ogy constitute a point of view that I believe brings out the orig-inality of Hegel. My aim is not Hegel made simple. Thereader may not agree with all that is said, nor, in the interest ofthe pursuit of philosophy, do I think that the reader shouldagree, but it is a place to stand from which the inner form ofHegels thought may be seen. I have not attempted to conceal

    my own eccentricities in regard to how I see Hegels originality.What follows differs from what is to be found in encyclopediaarticles, standard commentaries, and textbook chapters onHegel. This work is directed to the advanced or intermediatereader of philosophy who has some understanding of Kant,and to the professional philosopher who has interest in therevival of speculative philosophy. I also believe that much ofwhat is said in these chapters may be useful to any reader whohas decided to attempt the colossus of Hegel. To my mind, thegreatest interpreter of Hegel in our time was John Findlay. Inconversation and in his writings, he, more than anyone else,captured not only the sense but the spirit of Hegel. The readerwould benefit from any of his works.

    These chapters extend and restate some of the views of myHegels Recollection (1985), but what I say is specificallydirected to the problem of reading the Phenomenology. Read-ers who wish fuller discussions of such issues as Hegels dou-bling of the in-itself, the logic of the inverted world, or the

    xiiiPreface

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    15/150

    importance of Hegels criticism of phrenology, may wish toconsult the earlier work. The chapters that follow exhibit myconviction that the two central principles of Hegels philosophyare recollection (Erinnerung) and speculation. Hegel identifiesthem with reason (Vernunft). To comprehend these two princi-ples is to comprehend the Hegelian point of view.

    Quotations from Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit arefrom A. V. Millers translation, occasionally modified by mytranslation, and cited by Millers paragraph enumeration.Millers translation is at present the most-read English edition ofthe Phenomenology. The earlier translation by J. B. Baillie is

    often less accurate to the original, but Baillies renderings ofHegels metaphors and key phrases generally achieve a higherEnglish and they are more memorable than Millers. The readerof the Phenomenology in English may wish to consult both. Fullbibliographic references for these translations and for all otherworks that appear in the text are in the list of works cited.

    The first draft of this work was written in May 1996, onthe terrace of the villa of my long-time friend Marco Olivetti,at Lavinio, the ancient Lavinium, on the Italian coast near

    Rome, where Aeneas is said to have landed. I thank ProfessorOlivetti of the philosophy faculty of the University of RomeLa Sapienza for his generosity as host, and the University ofRome for the generosity of my appointment as research fellowwhile I was writing this work. The connection with Aeneas isapt, for Hegels work is a journey in which spirit enters its ownunderworld, its own highway of despair. As the reader trav-els from one illusory stage of consciousness to another, inspect-ing the shades of spirit, the reader realizes that the journey isone of self-knowledge. The golden bough that Hegel offers thereader to exit this underworld is the absolute that will emergeat the end of the journey with the realization that the readerhas possessed it all along; hence the title of this book.

    I am grateful to the several generations of graduate andadvanced undergraduate students on whom I have tried outthese ideas of how to read Hegel. I have benefited much fromtheir responses to versions of these chapters. As always, I amgrateful to Molly Black Verene for transcribing these chapters

    xiv Preface

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    16/150

    from my handwriting and putting the manuscript in goodorder. I thank my colleagues who have generously read andoffered comments on this work: Thora Ilin Bayer, Ann Hartle,Donald Livingston, David Lovekin, and William Willeford.Philosophy depends on friendship.

    It is a pleasure to have this work appear on the 200thanniversary of the publication of the Phenomenology of Spirit(1807).

    xvPreface

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    17/150

    This page intentionally left blank.

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    18/150

    Hegel wrote his preface to the Phenomenology after the workwas finished. It is a general statement of his system, not simply

    an opening to the Phenomenology. The preface is a whole, astatement of the nature of true philosophy that compresses inone narrative more themes than a single set of remarks can cover.The preface is Hegels phenomenology of philosophy; it treatsthe various forms of philosophizing and delineates their defects.In a sense the preface is the completion of the section on absoluteknowing. The book is itself a circle, the form Hegel attributes tothe system as a whole. A theme that runs through the center ofthe preface is Hegels criticism of reflection and the understand-ing (Verstand) as capable of producing true philosophy and hischaracterization of speculation and reason (Vernunft) as thereplacement for this inadequate form of philosophizing.

    We find two sets of images in the preface. On the firstpage Hegel speaks of anatomy as being not a true science butonly an aggregate of information (par. 1). Because it is aknowledge of only the parts of the body regarded as inanimate,we lack, in anatomy, a knowledge of the living body itself, ofits principle of life. On the second page Hegel introduces thecontrasting image of the bud of a plant producing a blossom

    that becomes a fruit. He characterizes this as an image oforganic unity (par. 2) and as representing stages of necessityin the life of the whole. He plays on the image of the dead, thecorpse (par. 3), and on the concrete richness of life (par. 4).

    Further, he compares spirit with the birth of a child and tobringing forth a new world (pars. 1113). Later, in sharp con-trast to this, he speaks oftriadic form reducing all to a lifelessschema (lebloses Schema) (par. 50). He speaks of a synoptic

    1

    C H A P T E R 1

    Hegels Preface:Reflection versus Speculation

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    19/150

    table like a skeleton with tickets stuck all over it, the flesh andblood having been stripped off. Such schematic orderings, hesays, are the products of reflection, and he says all areequally products of the lifeless understanding and external cog-nition (par. 51). He speaks of spirit being deprived of life, ofbeing flayed and then seeing its skin wrapped around a lifelessknowledge and its conceit (par. 52). In contrast to this is hisfamous image that The true is thus the Bacchanalian revel atwhich not a member is sober; yet because each member col-lapses as soon as he drops out, the revel is just as much a sceneof transparent unbroken calm (par. 47). There is no schematic

    order to the revel; it is an activity of a whole, alive within itsown limits. Hegel says that the understanding schematizes expe-rience, a table of contents is all that it offers (par. 53).

    The understanding, which proceeds through reflection onthe object, produces, in thought, a world that is dead. Allobjects are fully categorized and rendered lifeless, labeled, likeparts of a skeleton, or pigeon-holed, like boxes in a grocersstall. Reason, which proceeds speculatively, seeks out the prin-ciple of motion or life that is within the object, that makes the

    object, so to speak, what it is. Reflective understanding graspsthe body as an anatomically ordered substance. Speculativereason goes within the body to its spirit to grasp its principle asa living subject. The images Hegel is using fix for us the archaiof the question he is asking. What is this question?

    The answer to this lies principally with Kant, with tran-scendental philosophy and critique. In his effort to answerDavid Hume and to secure, for the understanding, its own cat-egories of experience, not derived from the senses, Kant forceshimself to abandon reason. This causes Kant to formulate a verylimited notion of experience, in which reason plays no role inthe constitution of the object. Once one enters the world of cri-tique there is no way out, no way to restore reason to its right-ful place. Reason is sacrificed to reflection and to the trap of thetranscendental. Even as Kant tries to loosen the bonds of cri-tique, in the Third Critique, and include aesthetic and organicnatural form within his system, he finds he cannot make theideas that govern reason constitutive of the being of the object.

    2 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    20/150

    The Third Critique may show us Kant at his most attrac-tive moment, but he still finds himself and his fellow workerbound to the Caucasus of critique. Kant finds he cannot escapefrom the island, that in the First Critique he says is the pureunderstanding, enclosed by nature itself within unalterablelimits. It is a land of truthenchanting name!surrounded bya wide and stormy ocean, the native home of illusion, wheremany a fog bank and many a swiftly melting iceberg give thedeceptive appearance of farther shores, deluding the adventur-ous seafarer ever anew with empty hopes, and engaging him inenterprises which he never can abandon and yet is unable to

    carry to completion (A23536; B29495). Kants warningabout reason echoes Ren Descartes warning in the Discourseon Methodto those who would listen to fictitious narratives.They are liable, Descartes says, to fall into the excesses of theknights-errant in our tales of chivalry, and to conceive plansbeyond their powers (pt. 1). To seek the realm of reason is toseek the Abenteuer of deluded seafarers or the extravagance ofpaladins tilting at windmills in philosophy, engaging in fictionsas if they were real life.

    Hegel singles out Kants schematism as the great flaw ofthe understanding because it is often taken as the great achieve-ment of transcendental reflection. The schematism is oftentaken to be the element in the First Critique that leads to thesympathetic treatment of organic form in the Third. Theschema is the leading example of the triadic form that is at thefoundation of Kants philosophy of critique. The problemstated in Kants famous assertion, Thoughts without conceptsare empty, intuitions without concepts are blind (A51; B75),is thought to be solved by the schema, that through which intu-itions and concepts are held together. The schema is claimed tobe the concrete form from which they are factored out. Hegelsays: Kant rediscovered this triadic form by instinct, but in hiswork it was still lifeless and uncomprehended (par. 50).

    Hegel says the formalism inherent in this manner of think-ing imagines that it has comprehended and expressed thenature and life of a form when it has endowed it with somedetermination of the schema as a predicate (ibid.). In other

    3Hegels Preface

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    21/150

    words, coming upon a problem, this way of thinking justmakes a further distinction, then considers the problem over-come. How is the concept related to the intuition? They arepart of a third thing, the schema, and like this on down the line.Hegel says: Such predicates can be multiplied to infinity, sincein this way each determination or form can again be used as aform or moment in the case of an other, and each can gratefullyperform the same service for an other. In this sort of circle ofreciprocity one never learns what the thing itself is, nor whatthe one or the other is (ibid.).

    What is Hegels question, exactly? Given the important suc-

    cess of critique, of rescuing philosophy from both rationalism andempiricism, is there any way now to rescue reason from critiqueand reestablish it in some sense similar to the ancients principleofnous and to recover a doctrine of ideas that makes them morethan sirens calling out to the philosophical seafarer from the fogbanks of illusion? Hegel, finishing the Phenomenology in 1807,having worked out the full nature of his system several years ear-lier, in Jena, could see what we often have difficulty in seeingthat Kants philosophy is the pinnacle of Enlightenment thought.

    In his doctrine of critique Kant has taken raisonnement, thatpower natural to reflection, and made its distinction-makingpower the systematic activity of the understanding. The under-standing is the creation of Descartes Discourse and John LockesEssay, which develop it in terms of the idea of reflection as thecentral activity of the mind in its act of knowing.

    In the Science of Logic, Hegel says that ancient meta-physics believed thought could achieve a true knowledge ofthings, But reflective understanding took possession of phi-losophy [Aber der reflektierende Verstand bemchtigte sich derPhilosophie]. He says the view that philosophy is essentiallyreflective has become a slogan (Schlagwort) (p. 45). Throughreflection formulated as critique we only know the object as aphenomenon, as reflected, and by transcendentally turningreflection on the knower we know the necessary conditionsunder which the phenomenal object can be known. For wemoderns, this is our secure island. The ancients, and Hegel,thought they could know more.

    4 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    22/150

    How does Hegel move from the established fact of reflec-tion to speculation? To do this he first embraces a doctrine ofthe absolute. A doctrine of the absolute means that The true isthe whole [Das Wahre ist das Ganze] (par. 20). Critique movesacross experience, not within its inner life. Since critique is adoctrine of the part, analyzing this kind of knowledge and thenthat, we never can produce the whole. To analyze a great num-ber of words will not produce a language and to analyze a greatnumber of phenomena will not produce a world. The true asthe whole is what we must begin with, and it is a circle. Spec-ulative truth is always a circle. The true, Hegel says, is the

    process of its own becoming, the circle that presupposes its endas its goal, having its end also as its beginning (par. 18).

    We cannot achieve the absolute by a formalism of the ideaany more than we can achieve it by a formalism of the schema.To relate the contents of experience to the idea externally,showing how each instance is an instance of the absolute iswhat Hegel calls a monochromatic formalism (par. 15). It isa form of thought that repeats the same formula in the sameway in relation to whatever it encounters. This way of thinking

    notices the connections among things and then passes on to theassertion that in the absolute all is one. This is an absolute inwhich A = A, or the night in which all cows are black (par.16). It is a static form of speculation because there is no prin-ciple of self-development whereby the particular determina-tions of things are comprehended as transforming themselvesinto larger and larger wholes so that the whole itself is articu-lated in terms of the particular determinations it encompasses.

    Hegel attributes this formalistic or empty absolute of pureidentity to Friedrich Schelling. He regards Schelling as havingmoved from the subjective idealism of Kant to the objectiveidealism of the absolute, but as not having overcome the for-malism inherent in reflection by so doing. The other sense ofthe absolute Hegel rejects is one he attributes to FriedrichJacobi, Novalis, and Friedrich von Schlegel. They attempt toreplace reflection with edification and enthusiasm (par. 7). Onthis view the absolute is to be reached directly by insight andintuition. It is to be not thought but felt. Hegel says: For the

    5Hegels Preface

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    23/150

    absolute is not supposed to be comprehended, it is to be feltand intuited; not the Begriffof the absolute, but the feeling andintuition of it, must govern what is said, and must be expressedby it (par. 6). The absolute as an object of edification is con-nected to the beautiful, the holy, the eternal, religion,and love (par. 7). Hegel says these are held out to entice usto embrace such a position.

    Transcendental reflection (see Kants First Critique, A262;B317 and A260; B316) cannot be opposed by a formalism ofthe absolute nor by its intuition through edification. It can onlybe opposed by what Kant has excluded as constitutive of the

    objectreason (Vernunft). What is the relationship of reasonto reflection? Hegel says the activity of dissolution is thepower and work of the understanding, the most astonishingand mightiest of powers, or rather the absolute power (par.32). Reason does not dissolve experience into its elements.Hegel says: Reason is purposive activity (par. 22). Theunderstandings uses of reflection, which are directed solely tothe object with the subject simply attached as the I think, isthe opposite of reason. Properly used, reflection is part of the

    true and part of reason. Hegel says: Reason is, therefore, mis-understood when reflection is excluded from the true, and isnot grasped as a positive moment of the absolute. It is reflec-tion that makes the true a result, but it is equally reflection thatovercomes the antithesis between the process of its becomingand the result, for this becoming is also simple, and thereforenot different from the form of the true which shows itself assimple in its result; the process of becoming is rather just thisreturn into simplicity (par. 21).

    Reflection placed at the service of reason is the basis ofspeculation. Hegel must take up reflection and absorb it intospeculation, thus passing beyond it. The fundamental point onwhich the Phenomenology turns is Hegels claim that substancebecomes subject. He says: everything turns on grasping andexpressing the true, not only as substance, but equally as sub-ject (par. 17). Kantian formalism cannot get beyond sub-stance; it can offer the object of reflection only as externallyordered. Such reflection cannot offer us the inner form of the

    6 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    24/150

    object. The object becomes something only when it is external-ized from what it is in itself and is taken up by the knower asthe phenomenal object. The phenomenal object is functional,but the thing-in-itself is substantive.

    Speculation requires us to approach the object as not sub-stance but subject, as having an inner lifenot simply, so tospeak, as a body with anatomy but as a living body governed byspirit. Applicable here is A. N. Whiteheads concept in Processand Reality of vacuous actuality (pp. 43; 253). Understood assubstance, the object is vacuous in its actuality, a mere phe-nomenon for the knower to schematize in the production of

    judgments. Approached as subject, the object, like reason, isinternally ordered, its actuality is not vacuous, not inert. It hasan inside. Reflection at the service of reason becomes anactivity of mediation. To know something under the aspect ofthe true is to know it as subject, as Hegel says: Something thatis reflected into itself, a subject (par. 23). He says: Only thisself-restoring sameness, or this reflection in otherness withinitselfnot an originalor immediate unity as suchis the true(par. 18). He says that spirit as substance is nothing but its own

    acquisition of self-consciousness, the bringing-about of its ownbecoming and reflection into itself (par. 28).Reflection in the service of reason becomes a process of

    consciousness wherein the knower meets itself in the known.Reflection becomes an activity internal to what is known ratherthan an external formation of it. Reflection is taken up intodialectic, which is the science of spirit or the organic unity ofthe whole. Spirit is reflection which is itself simple, and whichis for itself immediacy as such, beingthat is reflected into itself(par. 26). Dialectic is reflection turning back on itself, whichcan capture in thought the self-movement that is substancebecome subject.

    Dialectic enters into the content of the thing, which is incontrast to the formal understanding, which, Hegel says:Instead of entering into the immanent content of the thing, it isforever surveying the whole and standing above the particularexistence of which it is speaking, i.e. it does not see it at all (par.53). Argumentation or raisonnement, that the understanding can

    7Hegels Preface

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    25/150

    practice, is reflection into the empty I, the vanity of its ownknowing (par. 59). Mathematical cognition is also inadequateas a model for a science of spirit, for mathematical truths are trueindependently from whatever proof we may subjectively use toestablish them. Their proofs do not form a necessary part of theirresult. Propositions that state ordinary facts or that state histor-ical conclusions should be affirmed or denied straightway,depending on the evidence.

    Thinking that apprehends the true as the whole and canthus produce a science of spirit requires a different sense of theproposition than that which attaches a subject to a predicate to

    state a particular truth. This requires what Hegel calls thespeculative proposition or speculative sentencespekula-tiver Satz (par. 61). The speculative sentence or what he alsocalls the philosophical proposition (ibid.) is Hegels specialidea in the preface. It has within it the dialectical motion nec-essary to present consciousness as alive and self-developingthrough its determinate shapes to the organic whole of spirit asabsolute knowing.

    With it we can distinguish Hegels phenomenology, which

    is based in a speculative use of reason from the phenomenologyof Edmund Husserl, which remains a reflective phenomenology.Husserl says: The phenomenological method operates exclu-sively in acts of reflection (Ideas, sec. 77). Husserls phenome-nology is a descriptive, schematic phenomenology of the con-tents of experience. We may also distinguish Hegels speculativereason from Gadamers hermeneutic reflection. Gadamer inTruth and Methodsays: What role does reason play in the con-text of human practice? In every case it takes the general formof reflection (p. 569). Indeed, the legacy of Descartes, Locke,G. W. Leibniz, and Kant is the unexamined tenet of modern phi-losophy that to think philosophically is to reflect.

    Regarded from the standpoint of speculative reason, reflec-tion immediately lacks two things: a principle of inversionand a principle of determinate negation. Hegel says: Theimmediate existence of spirit, consciousness, contains the twomoments of knowing and the objectivity negative to knowing(par. 36). Speculation or dialectical reason follows conscious-

    8 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    26/150

    ness as it turns its object to its opposite, as it inverts the truth itholds to in one moment to the opposite that it holds to in thenext. Hegel says: Let science be in its own self what it may, rel-atively to immediate self-consciousness it presents itself in aninverted posture (par. 26). Science, Hegel says, causes naturalconsciousness to walk on its head (ibid.). He says the scienceof this pathway is the science of the experience which con-sciousness goes through (par. 36). The movement of con-sciousness from one moment to the other is not the simple nega-tion of argumentation (raisonnement) when it refutes somethingas false. In the actual process of consciousness what is rejected

    as false is also part of the true. The false has content (par. 39).True and false are relative determinations dependent upon theirposition in the development of the experience of consciousness.

    Hegel says: In speculative [begreifenden] thinking, as wehave already shown, the negative belongs to the content itself,and is thepositive, both as the immanentmovement and deter-mination of the content, and as the whole of this process.Looked at as a result, what emerges from this process is thedeterminate negative which is consequently a positive content

    as well (par. 59). What is the speculative sentence upon whichthe doctrines of dialectical inversion and determinate negationand, in general, the experience of consciousness depend? Hegeldescribes it in musical terms. The distinction between subjectand predicate that exists in the general form of a propositionis destroyed by the speculative proposition (par. 61). He saysthe conflict between the general form of the subject and predi-cate and the unity produced between them by its transforma-tion into true conceptual form is like the conflict that occursin rhythm between metre and accent. Rhythm results from thefloating centre and the unification of the two (ibid.). Hegelsays that in the speculative or philosophical proposition theunity of the subject and predicate is meant to emerge as a har-mony, that is, the subject is not simply dissolved into the pred-icate or the reverse.

    Putting this in general terms, Hegel says that in specula-tive thinking the passive subject of reflective thinking or raison-nementperishes in an active relation with its object and enters

    9Hegels Preface

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    27/150

    into the differences and the content, and constitutes the deter-minateness (par. 60). Picture-thinking (Vorstellung), Hegelsays, also cannot cope with this disappearance of the subjectinto its predicates. Vorstellungnormally is a way of thinkingthat runs through predicates in order to get beyond them. Butit discovers that the predicate is really the substance, the sub-ject has passed over into the predicate (ibid.). AlthoughVorstellung, unlike raisonnement, is a holistic way of thinking,it is unable to go further because the subject cannot be locatedand has disappeared into the predicates. Vorstellung suffersfrom not being a truly dialectical way of thinking. It can only

    presentthe subject as its predicates, so to speak.Hegel explains the speculative sentence in paragraph

    sixty-two, which deserves to be read several times. He uses theexample: God is being. God, the subject, in order to be whatit is, is taken up or dissolved into the predicate, being. WhatGod is, after all, is being. That is the meaning of the propo-sition. But as being, God, as a definite subject, so to speak,ceases to be. We are taken back to God as the subject to deter-mine exactly what the predicate is. Hegel explains this circular

    motion a second time, with the example: The actualis the uni-versal. We move from subject to predicate to subject again.The crucial point is that on the return to subject we do not pos-sess the same subject. It has been affected by the process of themovement, because now it is a subject that stands as somethingdetermined by its predicate. Hegel says: Thinking thereforeloses the firm objective basis it had in the subject when, in thepredicate, it is thrown back on to the subject, and when, in thepredicate, it does not return into itself, but into the subject ofthe content (par. 62).

    Hegels point concerning the difference between reflectionand speculation can be seen from their Latin roots. Reflexio(reflectere) is to bend back, to turn back or reverse. Spe-cio (specere) is to spy out, to see into. In the general formof the proposition typical of reflective thinking, the subjectmoves to the predicate and is thought simply to turn back tothe subject. No dialectical change has occurred. In the specula-tive proposition, in the movement from the subject into the

    10 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    28/150

    predicate, something has been seen into about the nature ofthe subject such that as it returns, keeping the predicate in rela-tion to itself, it is no longer the same as the original subject.Upon this sense of thinking Hegels Phenomenology depends.

    In summary, reflection in the service of the understandingallows us to experience the world commonsensically, as aworld of particular things that can be brought together intovarious orders of things and various levels of these orders. Forthe understanding the knower is separate from the known. Theknower, through the power of reflection, can grasp the known.Reflection allows us to understand the world. The hallmark

    of this understanding is that the knower regards the object itknows as having a reality other than its own reality. Reflectionbegins to be in the service of reason when the knower turns itsreflective activity away from the reality of the world as some-thing other than itself and attempts to use reflection as themeans to have access to its own reality. The knower attemptsto reflect on itself, not on what it takes to be other than itself.This self-reflection is the step that consciousness requires inorder to transpose reflection into speculation and to allow the

    understanding to be superseded by reason.The phenomenon of self-reflection suggests to the knowerthat all knowing, including knowledge of the object, may beapprehended as a kind of self-knowledge. The knowers self-knowledge is not separate from the object as known. Speculationstems from this sense of self-reflection. Consciousness enters intospeculation when it realizes that what it knows of itself cannotbe divorced from what it knows of the object. Reflection whenturned backward onto the knower becomes self-reflection, andwhen self-reflection is extended back onto the selfs relation tothe object, speculation is born for consciousness. In a widersense, speculation has been there all along and was presupposedby reflection. Once consciousness, in its drive toward knowing,is in possession of the speculative moment, it can experience allknowing as a kind of self-knowing.

    11Hegels Preface

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    29/150

    This page intentionally left blank.

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    30/150

    Hegel did not give a title to the approximately one dozen pagesnow called the Introduction to the Phenomenology. In the

    original they stand as simply some opening pages, and neartheir end Hegel says the Phenomenology is the science of theexperience of consciousness (par. 88). The science properbegins with the first stage of Consciousness, that is, Sense-certainty. In the preface Hegel gives us a phenomenology ofphilosophical consciousness broadly drawn, directed to thereader who may hold the positions he describes: the criticalphilosopher of subjective idealism; the absolute idealist whosedialectic is based on the principle of identity; the romanticphilosopher of edification and enthusiasm; the Enlightenmentadherent to argumentation or raisonnement; the rationalistadvocate of mathematical method as a model for a science ofspirit; and the common-sense thinker who cannot pass beyondappearance, appealing to an oracle within his breast to solvephilosophical problems.

    The preface also addresses the reader who believes inprefaces, that is, the belief that a subject matter can be knownprior to and apart from thought entering into the world of thesubject matter, on the subject matters own terms. Hegel sati-

    rizes those philosophers who, in order to keep up with thetimes, and with advances in philosophy, read reviews of philo-sophical works, perhaps even read their prefaces and firstparagraphs (par. 70). Hegel abuses in advance the profes-sional philosopher, saying that such readers blame the authorif they cannot understand a work, speaking of the noiselessaction of these dead men when they bury their dead (par.71). Hegel says comprehension of his work requires a rare

    13

    C H A P T E R 2

    Hegels Introduction:The Double Ansich

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    31/150

    individual who can overcome his own concerns and achievethe level of true science.

    In the dozen pages of introduction Hegel gives us a secondset of phenomenological comments. If the preface is, broadlyspeaking, a phenomenology of the reader, these pages of intro-duction are a phenomenology of the phenomenon. By this Imean Hegel presents the reader with an account of conscious-ness itself as a phenomenon. He says what, in general, con-sciousness is.

    In the preface he has defined consciousness as the imme-diate existence of spirit that contains the two moments of

    knowing (par. 36). In the preface, as in the introduction,Hegel defines experience (Erfahrung) as the movement ofconsciousness between those two moments of knowing thatconsciousness exercises on itself (pars. 36 and 86). In theintroduction Hegel presents the reader with the shape of thegeneral phenomenon of consciousness, apart from any specificcontent. This general shape, characterized by the polarity of itstwo moments, will be recognizable in the particular shapes ofconsciousness as we follow its pathway toward its final shape

    as absolute knowing. In the introduction we see the shape ofconsciousness itself. In the rest of the Phenomenology we willsee this shape as it enters into the various contents or stages ofconsciousness.

    Hegel presents the phenomenon of consciousness in thesecond half of the introduction (pars. 8189). In the first half(pars. 7380) he discusses the phenomenon of cognition(Erkenntnis). His organizing image is the fear of error, whichhe opposes to the light of truth (pars. 7374). Hegels ques-tion is: What should be the starting point of science? Sciencewishes to know the true itself, the absolute. How can we avoiderror? Whether cognition is seen as an instrument or as amedium, the problem is the same. Science can attempt to deter-mine what form it must take to avoid error, in advance ofengaging in the actual production of knowledge, or science cansimply begin and see if it can produce knowledge, treating theproblem of error as it goes. The first of these choices is thattaken by Locke and, especially, by Kant.

    14 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    32/150

    Kant is the frightened philosopher. His fear of error leadshim into critique, to try to establish the perfect conditionsunder which philosophy or cognition can function. He is thephilosopher of prolegomena, concerned to delineate the basisfrom which philosophy or scientific cognition can think. Inordinary experience the fear of error is what leads us to try toestablish whether we can actually do what we can do, beforewe do it. The fear of error is a deep impulse in one type ofphilosophical mind. The outcome of this drive to prolegomena,to the avoidance of error in philosophy, Hegel says, is alwaysthe conclusion that cognition cannot secure a knowledge of

    what exists in itself.Hegel has in mind Kants restriction of cognition to the

    phenomenal object and the separation of it from the thing-in-itself (Ding-an-sich). Hegel says: This feeling of uneasiness issurely bound to be transformed into the conviction that thewhole project of securing for consciousness through cognitionwhat exists in itself is absurd, and that there is a boundarybetween cognition and the absolute that completely separatesthem (par. 73). Since its inception, Kants account of knowl-

    edge has faced the grand embarrassment, if not the granddeception, that we can know only what the object is for us, thatwhat it is in itself cannot be known.

    Kant asks that we grant this one distinction and promisesthat if we do, then all else can be epistemologically perfect. Wecan discover the necessary principles of cognition of the objectas a phenomenon for the knower. Then we can proceed, withthe luxury of advancing all sorts of creative views of what theworld is like in itself, as Kant does in the Third Critique, main-taining the sweeping distinction of what is constitutive versuswhat may be considered regulative of the object. If we hold tothis program as rigorously as Kant does, we can be free of thefear of error. Of course, the thing-in-itself is there and will notgo away. We know about it in some important sense becausewe continue to talk about it, even within the confines of Kant-ian philosophy.

    Hegel asks: Should we not be concerned as to whetherthis fear of error is not just the error itself? (par. 74). He says:

    15Hegels Introduction

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    33/150

    Above all, it presupposes that the absolute stands on one sideand cognition on the other, independent and separated from it,and yet is something real; or in other words, it presupposes thatcognition which, since it is excluded from the absolute, is surelyoutside of the truth as well, is nevertheless true, an assumptionwhereby what calls itself fear of error reveals itself rather asfear of the truth (par. 74). Kantianism is an early form of ana-lytic philosophy; it is a process of making distinctions that goeson until a framework of limitations is established within whichall the distinctions work; that is, until they all are mutually sup-portive. But what of the light of truth? The true is the whole,

    not the part. If it is to be anything, Hegel holds, philosophymust attempt to see the real directly in terms of the light oftruth. It must attempt to know the thing itself, the absolute,and to know in terms of the absolute all that is not absolute.Hegel says: This conclusion stems from the fact that theabsolute alone is true, or the truth alone is absolute (par. 75).

    Having abandoned the fear of error, Hegel now canallow doubt and skepticism to enter into the search by con-sciousness for truth. He introduces this through a second

    image, the highway of doubt or despair (der Weg desZweifels or der Verzweiflung). Hegel intends this to be a realpathway of doubt, as distinct from the doubt undertaken inorder to convert doubt immediately into certainty. He gives aone-sentence description of Descartes doubt, this road ofdoubt or despair: For what happens on it is not what is ordi-narily understood when the word doubt is used: shilly-shally-ing about this or that presumed truth, followed by a return tothat truth again, after the doubt has been appropriately dis-pelledso that at the end of the process the matter is taken tobe what it was in the first place (par. 78). Descartes offers nocausal account of the true. Through his method of doubt hesimply stamps as certain the basic tenets we hold at the begin-ning of his inquirythat the thinker exists, that God exists,and that the world exists. Nothing beyond the relief of the fearof error has been gained by the guarantee of certainty.

    Skepticism in Hegels sense is not directed to doubt ofparticular propositions or beliefs. It is skepticism directed to

    16 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    34/150

    whether any truth can be found in the phenomenal world atall. All may be illusion. Hegels science of the experience ofconsciousness prepares the reader to answer Descartes ques-tion of the evil genius. Of the type of skepticism he intends,Hegel says, The skepticism that is directed against the wholerange of phenomenal consciousness, on the other hand, ren-ders the spirit for the first time competent to examine whattruth is (par. 78). The discovery of illusion enters the path-way of the stages of the education of consciousness at everypoint. Each stage of consciousness appears to consciousness asholding the principle necessary for the science of spirit. But as

    consciousness attempts to grasp and develop the shape of thisprinciple at any stage, the form of knowing it has discovereddissolves into illusion before its eyes. Out of this illusion, con-sciousness necessarily assumes a new shape and its educationcontinues toward its goal of absolute knowing, toward a graspof the self-determined whole. Skepticism, like reflection, issubsumed within the process of speculative thought. Each isturned against itself in order to grasp the thing itself. Likecommon sense, both are inverted; each is made to walk on its

    head. The evil genius is forced to prove its own existence andin so doing dissolves its powers.In the second half of the introduction (pars. 81ff.), Hegel

    offers his method, or what he calls the presupposition whichcan serve as its underlying criterion (par. 81). This criterion oftrue knowing is internal to consciousness itself. Hegel says:Consciousness provides its own criterion from within itself, sothat the investigation becomes a comparison of consciousnesswith itself (par. 84). From this criterion Hegel will derive bothhis conception of experience and his conception of necessity,that is, all that is required for his science in general. We mustgive these statements of Hegel our closest attention to be cer-tain we understand them. If we do not grasp them, we will bemistaken about what is taking place at every stage of the Phe-nomenology, and since they contain the nature of Hegels con-ception of dialectic, we will be confused about the internalorder of Hegels whole system as developed in the Science ofLogic and other works.

    17Hegels Introduction

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    35/150

    What Hegel actually says, in these few pages, is not whathe has often been taken to have said. The major errors of mis-interpretation of Hegel by his commentators comprise a list aslong as the catalog of ships in the second book of the Iliad, andI do not intend to enter into them in any extensive way. In theend one must read the book for oneself. Present in the roomshould be only Hegel and the reader. Forget the interpretations;they are an excuse for not absorbing the text originally on onesown. No one can become a philosopher who worries aboutcomparing interpretations or keeping up with recent views.One might become a scholar this way, or an expert, but not a

    philosopher. This said, I wish to call attention to two com-monly heard views concerning Hegels criterion. One is thatHegel has a dialectic of thesis-antithesis-synthesis, or some-thing like this three-step movement. The other, related to thisclaim, concerns Hegels use of the German verb aufheben (sub.Aufhebung) as a doctrine of synthesis.

    No first-rate Hegel scholar speaks of Hegel having adialectic of thesis-antithesis-synthesis. In 1958 Gustav Mller,in an article, The Hegel Legend of Thesis, Antithesis, Synthe-

    sis, pointed out that Hegel never uses these three termstogether to describe the dialectic. As mentioned above, Hegelattributes triadic form to Kant as a lifeless schema (par. 50).Mller asks how this legend of the Hegelian triad came about,since it is not something one would naturally conclude directlyfrom Hegels text. He traces the likely origin to some lecturesgiven several times by Heinrich Moritz Chalybus, who shortlyafter Hegels death interpreted the new philosophy using thetriadic formulation from Kantian and Fichtean philosophy. Hegave these lectures on one occasion in Berlin, at which time,Mller says, Karl Marx may have been present, as a student.But the myth persists, conveyed to students in survey courses inthe history of philosophy. It is commonly held, both within andoutside the field of philosophy, by those who have only a sec-ond- or third-hand awareness of Hegel.

    Beyond this specific, historical origin, the triadic form ofHegels dialectic is often embraced by those who haveapproached Hegels system in the reverse of its own course of

    18 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    36/150

    development. The most accessible work of Hegel is the Ency-clopaedia of Philosophical Sciences in Outline. This has threeparts: the logic, philosophy of nature, and philosophy of spirit,and the subdivisions of these parts are also triadic. ManyBritish Idealist interpreters have approached Hegels systemfrom the Encyclopaedia. The book of W. T. Stace, The Philos-ophy of Hegel: A Systematic Exposition, is rigidly based onthis, making it a work of easy access to Hegel for generationsof English-reading students. It must be kept in mind that Hegelwrote the Encyclopaedia as a handbook for teaching philoso-phy to young students. It presupposes the dialectic of con-

    sciousness in the Phenomenology, in which philosophicalknowing is itself generated for the philosopher. The Ency-clopaedia presupposes Hegel, the philosopher of his own sys-tem, present, as the guide to what is meant, and directing thestudent who is listening to his oral amplifications of the text.

    The triadic conception of Hegels dialectic has beenclosely interwoven with his use of aufheben. Aufheben hasbeen a doctrine of great importance for those who have a moresophisticated version of the dialectic than the mechanism of

    thesis-antithesis-synthesis. Aufheben is an untranslatable Ger-man verb made from the ordinary verb in German, meaningto raise, or raise up, lift upheben, with the prefix auf.Aufheben is often translated in Hegelian works as to sublate;in Millers translation it is rendered as supersede (Aufhe-bung, sublation). Aufheben can mean two things at once:to cancel or transcend and to preserve. It is in this doublesense that Hegel most often uses it. How seriously are we totake Hegels use ofaufheben?

    Many commentators have taken it very seriously andhave found in it a doctrine of how one stage of consciousnessoriginates from the next on the pathway toward the absolute.This has produced what I will call the snowball theory ofthe absolute. Some recent writers on Hegel, such as John H.Smith in The Spirit and Its Letter, have suggested that we havetaken aufheben too seriously, and that it has an ironic conno-tation in the Phenomenology. This is an interesting suggestion,and it fits with Hegels general use of the trope of irony in the

    19Hegels Introduction

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    37/150

    Phenomenology. The ironic interpretation fits with the factthat in the Phenomenology one stage of consciousness seemsjust to collapse, and consciousness jumps straight to the nextstage. There is no clear sense of progression or transformation,no sublation. The Phenomenology is in essence a scene ofironic juxtapositions that lead up to absolute knowing.

    The snowball theory regards the Phenomenology, andHegels system as a whole, as a progression of forms in whicheach stage is taken up into the next and preserved in its differ-entiations. Like a snowball rolled across a lawn, it starts smalland gets bigger and bigger until, in this view of Hegels stages,

    we have a whole. The snowball theory is strong on the preser-vation or taking up meaning ofaufheben. The ironic viewdoes more justice to the sense of cancellation and transcen-dence. The ironic view is certainly more interesting, and likelycloser to a true reading of Hegels text. Hegels dialectical jux-tapositions, like those in an ironic statement, are based on thepower of human wit or ingenium, an ability well-known to theRenaissance humanists but lost to modern thinkers who, fromDescartes on, approach thought in terms of method.

    Ingenium (ingenuity, wit) is the ability to see a connectionbetween two seemingly diverse things. It lies behind the creation ofhypotheses in the sciences and behind the tropes of metaphor andirony in the poetical and rhetorical use of language. Necessity isthe mother of invention, and invention depends upon the power ofingenium to see new connections. Ingenium cannot be taught assuch. It is unlike method, which can be taught. Ingenium may begrasped and developed through examples, but it is not subject totheoretical instruction. Hegels dialectical method, like Socraticmethod, is not properly a method. Dialectic is a direct exercise ofingenium to connect diverse moments of experience. Hegel andSocrates show how this can be done. Once Hegels dialectic is seenas an exercise ofingenium and not as a peculiar form of deduction,the reader can relax and set about to see what Hegel sees.

    What does Hegel say the criterion that consciousness car-ries within itself is? His statement of it is extremely clear andcarefully drawn (esp. pars. 8587). I will call attention to someof its basic features.

    20 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    38/150

    1. It concerns the in-itself(Ansich) and the way the in-itself istaken up as a moment within consciousness.

    2. It concerns two moments as Hegel describes it, not three.Hegel speaks of these two moments as entsprechend, asanswering to each other in accord, or asgleich, as alike, pro-portionate. Consciousness never unifies them or synthesizesthem. It holds them together only as inseparable moments ofitself.

    3. Hegels most important statements of this are as follows, andprobably should be committed to memory:(a) But the distinction between the in-itself and knowledge is

    already present in the very fact that consciousness knowsan object at all. Something is for itthe in-itself; and knowl-edge, or the being of the object for consciousness, is, for it,another moment. Upon this distinction, which is present asa fact, the examination rests [Auf dieser Unterscheidung,welche vorhanden ist, beruht die Prfung] (par. 85).

    (b) Consciousness knows something; this object is theessence or the in-itself; but it is also for consciousness thein-itself. This is where the ambiguity of this truth enters.

    We see that consciousness now has two objects: one isthe first in-itself, the second is the being-for-conscious-ness of this in-itself (par. 86).

    4. What it means for consciousness to have experience is topass from the first to the second of these moments.

    5. These are two completely distinct moments. One cannot becollapsed into the other, yet nothing separates them. Wemight apply here Hegels comments on the voidas a princi-ple of motion, which he discusses favorably in the preface(par. 37). There is a voidbetween the two moments. Theyare not held together by a specifiable relation or connection.They simply standto each other. The fact that, for either tobe at all the other must be, expresses exactly what is meantby necessity. Their distinctness yet mutuality of existence isthe basis of Hegels claim that the progression of the formsof consciousness is necessary.

    6. Consciousness moves forward through its necessary progres-sion, apprehending the object by the doubling of the in-itself.

    21Hegels Introduction

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    39/150

    The in-itself as an object for consciousness now becomes anew in-itself that becomes a further object for consciousness,and so on. In this way consciousness acquires experience anddevelops toward the standpoint of the whole or absoluteknowing.

    7. There is one further dimension of this process of conscious-ness, and that is what this process is for us, the we (wir)that have somehow already undergone this process and arenow witnessing it as a necessary sequence. For we who wit-ness this process, we have an apprehension of consciousnessas it is in-itself and as it is for-itself. We can comprehend to

    ourselves both moments as in-and-for-itself. We have theperspective of the and. Hegel says: But it is just thisnecessity itself, or the origination of the new object, that pre-sents itself to consciousness without its understanding howthis happens, which proceeds for us, as it were, behind theback of consciousness. Thus in the movement of conscious-ness there occurs a moment ofbeing-in-itselfor being-for-uswhich is not present to the consciousness comprehended inthe experience itself (par. 87).

    These seven aspects of the criterion carried within con-sciousness in its apprehension of its object can be compre-hended in a more holistic manner. Consciousness has experi-ence by placing itself at odds with itself. It divides itself intotwo moments. One moment is the simple act of knowing orapprehending something that seems to be before it. The otheris the immediately subsequent self-awareness that it hasengaged in this act. In ordinary terms: I know, and, I know thatI know. Consciousness is a twone. Consciousness is one butit is a one that meets itself in this double sense. When con-sciousness steps back from its first moment to its second, thesecond moment becomes a new first moment from which it cannow step back. I wish to call this sense of the two first momentsthe double Ansich, the double in-itself. Consciousness doublesup. Experience is this process of the movement of conscious-ness against itself. The internal motion of consciousness cap-tured in these two moments is not a pendulum. Its internal

    22 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    40/150

    motion is not a simple back-and-forth oscillation. The twonessformed in each passage from one moment to the other gener-ates a further sense of twoness, a new sense of the world thatpresupposes the sense of the world of the previous twoness.This dialectic of pairs of moments is the sense of time that func-tions within consciousness.

    There is even a larger principle of twoness that prevailsbetween this temporal process of the increasing comprehensionof consciousness of itself and the whole of consciousness thatis the ever-present reality in which this temporality occurs. Thetemporality of consciousness is the pursuit of this wholeness.

    The two ultimate senses of consciousness, as a process and asa whole, is what Hegel intends to capture in his metaphor ofthe revel in which all participants are collapsing into eachother, producing ever-new configurations of activity, but, as hesays, apprehended from afar, as a whole, it is just as much ascene of transparent, unbroken calm (par. 47). Consciousnessalways finds itself paradoxically at both of these standpoints atonce, never able fully to join itself in its specific forms of activ-ity with its sense of the oneness of itself as a whole.

    23Hegels Introduction

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    41/150

    This page intentionally left blank.

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    42/150

    According to Hegel, philosophical thought can engage in eitherreason or understanding. Understanding is essentially an activ-

    ity of making distinctions and labeling. It is Hegels contents-mentalityexperience as a skeleton with tickets stuck all overit. Reason is the process of speculation; it occurs through theformulation of speculative sentences in which subject and pred-icate are folded back on themselves. The aim of speculation isto penetrate the inner life of the object and to capture inthought the intrinsic movement of the object. Thus every objectis in truth a subject. The life of a subject is caught up in the lifeof all things. The life of reason allows the minds eye to see intothe inner illumination of the object. The understanding has nointerest in the inner life of the object. The understanding is con-cerned with the object only to the extent that it can reflect itsown powers off the object and thus know it.

    Descartes and Locke are the first philosophers of reflec-tion. Locke, in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, isthe first to use reflection in the philosophical sense in Eng-lish. Locke distinguishes two sources of our ideas. One is sen-sation, the means by which we experience objects. The othersource of ideas is the experience our own mind has of its oper-

    ations. This is internal sense; the other is external sense. Lockesays: But as I call the other Sensation, so I call this REFLEC-TION, the ideas it affords being such only as the mind gets byreflecting on its own operations with in itself (I: 12324).

    In a letter to Antoine Arnauld, on July 29, 1648, Descarteswrites: We make a distinction between direct and reflectivethoughts corresponding to the distinction we make betweendirect and reflective vision, one depending on the first impact of

    25

    C H A P T E R 3

    Hegels Reason:A Digression

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    43/150

    the rays and the other on the second. Descartes says the simplethoughts of infants are direct and not reflective, such as whenthey have feelings of pain or pleasure originating in the body.But when an adult feels something, and simultaneously per-ceives that he has not felt it before, I call this second perceptionreflection [hanc secundam perceptionem reflexionem appello],and attribute it to the intellect alone, in spite of its being solinked to sensation that the two occur together and appear to beindistinguishable from each other. In this passage Descartesdraws the analogy that is the basis of the modern conception ofreflection. He compares the reflection of light in perception, the

    subject of optics, with reflection in the intellect, the subject ofmental philosophy. The historical source for reflection in Frenchis the Discourse (1637), where Descartes uses reflection in parts4 and 5. I have given an account of the history of reflection andits connection to the development of the science of optics in Phi-losophy and the Return to Self-Knowledge.

    The understanding, in its distinctive marking and labeling,ignores time except as Kant conceives itas one of the formsof intuition. The understanding attempts to achieve necessity in

    its formation of experience by ignoring time as a feature of thereal. Hegels reason, in contrast, is a way of realizing the natureof time as part of the inner life of the object become subject. Tothink dialectically is to bring reason into time, into the actualmovement of experience. Dialectical thought takes the knowerinto the movement of experience and imitates it, in the sense ofdirectly capturing this movement in language.

    To bring reason into time is always in some sense to makethe process of reasoning a narrative process. Narrative is thenatural form of temporal thinking. There is no narrative of thepresent or the future; the narrative always connects the pastremembered to the present or the future. The art of the narra-tive is the art of the Muses who, as Hesiod says, could sing ofwhat was, is, and is to come (Th. 3639). The art of the Musesis the basis of reason, in Hegels sense. The original product ofthe Muses is not philosophy but the fable, the work of the poets.As Joyce says: Fabled by the daughters of memory. And yet itwas in some way if not as memory fabled it (Ulysses, I, 24).

    26 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    44/150

    Once reason becomes the form of time it becomes a formof memory. What kind of memory is reason? Reason is not sim-ple narrative, nor is it chronology. As history, reason is thecomprehensive form of philology; that is, of the deeds, words,laws, and customs of nations at war and in peace. As philoso-phy, that is, as wisdom loved, it is what Hegel calls Erinnerung,or recollection. Recollection is distinct from ordinary memory.

    To remember is to live in time. In his short treatise OnMemory Aristotle says: The object of memory is the past. Allmemory, therefore, implies a time elapsed; consequently onlythose animals which perceive time remember, and the organ

    whereby they perceive time is also that whereby they remem-ber (449b2730). The human animal both has a power overtime and is in time. Aristotle says, in the History of Animals:Many animals have memory, and are capable of instruction;but no other creature except man can recall the past at will(488b2526). To remember in a human sense is to be able torecall the past at will, to know that one was born and has livedthrough time. To remember is to have memories, and further,to employ them as a basis of education and practical life.

    Aristotle says, in On Memory: If asked, of which amongthe parts of the soul memory is a function, we reply: mani-festly of that part to which imagination [phantasia] alsoappertains; and all objects of which there is imagination are inthemselves objects of memory (450a2123). Both memoryand imagination originate in sense perception: As to thequestion of which of the faculties within us memory is a func-tion, it has been shown that it is a function of the primary fac-ulty of sense-perception, i.e., of that faculty whereby we per-ceive time (451a1719).

    Memory depends upon the power of the imagination toform sense perceptions of things into images in which it altersor imitates them. Both memory and imagination are activeforces. In the Topics Aristotle says: Perception is a state,whereas movement is an activity . . . for memory is never a state,but rather an activity (125b1719). In the Posterior Analyticshe says: So from perception there comes memory, as we call it,and from memory (when it occurs often in connection with the

    27Hegels Reason

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    45/150

    same thing), experience; for memories that are many in numberform a single experience (100a36).

    Imagination is the way memory in its activity fixes andretains the sense perception. The imagination is an active force.This is evidenced by the fact that imagination can be employedby the poet in the act of making. Through the power of theimagination the poet makes metaphors. Plato understandsphantasia in the Theatetus as a blend of judgment and percep-tion (195D). In the De anima Aristotle understands it as inter-mediary between perceiving (aisthe\sis) and thinking (noe\sis)(427b29a). Cicero says that it is an impulse from the out-

    side that can be grasped by the soul (Acad. post. I.11.4042).Aristotle says: Imagination must be a movement resultingfrom an actual exercise of a power of sense. As sight is the mosthighly developed sense, the name phantasia (imagination) hasbeen formed fromphaos (light) because it is not possible to seewithout light (De an. 429a14).

    Francis Bacon states in Sylva Sylvarum: Imagination, isof three kinds: the first joined with belief of that which is tocome: the second joined with memory of that which is past:

    and the third is of things present, or as if they were present.The song of the Muses, with its three moments of time, sug-gests from the beginning that memory in its full capacity is notsimply recalling past impressions, or remembering things.Memory in its fullest sense is recollection. This means that thethings remembered and formed by the imagination must be putinto a proper order.

    A song has an order; like a narrative, it has a beginning,middle, and end. Aristotle says, in On Memory: When onewishes to recollect, that is what he will do: he will try to obtaina beginning of movement whose sequel shall be the movementwhich he desires to reawaken. This explains why attempts atrecollection succeed soonest and best when they start from abeginning (451b2932). To recollect requires the location ofthe beginning of a thing and the formation of it in the mind asit develops from its past to the present and anticipates a future.

    In On Memory, Aristotle distinguishes memory from rec-ollection. Recollection implies memory, but not the reverse. He

    28 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    46/150

    also distinguishes two types of recollection, necessary andcustomary. Acts of recollection occur when one impulse nat-urally succeeds another: now if the sequence is necessary, it isplain that whoever experiences one impulse will also experi-ence the next; but if the sequence is not necessary, but custom-ary, the second experience will normally follow (451b).

    Recollection requires a beginning and an ordering of its con-tents into a sequence from that beginning. Hegel says, in the finalparagraph of the Phenomenology: Spirit has to begin unbiasedfrom its immediacy in this new world and move once more tomaturity, as if all that preceded was lost and it had learned noth-

    ing from the experience of the earlier spirits. But the re-collection[Er-innerung] has preserved this and is the inner being, and, infact, higher form of substance (par. 808, my trans.).

    The act of recollection, which is the act of reason, takes uswithin experience. In An Essay on Man, Cassirer says: In manwe cannot describe recollection as a simple return of an event,as a faint image or copy of former impressions. It is not simplya repetition but rather a rebirth of the past; it implies a creativeand constructive process. It is not enough to pick up isolated

    data of our past experience; we must really re-collectthem, wemust organize and synthesize them, and assemble them into afocus of thought. It is this kind of recollection which gives usthe characteristic human shape of memory, and distinguishes itfrom all other phenomena in animal or organic life (p. 51).

    Philosophical recollection, as opposed to historical or lit-erary recollection, is causal orderingknowledgeper causas. Itis not customary but necessary, in Aristotles terms. Philosoph-ical recollection, which is expressed in the sequence of specula-tive sentences, is dialectical order, and this order is necessary.What is narrated is a necessary order of events remembered.The art of the philosopher is to see, in time-remembered, a nec-essary order of thingsto see how things could not have beenotherwise. In this way the philosopher is a master of time. Tomaster time is to find beginning points and to find the neces-sary sequence of order. It is the eye for the good infinity inwhich each thing in the sequence illuminates the other, in alight shown face to face.

    29Hegels Reason

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    47/150

    In this way reason enters time, but time is always indialectical opposition to a Jenseits, a beyond, what is beyondtime at any point of beginning. Thus to set a beginning for rec-ollection the philosopher is out of time. To pass back inthought to a place of beginning is to escape the sequence at thatpoint. There is the Jenseits. In Hegels term theJenseits is thevoid between the in-itself and the in-itself-for-consciousness,what lies inside the double Ansich. Seeing inside the twoness ofthe Ansich is the moment of speculative beginning. Not to seethis is to settle for the understanding, for reflection, or externalknowing. Hegel is the artificer of dialectic, who escapes from

    the island of pure understanding, with its labyrinth of tran-scendental distinctions. We who would go with him must heedthe warning not to go too near the direct light of the sun.

    30 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    48/150

    Hegel published four books, and posthumously there appearedthe volumes of lectures on the philosophy of history, the history

    of philosophy, philosophy of art, and philosophy of religion. Inaddition there are early and miscellaneous writings. Thesemake up Hegels corpus. In the lectures, Hegel is inventingwhole fields of study that have become the center of thehumanities in the contemporary world. Except for the philoso-phy of history, the lectures present the historical materialbehind Hegels divisions of absolute spirit: art, religion, andphilosophy.

    Hegels little writings are interesting in themselves and insome instances provide insights into how his system came tobe. There are Hegels so-called Differenzschrift, on the differ-ence between Johann Gottlieb Fichtes and Schellings systems;Glauben und Wissen, Hegels little treatise on faith and knowl-edge; the early theological writings; the fragment of a system of1800; the fragment on love; the lesser political writings thathave been collected in English by Z. A. Pelczynski; and theJena System, the system as Hegel first sketched it out, whileteaching at Jena. There is also Hegels correspondence, a goodportion of which has been translated by Clark Butler in a large

    volume, Hegel: The Letters. The four volumes upon whichHegels mature system rests are Phenomenology of Spirit(1807), Science of Logic (181216), Encyclopaedia of Philo-sophical Sciences in Outline (in the original and two revisedversions1817, 1827, 1830), and Philosophy of Right, pub-lished in 1821, ten years before Hegels death.

    The Philosophy of Right is an expansion of sections onforms of moral and political life from the Philosophy of Spirit

    31

    C H A P T E R 4

    Hegels System:Dialectic of Andness

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    49/150

    of the Encyclopaedia. Both the Philosophy of Right and thewhole of the Encyclopaedia contain Zustze attached to eachof their sections. Both of these works were written directly astextbooks and used in various periods of Hegels teaching. TheZustze are summaries of points, taken from Hegels lectures,that amplify the original text. These four major books of hissystem were all closely connected with his teaching. In Jena heannounced the Phenomenology as a course, prior to writing it,and the Science of Logic was connected to his teaching in Hei-delberg. When Hegel was not lecturing on the history of phi-losophy, which he did throughout his career, or on other fields,

    he was teaching his own system directly.What is the system? I wish to give a basic overview of its

    paradoxes and possible general order. One thing is clear: Hegelconceived the system as having two partsthe phenomenologyor the doctrine of appearance, showing the ways in which phe-nomena are known, and the science of logic or the doctrine ofthe real idea, showing the forms of metaphysical or categorealknowledge. The science of the experience of consciousnessresults in the science of logic. By logic Hegel means, not

    logic as an organon or instrument of thought, but meta-physicslogic as the rational form of the actual. At the begin-ning of the Science of Logic Hegel says that the categories,which are the subject matter of the Logic, are nothing morethan what is already present in language. In this Hegel is fol-lowing Aristotle, in that the categories are the most universalpredicates, but he does not accept Aristotles notion of theorganon.

    At the end of the section on sense-certainty in the Phe-nomenology Hegel writes of the divine nature of language,which is its power to take thought to the universal. Hegelunderstands language as the embodiment of rationality inregard to this power. Any language is implicitly a logic andhence a metaphysics. Language itself as the form of spirit is thepower to grasp the actual in thought, to form it as the idea.Ordinary logic, that taught to philosophy students and as theinstrument needed to think well in all fields of inquiry, focusesonly on certain aspects of language and how these can be used

    32 Hegels Absolute

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    50/150

    to guide thought in its formal endeavors, the forms of theproposition, the syllogism, logical analogy, etc. These are sub-sumed within Hegels full sense of logic and are explicitlytreated in the Science of Logic.

    Hegel is clear, in the preface to the Phenomenology, whichfalls between the completion of that work and the Science ofLogic, that the forms of spirit of the Phenomenology lead up tothe Logic. He says: Their movement, which organizes itself inthis element into a whole, is logic or speculative philosophy(par. 37). At the beginning of the Science of Logic Hegel reiter-ates this connection. In the title page of the original edition,

    Hegel designates the Phenomenology as System of science,first part. Until the Phenomenology was given attention byFrench commentators such as Jean Hyppolite and AlexandreKojve it was regarded as an early work of Hegel, not impor-tant to the system, and it was not much read.

    Findlay, in his foreword to the Miller translation, saysthat the Phenomenology is meant to be a forepiece to thesystem (which he identifies with that of the Encyclopaedia),but it is meant to be a forepiece that can be dropped and dis-

    carded once the student, through deep immersion in its con-tents, has advanced through confusions and misunderstandingto the properly philosophical point of view (p. v). Findlay hasalso called the Phenomenology an auto-da-f, the burning of aheretic as ordered by the Inquisition. In other words, once theindividual gets to the stage of absolute knowing and has prop-erly comprehended everything, the ladder, which Hegel says thereader has a right to demandthat will take his own con-sciousness to the standpoint of the absolutecan be thrownaway (par. 26).

    At no point does Hegel clearly take so extreme a view ofthe disposal of the Phenomenology as does Findlay. In fact, hespeaks of the need to read philosophical works many times(par. 63), although this comment in itself is not incompatiblewith Findlays view. Presumably Findlay agrees that the Phe-nomenology must be read many times. The way Hegel speaksat the beginning of the Science of Logic, suggests that the Phe-nomenology needs to be kept in an active relationship to the

    33Hegels System

  • 7/29/2019 Verene Hegel s Absolute an Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

    51/150

    second part of the system, perhaps in the way that the philoso-pherthinking purely speculative thoughts and, in this sense,not living in the world the way others dostill lives in theworld and does not exist apart from its appearances.

    Hegel says his system is a circle. In the Science of Logic hesays it is a circle of circles joined as a chain, a Kette. How arewe to understand the first major link in this chain, thatbetween the Phenomenology and the Logic? The ke