Turner FINAL paper - Yale University ·...

27
Christians, Muslims and the name of God: Who owns it, and how would we know? Denys Turner, Yale Divinity School A paper presented at the Yale Center for Faith and Culture consultation “The Same God?” sponsored by the McDonald Agape Foundation The identity of individuals is problem enough in the case of Sir John Cutler’s stockings, which, being originally silk have been continuously darned with wool until none of the silk remains. Are they the same socks, even though none of the original matter remains at the end of the process? Of course if you produce a pair of silk socks from behind your back, and then immediately a pair of wool socks, we can be certain that they are not just the same pair of socks, because one and the same pair of socks cannot be simultaneously all silk and all wool. But as for Sir John’s socks it’s different, for they have history on their side: intuitively, I guess, we are inclined to say that they are the same socks, because what links the end with the beginning is a single, unbroken, spatiotemporal process of change, or, as we might say, a single narrative of space and time coordinates. And if that intuition is correct, then it follows that even as of purely material individuals you do not need any actual sameness of matter as a condition of their identity. And that is just as well, given that since Heisenberg’s discovery of his ‘uncertainty principle’ the velocities and positions of subatomic particles of matter have themselves been shown to be simultaneously indeterminable. For Newtonian middlesized material objects, fortunately, all we need is Newtonian spatiotemporal continuities on a middle sized scale.

Transcript of Turner FINAL paper - Yale University ·...

Page 1: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

Christians,  Muslims  and  the  name  of  God:  Who  owns  it,  and  how  would  we  know?  

 

Denys  Turner,  Yale  Divinity  School  

A  paper  presented  at  the  Yale  Center  for  Faith  and  Culture  consultation  “The  Same  God?”  

sponsored  by  the  McDonald  Agape  Foundation      

  The  identity  of  individuals  is  problem  enough  in  the  case  of  Sir  John  Cutler’s  

stockings,   which,   being   originally   silk   have   been   continuously   darned   with   wool  

until   none   of   the   silk   remains.   Are   they   the   same  socks,   even   though   none   of   the  

original  matter  remains  at  the  end  of  the  process?  Of  course  if  you  produce  a  pair  of  

silk  socks  from  behind  your  back,  and  then  immediately  a  pair  of  wool  socks,  we  can  

be  certain  that  they  are  not   just  the  same  pair  of  socks,  because  one  and  the  same  

pair   of   socks   cannot   be   simultaneously   all   silk   and   all   wool.   But   as   for   Sir   John’s  

socks   it’s   different,   for   they  have  history  on   their   side:   intuitively,   I   guess,  we   are  

inclined   to   say   that   they  are   the   same   socks,   because  what   links   the   end  with   the  

beginning  is  a  single,  unbroken,  spatio-­‐temporal  process  of  change,  or,  as  we  might  

say,  a  single  narrative  of  space  and  time  co-­‐ordinates.  And  if  that  intuition  is  correct,  

then  it  follows  that  even  as  of  purely  material  individuals  you  do  not  need  any  actual  

sameness  of  matter   as   a   condition  of   their   identity.  And   that   is   just   as  well,   given  

that   since   Heisenberg’s   discovery   of   his   ‘uncertainty   principle’   the   velocities   and  

positions   of   sub-­‐atomic   particles   of   matter   have   themselves   been   shown   to   be  

simultaneously   indeterminable.   For   Newtonian   middle-­‐sized   material   objects,  

fortunately,   all   we   need   is   Newtonian   spatio-­‐temporal   continuities   on   a   middle-­‐

sized  scale.    

Page 2: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

In  my  opinion  sameness  of  persons  is  obedient  to  much  the  same  conditions,  

at  any  rate,  speaking  as  a  non-­‐dualist.  I  do  not  suppose,  as  a  certain  kind  of  Cartesian  

might,  that  what  makes  me  at  the  age  of  66  to  be  the  same  person  as  a  certain  Denys  

Turner  was  on  August  5,  1942,   is   the  sameness  of  Denys  Turner’s   soul.  Or,   at  any  

rate,  since  his  soul  does  come  into  it,  it  does  so  because  his  soul  is  individuated  by  

his  body,  which  is  in  turn  individuated  along  the  same  lines,  and  meeting  the  same  

conditions,   as   are   Sir   John   Cutler’s   silk   stockings:   there   is   a   single   unbroken  

narrative   of   the   spatio-­‐temporal   co-­‐ordinates   which   make   a   body   to   be   just   this  

body,   and   so   a   soul   to   be   the   soul   of   just   this   person.   Otherwise,   like   Thomas  

Aquinas,  I  have  no  idea  how  a  dualist  imagines  a  soul  just  in  its  own  terms  could  be  

an   existent   individual.   To   put   it   simply,   “I   am  not  my   soul”—   anima  mea   non   est  

ego—  as  Thomas  says   in  his  commentary  on  I  Corinthians.  For  a  soul   is  not  a  self;  

my  soul  is  just  how  a  self  is  alive  with  a  certain  kind  of  life,  namely  human.  And  I  can  

make   no   sense   of   an   ‘how-­‐I-­‐am-­‐alive’   which   is   not   an   ‘how   this   body   is   alive’,  

individuated,  by  the  body  it  is  the  soul  of.  

  I   say   these   things   merely   so   as   to   set   the   scene   as   far   as   concerns   our  

ordinary,  secular,  concepts  of  ‘sameness’,  and  not  dogmatically,  for  I  am  aware  that  

if   the   issues   about   the   sameness   of   individuals   are   horrendously   complex,   all   the  

more   contested   is   the   kind   of   solution   to   them   I   have   just   so   superficially  

paraphrased.   I   raise   the   issues   here   as   preliminary   to   a   brief   reflection   upon   the  

following  quotation  from  a  Christian  authority,  who  says  much  the  same,  I  guess,  as  

most   of   us   here   would   want   to   hear   said,   in   support   of   the   proposition   that  

Page 3: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

Christians   and  Muslims   believe   in,   and   worship,   ‘one   and   the   same   God’.   Here   is  

what  that  Christian  authority  says:  

God,   the   Creator   of   all,   without   whom   we   cannot   do   or   even   think  anything  that   is  good,  has  inspired  to  your  heart  this  act  of  kindness.  He   who   enlightens   all   men   coming   into   this   world   (John   1.9)   has  enlightened  your  mind  for  this  purpose.  Almighty  God,  who  desires  all  men  to  be  saved  (1  Timothy  2.4)  and  none  to  perish  is  well  pleased  to  approve  in  us  most  of  all  that  besides  loving  God  men  love  other  men,  and  do  not   do   to   others   anything   they  do  not  want   to   be  done  unto  themselves  (cf.  Mt.  7.14).  We  and  you  must  show  in  a  special  way  to  the   other   nations   an   example   of   this   charity,   for   we   believe   and  confess  one  God,  although   in  different  ways,  and  praise  and  worship  Him  daily  as  the  creator  of  all  ages  and  the  ruler  of  this  world.  For  as  the  apostle  says:   "He   is  our  peace  who  has  made  us  both  one."   (Eph.  2.14)  Many   among   the  Roman  nobility,   informed  by   us   of   this   grace  granted  to  you  by  God,  greatly  admire  and  praise  your  goodness  and  virtues...  God  knows  that  we  love  you  purely  for  His  honour  and  that  we   desire   your   salvation   and   glory,   both   in   the   present   and   in   the  future  life.  And  we  pray  in  our  hearts  and  with  our  lips  that  God  may  lead   you   to   the   abode   of   happiness,   to   the   bosom   of   the   holy  patriarch  Abraham,  after  long  years  of  life  here  on  earth.1    

 

It  might  surprise  you  to  know  that  the  author  of  these  words  was  a  pope.  It  

will   almost   certainly   surprise   you   to   know   that   they   are   the  words   of   a  medieval  

pope,  Gregory  VII,  writing  in  the  late  eleventh  century  –   in  notably  more  generous  

terms  than  his  current  successor  -­‐   to  the  Muslim  King  Anzir  of  Mauritania:  no  soft  

liberal  eirenicist  this  Gregory,  nor  was  he  a  respecter  of  persons  who  could  require  

Henry   II,   the  Holy  Roman  Emperor,   to   travel   to  Rome  bare-­‐footed   in   the   snow   in  

penance  for  his  assertion  of  imperial  claims  against  the  papacy.  And  what  does  this  

pope  say?  Not  only   that  we,  Christians  and  Muslims,  believe  and  confess   the  same  

                                                                                                               1  Gregory  VII,  Letter  to  Anzir,  King  of  Mauritania,    in  Jacques  Dupuis,  The  Christian  Faith  in  the  Doctrinal  Documents  of  the  Catholic  Church,  7th  ed.,  (New  York:  Alba  House,  2001),  418-­‐‑419.      

Page 4: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

God,  but  also  that  we  ‘praise  and  worship  Him  daily  as  the  creator  of  all  ages  and  the  

ruler  of  this  world’,  albeit  ‘in  different  ways’:  for  Gregory  it  is  with  the  lex  orandi  as  

it  is  with  the  lex  credendi.  Now  I  wonder:  how  can  Pope  Gregory  be  so  sure  of  that?  

What   would   count   as   believing,   confessing,   praising   and   worshipping,   ‘the   same  

God’?   Much   to   the   same   point:   what   would   count   as   Christians   and  Muslims   not  

believing,   confessing,   praising   and  worshipping,   the   same   God?   Or   just   generally,  

how   do  we   know   that   your   God   and  my   God   are   one   and   the   same   God?   Or,   yet  

again—  but  this  time  to  ask  somewhat  more  pointedly  and  less  theoretically—  are  

those  Malaysian  Muslims  doctrinally  justified,  if  ecumenically  ungenerous,  who  are  

giving   their   Christian   compatriots   a   hard   time   for   taking   to   themselves   the   name  

“Allah,”  on  the  grounds  that  what  is  in  the  one  case  the  true  God  and  in  the  other  an  

idol  cannot  share  the  same  name?  

I   do   not   think   these   questions   are   idle.   I   do   not   think   you   can   just   say:   “it  

doesn’t  really  matter  whether  we  do  or  do  not  believe  in,  or  worship,  the  same  God,  

because   what   matters   is   that   Christians   and   Muslims   are   amicable,   do   not   feel  

divided  over  such  issues;  and  if  the  point  is  not  to  be  divided  over  issues  of  theology,  

the  best  way  is  to  avoid  entertaining  theological   issues  in  the  first  place.  So  let  the  

matter  rest  as  to  whether  we  believe  in  the  same  God,  on  some  agreed  criterion  of  

sameness.   For   in   any   case,     is   it   not   optimistic   enough   to   suppose   that   we   could  

agree  as   to   the  same  God  when  we  are   faced  with   the  even  more  dismal  prospect  

that  we  probably  will  not  agree  even  as  to  the  appropriate  criterion  of  sameness?  So  

let  us  not  divide  over  issues  which  in  principle  cannot  be  settled  and  attend  to  the  

more  practical  matter  of  how   to   live   in  peace,   and   to   the   areas  of  practical   action  

Page 5: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

where  we   can   find  uncontested   common  ground,   in  work   for   justice   and  peace   in  

our  global  village.”    

This   line   of   response   is,   I   concede,   good   ecumenical   practice   in   certain  

circumstances   –   I   mean,   often   it   is   good   practice   to   eschew   divisive   issues   of  

theology  pro  tempore  for  the  sake  of  practical  co-­‐operation  over  issues  on  which  we  

can   presuppose   agreement,   if   only   for   the   reason   that   the   habits   of   practical   co-­‐

operation  can  create  circumstances  more  favorable  to  successful  doctrinal  dialogue  

than  does  going   for   the   theological   jugular   from   the  outset.  But  neither  Christians  

nor  Muslims  can  ever  more  than  provisionally  detach  the  theological  issues  from  the  

practical,  justice  from  the  knowledge  of  God,  and  soon  enough  both  will  want  to  re-­‐

engage  the  one  with  the  other.  In  any  case,  though  I  do  know  some  Christians  who  

seem  not  theologically  to  mind  if  others  have  got  God  wrong  and  worship,  as  if  God,  

something  other  than  what  they  themselves  worship,  it  matters  to  me.  And  even  if  I  

am  in  a  minority  among  Christians  in  respect  of  this  theological  prescriptiveness,  it  

certainly  does  matter   to  most  Muslims  of  my   acquaintance.  Moreover,   I   share   the  

Muslim  view  that  others’  worship  of  the  wrong  God  is  a  sort  of  offence  against  mine,  

indeed  it  is  just  about  as  fundamental  as  offences  get,  being  a  form  of  idolatry.    Even  

if   I  believe   they  are  wrong   to   think   it   so,   I   can  very  well   see  why  my  belief   in   the  

incarnation   of   the   second   person   of   the   Trinity   in   the   human   nature   of   Christ  

matters   to   a   Muslim,   for   this   must   seem   simultaneously   to   have   introduced  

multiplicity   into  the  One  God  and  an   idolatrous  worship  of  a  human  person.  And  I  

expect   most   Muslims   will   understand   why   their   belief   that   the   Word   of   God   is  

incarnate  in  the  Q’ran  seems  to  me  hard  to  distinguish  from  the  idolatrous  worship  

Page 6: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

of  a  book,  even  if  they,  no  doubt,  will  maintain  that  I  am  wrong  to  do  so.  In  short,  I  

begin  from  the  proposition  which  in  my  experience  of  Muslims  I  share  with  most  of  

them,  namely,   that   if   it   is   true  that  we  do,  genuinely,  disagree  about  God,   then  our  

doing  so  matters  more  than  anything  else  at  all  on  which  we  do  happen  to  agree.  So  

do  we  disagree  about  God?  More  particularly   (it   is   the   focus  of   this  paper)  does  a  

Muslim’s  saying  ‘God  is  one’  and  a  Christian’s  saying,  ‘God  is  three  in  one’  mean  that  

Christians  and  Muslims  cannot  be  said  to  worship  the  same  God  -­‐  because  what  the  

one  affirms  about  God  the  other  denies?  

 

 Hick’s  “Kantian  apophaticism”    

 

  There  is  a  way,  proposed  by  John  Hick,  of  construing  the  differences  between  

Christians   and   Muslims   on   the   oneness   of   God   which,   without   eliding   those  

differences,  allows  the  conclusion  nonetheless  that  they  do  worship  the  same  God.  

Now  I  have  the  greatest  respect   for   John  personally,  and  for  his  views  –  after  all,   I  

was  for  a  few  years  his  successor  in  the  HG  Wood  chair  of  Theology  in  Birmingham  

University,  and  we  have  been  the  very  best  of  friends  since.  But  I  think  his  position  

is  profoundly  wrong,   though   interestingly   it   can   sound   curiously   like   that  of  Pope  

Gregory.   Like  Gregory,  Hick   concedes   that  we  believe   in   and  worship  God  each   in  

our   ‘different  ways’;   but  Hick,   also   like  Gregory,  believes   that   it   is,   to  use  his  own  

expression,  one  and  the  same  ‘ultimate  reality,’  unknowable  in  itself,  in  which,  or  in  

whom,  we  differently  believe  and  worship.  

Page 7: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

Of  course  I  cannot  here  do  justice  to  the  subtlety  of  Hick’s  argument,  though  I  would  

at   this   point   like   to   interject   a   note   of   generalised   anxiety   about   the   conduct   of  

interfaith   dialogue   in   that   form   in  which   it   takes   its   terms   from   the   comparative  

study   of   religion.   It   is   obvious,   I   suppose,   that   the   category   of   ‘religion’   is   a  

taxonomical  term  of  principally  academic  provenance.   I  mean,  I  know  of  no  one  at  

all   who   actually   practices   ‘religion’.   For   sure   I   don’t.   I   am   a   practicing   Catholic  

Christian.  Speaking  for  myself  it  bothers  me  little,  one  way  or  the  other,  if  someone  

within  the  academic  community  wants  to  tell  me  that,  in  going  to  Mass  on  a  Sunday,  

I  am  practicing  ‘religion’.  It  doesn’t  bother  me,  because  it  affects  my  going  to  Mass  in  

no  way  at  all  that  the  academic  student  of  religion  wants  so  to  describe  what  I  am  

doing   there,   for   there   is   nothing   internal   to   that   practice   of   mass   attendance   to  

which   that   academic’s   describing   it   as   ‘religious’   makes   the   least   difference.   The  

category   of   ‘religion’   may   be   important   to   the   academic   who   has   other,  

comparativist,   fish   to   fry.   But   the   believer   needs   no   such   term   of   art   in  which   to  

mediate  his  practice,  as  the  case  may  be,  of  Islam,  or  Christianity,  or  Zoroastrianism,  

or  whatever.  

What  begins  to  trouble  me  a  bit   is  when  that  academic  describes  the  whole  

system   of   belief   and   practice   of   Christianity   as   a   ‘religion’,   if   that   is   supposed   to  

entail   that   what  makes   that   belief-­‐system   not   something   else,   say,   not   a   ‘secular’  

practice,   is   some  character   it   has  on  a   comparativist’s   common   terms  with   ‘other’  

religions.  For  that  would  seem  to  amount  to  the  claim  that  what  I  would  find  in  my  

faith  tradition  which  makes  it   ‘religious’   lies  either  in  the  lowest  common  factor  of  

belief,  symbol,  ritual  and  practice  shared  by  all  ‘religions’,  that  is,  that  it  consists  in  a  

Page 8: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

sort  of  minimal  thread  of  continuity  between  them;  or  else  that  it  lies  in  something  

other   than  that  which   is   embodied   in   the  divergent  practices   of   a   particular   faith,  

something  that,  as  one  might  say,  they  all  in  some  way  are  said  to  aspire  to,  or  would  

ideally   converge   upon,   could   they   be   got   to   acknowledge   the   particularity   and  

cultural  contingency  of  their  avowed  and  explicit  practice  of  belief.    

Now   what   seems   wrong   with   the   LCF   standard   of   comparison   is   that   the  

minimum   that   is   common   to   all   ‘religions’   is   almost   certainly   going   to   be  what   is  

least   interesting   in   any   of   them;   and   what   seems   wrong   with   the   ‘convergent’  

account  of  the  commonality  uniting  religions  is  that  it  relativises  mine,  down-­‐sizing  

to  the  standing  of  the  provisional  what  I  think  of  as  absolute  claims,  while  offering  

nothing   in   epistemic   return.   For   what   my,   and   other   ‘religions’   are   supposed   to  

converge  upon  will  have  to  be  described  in  terms  that  are  neutral  between  them  all  

and  owned  by  none.  And   that,   it   seems   to  me,   is  no  basis   for   any   sort  of  dialogue  

between   them.  What   that   ‘convergent’  understanding  of   ‘religion’   appears   to  yield  

up   is   a   bastard   conception   of   dialogue   which,   as   between   any   two   religious  

traditions,   amounts   to   a   sort   of   tertium   quid:   a   sui   generis  discourse   of   dialogue  

standing  on   its  own  and  additional  to   the  discourses  proper   to  and  natural  within  

the   faith   traditions   themselves.   It   is  within   this   latter   conception  of   the   ‘religious’  

that  it  seems  right  to  place  Hick’s  account  of  it.  

    As   I   say,   in   comments   as   necessarily   brief   as   these,   it   is   hard   not   to   do   an  

injustice   to   Hick’s   way   of   making   the   distinction   between,   on   the   one   hand,   the  

culturally   specific   and   contingent   beliefs   and   ritual   practices   of   Islam   and  

Christianity,   and  on   the  other   the   ‘ultimate   reality’  which   is   the  common  object  of  

Page 9: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

both.  But  in  principle  the  distinction  seems  to  rely  on  two  different,  and  in  my  view  

incompatible,  antecedents,  one  philosophical  and  Kantian,  the  other  theological  and  

Eckhartian.   The   distinction   between   what   in   a   religious   formation   is,   as   it   were,  

‘cultural’   and  contingent  and   the   ‘ultimate   reality’   thus  diversified  by   its  doctrines  

and  rituals,   leaves  us  with  all   the  epistemological  problems  of  Kant’s  Ding  an  sich.  

For,  being  beyond   the   reach  of  all  possible  description,   this   ‘ultimate   reality’   is   an  

empty   category,   and   its   evacuation   of   all   descriptive   content   offers   merely   the  

appearance  of  providing  some  common  ground  –  some  sameness  of  God  –  while  at  

the  same  time  cutting  the  ground  from  under  any  possibility  either  of  affirming  or  of  

denying   that   ‘sameness’.   For   the   absolute   unknowableness   of   ‘ultimate   reality’  

eliminates   all   content   on  which   any   criteria   of   sameness   and   difference   can   get   a  

grip.   After   all,   if   your  doctrines   of   God   can   no   more   get   a   grip   on   this   ‘ultimate  

reality’   than  can  mine,  the  sameness  we  can  be  said  to  share   is  nothing  more  than  

the   common   possession   of   a   nescio   quid:   we   might,   in   short,   be   said   to   share   a  

common  ignorance.  But  I  am  afraid  that  if  you  share  with  me  my  complete  ignorance  

of  mathematics,  it  isn’t  as  if  there  is  any  mathematics  that  we  can  be  said  to  share.  

All  we  share   is   the   ignorance,  describable  as   ‘mathematical’  only   in   the  sense   that  

that  is  what  it  is  ignorance  of.  

Hick,  in  more  recent  writings,  however,  seems  to  think  that  he  gains  support  

for   his   neo-­‐Kantian   epistemology   in   some   specifically   Christian,   and   pre-­‐Kantian,  

‘mystical   theologies’,   especially   in   that   radically   ‘apophatic’   theology   of   the  

fourteenth   century   German   Dominican,   Meister   Eckhart.   For   sure,   Eckhart   does  

tempt  the  Hick-­‐minded  comparativist.  Indeed  he  does  distinguish  between  what  he  

Page 10: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

calls  Gott  and  the  Gottheit,  between  the  ‘God’  who  is  known  indirectly  as  mediated  

through  his/her  relation  with  creation,   that   is,  by  analogy  derived   from  the  divine  

effects,  and  the  ‘Godhead’  which  is  beyond  all  knowing,  even  by  analogy.  Famously,  

Eckhart  even  prays   to  God   ‘that  he  may  set  me   free   from  God’,  where  around  that  

second  occurrence  of   ‘God’,   naming   the  God   from  whom  Eckhart  wishes   to  be   set  

free,   it   has   become   customary   in   English   translations   to   insert   the   device,  

unavailable   to  medievals,   of   scare   quotes.   And   this   distinction   between   ‘God’   and  

‘the   Godhead’   can   seem   to   be   akin   to   Hick’s,   as   if,   on   an   extension   of   Eckhart’s  

ground   you   could   say:   ‘God’   as   known   by   us,   known   in   this  way   or   that  within   a  

particular  faith  tradition,  is  a  sort  of  provisional  God,  whereas  the  hidden  Godhead  

is  beyond  all  knowledge  and  description,  the  same  for  us  all.  

Admittedly,   Eckhart’s   distinction  between  Gott  and  Gottheit   is  misleadingly  

set   out   in   that   famous   sermon.   But   the   appropriation   of   the   distinction   on  Hick’s  

neo-­‐Kantian  lines  is  plausible  only  on  a  misinterpretation  of  it.  Eckhart’s  theological  

epistemology  is  much  indebted  to  Islamic  and  Jewish  sources,  and  especially  to  Ibn  

Sina,   or   “Avicenna,”   as   Eckhart   knew   of   him.   Both   acknowledge   the   ultimate  

unknowability   of   God,   though   Eckhart   frequently   presses   this   ‘apophaticism’   to  

rhetorical   extremes  –   especially,   it   goes  without   saying,   in  his   intensely   rhetorical  

vernacular   sermons.   But   neither   Eckhart   nor   Ibn   Sina   ever   deny   that   true  

affirmative  utterances  are  possible  of  the  one  and  only  God.  For  neither  of  them  is  

the  apophatic  the  doctrine  that  we  are  short  of  things  to  say  about  God  for,  on  the  

contrary,   both  maintain   that   creation   is   an   inexhaustible   repertoire   of   names   for  

God  –  they  agree  that  there  are  (at  least)  99  of  them.  The  apophatic  is  no  more  than  

Page 11: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

the  doctrine  that  true  of  God  as  99  names  are,  they  all  fall  short  of  him  –  and  let  us  

add  that  ‘him’  also  falls  short  of  God,  if  only  to  exactly  the  same  extent  as  does  ‘her.’    

And  I  suppose  it  is  all  of  a  piece  with  this  apophaticism  to  say,  as  Eckhart  does,  that  

if   what   you   mean   by   ‘God’   is   tied   up   too   closely   with   what   we   know   of   God’s  

relationship  with   creation,   then   that   knowledge   ‘fails’   of   God.   For   God  would   not  

cease   to   be   God   had   she   or   he   created   nothing   at   all.   For   Eckhart,   then,   the  

‘unknowability’   of   the   Godhead   is   not   the   unknowability   of   something   else   than  

‘God’.  The  unknowable  Godhead  is  just  the  other  side  of  the  divine  knowability,  and  

you  cannot  get  to  that  ignorantia  of  God  unless  it  is  a  docta  ignorantia,  an  ignorance  

acquired  through  the  patient  amassing  of  the  true  names  of  God,  on  the  other  side  of  

which   alone   the   true   unknowability   of   God   is   reached.   That   is   to   say,   through  

knowing  alone  do  you  make  it  into  the  ‘cloud  of  unknowing.’  That  is,  you  can’t  get  to  

where  the  unnameableness  of  God  lies  unless  you  get  those  true  names  right.  As  one  

might   say   in   Wittgensteinian   spirit,   you   cannot   in   a   sort   of   fit   of   apophatic  

enthusiasm  throw  the  ladder  of  naming  away  until  you  have  climbed  all  99  rungs  on  

the  way  to  the  top  of  it.  Or  to  deploy  a  different  metaphor,  the  knowability  and  the  

unknowability  of  God  are  like  shot  silk:  it  is  one  and  the  same  piece  of  dyed  silk,  but  

the  colour  you  see  varies,  depending  on  the  angle  of  refraction.  

I   very   much   doubt,   therefore,   that   Hick’s   appeal   whether   to   Kant   or   to   a  

misinterpreted  version  of  Eckhart  solves  the  problem  of  the  divine  ‘sameness’  with  

any  adequacy  of  fit  with  the  classical  traditions  of  either  Christian  or  Muslim  forms  

of  apophaticism.  Hick’s  position,  moreover,  would  seem  to  leave  us  with  the  worst  

of   both  worlds   from   an   ecumenical   point   of   view:   with   an   equivocal   dividedness  

Page 12: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

unresolved   so   far   as   concerns   anything   we   do   say   about   God   in   our   different  

traditions,  and  with  nothing  we  can  say  as  to  the  identity  of  any  ‘ultimate  reality’  we  

could   unite   on.   In   short,  we   need   a   solution  which   is  more   openly   dialectical.  We  

need  the  rough  and  tumble  of  argument.  We  appear  to  disagree,  especially  as  to  the  

‘oneness’   of  God.  But   do  we?  And  how   could   you   tell?   Is   it   simply   that  we  do  not  

understand  one  another  and  are  at  cross-­‐purposes,  or  is  the  disagreement  genuine,  

such  that,  agreeing  on  what  would  count  as  the  oneness  of  God,  I  say,  God  is  not  in  

that   sense   ‘one’   and   you   say   he   is?   And   if   there   is   between   us   a   genuine  

disagreement,  is  there  agreement  between  us  that  that  sort  of  disagreement  can  be  

settled   on   common  ground   and   rules   of   argument?   If  we  do  not   occupy   the   same  

territory  theologically,  is  there  any  meta-­‐theological  common  territory  on  which  to  

settle   our   disagreements?   Or,   to   put   it   in   other   terms,   what   are   the   rules   for  

disagreement?                                                

 

Christians  and  Muslims:  how  to  disagree  

 

Undoubtedly  Christians  and  Muslims  do  disagree  about  God.  But  of  what  kind  

is  their  disagreement?  Does  a  Muslim’s  saying  ‘God  is  one’  and  a  Christian’s  saying,  

‘God  is  three  in  one’  mean  that  Christians  and  Muslims  cannot  be  said  to  worship  the  

same  God  -­‐  because  what  the  one  affirms  about  God  the  other  denies?  Immediately  

we  ask   that  question  we  notice  an  asymmetry:  on  the  whole  Christian   theologians  

do  not  believe  that  the  Trinitarian  nature  of  God  excludes  the  Muslim  doctrine  of  the  

divine   oneness,   whereas   on   the   whole   Muslims   believe   that   it   does.   We   need   to  

Page 13: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

know  if  this  is  just  a  misunderstanding  on  one  side  or  the  other,  or  both,  if  we  are  to  

get  anywhere  at  all  with  our  central  question:  “Do  we  believe  in  the  same  God?”  Let  

us   begin,   then,   with   some   clarifications   which   will   help   us   narrow   down   the  

territory  of  this  potential  disagreement,  for  even  if  we  are  led  to  the  conclusion  that  

the  disagreement  is  real,  there  is  much  in  the  meantime  on  which  classical  Christian  

and   Muslim   theologies   would   appear   agree,   at   least   on   a   somewhat   negative  

semantic  condition,  namely  that  since  they  agree  as  to  what  their  respective  beliefs  

rule  out,  to  boot,  polytheism,  to  that  extent  at  least  they  agree  on  a  meaning  for  the  

oneness  of  God.  

What,   then,   does   it   mean   to   say   that   God   is   ‘one’?   It   means   at   least   two  

distinguishable   things   on  which   Christians   and  Muslims   undoubtedly   agree.   First,  

Christians  and  Muslims  that  there  is  one  and  only  one  God,  polytheism  is  ruled  out,  

there   is   no   multiplicity   of   gods.   Secondly,   they   are   agreed   that   there   is   no  

multiplicity   in   God,   God   is   utterly   simple,   without   composition   and   without  

distinction.  And  in  conjunction  the  two  propositions  mean  that  God  does  not  enter  

into   any   sort   of   relations   of   multiplicity   at   all.   Christians   and   Muslims   agree   on  

ruling  out  at  least  that  much.  When  it  comes  to  God  there  is  no  counting  to  do  of  any  

kind,  and  Eckhart  is  not  departing  from  mainstream  Christian  theologies  in  any  way  

when,  Trinitarian  theologian  though  he  be,  he  says  without  qualification:  ‘there  is  no  

number  in  God.’  How  so?  

You  can  look  at  one  side  of  this  ‘uncountability’  in  God  this  way.  Suppose,  in  

the   conduct   of   some   quite   lunatic   thought-­‐experiment,   you   were   to   imagine  

counting  the  total  number  of  things  that  there  are,  have  ever  been,  and  will  be,  and  

Page 14: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

you  get  to  the  number  n.  Then  I  say:  “fine,  that’s  the  universe  enumerated,  but  you  

have  left  out  just  one  being,  the  being  who  made  all  that  vast  number  of  things  that  

is  the  universe,  namely  God,”  and,  because  you  are  not  an  atheist,  you  agree  that  this  

is  so.  Do  you  now  add  God  to  the  list?  Is  that  what  I  am  asking  you  to  do?  Does  the  

total   number   of   things   that   there   are   now   amount   to   n+1?   Emphatically   not   for  

Eckhart;   and   –   just   in   case   you   were   to   agree   with   Pope   John   XXII   who   in   1329  

declared  Eckhart’s  theology  to  be  of  dubious  Christian  orthodoxy  –  emphatically  not  

for   the   unquestionably   orthodox   Thomas   Aquinas   either.   For   Aquinas   is   as  

unambiguous   as  Eckhart,   and   says   that  God’s   oneness   is   not   such   that  God   is   one  

more   in   any   numerable   series   whatever.   And   this   is   because   both   Eckhart   and  

Thomas   agree  with   the   pseudo-­‐Denys   that   ‘there   is   no   kind   of   thing   that   God   is.’  

Hence,  not  being  any  kind  of  thing,  not  being  ‘one  of  the  things  that  there  are,’  God  

cannot   be   counted   in   any   list   of   the   ‘everything   that   is.’   God’s   oneness   is   not   the  

oneness  of  mathematics,  as  it  would  be  were  I,  as  if  equivalently,  to  say:  ‘I’ll  have  one  

pie  for  lunch,  not  two.’  

You   might   object:   the   oneness   of   God   must   be   at   least   minimally  

mathematical,   for   it   enters   into   mathematical   relations   of   negation—‘ruling   out’  

must  come  into  it  again.  For  however  transcendent  you  may  say  your  understanding  

of  God’s  oneness  is,  it  must  entail  the  denial  of  a  plurality  of  gods.  You  must  know  at  

least  this  much  about  there  being  one  and  only  one  God:   like  my  one  pie  for  lunch  

the  oneness  of  God  excludes  there  being  two  of  them.  That,  of  course,  is  so,  but  not  

for   the  reason   that  God’s   ‘oneness’  excludes  plurality   in   the  same  way  as  does   the  

oneness   of   the   numeral   ‘one’.   What   is   wrong   with   saying   that   there   are   two,   or  

Page 15: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

twenty  two,  gods   is  not   that  you  have  added  up  the  number  of  gods   incorrectly.  A  

plurality  of  gods   is   ruled  out  by  God’s  oneness  because  God’s  oneness  entails   that  

counting  is  ruled  out  in  every  way.  It  is  the  adding  up  itself  which  is  mistaken.  For  if  

in  counting  more  than  one  God  you  get  polytheism,  in  saying  that  the  one  and  only  

God  is  numerably  ‘one’  you  are  neither  more  nor  less  mistaken  than  in  saying  there  

are   many.   Either   way   you   have   but   idolatry,   in   a   form   of   which   the   classical  

theologies  of  both  Christianity  and  Islam  have  long  had  the  measure.  Thus  far,  to  the  

extent   that   I   understand   both,   Christian   and   Muslim   theologies   have   no   need   to  

quarrel  over  the  oneness  of  God  understood  as  the  denial  of  polytheism.  You  need  to  

say  two  things  here  on  which  both  traditions  are  agreed.  First,   that,  as  of  God,  our  

grip  on  ordinary  senses  of  oneness  is  loosened,  perhaps  (as  some  Christians  in  the  

Middle  Ages  were  wont  to  say)  analogically.  Second,  that  if  positively  God’s  oneness  

is   beyond   our   ken,   our   grip   on   the   divine   oneness   is   not   so   slack   that  we   cannot  

know  what  it  excludes.  

But   does   not   Christian   Trinitarian   doctrine   reverse   all   this   as   regards   the   divine  

simplicity,  as  regards,  that  is,  number  in  God?  Granted  that  an  agreed  understanding  

of  God’s  oneness  rules  polytheism  out,  does  not  this  trinitarian  understanding  of  the  

divine  oneness  introduce  multiplicity  and  counting  into  God’s  inner  life  by  means  of  

its  differentiation  of  persons?  Do  not  Christians  say  that  there  are  three  persons  in  

one   God,   not   two,   not   four?   To   make   matters   worse,   do   you   remember   Bernard  

Lonergan’s  famous  theological  equation  with  which  he  used  to  introduce  every  class  

in  the  Gregorian  University  in  Rome:  that  5+4+3+2+1=0?    “In  the  Trinity,”  he  would  

say,   “there   are   five   ‘notions,’   plus   four   ‘appropriations,’   plus   three   ‘persons,’   plus  

Page 16: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

two  ‘relations,’  plus  one  ‘being,’  collectively  adding  up  to  the  zero  of  the  unknowable  

Godhead.”   What   now   about   Eckhart’s   ‘there   is   no   counting   in   God,’   resolutely  

Trinitarian  as  his  theology  is?  That  Christians  do  not  just  happen  to  say  such  things,  

that  they  are  impelled  to  say  them  by  force  of  their  core  doctrine  of  the  Incarnation,  

can   only   make   matters   worse,   for   that   nexus   between   the   doctrines   of   the  

Incarnation   and   of   the   Trinity,   so   tight   as   it   is   in   Christian   theology,   shows   to   a  

Muslim   just   what   is   wrong  with   the   doctrine   of   the   Incarnation   too.   The  Muslim  

responds  that  you  cannot  consistently  say  ‘God  is  one’  in  the  sense  of  being  utterly  

simple,  and  maintain  that   Jesus   is   the   incarnation  of   just  one  of   the  three  persons.  

Three   persons   in   one   God   is   an   idolatrous   oxymoron.   In   short,   Muslim   oneness  

appears  to  rule  out  the  Christian  Trinity.  

As   I   understand   it,   the   Muslim   objection   to   Trinitarian   theology   –   on   this  

point  of   the   logic  of   theological   language  –  ought  not   to  be   thought   to   rest  on   the  

vulgar  case,  easily  dismissed  on  their  own  grounds  as  much  as  on  Christian,  that  it  

involves  a   contradiction  of   a   simple  mathematical   sort,   since   it   seems   to  maintain  

that   the  personal  God  who   is  one  and   in  every  way  undivided   is  at   the  same   time  

divided   three  ways  by  a   trinity  of  persons.  Of   course  nothing’s  being   just  one   in  a  

certain  respect  can  be   three   in   just   that  same  respect.  There  cannot  be  more   than  

one  Denys  Turner,   even   if,   for   all   I   know,   there   are   three  people   in   the   telephone  

directory  called  ‘Denys  Turner’.  Now  you  might  think  that  in  speaking  of  the  Trinity  

of  persons  in  one  Godhead  nothing  more  is  claimed  than  to  say  that  there  are  three  

instantiations  of  the  divine  nature  in  the  same  way  that  three  persons  called  ‘Denys  

Turner’   are   three   instantiations   of   the   one   human   nature.   But   Christians   are   not  

Page 17: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

saying   that.   They   are   not   saying   that   just   as   there   are   three   human   beings   called  

‘Denys  Turner’,   one   in  New  Haven,   one   in  New  Canaan,   one   in   Litchfield,   three   in  

that  they  are  three  persons,  one  in  that  all  three  are  human  beings;  so,  in  the  same  

way,  there  are  three  divine  persons,  one  the  Father,  another  the  Son,  and  the  third  

the  Holy  Spirit,  albeit  one  in  that  each  is  an  individual  instance  of  the  divine  nature.  

For   that   is  self-­‐evidently   tri-­‐theism  and   is  utterly   indefensible,  even   for  Christians,  

and  of  course  for  Muslims.  But  if  Christians  are  saying  anything  other  than  that,  then  

are   they   not   perforce   saying   that   these   three   persons   are   one   person?   And   that  

amounts  to  a  plain  contradiction  –  no  mystery  there,  just  muddled  nonsense.  

Augustine   and   Thomas   Aquinas   alike   saw   that   what   gets   in   the   way   of  

Trinitarian  orthodoxy  here  is  the  troublesome  word  ‘person.’  You  can  see  why  you  

need  the  word  theologically;   indeed,  both  Christians  and  Muslims  want  to  say  that  

God  is  ‘personal,’  for  how  else  than  in  and  through  the  vocabulary  of  ‘person’  is    the  

language  of  knowledge  and  love  to  get  any  purchase  on  God,  which  the  scriptures  of  

both  our   traditions  not  merely  warrant  but   require.    But   I   think   it  worth  pointing  

out  that  it  is  not  only  for  Christian  Trinitarians  that  on  our  ordinary  understanding  

of   it,   the  word   ‘person’   is   going   to   cause   trouble.  As   I   say,  Augustine   and  Thomas  

knew,  and  do  not  need  instruction  from  us,  that  only  tri-­‐theistic  mayhem  would  be  

visited  upon  their  Trinitarian  theologies  were  they  to  try  to  work  them  through  on  

the   basis   of   the   standard  meanings   of   ‘person’   available   in   their   own   times.  More  

especially  Thomas  is  sensitive  to  the  problems  generated  by  the  accepted  standard  

definition   of   ‘person,’   inherited   from   Boethius,   as   ‘an   individual   substance   of   a  

rational  nature.’  It  is  because  he  defers  to  the  tradition  of  translation  which  renders  

Page 18: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

Nicaea’s  Greek  hypostasis  by   the   Latin   persona   that   he   uses   the   term  at   all   in   his  

Trinitarian  theology.  And  it  is  because  he  is  made  uneasy  by  the  term  that  he  avoids  

using  it  whenever  he  can.  The  problem  is  not  so  much  that  of  the  overtones  of  the  

word   ‘rational’   that   could   be   carried   over   into   a   misrepresentation   of   the   divine  

knowledge   (though   there   is   trouble   enough   in   wait   there),   but   because   of   the  

implications   of   the   expression   ‘individual   substance   of’   any   ‘nature.’   If   there   are  

three  Boethian  substances  in  God  –  individual   instantiations  of  a  common  nature  -­‐  

then  necessarily  tri-­‐theism  follows.    

But   Muslims   should   not   too   eagerly   gloat   over   this   Christian   theological  

predicament.   If   they  too  want  to  speak  of  God  as  a   ‘person,’   they  had  better  watch  

out  for  the  consequences  for  their  own  conceptions  of  the  oneness  of  God.  For  just  

as  indefensible  as  Christian  tri-­‐theism  would  be  a  Muslim  account  of  the  oneness  of  

the  divine  personhood   that   construed   it   as   the  one  and  only,   even  as   the  one  and  

only  possible,  instantiation  of  the  divine  nature.  For  that,  after  all,  is  the  condition  of  

the  last  dodo.  The  last  dodo  is  of  course  unique.  And  being  the  last  one  of  a  species  

which  procreates   sexually,   it   is  necessarily  unique:   there  cannot  be  any  more.  But  

otherwise  than  on  a  merely  contingent  and  de  facto  circumstance  such  as  that  of  the  

extinction  of  all  but  one  dodo,  there  is  no  possible  sense  to  the  notion  that  logically  

there   can   be   only   one   instantiation   of   a   nature.   For   any   nature   whatsoever,   it   is  

necessarily   the   case   that   logically   it   can  be   replicated.  God   is  not   the   individuated  

instance   of   any  nature,   even   of   the   divine   nature:   that   is   what   the   pseudo-­‐Denys  

meant  when  he  said  that  God  is  not  any  kind  of  being.  Hence,  it  is  not  and  cannot  be  

as  just  one  of  a  kind  that  God  is  ‘one;’  but  then,  neither  can  it  be  how  the  persons  of  

Page 19: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

the  Trinity   are   counted  as   ‘three.’  As  Eckhart   said,   ‘there   is  no   counting   in  God’—  

not,   as   we   must   now   understand   him   to   have   meant,   as   thereby   somehow  

prioritizing  the  oneness  of  God  over  the  Trinity,  but  as  a  condition  equally  of  non-­‐

idolatrous  talk  of  the  Trinity  and  of  non-­‐idolatrous  talk  of  the  divine  oneness.  There  

can  be  no  such  counting  in  God  either  way.  

The  trouble  with  talk  of  persons,  whether  deployed  of  the  divine  Trinity  or  of  

the  divine  oneness,   is,  then,  that,  by  force  of   its  natural  meaning,   in  the  one  case  it  

tends   to   generate   either   tri-­‐theistic   heresy   or   plain   contradictory   nonsense,  

depending   on  which  way   you   play   it;   and   in   the   other   it   generates   an   idolatrous  

conception  of  God   as   just   a   special   case   of   an   individuated  nature  where   just   one  

individual  exhausts  all  that  nature’s  possibilities.  And  that  cannot  be  what  Muslims  

teach   about   the   divine   oneness.   And   given   the   requirements   of   the   respective  

scriptural  authorities,  in  both  traditions  alike,  to  speak  of  the  ‘personal’  character  of  

God,  we  have   to  ask  how  much  of   that  natural  meaning  of   ‘person’  can  survive   its  

transference  upon  the  divine  being.  Or,  to  turn  the  problem  around  the  other  way  (it  

amounts  to  the  same  problem)  when  it  comes  to  the  personhood  of  God,  what  can  

be  left  of  our  secular  notions  of  either  oneness  or  threeness?  

Given   their   warnings   about   the   theological   trouble   caused   by   a   naïve  

employment  of   the   language  of   ‘persons,’   both  Augustine   and  Thomas   resorted   to  

the   admittedly   more   abstract,   and   certainly   humanly   less   appealing,   category   of  

divine  relations;  not,  be  it  known,  to  relations  of  or  between  divine  persons,  but  to  

persons  as  being  nothing  but  relations.  That,  of  course,  is  hard  talk,  and  the  language  

twists  and  bends  under  the  pressure  of  having  to  say  not  that  the  Father  generates  

Page 20: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

the  Son,  but  is  the  generating  of  the  Son;  not  that  the  Son  is  what  is  generated  by  the  

Father,  but  is  the  being  generated  by  the  Father;  and  even  more  awkwardly,  not  that  

the  Holy   Spirit   is  what   is   ’breathed   forth,’   or   ‘spirated,’   by   the  Father   through   the  

Son,  but  is  the  being  spirated  by  the  Father  through  the  Son.  There  is  nothing  here  

but  relatings,  no  somewhats  doing  the  relating.  The  language  strains.  But  bent  and  

twisted  as  the  language  is,  does  it  break?  

Here  is  an  analogy  which,  like  all  such  analogies,  does  some  good  explanatory  

work  so  long  as  it   is  not  thought  to  do  all  of  it.  There  is  one  and  only  one  highway  

known   as   the   Interstate   95.   But   it   has   two   directions,   one   south   from   Boston   to  

Miami,  the  other  north  from  Miami  to  Boston.  The  direction  north  is  of  course  really  

distinct  from  the  direction  south,  as  anyone  knows  to  their  cost  who  has  entered  the  

I-­‐95  in  the  wrong  direction  a  long  way  from  the  next  intersection.  And  yet  both  are  

really  identical  with  the  one  and  only  I-­‐95.  In  this  case,  we  are  under  no  temptation  

to  say  that  the  difference  between  the  direction  north  and  the  direction  south  is  just  

a  driver’s  point  of  view,  because  if  you  are  mistakenly  traveling  to  Boston  when  you  

want  to  get  to  Miami  it  is  the  direction  you  need  to  change,  not  your  point  of  view.  

As  a  Christian  theologian  might  analogously  say,  ‘modalism’  won’t  meet  the  case,  the  

distinction  of  persons  is   ‘real,’  not  notional.  But  equally,   in  the  case  of  the  I-­‐95,  we  

are  under  no  temptation  to  say  that  there  are  three  I-­‐95s,  the  road  north,  the  road  

south,  and  the  road  that  north  and  south  are  the  two  directions  of.  For  the  relations  

of   north-­‐bound   and   south-­‐bound   directions   are   really   identical   with   one   and   the  

same  I-­‐95.  As  we  might  say,  tri-­‐theism  is  not,  on  this  analogy,  entailed.  

Page 21: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

Of  course  I  admit  that  this  is  at  best  a  partial  analogy,  one  designed  to  allay  

some  initial  suspicions  concerning  the   logical  consistency  of  Trinitarian  orthodoxy  

with  a  resolute  defense  of  the  oneness  of  God.  But  that  the  analogy  at  best  limps  is  

shown   by   the   fact   that  whereas   the   two   directions,   north   to   Boston   and   south   to  

Miami,  are  real  relations,  and  are  really  distinct   from  one  another  as  relations,   the  

tarmac  covered  strip  is  a  real  entity,  distinct  from  the  directions  north  and  south  not  

as   they  are  distinct   from  one  another,  but  only  as   in  general   any  entity   is  distinct  

from  any  relation  –  in  the  way,  for  example,  that  I  am  distinct  from  my  being  on  the  

right  or  on  the  left  of  this  table.  And  if  you  were  to  press  my  analogy  on  the  doctrine  

of   the   Trinity,   you   might   indeed   avoid   modalism   and   tri-­‐theism,   but   you   would  

certainly   get   out   of   it   some   form   or   other   of   a   heterodox   subordinationism—   the  

doctrine  that  the  Father  is  existentially  prior  to  the  Son  and  the  Holy  Spirit,   just  as  

an   entity   is   existentially   prior   to   the   relations   which   depend   on   it.   And   for  

Christians,  Nicaean  orthodoxy  plainly  rules  that  out.    

What  Nicaean   orthodoxy   requires   Christians   to   say   is   that   Father,   Son   and  

Holy  Spirit  are  all  three  ‘relatednesses.’  And  however  strange  such  talk  may  seem  –  

and  it  is  extraordinarily  strange  –  you  say  it  because  only  on  such  terms  could  you  

say  without  gross  inconsistency  both  that  the  three  persons  are  really  distinct  from  

one  another  and  really  identical  with  the  one,  undivided,  Godhead.  But  therein  lies  

the  point:   if,   under   the  pressure  of   Christian  belief,   to  whit,   in   the  doctrine  of   the  

Incarnation,   the   meanings   of   ‘person’   and   of   ‘threeness’   have   migrated   off   the  

semantic  map  of  our  secular  vocabularies,   so  has   the  Muslim   ‘oneness.’  For,  as  we  

have   seen,   the   oneness   of   the   one   personal   God   of   Islam   cannot   be   thought   of   in  

Page 22: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

terms  of   the  one  and  only   instance  of   the  divine  nature  either.   In  either   tradition,  

then,   the   meanings   of   ‘person,’   ‘threeness’   and   ‘oneness’   have   all   migrated  

theologically   off   the   same   semantic   map,   and   to   the   same   extent.   To   which  

conclusion  I  would  add  only  this  rider,  that  it  is  much  easier  for  a  Muslim  than  it  is  

for  a  Christian  to  forget  this,  as  if  the  ‘oneness’  of  God  were  easier  to  get  into  your  

head  than  the  Trinity.  It  isn’t.  

 

Getting  the  “apophatic”  right  

 

At  this  point  it  is  tempting  on  both  sides  to  appeal  to  the  ‘apophatic’  distance  

between   God   and   any   creatures   or   any   creaturely   analogy.   This   was   Augustine’s  

move  –   it  surprises  some,   though   it  shouldn’t  –   that   in  book  15  of  his  De  trinitate,  

where,  having  for  fourteen  books  played  out  his  analogy  between  the  soul’s  highest  

powers  and  the  persons  of  the  Trinity  for  all  its  worth,  he  concludes  that  of  course  it  

doesn’t  work;  or,  as  in  his  more  compendious  way,  Lonergan  did,  who  having  piled  

up  on  top  of  one  another  all  fifteen  of  the  Trinitarian  enumerations  concluded  that  

they  added  up   to  a   zero,   cognitively   speaking.  Well,   as  we  will   see,  we  do  have   to  

make   some   such   appeal.   God   is   a  mystery,   and   I   think   it   fair   to   say   that   the   best  

theologies  in  either  faith  tradition  are  designed  not  to  eliminate,  but  on  the  contrary,  

to  safeguard,  the  mystery  which  God  is.  But,  as  we  saw  with  Hick,   it   is  essential  to  

get  the  mystery  of  God  in  the  right  place.  And  there  are  two  ways  of  getting  it  in  the  

wrong   place.   You   have   certainly   misplaced   it   if   what   you   say   in   your   theology  

amounts  to  forms  of  contradiction  detectable  by  the  means  of  ordinary  logic.  Plain  

Page 23: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

contradictions  are  not  apophatic:   they  are  simple  nonsense.  Contradictions  do  not  

point  to  mysteries  beyond  our  understanding.  They  simply  fail  to  point.  

On  the  other  hand,  if  the  appeal  to  the  apophatic  is  meretricious  in  support  of  

plain   nonsense,   neither   can   we   allow   the   Hickian   move   which   simply   shifts   the  

problem  over  to  the  other  horn  of  the  dilemma.  There  is  no  way  out  of  the  apparent  

conflict   between   Islam   and   Christianity   on   the   question   of   the   oneness   and  

threeness   of   God   simply   by   evacuating   both   of   all   such   content   as   could   entail   a  

contradiction.  That  would  be  no  more   justifiable  an  appeal   to   the   ‘apophatic’   than  

would  Hick’s,  indeed  it  would  be  wrong  for  exactly  the  same  reason.  That  is  to  say,  

just   as  Hick’s   ‘ultimate   reality’   conflicts  with   nobody’s   theology   because   a   fortiori  

there   can   be   no   knowable   descriptions   true   of   it   to   conflict   with   anything,   so  

concepts   of   the   divine   oneness   and   of   Trinitarian   threeness   which   have   no  

consequences   for   counting   in  God   gain   an   ecumenical   reduction   in   conflict   by   the  

device   of   nothing’s   being   asserted   on   either   side.   But   both   Christian   and  Muslim  

doctrines   of   God   do,   as   we   have   seen,   have   some   exclusionary   consequences   for  

counting:  for  Christians  there  are  three  persons  in  one  God,  not  two  or  four;  and  for  

both  Christians  and  Muslims,  there  is  one  God  and  not  two  or  twenty  two.  For  both  

alike,  the  simplicity  of  God  is  preserved;  for  both  alike,  everything  true  of  God  is  God.  

So  have  we  made  any  progress  at  all?  Certainly  some,  but  not  very  much.  But  

then  I  am  not  sure  how  much  progress  we  should  expect  to  have  made.  At  its  most  

pessimistic  you  might  say  that  all   I  have  achieved  so   far   is  a  sort  of   logical   throat-­‐

clearing,   nothing   yet   having   been   offered   positively,   but   only  what  will   not   do   by  

way  of  an  answer  to  the  question,  “Do  Christians  and  Muslims  believe   in  the  same  

Page 24: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

God?”  On  the  Christian  side  we  have  apophatically  to  say  that  our  way  of  counting  

persons   in  God   is   a   pretty   off-­‐beat   sort   of   counting,   since   it   is   not   really   persons,  

because  not  really  individuals  in  any  countable  sense,  that  we  are  talking  about;  and  

yet,   those   Christians   cannot   so   apophatically   evacuate   the   divine   three-­‐ness   as   to  

disable  their  entitlement  to  say:  ‘three,  not  two,  not  four.’  And  the  case  matches  up  

on  the  Muslim  side.  Muslims  must  place  an  apophatic  restriction  on  their  ‘oneness’  

of  God,  for  they  know  that  it  cannot  be  as  you  might  count  the  number  of  Gods  that  

you  know  there  is  only  one,  even  if  they  also  know  better  than  to  be  so  apophatically  

extreme  about  the  divine  oneness  as  to  disable  their  right  to  reject  polytheism.  But  

that  being  so,  it  is  on  their  own  account  of  the  divine  oneness  that  Muslims  should  

beware  of   concluding   that  Christians  merely   contradict   themselves  when   they  say  

that  there  are  three  persons  in  one  God,  or  that  they  thereby  compromise  the  divine  

oneness.  Muslims  might  have  other  reasons  to  say  that  Christians  are  wrong  about  

God,  perhaps  even  that  they  are  idolatrously  wrong.  But  what  Christians  claim  about  

the  Trinity  does  not  at  least  contradict  what  Muslims  say  about  the  divine  oneness.  

But  are  they  the  same  God?  What  little  my  argument  at  best  demonstrates  is  

that  Christians  and  Muslims  meet  a  necessary  condition  for  the  sameness  of  the  God  

they   confess   and   worship,   namely   that   both   rule   out   the   same   contraries   (all  

plurality  of  gods  and  all  plurality  in  God)  and  that  neither  need  rule  out  the  other  in  

so   doing.   But   I   have   made   no   attempt   to   meet   those   sufficient   conditions   for  

sameness   that   would   be   required   to   establish   that   Christians   and   Muslims   do  

worship  the  same  God.  That  is  simply  because  I  do  not  know  what  those  conditions  

are—I  don’t  know  how  to  describe  them,  though  I  do  believe  that,  whatever  they  are  

Page 25: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

they   can   and  will   be  met   in  what   Christians   call   the   ‘beatific   vision’   and  both   call  

‘paradise.’   This   plea   of   ignorance   is   not   a   merely   English   conceit   of   academic  

modesty.   I  mean,  really   I  don’t  know  what  those  conditions  are.  But  then  I  am  not  

pretending  to  think  you  don’t  know  what  they  are  either.  Really  you  don’t.  And  this  

is  because,  as  I  have  said,  all  our  secular  criteria  for  identity  are  disabled  as  of  God,  

whether   these   are   appropriate   for   silk   or   wool   stockings   or   for   the   identity   of  

persons.   For   if   we   cannot   say   that   God   is   in   any   ordinary,   secular,   sense,   an  

individual   then   it   follows   that  we   cannot   employ   our   standard   secular   criteria   to  

establish  individual  sameness.  Likewise,   if  we  cannot  say  that  the  three  persons  of  

the  Trinity  are  in  any  ordinary  sense  three  ‘somewhats,’  then  it  does  not  seem  clear  

on   what   grounds   you   could   say   that   they   are   not   each   identical   with   the   one  

undivided   God.   So   to   say,   the   question   of   whether   it   is   true   that   there   are   three  

persons   in  one  God  is  rationally  undecidable,  a  matter  of   faith,  of  what   is  or   is  not  

revealed.   Of   course,   then,   Christian   do   not   and   cannot   claim   to   know   how   there  

could  be  three  persons  in  one  God.  But  then,  the  oneness  of  God  is  no  less  beyond  

our  understanding  too.  And  it  is  just  for  that  reason  that  it  seems  impossible  to  come  

up   with   any   knock-­‐down   way   of   establishing   the   identity   of   the   Christian   and  

Muslim  Gods,  as  if,  like  the  two  pairs  of  socks,  I  could  produce  a  pair  from  behind  my  

back,  and  then  do  it  again,  and  ask  you  to  compare  them  for  identity.    

But   if,   short   of   the   beatific   vision   in  which  we   Christians   and  Muslims   can  

hope  to  share,  I  am  skeptical  of  any  conclusive  demonstration  of  sameness,  there  is  

something  else  I  can  do  -­‐  and  I  hereby  do  it.  I  can  offer  a  challenge,  to  both  Christians  

and  Muslims,   to   come   up  with   a  way   of   showing   that  when   in  Malaysia   both   call  

Page 26: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

upon   “Allah”   they   are   not   calling   on   the   same   God.   That   is,   I   challenge   them   to  

provide  such  demonstration  of   their  dismissals  of   the  other’s  claims  on   that  name  

as,  each  on  their  own  terms,  does  not  presuppose  or  entail  a  reductively  idolatrous  

and  fundamentalist  betrayal  of  their  own  best  traditions.  For  my  part,  I  will  offer  no  

prize   for   the  best  entry.  That  would  be  unfairly   to   rig   the  competition.  For   if   I  am  

right  it  cannot  be  done  at  all.    

And  that’s  because,  in  concluding  on  what  will  seem  an  excessively  downbeat  note,  I  

have  not   told   the  whole  story.2  Not  by  a   long  chalk.  Not,  however,  because   I   could  

have  told  it  but  didn’t,  but  because  it  cannot  be  told  at  all  and  because  there  is  only  

an  idolatrous  and  reductive  betrayal  in  the  attempt  to  tell  it.  Indeed,  all  along  in  this  

paper   that   has   been  my   point,   namely,   that   short   of   the   beatific   vision   the  whole  

story  does  not  lie  within  our  pre-­‐mortem  power  to  tell.  And  also  my  point  has  been  

to  argue  for  that  impossibility,  or  maybe  just  to  exhibit  it,  because  it  is  essential  to  

know  that  we  cannot  tell  the  whole  story,  and  because  it  is  essential  not  only  that  we  

do   our   theologies,   but   also   that   we   live   our   lives,   under   the   constraint   of   that  

impossibility.  To  possess  the  whole  story  is  possible  only  within  the  beatific  vision,  

indeed  being  able  to  tell  it  is  paradise.  So  if  it  is  so  important  to  know  that  we  cannot  

for  the  nonce  tell  it,  it  is  just  as  important  to  know  that  it  is  there  to  be  told  and  that  

one  day  we  will  find  ourselves  partaking  in  the  unimaginable  joy  of  its  telling.  

                                                                                                               2    An  earlier  version  of  this  paper  concluded  at  the  end  of  the  last  paragraph.  I  wrote  this  revised  conclusion  after  a  conversation  with  Elena  Lloyd-­‐‑Sidle,  a  Muslim  student  at  the  Yale  Divinity  School.  She  made  me  think  of  Dante’s  Folco.  I  am  deeply  grateful  to  Elena  for  that  conversation.  

Page 27: Turner FINAL paper - Yale University · where!we!can!find!uncontested!common!ground,!in!work!for!justice!and!peace!in! ourglobalvillage.”!! This line of!response! is,! I! concede,!

As  Dante  knew.  Folco,  in  Dante‘s  Paradiso,  tells  us  that  there  within  the  vision  

of  God,  where  at  last  all  see  and  all  is  seen  and,  being  seen,  all  is  thereby  redeemed,  

‘we   do   not   remember   our   fault,   here   we   simply   smile’3  at   the   ‘art   that   makes  

beautiful  the  great  result.’4  Within  that  ‘great  result,’  Folco  tells  us,  he  can  afford  to  

forget  that  which  on  earth  he  had  need  to  be  weighed  down  by,  the  memory  of  his  

sins.     And   so   in   paradise   he   can   afford   to   smile.   And   we,   like   Folco,   will   be   able  

simply  to  smile  at  our  sins,  because  then,  without  either  excusing  or  trivializing  their  

depravity,   they   can   no   longer  weigh   us   down,   can   place   no   burden   of   guilt   upon  

memory.  And  as   it  will  be  with  our   sins   so  will   it  be   for  our  presently  unresolved  

theological  divisions.  Then  together  we  will  be  able  to  do  what  we  cannot  do  now.  

For  now  we  must   remember   them,   there   is  no  honesty   in  a  premature  attempt   to  

forget  them.  Only  then  will  we  be  able  to  smile  at  those  divisions—with  smiles  far  

removed  from  the  raucous  laughter  of  those  who  ridicule  them,  as  if  it  had  been  only  

for   foolishness   that   those   divisions   had   mattered   to   us.   For   they   did   matter.   We  

could  not  have  abandoned  them  without  loss  of  such  truth  as  was  then  possible  for  

us.  For  now  we  must  live  with  those  divisions,  sure  only  of  a  common  hope  that  they  

will  be  overcome,  that  memory  redeemed  will  be  able  to  tell  a  healing  narrative  that  

we  cannot  now  tell.  But  in  paradise  we  will  look  one  another  in  the  eye  and  simply  

smile   at   the   glint   that   we   see   there.   Then   we   will   smile   with   the   joy   of   memory  

healed,  with  the  joy  that  we  each  see  in  the  eyes  of  the  other  at  our  divisions  at  last  

resolved.  Then,  indeed,  but,  for  now,  not  yet.  

                                                                                                               3  Paradiso,  9,  103-­‐‑4.  4  Paradiso,  9,  106-­‐‑7.