Understanding the role of Intelligence in the Onset of...

34
1 Understanding the role of Intelligence in the Onset of War: A Quantitative Approach 1 Jacquelyn Schneider Arizona State University [email protected] Abstract: Explanations for war onset span the theoretical sphere: the distribution of power, misperceptions, the dynamics of capabilities, or domestic motivations. Scholars may disagree about the causal mechanisms that affect the likelihood of war, but all agree that information and uncertainty about information plays a role in the onset of war. Despite the fact that information is often alluded to within the causes of war, very little literature discusses the effects of institutional information, or organized intelligence, on conflict initiation. Further, the literature that does examine the relationship between intelligence and war is dominated by intensive single-event case studies, which fail to provide generalizable understandings about the role of intelligence in the onset of war. I attempt to solve these problems by examining the presence and effect of intelligence failures in crises from 1935 to 2007. Based on the data collected from source reporting and scholarly analysis, I use logit analysis to test the effect of including an intelligence variable within existing understandings of why states go to war. I find that intelligence adds a statistically significant explanatory value to understanding why states go to war. Further, my analysis confirms the assumption that intelligence failures have a positive correlation with the likelihood of war onset. The research provides a valuable opening for the inclusion of intelligence within the war onset research agenda and suggests that quantitative explorations of intelligence failure can elucidate important relationships between intelligence and crisis escalation. Why do states go to war? War is costly, unpredictable, and risky (Fearon 1995)— and yet it occurs. Explanations for this puzzle span the theoretical sphere: the distribution of power (Waltz 1979, Mearsheimer 2001), misperceptions (Lebow 1984), the dynamics of capabilities (Van Evera 1999), and domestic motivations (Schultz 1999, Bueno de Mesquita et al 2003). The causal mechanisms may vary, but what all of these 1 Prepared for presentation at the 2013 Annual Meeting of the International Studies Association, San Francisco, CA, April 3-7, 2013. Do not cite or quote without author’s permission

Transcript of Understanding the role of Intelligence in the Onset of...

  •   1 

    Understanding the role of Intelligence in the Onset of War:

    A Quantitative Approach1

    Jacquelyn Schneider

    Arizona State University

    [email protected]

    Abstract: Explanations for war onset span the theoretical sphere: the distribution of power, misperceptions, the dynamics of capabilities, or domestic motivations. Scholars may disagree about the causal mechanisms that affect the likelihood of war, but all agree that information and uncertainty about information plays a role in the onset of war. Despite the fact that information is often alluded to within the causes of war, very little literature discusses the effects of institutional information, or organized intelligence, on conflict initiation. Further, the literature that does examine the relationship between intelligence and war is dominated by intensive single-event case studies, which fail to provide generalizable understandings about the role of intelligence in the onset of war. I attempt to solve these problems by examining the presence and effect of intelligence failures in crises from 1935 to 2007. Based on the data collected from source reporting and scholarly analysis, I use logit analysis to test the effect of including an intelligence variable within existing understandings of why states go to war. I find that intelligence adds a statistically significant explanatory value to understanding why states go to war. Further, my analysis confirms the assumption that intelligence failures have a positive correlation with the likelihood of war onset. The research provides a valuable opening for the inclusion of intelligence within the war onset research agenda and suggests that quantitative explorations of intelligence failure can elucidate important relationships between intelligence and crisis escalation.

    Why do states go to war? War is costly, unpredictable, and risky (Fearon 1995)—

    and yet it occurs. Explanations for this puzzle span the theoretical sphere: the

    distribution of power (Waltz 1979, Mearsheimer 2001), misperceptions (Lebow 1984),

    the dynamics of capabilities (Van Evera 1999), and domestic motivations (Schultz 1999,

    Bueno de Mesquita et al 2003). The causal mechanisms may vary, but what all of these                                                         1 Prepared for presentation at the 2013 Annual Meeting of the International Studies Association, San Francisco, CA, April 3-7, 2013. Do not cite or quote without author’s permission

  •   2 

    explorations seem to agree on is that variances in information have a significant effect on

    war (Fearon 1995, Jervis 1976, Bueno De Mesquita 1984, Morrow 1989). War is, on

    some level, a product of uncertainty (Clausewitz 1976).

    In the past, this uncertainty, or variance in information about capabilities,

    intentions, or outcomes has been included more as an immeasurable error term than an

    understandable part of war onset (Gartzke 1999). My exploration here aims to tackle that

    error term by defining and measuring a significant part of the uncertainty that affects war

    onset. In particular, I posit that we can understand variances in uncertainty (and therefore

    the error term) by proxying uncertainty with intelligence (or the institutional collection,

    processing, analysis, distribution, and reception of private information) in crisis decision-

    making. In other words, explanations for why states go to war can better capture true war

    dynamics by including an intelligence variable that operationalizes the inherent variance

    in information by which states and their leaders make decisions to go to war. By

    understanding the error term as a variable, I am able to explore not only how intelligence

    affects the onset of war, but also how intelligence can further explain existing theories

    about the causes of war.

    In this paper, I first provide a definition of intelligence and next introduce

    structural, behavioral, and domestic explanations for war onset. I then examine the role

    intelligence could play in expanding the explanatory capability of each of these theories.

    Using these theoretical categories, I then develop a model of war onset that introduces

    intelligences to the existing war explanation. This model is tested with a data set of

    crises drawn from the International Crisis Behavior Database (ICB) (Brecher and

    Wilkenfeld 2000), each coded for intelligence failure through archival and historical

  •   3 

    research of intelligence’s role within crisis decision-making. This intelligence variable is

    used alongside ICB variables for power, perception, and domestic regime to test the

    additive value of intelligence to understanding war onset.

    By attempting to understand war onset’s error term as both identifiable and

    measurable, I introduce an important explanatory variable to the currently unsettled

    debated about the causes of war. To be clear, I do not suffer from the belief that

    inclusion of intelligence will explain all conflicts. There are going to be times in the

    international system when two countries, even faced with all the correct information

    about the repercussions of their actions, will choose to go to war with each other. My

    aim is not to replace the current explanations, but to add to their explanatory ability. In

    addition, in introducing intelligence as a variable in the causes of war, I hope to provide a

    theoretical opening for systematic analysis of intelligence within the causes of war

    literature.

    Furthermore, I hope that the use of a large-N quantitative method will fill a large

    hole within the current intelligence literature, which is dominated by single event case

    studies (Bar-Joseph and Kruglanski 2003, Wohlstetter 1965, Jervis 2010, Lebow 1983).

    While this literature is rich with detail and lends important knowledge about

    intelligence’s role in the decision-making process, it has two major weaknesses. First,

    the literature focuses on a few key (and obvious) intelligence failures—particularly

    failures involving British, American, and Israeli conflicts. Secondly, the literature’s

    focus on singular events fails to provide more generalizable conclusions about

    intelligence failures and their relationship with war.

  •   4 

    What is intelligence?

    In order to make these more generalizable conclusions, it is essential to define

    intelligence. Are diplomatic discussions intelligence? Newspaper articles? Is

    intelligence a product, an action, an actor, an institution, or all? A true definition of

    intelligence must not only incorporate all these understandings of intelligence, but also

    demarcate intelligence from a broader understanding of information or informational

    processes (Warner 2002). As Sherman Kent, the father of U.S. intelligence analysis,

    noted “the main difficulty seems to lie in the word 'intelligence' itself, which has come to

    mean both what people in the trade do and what they come up with. To get this matter

    straight is crucial: intelligence is both a process and a product” (Kent 1946).

    To begin first with intelligence as an actor, we must identify what separates

    intelligence from policy makers. Intelligence exists, not as an individual actor, but as its

    own institution. It is not a spy or a ring of spies, but an institution created by the state as

    an official representation of the state’s informational needs on foreign activities.2

    Accordingly, intelligence is an official organization or set of organizations responsible to

    a country’s leadership. But intelligence is also a process. It is the initial collection of

    private information, the analysis of that information, the dissemination to the appropriate

    parties, and the reception of that information by decision-makers. The information

    received by decision-makers then informs their perception of requirements and begins the

    intelligence process again. Therefore, the process of intelligence is a feedback cycle of

    information processing. In this way, one can discuss intelligence analysis or collection as

                                                            2 A clearer example of this may be to look historically to determine when intelligence began to exist as an institution. Spies and reconnaissance have existed since it seems the beginning of warfare. However, the first real evidence of the institutionalizing these capabilities and personnel occurs after World War I, when the British, French, and Germans created organizations specifically devoted to the collection, analysis, and dissemination of information about foreign capabilities and intentions (Kahn 2001).

  •   5 

    a part of intelligence, but the overall concept of intelligence implies that the totality of the

    process. Therefore, intelligence is also the collection, analysis, dissemination, and

    reception of private information.

    This leads us to understanding that intelligence is also a distinctive type of

    information. If all information were intelligence, then there would be no difference

    between journalism and intelligence, between business research and intelligence

    estimates (Agrell 2002). What makes intelligence unique is that it is considered private

    information, information that the consumer (the state) does not want to share with others.

    While the way that information is obtained may classify it as more or less private, the

    overall understanding of the information is that it is for the use of the state only. This

  •   6 

    also assumes that the information is targeted, i.e. the state has identified as a need to

    know piece of information for making policy decisions. In sum, intelligence is private

    information on foreign entities deemed relevant to policymaker and defense consumer’s

    needs. And, finally, intelligence must be a product, disseminated to the consumer as a

    representation of the totality of the process. This could be a long-range analytical

    product like the National Intelligence Estimate or a tactical report, like a predator feed of

    insurgent activity or a communications intercept of an adversary conversation. In this

    sense, intelligence is disseminated to consumers as a finished product representing the

    totality of the processes.

    Therefore, intelligence is:

    An official organization or set of organizations responsible to a country’s leadership,

    tasked with the collection, analysis, and dissemination of private information on foreign

    entities deemed relevant to policymaker and defense consumer’s needs, which is

    disseminated to consumers as a finished product representing the totality of the

    intelligence process.

    What, then, is an intelligence failure? Jervis offers a starting point, declaring that,

    “the most obvious sense of intelligence failure is a mismatch between the estimates and

    what later information reveals” (Jervis 2010 pg. 2). But Jervis admits that this definition,

    while valid, is also unsatisfyingly constrictive. He broadens his conception of

    intelligence failure to include “a falling short of what we expect from good intelligence”

    (Jervis 2010 pg. 2). Based on these criteria, an intelligence failure can be defined as

    intelligence’s failure to correctly estimate enemy capabilities or intentions or

    intelligence’s failure to meet policymakers expectations of good intelligence as evidenced

  •   7 

    by a failure in acquisition, analysis, dissemination, and/or appreciation of pertinent data.

    Intelligence success, conversely, is the correct estimation of enemy capabilities or

    intentions or meeting policymaker’s expectations of good intelligence. This

    understanding of success allows for mini-failures within the intelligence cycle as long as

    final product estimations are correct and/or satisfy policymaker’s desires.

    Causes of War and Intelligence

    Why do wars begin? Fearon provides a categorization of three types of

    explanations: rational, irrational (or emotion-based), or regime-dependent (Fearon 1995).

    Placed in more theoretical terms, the explanations for the cause of war can be divided

    into structural (rationalist), behavioral (irrational), or domestic explanations (regime-

    dependent). The first categorization, structural explanations, points to redistributions of

    power and the anarchical international system as key determinants in states’ decisions to

    go to war (Waltz 1959, 1979, Mearsheimer 2001, Organski and Kugler 1981). As Waltz

    asserts, “war occurs because there is nothing to prevent it . . . In the absence of a supreme

    authority there is then the constant possibility that conflicts will be settled by force”

    (Waltz 1959, 188). For these theorists, war is best understood as a state-level

    phenomenon in which the re-balancing of power is the primary war driver and is most

    often material—a country’s economic or military ability to compel or deter others from

    actions which would negatively affect their position within the international system.

    Behavioral explanations, on the other hand, focus much more closely on agent-level

    decisions. For behavioralists, war is a problem of misperception and decision-making

    biases. It is the distinction between a balance of power and a balance of threat (Walt

  •   8 

    1985) and takes into account the inherently human nature of war. Finally, the third type

    of explanations, domestic, looks at the role of regime and regime survival in decisions to

    go to war. For domestic advocates, the decision for war is initiated and motivated by

    inherently domestic survival incentives.

    Structural

    Since structural explanations for war focus on power distributions, intelligence’s

    main role in these explanations is the ability to provide accurate estimates of adversary

    capabilities. We can think of this as one of four types of estimates. The first and second,

    overestimation of power and underestimation of power, involve the inaccurate

    assessment of an adversary’s capability to wage war. For example, an underestimation of

    the amount of tanks an enemy has in its order of battle, an overestimation of a state’s

    industrial capacity, or an underestimation of a state’s ability to implement a new tactic.

    Both of these estimates assume that the assessment is delivered in a coherent and timely

    manner to the decision-maker. The third category of intelligence, no estimation of

    power, assumes that intelligence fails to provide an analysis of the adversary’s power

    capabilities. This could be because of lack of ability to collect information, lack of

    forward thinking to collect information, lack of dissemination within the intelligence

    community, or lack of access to the decision-maker.3 Finally, the last category of

    intelligence’s relationship with structural explanations for war is a correct estimation of

    power capabilities.

                                                            3 The last two reasons for no estimation may also be explained within domestic cause of war explanations, so we should expect a relationship between this type of structural intelligence interaction term and the domestic intelligence interaction term. Therefore, we can expect that a structural interaction variable with no estimation of power may display a statistical relationship with the domestic-intelligence interaction term.

  •   9 

    Overestimation of power has often been discussed within the intelligence

    literature as a bureaucratic tendency for military intelligence to overestimate its

    adversaries. For example, the U.S. tended to overestimate Soviet missile capability,

    despite intelligence that would suggest their capabilities were not as great as expected

    (Aronsen 2001). This can be advantageous to deterrence—overestimating an enemy’s

    capability (especially if the enemy is a pure security-seeker and not a greedy state) can

    keep the opposing state from pursuing aggressive policies because it fears the adversary

    has the capability to respond. The argument has been made that the overestimation of

    Soviet military capabilities served as a check on U.S. potentially aggressive policies

    during the Cold War (Botti 1996).

    However, overestimation of an adversary’s capabilities can also lead to a decision

    for war. George W. Bush’s recent decision to invade Iraq was predicated on a severe

    overestimation of Iraq’s weapons of mass destruction program (Jervis 2006). This could

    suggest that overestimation of capabilities increases the likelihood of war when the

    estimation presents an image of the enemy as being on the precipice of an either

    revolutionary technology or major capability advantage (as suggested by power transition

    theory). Therefore, you would expect that overestimation of threat would be most likely

    to lead to war when a state felt like a preemptive attack (or first-mover advantage) would

    be necessary to win a conflict. In terms of the structural causes of war vocabulary,

    overestimation of threat may provide an impetus towards war when it changes a state’s

    understanding of who has the first move advantage. As Kenneth Waltz argues (Sagan

    and Waltz 1995), preemptive attack might be necessary to stop an aspiring nuclear state

    from developing nuclear capability. Once a state has crossed the nuclear threshold, an

  •   10 

    adversary loses the power of conventional advantage. Policy options are held captive by

    nuclear deterrence. This is why the estimation of nuclear weapons capabilities becomes

    so important to decisions to go to war.

    Intelligence may also underestimate the adversary’s power capabilities. This

    could be because the opposing state exercises good denial and deception tactics, or

    because the intelligence community fails to collect on game-changing tactics,

    technologies, or industries that qualitatively change the nature of a state’s power. For

    example, the United States underestimated Hussein’s weapons of mass destruction

    program before the Gulf War because Saddam executed excellent denial and deception of

    facilities (Dolley and Leventhal 2001). Sometimes an underestimate of adversary power

    can have dire consequences. For instance, in the Falklands War, the Argentine junta

    underestimated Britain’s capability to respond to the Argentine invasion of the Falkland

    Islands. In particular, their mistaken belief that the British submarine Endurance was out

    of area caused them to greatly underestimate the potential success of the invasion (Welch

    1997, Freedman 2008).

    Behavioral

    While structural explanations focus on the role of power in war, behavioral

    explanations center more on the role of intentions and perceptions. Therefore, perception

    of threat is more important than absolute power capabilities. Conflict, then, is not

    predetermined by structural constraints. Instead, it is the “world in their minds” which

    drives misperceptions and conflict (Vertzberger 1990). Accordingly, intelligence’s role

    in these explanations is in either overestimation of threat, underestimation of threat, or

  •   11 

    the correct estimation of threat. Overestimation of threat can cause a state to act with

    restraint against an adversary (especially if the state believes that the adversary has the

    capability to win in a conflict). However, overestimation of threat can also lead a state to

    believe that the adversary poses an immediate or existential threat to their existence and

    therefore initiate war to garner either a first-move advantage or a hail-mary to save their

    state. A good example of the overestimation of threat is Lyndon Johnson’s decision to

    send forces to Vietnam. The initial event that triggered his decision, the Maddox attack,

    was later debunked as an intelligence failure (Hanyok 2010). The “torpedo attack” that

    was reported to Johnson was actually a false radar return. Meanwhile, domino theory

    analysis from some elements of the intelligence community incorrectly assessed a North

    Vietnamese victory as potentially devastating for the U.S. and its interests (Rovner 2011).

    While overestimation of threat may be thought of as a failure of commission

    (Walker and Malici 2011), the underestimation of threat may be thought of as a failure of

    omission—a failure to deter. By underestimating threat, a state may fail to take the

    appropriate defensive actions in order to deter an adversary from going to war. For

    example, the United States in the Korean War underestimated the threat of North Korean

    invasion and the North Koreans underestimated the possibility that the U.S. would

    intervene for South Korea. Not only did the United States fail to signal its resolve in

    order to deescalate tensions, but it also failed to posture forces on the peninsula. Because

    the U.S. didn’t believe the North would invade (underestimated the threat), the North

    Koreans in turn also underestimated the threat and initiated war (Cumings 2004, deWeerd

    1962).

  •   12 

    Domestic

    Domestic explanations for war focus on the second image of Waltz’s Man, the

    State, and War. These explanations posit a relationship between domestic regimes and

    decisions to go to war. They can be thought of broadly as one of two types of

    explanations: war explained by the type of regime (Maoz and Russett 1994, Rousseau et

    al 1996, Gartzke 1998), and as an extension of that argument, war explained by regime

    motivations for survival (Bueno de Mesquita et al 1999, Bueno de Mesquita et al 2003,

    Reiter and Stam 2002).

    Domestic explanations for the causes of war point to regime characteristics and

    their calculation for survival. A state that chooses war for domestic reasons believes that

    war will enable their regime to hold onto power. Therefore, intelligence’s relationship

    with domestic causes for war centers on a regime’s inability to properly organize or

    utilize intelligence because of domestic reasons. These reasons could be related to

    distrust of intelligence as an organization, a need for intelligence to reach a certain

    conclusion for domestic reasons, an ineffective organization of the intelligence

    community, an excessive harmony between intelligence and decision-making, or a

    decision-making apparatus that fails to allow for effective use of intelligence. This

    breaks down broadly into four categories: politicization, neglect, polythink, and failure to

    share (Mintz and Derouen 2010, Rovner 2011). When no evidence of these is found,

    then more than likely the intelligence community and the decision-making apparatus

    utilized proper dissemination and reception of intelligence. Therefore, we should expect

    that in these situations of proper dissemination and reception of intelligence, then the

    only role intelligence would play in war onset would be structural or behavioral.

  •   13 

    Politicization is one of the most well-known and well-documented examples of

    domestic intelligence factors that may lead to war. As Rovner argues in his exploration

    of politicization and intelligence, “domestic political pressures create incentives for

    policymakers to oversell the amount and quality of information on security threats,

    regardless of the nature of personal relationships or organizational design” (Rovner 2011,

    11). In this construct, while politicization may affect individual or bureaucratic decision-

    making, the domestic variables serve as the causal mechanism for intelligence to be

    politicized. Here, I understand politicization as a deliberate (if subconscious) altering of

    the intelligence process—whether that be in the collection requirements, the analytical

    products, or who the information is disseminated to—in order to fulfill domestic

    objectives. In this sense, a regime that directs intelligence to devote all resources to one

    adversary and not look at the other would not necessarily be guilty of politicization (this

    is after all, how requirements for the intelligence community are generated). However, if

    that regime directed the intelligence community to ignore the other adversary because it

    believed that the other adversary’s actions would make them lose ground with their

    selectorate, then that would be politicization. As Rovner argues, politicization can be the

    direct or indirect manipulation of intelligence by the regime, the influence of regime

    norms on intelligence analysis, the use of intelligence by political parties to influence

    their political control, and actions taken by intelligence to support regimes perceived as

    friendly to intelligence’s interests (Rovner 2011, 205).

    President Johnson’s need to secure domestic support for his advertised attrition

    strategy in Vietnam serves as a compelling example of politicization due to regime

    manipulation. Because Johnson had publicly committed to this strategy, the failure of

  •   14 

    attrition in Vietnam would inflict serious audience costs for the leader and threaten his

    hold on power. Because Johnson had publicly invested in this strategy, Johnson needed

    North Vietnamese casualty estimates that showed North Vietnamese were losing more

    members than they were able to recruit. This “crossover point” would then be used to

    demonstrate to the American public that the U.S. was winning the war (and not caught in

    a stalemate). Military estimates supported Johnson’s position and, leading up to the 1968

    election, he pushed for a consensus from the intelligence community that the crossover

    point had been reached. Unfortunately for Johnson, CIA casualty estimates (based on a

    different methodology) did not support the military’s estimates. Choosing to politicize

    the intelligence, Johnson ignored the CIA analysis and instead insisted on the military’s

    estimates as the official order of battle in calculating Vietnam strategy success. This

    allowed Johnson to continue massive bombing campaigns despite contradictory evidence

    about their effectiveness. And, most importantly, it allowed Johnson to combat mounting

    anti-war dissension with what he advertised to the American public as intelligence facts

    (Rovner 2011).

    Denial, as opposed to politicization, is a more passive form of failure in the

    relationship between intelligence and the decision-maker. It can manifest itself in one of

    two ways: the denial of information presented to the decision-maker and the denial of a

    relationship between intelligence and the decision-maker. Rovner provides an example

    of the first form of denial in Johnson’s initial decision to escalate conflict in Vietnam.

    First, in 1964, Johnson commissioned an intelligence estimate to evaluate the domino

    theory. He believed that the fall of South Vietnam to the communists would lead to a

    domino effect within Southeast Asia, leaving the Soviets with a dangerous foothold in the

  •   15 

    region. Though the theory was foundational to Johnson’s national security, it was not an

    explicit point presented to the American people. Therefore, Johnson had significant

    domestic flexibility in decisions about the domino theory. Despite this flexibility, when

    the estimates came in refuting the domino theory, Johnson’s administration ignored the

    findings. No significant domestic group had come out for or against the Vietnam War or

    domino theory and therefore Johnson had no need to evaluate the intelligence (Rovner

    2011).

    Many autocratic rulers exemplify the second form of denial: the denial of a

    relationship between intelligence and the decision-maker. For instance, after-action

    reporting from Hussein’s security apparatus indicate that Hussein refused to hear accurate

    reporting of an impending and potentially dangerous attack by the United States in both

    the first Gulf War and the subsequent invasion in 2003. Taped recordings of a 1990

    discussion about the U.S.’ possible intervention against the Iraqi invasion of Kuwait

    (found in the aftermath of the Operational Iraqi Freedom invasion) reveal a decision-

    maker who refused to even meet with intelligence:

    America is a complicated country. Understanding it requires a politician’s alertness that is beyond the intelligence community . . . I said I don’t want either intelligence organization to give me analysis—that is my specialty . . . we agree to continue on that basis . . . which is what I used with the Iranians (as cited in Woods 2006, 12)

    Intelligence may also fail to reach a decision-maker because of internal

    intelligence failure to disseminate. In this scenario, the failure occurs because the

    community itself did not think the information was important or because it failed to

    create an effective mode of dissemination. While the most recent example may be the

  •   16 

    failure for the intelligence community to warn of an impending attack on the World

    Trade Center (9/11 Commission), a similar phenomenon occurred in the 1999 Kargil

    War. As Indian after action reports documented, Indian intelligence failed to disseminate

    warnings of a potential Pakistani action because it “was conditioned by the two decade

    old mindset that Kargil was unsuitable for cross-LOC military action” (Kargil Review

    Commission 1999). Therefore, the warning reports stayed at the ground level among

    some small Army units, instead of disseminating warning to political leadership (Lavoy

    2009).

    The failure to share intelligence encompasses not only that final failure to provide

    intelligence to the decision-maker, but also the failure to provide intelligence within the

    intelligence community. It is often argued that Pearl Harbor is an example of this type of

    failure. Though the correct information was collected, the community did not have an

    effective means of sharing warnings and therefore was unable to put together an accurate

    depiction of the Japanese threat (Wohlstetter 1962).

    Table 1. Theoretical explanations of how intelligence failure affects onset of war

    The Model: Causes of War and Intelligence

    Empirical and case study evidence suggests that each cause of war explanation

    offers significant explanatory value to understanding conflict onset. However, they

    remain unable to satisfactorily explain anomalies—the black swans of states’

    interactions. As it currently exists, these explanations can be captured within the a simple

  •   17 

    additive explanatory model, where each variable represents the totality of

    operationalizations within each intellectual category and the error term represents the

    uncertainty in which conflict often occurs (also posited by Gartzke to be where the real

    explanation for war lies, Gartzke 1999):

    Model 1: War is in the error term

    War= structural variable + behavioral variable + domestic variable + error term

    This model allows us to conceptualize explanations for the causes of war and to even test

    each term for their relative significance, but it fails to explain any relationship between

    the error term and the variables. Further, in accepting the error term as an immeasurable

    element of the equation, we are left intellectually unsatisfied about what causes conflict

    to occur. In order to solve this problem, I create a model in which intelligence is

    included as a measurable way of understanding the error term.

    Model 2: Intelligence as an additive explanatory variable

    Likelihood of War= structural variable + behavioral variable + domestic variable +

    intelligence

    Based on my theoretical argument, this model, which substitutes intelligence for

    the error term, should have significantly more explanatory capability than Model 1. In

    this simple additive model, the intelligence variable should capture the variance

    previously unexplained by the three core explanations for war onset. It will therefore

  •   18 

    provide a more robust overall explanation for war onset and explain anomalies within the

    existing theoretical arguments.

    Methods: Measuring the Effects of Secrets on both War and Non-Events

    There are two major challenges in understanding the role of intelligence on war at

    an aggregate level: first, tracing the impact of intelligence on not only war but the non-

    event of peace; and, second, the difficulty in determining intelligence failure. The first

    problem can be solved through effective case selection and the second through in-depth

    case analysis and a clearly defined operationalization of the intelligence variable.

    Most case study work exploring the role of intelligence and the onset of war

    examines cases in which war begins (Bar-Joseph and Kruglanski 2003, Freedman and

    Gamba-Stonehouse 1991, Shlaim 1976). This selection on the dependent variable leads

    to rich analysis of specific cases, but biases our overall understanding of intelligence and

    war. Are there examples of intelligence failure in which war did not occur? Intelligence

    success and war onset? Is there enough variation within the overall sample of both war

    and peace to challenge the common perception that intelligence failures have a

    correlation with war initiation? In order to account for this bias, I chose a sample of 265

    inter-state crises beginning after 19354 from the ICB. By utilizing crises instead of cases

    of war, I am able to examine both war and peace. Further, by using crises as opposed to a

    random sample of dyads and years, I limit my analysis to politically relevant dyads and

    instances for which intelligence should have been used to solve the policy puzzle. Even

    with this case refinement, information about crisis intelligence can be difficult to find for                                                         4 Cases used from ICB satisfied the following criteria: 1) crisis trigger date after 1 Jan 1935, 2) triggering entity not a non-state actor, 3) at least two actors, and 4) crisis either an entry of a major actor in a war, an initiation of a war, or not an intra-state war.

  •   19 

    less salient crises, crises between smaller powers, and crises involving closed regimes. In

    total 53 cases were successfully coded for intelligence success or failure.5

    Table 2. Sample characteristics

    To solve the second problem of determining intelligence failure, I chose a

    dichotomous operationalization of intelligence based on the definition of failure outlined

    above. Therefore, intelligence was either a failure (1) or not a failure (0). Cases where

    evidence could not be found about intelligence’s involvement in the policy decision were

    not coded and not included in the final sample. Based on after-action reporting, post-

    incident interviews, and historical or journalistic accounts, an incident was categorized as

    a failure if there was a clear example of an incorrect intelligence estimate of threat or

    capabilities that significantly altered the ability for policymakers to utilize the most

    appropriate policy and/or evidence that intelligence did not meet policymakers’

    expectations.

    For example, if intelligence failed to detect an impending invasion or significantly

    underestimated an opposing country’s development of offensive weaponry, the case was

    coded as a failure (whether this information was used by policymakers or not). But there                                                         5 Because evidence of intelligence involvement in policy was more likely to be found for democracies, English-speaking nations, and highly salient events, there is a potential bias in the data. Further analysis of cases will be required to determine how influential this bias may be.

  •   20 

    were other examples in which intelligence had a good estimate of enemy capabilities or

    intentions and failed to communicate it effectively with policy makers. This would also

    be considered a failure because intelligence had the correct information but failed to

    communicate to the policymaker, despite the policymaker’s articulated need for that

    information.

    Operationalization of the existing causes of war explanations was based on the primary

    causal mechanisms posited by each theoretical camp. For structural explanations, which

    focus on material capabilities, I utilized ICB’s power discrepancy variable which captures

    GDP and military capabilities of each actor in the crises and assesses an overall power

    disparity between opposing sides. According to structural explanations, war is most

    likely in two possible situations: crises with low power discrepancies and crises in which

    the initiator has a greater power capability (positive power discrepancy). In other words,

    war is more likely to occur when the power discrepancy is greater than zero.

    Behavioral explanations focus on the perception of threat. Perception of an

    adversary is based on two significant factors: the history of conflict between the states

    (Diehl and Goertz 2000, Thompson 2001, Rasler and Thompson 2006) and the perception

    of the gravity of the threat (Jervis 1976). Therefore, in order to capture the power of

    these two perception issues on intelligence failures, I utilized two measures. The first,

    taken from the ICB, codes for gravity of threat where one=economic threat, two=limited

    military threat, three=political threat, four=threat to territory, five=threat to influence,

    six=threat of grave damage, and seven=threat to existence. The second measure, taken

    from Thompson’s dataset of enduring rivalries (Thompson 2001), captures the power of a

    rivalry relationship to the onset of war. This measure is dichotomous: the gravity of

  •   21 

    threat measure was multiplied by one if the dyad was not an enduring rivalry and by two

    if the dyad was an enduring rivalry. They hypothesis here is that states are more likely to

    go to war as the gravity of the threat increases and if the states exist within an enduring

    rivalry.

    Finally, I measured the domestic explanation using the ICB’s coding of regime

    type. According to the domestic causes of war genre, democratic regimes are less likely

    to go to war with one another, but not necessarily less likely to go to war with a non-

    democracy (Maoz and Russett 1993, Reiter and Stam 2002, Schultz 2001). One possible

    explanation for this phenomenon is that democracies do a better job of assessing the

    probability of victory or defeat. Because a democratic regime is more concerned about

    the effect of failure on their survival, democracies are less likely to enter a war that they

    cannot win (Bueno de Mesquita et al 2003, Chiozza and Goemans 2011). Democracies,

    therefore, have a better assessment of the capabilities and intentions of adversaries. This

    may be because of a better relationship between intelligence and the policymaker (for

    example, authoritarian regimes like Saddam Hussein and Stalin have been documented as

    ignoring intelligence estimates) or because democracies have better intelligence

    apparatuses because they can expend more resources on outside threats versus domestic

    threats. Crises were assigned a zero if none of the actors were democracies, a one if at

    least one actor was a democracy, and a two if all actors were democracies. Therefore, we

    should expect less likelihood of war between democracies and a greater chance of

    conflict when one or more of the actors is not a democracy.

  •   22 

    Table 3. Explanations of war operationalizations

    Results

    Table 4. Logit analysis of Model 1, explanations without intelligence

    To examine the robustness of the current explanations of war without intelligence,

    I ran a logit analysis of the effect of power, threat, and regime type on the onset of war. I

    found no statistical significance for any of the variables. In fact, estimates for all three

    variables were close to zero, indicating that the odds of any of the variables changing the

    likelihood of war onset was one.

    Table 5. Logit analysis of Model 2, explanations with intelligence

  •   23 

    Model 2, which included both the causes of war explanations and intelligence,

    offered more insight into war onset. Though power, threat, and regime remained

    statistically significant, with little overall impact on the likelihood of war onset,

    intelligence had a statistically significant effect. In fact, war was 5.8 times more likely to

    occur with intelligence failure. Overall, Model 2 provides a better explanation of the

    likelihood of war onset. Table 6 displays the result of a likelihood-ratio test comparing

    Model 1 to Model 2. The results indicate that Model 1 can be rejected in favor of the

    intelligence-included Model 2.

    Table 6. Likelihood ratio test: Model 1 vs. Model 2

    Conclusion

    The findings presented here represent a first step in understanding the role of

    intelligence in explaining the onset of war. The statistical analysis suggests that

    intelligence can help elucidate why some crises escalate to conflict and others diffuse

    without violence. However, the addition of intelligence to the discussion of why conflict

    occurs does not represent new theory about why states go to war. Inherent in all the

    current genres of war explanations is the role of information in conflict decisions. What

    this analysis provides is a quantifiable and observable way to capture both information

    and the uncertainty that bounds that information. In providing intelligence as a variable

    to explain the error term, we can attempt to both confirm assumptions about information

    and war, as well as test how intelligence helps fill in gaps where existing theoretical

    explanations leave off. Also, by placing a highly-qualitative body of work within a large-

  •   24 

    N quantitative framework, this paper attempts to solve the “rigor and parsimony”

    problems identified by Jervis (Jervis et al 1985 pg. 5) by exploring intelligence in a

    generalizable, systemic way.

    This paper represents merely a launching-off point to explore the role of

    intelligence in conflict. While mathematically, Model 2’s additive inclusion of the

    intelligence variable is the most logical transmutation of previous explanations, actual

    case studies of intelligence and the decisions to go to war (De Weerd 1962, Best 1996,

    Bar-Joseph and Kruglanski 2003, Bar-Joseph and Adamsky 2006) suggest that this un-

    interactive model is not representative of the way intelligence affects decisions to go to

    war. For instance, bad intelligence about an enemy’s power capabilities is not enough

    alone for a state to feel the need to go to war. In addition to that bad intelligence, the

    state must also have a theory that explains why an adversary’s increase in capability

    would affect their sovereignty or interests. So, for example, the U.S. consistently

    overestimated and underestimated Soviet capabilities during the Cold War, and yet war

    did not occur (Aronsen 2001). Bad information cannot in itself cause conflict; if that

    were the case, then every time a nation incorrectly counted tanks, conflict would ensue.

    Intelligence requires the existence of other theoretical explanations of war in order to be a

    causative element of war.

    But how does intelligence interact with the causes of war to explain war onset?

    Model 2 introduces intelligence as a univariate interaction between intelligence and all

    three causes of war. In this construct, intelligence’s effect is constant across all three

    variables. Therefore, if a state’s intelligence overestimates, then it overestimates

    invariably across all three causes of war explanations. This seems intuitively acceptable

  •   25 

    in at least some instances; it appears logical that a state that overestimates an opposing

    state’s power capabilities could also overestimate revisionist intentions or the threat to

    domestic regime survival. Indeed, this could be explained by a state’s tendency to “fit”

    intelligence within a pre-conceived image of the other (Heuer 1999).

    Model 3: Intelligence as a Multivariate Intelligence Effect

    War= ((intelligence) *(structural variable)) +((intelligence) *(behavioral variable)) +

    ((intelligence)*(domestic variable))

    In this final model, intelligence has not only an interactive effect on the causes of

    war, but is also variable within each interaction. Therefore, intelligence can be both an

    overestimation of power projection capabilities and an underestimation of threat. This

    would allow us to capture the inherent variability of intelligence within each cause of war

    and the dynamics of competing intelligence assessments. It is clear, therefore, from this

    model that intelligence can both increase and decrease the chances of war. It does not

    have a stand-alone effect on war, but instead is influenced by the cause of war to which it

    contributes.

    Future research should explore these multiplicative effects. Hopefully in

    understanding these relationships between intelligence and the explanations for war, we

    can not only provide a more robust model for war onset, but also generate pragmatic

    insight into how intelligence reform may affect conflict initiation.

    Bibliography

  •   26 

    _____2002. 9-11 Commission Report. New York: W.W. Norton & Company. Abbink, J. 1998. “Briefing: the Eritrean-Ethiopian Border Dispute.” African Affairs 97(389): 551-565. Aid, Matthew M. 2009. The Secret Sentry. New York: Bloomsbury Press. Aid, Matthew and Jeffrey T. Richelson. “Intelligence and China: Collection, Analysis, and Covert Action.” Nsarchive.chadqyck.com. http://nsarchive.chadwyck.com/collections/content/CI/intell_and_china_essay.pdf. Accessed 2 April 2012. Aleksa, Djilas. 1992. “Profile of Slobodan Milosevic.” Foreign Affairs (82): 81-97. Allison, Graham T. 1971. Essence of Decision. Boston: Little Brown. Alvarez, David. 1999. “Behind Venona: Americans signal intelligence in the early cold war.” Intelligence and National Security 14(2): 179-186. Aronsen, L. 2001. “Seeing Red: US Air Force Assessments of the Soviet Union, 1945-1949.” Intelligence and National Security 16(2): 103-132. Avirgan, Tony and Martha Honey. 1982. War in Uganda. Westport: Lawrence Hill. Baghough, Zouhair. 30 July 2011. “Western Sahara: War and Politics (56-58 Campaign).” MoroccoBoard.com. Accessed 2 April 2012. Bajoria, Jayshree. 7 Nov 2008. “RAW: India’s External Intelligence Agency.” Council on Foreign Relations. http://www.cfr.org/india/raw-indias-external-intelligence-agency/p17707. Accessed 2 April 2012. Bajwa, Kuldip Singh. 2004. Jammu and Kasmir War, 1947-1948: Political and Military Perspective. New Delhi: Har Anand Publications. Ball, Desmond. 1996. “Over and Out: Signals Intelligence in Hong Kong.” Intelligence and National Security 11(3): 474-496. Bar-Joseph, Uri and Arie W. Kruglanski. 2003. “Intelligence Failure and the Need for Cognitive Closure: On the Psychology of the Yom Kippur War.” Political Psychology 24(1): 75-99. Bar-Joseph, Uri and Dima Adamsky. 2006. “The Russians are not coming: Israeli intelligence failure and soviet military intervention in the War of Attrition.” Intelligence and National Security 21(1): 1-25.

  •   27 

    Bar-Joseph, Uri and Jack Levy. 2009. “Conscious Action and Intelligence Failure.” Political Science Quarterly 124(3): 461-488. Ben-Zvi, Abraham. 1990. “Between Warning and Response: The case of the Yom Kippur War.” International Journal of Intelligence and Counterintelligence 4(2): 227-242. Best, Anthony. 1996. “Constructing an Image: British Intelligence and Whitehall’s perception of Japan, 1931-1939.” Intelligence and National Security 11(3): 403-423. Betts, Richard K. 1978. “Analysis, War, and Decision: Why Intelligence Failures are Inevitable.” World Politics 31(1): 61-89. Betts, Richard K. 1998. “Intelligence Warning: Old Problems, New Agendas.” Parameters Spring: 26-35. Betts, Richard K. 2007. Enemies of Intelligence. New York: Columbia University Press. Blainey, Geoffrey. 1973. The Causes of War. London: The Macmillan Press. Bolia, Robert S. 2004. “Overreliance on Technology in Warfare: The Yom Kippur War as a Case Study.” Parameters 34(2): 45-56. Botti, Timothy J. 1996. Ace in the hole: Why the United States did not use nuclear weapons in the cold war, 1945 to 1965. No. 165. Greenwood Publishing Group. Brecher, Michael. 1979. Studies in Crisis Behavior. Piscataway: Transaction Publishers. Hoffman, Steven A. 1972. “Anticipation, Disaster, and Victory: India 1962-1971.” Asian Survey 12(11): 960-979. Brecher, Michael and Jonathan Wilkenfeld. 2000. A Study of Crisis. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, Alistair Smith, Randolph M. Siverson, and James D. Morrow. 2003. The Logic of Political Survival. Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press. Bush, George W. 2010. Decision Points. New York: Crown Publishers. Chang, Gordon H. and He Di. 1993. “The Absence of War in the US-China Confrontation over Quemoy and Matsu in 1954-1955: Contingency, Luck, Deterrence.” The American Historical Review 98(5): 1500-1524. Chiozza, Giacomo, and Hein Goemans. 2011. Leaders and International Conflict. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  •   28 

    Clausewitz, Carl von. 1976. Michael Howard and Peter Paret eds. and trans. On War. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Cohen, Raymond. 1988. “Israeli military intelligence before the 1956 Sinai Campaign.” Intelligence and National Security 3(1): 100-140. Cumings, Bruce. 2004. The Origins of the Korean War, Vol.2. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. de Weerd, Harvey. 1962. “Strategic Surprise and the Korea War.” Orbis 6: 435-452. Diehl, Paul and Gary Goertz. 2000. War, Peace, and International Rivalry. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Dimitrakis, Panagiotis. 2010. Military Intelligence in Cyprus: From the Great War to Middle East Crises. London: I.B. Tauris. Doron, Gideon. 1988. “Israeli Intelligence: Tactics, Strategy, and Prediction.” International Journal of Intelligence and Counterintelligence 2(3): 305-319. Engle, Eloise and Lauri Paananen. 1973. The Winter War: The Soviet Attack of Finland 1939-1940. Mechanicsburg: Stackpole Books. “Eritrea; A Fantasy that Led to Strategic Mistakes and Failures.” Africa News. 12 May, 2008. Fearon, J. D. 1994. Domestic political audiences and the escalation of international disputes. American Political Science Review, 577-592. Fearon, J. D. 1995. Rationalist explanations for war. International Organization, 49, 379-379. Freedman, Lawrence. 2008. “Intelligence Operations in the Falklands.” Intelligence and National Security 1(3): 309-335. Freedman, Lawrence and Virginia Gamba-Stonehouse. 1991. Signals of War. Princeton: Princeton University Press “Fujimoro Interviewed on casualties, military, and diplomatic strategy.” Television Panamericana. 0220 gmt 13 Feb 1995. Gartzke, E. 1999. “War is in the Error Term.” International Organization 53(3): 567-587. Gentry, John A. 2008. “Intelligence Failures Reframed.” Political Science Quarterly 123(2): 247-270.

  •   29 

    Gibbs, David N. 2000. “The United Nations, international peacekeeping and the question of impartiality: revisiting the Congo operation of 1960.” The Journal of Modern African Studies 38(3): 359-382. Gilpin, Robert. 1981. War and Change in World Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press. Golani, Moti. 1998. Israel in Search of a War: the Sinai Campaign, 1055-1956. Brighton: Sussex Academic Press. Garicano, Luis and Richard A. Posner. “Intelligence Failures—An Organizational Economic Perspective.” The Journal of Economic Perspectives 19(4): 151-170. Hallett, Robin. 1978. “The South African Intervention in Angola.” African Affairs 308: 347-386. Hanyok, Robert J. Declassified 2010. “Skunks, Bogies, Silent Hounds, and the Flying Fish: The Gulf of Tonkin Mystery, 2-4 August 1964.” Cryptologic Quarterly : pg. 1-55. Hermann, Margaret. 1984. “Personality and Foreign Policy Decision Making: A Study of 53 Heads of Government.” In Foreign Policy Decision-Making Perceptions, Cognition, and Artificial Intelligence, ed. David Sylvan and Steve Chan. New York: Praeger. Hermann, Margaret. 2003. “Assessing Leadership Style: Trait Analysis” In The Psychological Assessment of Political Leaders, ed. Jerrold Post. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Higgins, T. The Perfect Failure: Kennedy, Eisenhower, and the CIA at the Bay of Pigs. New York: Norton. Huth, Paul, Christopher Gelpi, and D. Scott Bennett. 1993. “The Escalation of Great Power Militarized Disputes: Testing Rational Deterrence Theory and Structural Realism.” The American Political Science Review 87(3): 609-623. Hopple, Gerald W. 1984. “Intelligence and Warning: Implications and Lessons of the Falkland War.” World Politics 36 (3): 339-361. Hosoya, Chihiro. 1968. “Miscalculations in Deterrent Policy: Japanese-US Relations, 1938-1941.” Journal of Peace Research V(2): 97-115. James, Laura. 2005. “Nasser and his Enemies: Foreign Policy Decision Making in Egypt on the Eve of the Six-Day War.” Middle East Review of International Affairs 9(2): 23-44. Janis, Irving L. 1972. A psychological study of foreign-policy decisions and fiascoes. Oxford: Houghton Mifflin.

  •   30 

    Jervis, Robert. 1982. “Deterrence and Perception.” International Security 7(3): 3-30. Jervis, Robert. 1986. “Intelligence and Foreign Policy: A Review Essay.” International Security 11(3): 141-161. Jervis, Robert. 2006. “The Politics and Psychology of Intelligence and Intelligence Reform.” The Forum 4(1): 1-9. Jervis, Robert. 2010. Why Intelligence Fails: Lessons from the Iranian Revolution and the Iraq War. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Jervis, Robert, Lebow, Richard and Janice G Stein. 1989. Psychology and Deterrence. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Jian, Chen. 1994. China’s Road to the Korean War. New York: Columbia Press. Kahn, David. 1991. “The Intelligence Failure of Pearl Harbor.” Foreign Affairs Winter: 138-152. Karsh, Efraim. 1987. “Military Power and Foreign Policy Goals: The Iran-Iraq War Revisited.” International Affairs 64(1): 83-95. Keegan, John. 2003. Intelligence in War. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. Kent, Sherman. 1946. “Prospects for the National Intelligence Service.” Yale Review 36. Keohane, Robert. 1980. “The Theory of Hegemonic Stability and Change in International Economic Regimes.” In Ole Holsti, Randolph Siverson, and Alexander George, eds., Change in the International System. Boulder: Westview Press. Kornet, Marek. 2009. “Choosing not to choose in 1939: Poland’s Assessment of the Nazi-Soviet Pact.” The International History Review 31(4): 771-797. Kugler, Jacek and Douglas Lemke, eds. 1996. Parity and War. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan. Kuisong, Y. 2000. “The Sino-Soviet Border Clash of 1969: From Zhenbao Island to Sino-American Rapprochement.” Cold War History 1(1): 21-52. Lawson, Fred H. 1989. “The Iran Crisis of 1945-1946 and the Spiral Model of International Conflict.” International Journal of Middle East Studies 21(3): 307-326. Lavoy, Peter R.. 2009., Asymmetric Warfare is South Asia. [online]. Cambridge University Press. Available from: 16 February 2012

  •   31 

    Lebow, Richard Ned. 1981. Between Peace and War. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press. Lebow, Richard Ned. 1983. “Miscalculation in the South Atlantic: The Origins of the Falkland War.” Journal of Strategic Studies 6(1): 5-35. Leffler, Melvyn P. 1985. “Diplomacy, Strategy, and the Cold War: The United States, Turkey, and NATO, 1945-1952.” The Journal of American History 71(4): 807-825. Leslau, Ohad. 2010. “The Effect of Intelligence on the Decisionmaking Process.” International Journal of Intelligence and Counterintelligence 23(3): 246-448. Levite, Ariel. 1987. Intelligence and Strategic Surprise. New York: Columbia University Press. Levy, Jack. 1983. “Misperception and the Causes of War: Theoretical Linkages and Analytical Problems.” World Politics 36(1): 76-99. Levy, Jack. 1991. “Long Cycles, Hegemonic Transitions, and the Long Peace.” In The long postwar peace, edited by Charles Kegley, Jr., 147-76. New York: HarperCollins. Maoz, Zeev and Bruce Russett. 1993 “Normative and Structural Causes of the Democratic Peace, 1946-1986.” American Political Science Review 87 (3): 624-38. Marcum, John A. 1976. “Lessons of Angola.” Foreign Affairs 54(3): 407-425. McDermott, Rose, Dominic Johnson, Jonathan Cowden, and Stephen Rosen. 2007. "Testosterone and Aggression in a Simulated Crisis Game." The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 614: 15-34. Mearsheimer, John. (2001). The tragedy of great power politics. WW Norton & Company. Mintz, Alex and Karl DeRouen Jr. 2010. Understanding Foreign Policy Decision Making. Cambridge: Cambridge Press. Mobley, Richard A. 2000. “North Korea’s Surprise Attack: Weak U.S. Analysis?” International Journal of Intelligence and Counterintelligence 13(4): 490-514. Mobley, Richard A. 2009. “US Joint Military Contributions to Countering Syria’s 1970 Invasion of Jordan.” JFQ 55: 160-167. Organski, A. F., & Kugler, J. (1981). The war ledger. University of Chicago Press. Palit, Dhatritri Kumar. 1972. The Lightning Campaign: The Indo-Pakistan War, 1971. New Delhi: Lancer Publishers.

  •   32 

    Rasler, Karen A., and William R. Thompson. 2006. “Contested Territory, Strategic Rivalries, and Conflict Escalation.” International Studies Quarterly 50: 145-67. Reiter, Dan and Allan C. Stam. 2002. Democracies at War. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Rieber, Robert W. ed. 1991. The Psychology of War and Peace: The Image of the Enemy. New York: Plenum Press. Rovner, Joshua. 2011. Fixing the Facts: National Security and the Policy of Intelligence. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Russell, Richard L. 2002. “CIA’s Strategic Intelligence in Iraq.” Political Science Quarterly 117(2): 191-207. Sandow-Quirk, Mary. 2002. “A Failure of Intelligence.” Prometheus 20(2): 131-143. Bar-Joseph, Uri and Jack Levy. 2009. “Conscious Action and Intelligence Failure.” Political Science Quarterly 124(3): 461-488. Schultz, K. 1999. “Do Democratic Political Institutions Constrain or Inform?” International Organization 53(2): 233-366. Schultz, Kenneth A. 2001. Democracy and Coercive Diplomacy. New York: Cambridge University Press. Schulze, Kirsten E. 1996. “Perceptions and Misperceptions: Influences on Israeli Intelligence Estimates During the 1982 Lebanon War.” The Journal of Conflict Studies 16(1): Sen, L.P. 1994. Slender was the Thread. Columbia: South Asia Books. Silberman-Robb [U.S. Commission on the Intelligence Capabilities of the United States Regarding Weapons of Mass Destruction]. 2005. Report to the President of the United States. Washington, DC, USGPO, March 31. Sheffy, Yigal. 1990. “Unconcern at dawn, surprise at sunset: Egyptian intelligence appreciation before the Sinai Campaign, 1956.” Intelligence and National Security 5(3):7-56. Shlaim, Avi. 1976. “Failures in National Intelligence Estimates: The Case of the Yom Kippur War.” World Politics 28(3): 348-380. Stein, Arthur. 1982. “When Misperception Matters.” World Politics 34: 505-526. Stoessinger, John G. 1993. Why Nations go to War. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

  •   33 

    Tareke, Gebru. 2000. “The Ethiopia-Somalia War of 1977 Revisited.” The International Journal of African Historical Studies 33(3): 635-667. Thompson, William R. 2001. “Identifying Rivals and Rivalries in World Politics.” International Studies Quarterly. 45: 557-86. “Uganda; How Idi Amin Era Ended.” 10 April 2009. Africa News. “Uganda; Our Intelligence Services; Tale of Many Mistakes and One Moment of Brilliance.” 13 February 2005. Africa News. Vandenbroucke, Lucien S. 1984. “Anatomy of a Failure: The Decision to Land at the Bay of Pigs.” Political Science Quarterly 99(3): 471-491. Van Evera, S. (1998). Offense, defense, and the causes of war. International Security, 22(4), 5-43. Van Evera, S. (1999). Causes of war: Power and the roots of conflict. Cornell University Press. Vehvilainen, Olli. 2002. Finland in the Second World War. New York: Palgrave. Vertzberger, Yaacov. 1990. The World in their Minds: Information Processing, Cognition, and Perception in Foreign Policy Decision-Making. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Verma, A.K. 2011. “Bangladesh 1971—Intelligence’s Finest Hour.” South Asia Analysis Group http://www.southasiaanalysis.org/%5Cpapers49%5Cpaper4805.html. Accessed 14 March 2012. http://www.defence.pk/forums/pakistan-defence-industry/551-isi-pakistan-inter-services-intelligence-11.html  Walker, Stephen and Akan Malici. 2011. U.S. Presidents and Foreign Policy Mistakes. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Walt, Stephen. 1988. "Alliance Formation and the Balance of World Power." International Security 9(4): 3-43. Waltz, Kenneth. 1979. Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Addison-Wesley. Wark, Wesley K. 1986. “In search of a suitable Japan: British naval intelligence in the pacific before the Second World War.” Intelligence and National Security 1(2): 189-211. Wark, Wesley K. 2010. The Ultimate Enemy: British Intelligence and Nazi Germany 1933 to 1939. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

  •   34 

    Warner, Michael. 2002. “Wanted: A Definition of ‘Intelligence.’” Studies in Intelligence 46(3). http://www.au.af.mil/au/awc/awcgate/cia/define_intel.htm#fn12 Accessed 16 April 2012. Weiner, Tim. 2007. Legacy of Ashes. New York: Anchor Books. Welch, David A. 1997. “Remember the Falklands? Missed Lessons of a Misunderstood War.” International Journal 52(3): 483-507. Welssman, Stephen R. 1974. American Foreign Policy in the Congo. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Wirtz, James J. 1991. “Miscalculation, Surprise, and American Intelligence after the Cold War.” International Journal of Intelligence and CounterIntelligence 5(1): 1-16. Wohlstetter, Roberta. 1962. Pearl Harbor; warning and decision. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Woods, Kevin M. 2006. The Iraqi Perspectives Report. Annapolis: Naval Institute Press.