The Simplicity of the Living God

27
Modem Theology 21:2 April 2005 ISSN 0266-7177 (Print) ISSN 1468-0025 (Online) THE SIMPLICITY OF THE LIVING GOD: AQUINAS, BARTH, AND SOME PHILOSOPHERS CHRISTOPHER A. FRANKS The notion of divine simplicity could hardly be mistaken for a favorite of most modern theologians. Simplicity is part of that set of divine attributes, along with immutability and impassibility, derived by way of a process of remotion often assumed to represent ancient Greek sensibilities rather than biblical ones. Twenty years ago, Robert Jenson could observe that "rejection of the dominant tradition just at this point is endemic in contemporary theology". 1 The past twenty years have done little to alter the situation. Alongside this theological dismissal has stood a robust tradition defend- ing divine simplicity. Philosophers of religion have analyzed the notion intently, not to defend it against suspicious theologians so much as to demonstrate to those suspicious of theism that the traditional concept of God is not incoherent. 2 Although these two conversations stand in some ways at cross purposes, the theologians and the philosophers share some significant agreements about simplicity. Specifically, these philosophers typically take themselves to be arguing about a notion of simplicity exemplified by Thomas Aquinas, and theologians rarely dispute the supposed identity between Aquinas's account of simplicity and the subject of contemporary debate. The simplic- ity discussed by so many pre-modern theologians is commonly understood by both theologians and philosophers to be a specifically philosophical (i.e., not derived from revelation) teaching in broad continuity with ancient Greek thought. 3 For philosophers, that is what recommends it for defense; for theologians, that is what marks it as a non-biblical accretion to be rooted Christopher A. Franks Department of Religion and Philosophy, High Point University, Box 3511, University Station, High Point, NC 27262, USA © Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005. Published by Blackwell Publishing, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxfoid OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Maiden, MA 02148, USA.

description

by Christopher Franks

Transcript of The Simplicity of the Living God

Page 1: The Simplicity of the Living God

Modem Theology 21:2 April 2005 ISSN 0266-7177 (Print) ISSN 1468-0025 (Online)

THE SIMPLICITY OF THE LIVING GOD: AQUINAS, BARTH, AND SOME PHILOSOPHERS

CHRISTOPHER A. FRANKS

The notion of divine simplicity could hardly be mistaken for a favorite of most modern theologians. Simplicity is part of that set of divine attributes, along with immutability and impassibility, derived by way of a process of remotion often assumed to represent ancient Greek sensibilities rather than biblical ones. Twenty years ago, Robert Jenson could observe that "rejection of the dominant tradition just at this point is endemic in contemporary theology".1 The past twenty years have done little to alter the situation.

Alongside this theological dismissal has stood a robust tradition defend­ing divine simplicity. Philosophers of religion have analyzed the notion intently, not to defend it against suspicious theologians so much as to demonstrate to those suspicious of theism that the traditional concept of God is not incoherent.2

Although these two conversations stand in some ways at cross purposes, the theologians and the philosophers share some significant agreements about simplicity. Specifically, these philosophers typically take themselves to be arguing about a notion of simplicity exemplified by Thomas Aquinas, and theologians rarely dispute the supposed identity between Aquinas's account of simplicity and the subject of contemporary debate. The simplic­ity discussed by so many pre-modern theologians is commonly understood by both theologians and philosophers to be a specifically philosophical (i.e., not derived from revelation) teaching in broad continuity with ancient Greek thought.3 For philosophers, that is what recommends it for defense; for theologians, that is what marks it as a non-biblical accretion to be rooted

Christopher A. Franks Department of Religion and Philosophy, High Point University, Box 3511, University Station, High Point, NC 27262, USA

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005. Published by Blackwell Publishing, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxfoid OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Maiden, MA 02148, USA.

Page 2: The Simplicity of the Living God

276 Christopher A. Frante

out. Thus, just as much recent philosophy of religion seeks to analyze sim­plicity with no reference to revealed doctrines, so much contemporary the­ology echoes the sentiment of Barth that in scholasticism simplicity was "exalted to the all-controlling principle, the idol . . . devouring everything concrete".4

This essay calls for a reconsideration of the notion of divine simplicity, especially as understood by Aquinas. The agreements I have described about the status of this notion only obscure the true character of Thomas's teach­ing. In response, I question the assumption that the traditional notion of simplicity was imported relatively unchanged from ancient Greek thought, largely unaffected by a theological investigation of biblical sources. On the contrary, Thomas's notion of simplicity is shaped by the church's reflections on trinity and Incarnation. Indeed, far from being a philosophical distortion that theologians can jettison without loss, this notion of simplicity, Thomas shows us, is at the heart of a fully Christian account of God. In particular, simplicity teaches us how to think about a God who is the fully Living One, the one who lives so fully and completely that this Life is uncontradictable. This God is the source of life for others, and precisely as cause of being, this God is fully free to create (or not to create), free even to enter into union with creation, even the intimate union of the Incarnation, without abandoning that Life.

After explicating this notion of simplicity, I will spend a great deal of the article comparing it with what is often taken to be Thomas's understanding of simplicity. The notion of simplicity is analyzed most often and in the most depth by philosophers of religion, and I will look at a particularly subtle example of such analysis in the defense of simplicity offered by Eleonore Stump and Norman Kretzmann. Stump and Kretzmann consider simplicity in abstraction from the ecclesial reflections on Trinity and Incarnation that are in fact determinative for how Thomas discusses simplicity. As a result, their analysis remains innocent of the lessons Thomas tries to teach by way of simplicity. Thomas fundamentally reorients our thought about God by pointing to the peculiar sort of discontinuity between God and creatures required by Christian doctrine. Thus, they discuss a God who is different from creation, but not different enough. Their concept of simplicity devel­ops within the horizon of being, rather than pointing to being's source. They end up struggling mightily over the problem of reconciling God's simplic­ity with God's freedom to create: how can a being with no distinctions, who wills himself necessarily, also will some things without necessity? The problem does not arise for Thomas's teaching, in which simplicity does nothing if not guarantee the divine freedom to be the same fully actual Life whether as creator or without creation. Because they miss the specific char­acter of what it means for Thomas to consider God as source of being, Stump and Kretzmann conduct their discussion in too univocal a fashion. As a result, although they claim to have solved the problem and rescued a

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 3: The Simplicity of the Living God

The Simplicity of the Living God 277

reduced version of simplicity, they remain stuck within the distinctions made within the world, and so cannot reconcile simplicity and freedom. Their 'defense' turns out to be a sell-out. Looking at how their defense of simplicity fails is instructive for recalling the crucial elements in an account of simplicity that is faithful to Thomas.

If we grasp how the standard assumption that simplicity is intelligible apart from revelation distorts our understanding of Aquinas's concerns, then perhaps we can come to see that Barth, rather than folks like Stump and Kretzmann, is truly the modern heir to Thomas's understanding of divine simplicity. I conclude this essay by showing how Barth's treatment of sim­plicity, while not at all identical to Thomas's, stands on the same lessons about God's causality, learned from reflection on the Trinity and the Incarnation.

Some of the confusions over what divine simplicity means have recently been confronted by Stephen R. Holmes.5 He tries to reclaim Christian tradi­tion for theologians by showing how old texts have been read in terms of a modern ontology. Simplicity in the tradition is not about the perfectly actu­alized monad whose attributes are explored by philosophers of religion and whose alleged Greek pedigree prompts its dismissal by theologians. Against such assumptions, Holmes suggests, on the one hand, that traditionally the­ologians have been more circumspect about accounting for God in terms of their own ontological assumptions, and, on the other, that recent attempts to recover "the assumed personal and relational ontology of the patristic tra­dition"6 offer a set of ontological assumptions in which divine simplicity might be less problematic.

The present article pushes the case for simplicity further. Holmes not only defends the traditional notion of simplicity while distinguishing it from the concept debated by analytic philosophers. He also suggests that simplicity might even be useful theologically. For example, it helps cut through the medieval nominalism-realism debate regarding universal ideas; they are neither arbitrary names nor real things that constrain God, for they are ideas in the divine mind, which are therefore nothing other than God.7 This is, of course, an important place to apply the doctrine of simplicity, but Holmes understates the importance of simplicity significantly. Simplicity is not merely a teaching that could be useful and could be recoverable if we rejected certain modern ontologies. In fact, the suggestion that our ontology makes all the difference seems to misidentify what is wrong with modern construals of simplicity. To recover the ancient teaching on simplicity, what is needed is not a revision in our account of being, but a lesson in what it means in the Christian story to be a cause of being. Simplicity learned from Aquinas not only proves useful in resolving certain theological puzzles; it conforms our speech about God to Christian convictions about the God-world relation learned from reflection on the Trinity and the Incarnation, and therefore it is crucial to a fully Christian discussion of God.

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005

Page 4: The Simplicity of the Living God

278 Christopher A. Frante

I also extend Holmes's treatment by paying sustained attention to the concept of simplicity employed by certain philosophers. Holmes acknowl­edges the philosophical debate, but leaves it to one side, citing his suspicion that "the forms of the doctrine being debated are not necessarily the most useful ones from a specifically Christian perspective".8 I concur with this judgment, but will show why the notion of simplicity under debate is prob­lematic for Christian theology, why it is unlike Aquinas's view, and why it ultimately fails even on its own terms. In short, the notion of simplicity evident in Stump and Kretzmann neglects the radical construal of the rela­tion between God and creation at the center of Aquinas's discussion of sim­plicity. It therefore proceeds too univocally and ends up describing not the Living God but what Barth would call a human notion of "the simple", a notion that cannot sit coherently with a free act of creation.

Thomas on Simplicity

My claim that Thomas's notion of simplicity depends on lessons learned from revelation may seem dubious. Surely Aquinas is among those Barth faults for treating simplicity first within the doctrine of God.9 The whole point of Barth's diatribe is to suggest that such a procedure fails to allow the doctrine of the Trinity to condition the discussion of simplicity.

It is true that the connection to Trinity and Incarnation is not emphatically announced in Thomas as it is in Barth. Nevertheless, Trinitarian and Incar-national concerns play a formative role. The key to understanding the dis­tinctive shape of Thomas's treatment of simplicity is to see how his whole discussion of God reflects a particularly Christian account of the distinction between God and creatures.

This distinction is such that God cannot be grasped from the side of the creature. A growing chorus of scholars has helped us to perceive the apophaticism of the Summa Theologians early questions on God.10 The five ways of question two, it has been noted, do not achieve anything like a knowledge of what God is; rather, natural theology "terminates in the judg­ment that there is that of which we have no knowledge".11 The following nine questions (3-11) must be read in light of the preface to question three on simplicity. There Thomas insists that having determined that God is, the inquiry must now turn not to what God is, but to what God is not, since from God's effects humans can have no knowledge of God's essence. These ques­tions thus do not develop a concept of God according to certain attributes. Rather, they develop a sort of negative theology, outlining rules for what we cannot say about the God of whom we have no concept. Not that we can say nothing, for we can in fact identify several rules for talking about God. But these rules do not mark out the space of a concept. On the contrary, they dis­qualify the use of certain earthly distinctions in talking about the One who cannot be captured by demarcations that set off one being from another. Such

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 5: The Simplicity of the Living God

The Simplicity of the Living God 279

distinctions fail before the One who causes all being, the One who is "outside the order of all beings".12

At work in these questions is, of course, a neoplatonic sensibility learned from Dionysius the Areopagite. But precisely as Dionysian, it goes beyond pagan neoplatonism to reflect the truth of the world as created. Thomas's fundamental insight into the discontinuity between God and the creature is expressed in his famous rejection of any distinction between existence and essence in God.13 His point is to shake up our normal assumption that "being" is a sort of given substratum onto which forms are added, bringing perfections with them. Burrell points out that when Aquinas interprets esse in terms of act, essence becomes not the perfecting factor but the limiting factor.14 Therefore, in Carlo Leget's words, "esse as actuality contains every possible perfection and the fact that a substance does not possess every per­fection must be ascribed to the limitations of its essence".15 A reversal is worked here whereby our existence, which appears more sure to us, is con­fessed to be contingent and fragile in the face of the absolute priority of the existence of God. This does not give us some handle by which to understand God. In fact, by identifying God's essence with esse as pure act, Thomas excludes the sorts of distinctions we would need to get a grasp on God. But this move does help us see the sort of dependence all beings have on their Creator, and thus it points in the direction of just how radically different God is from any being.

Using this notion of pure act to specify how God is incomprehensible to us is precisely what Thomas is doing in the discussion of simplicity. For Thomas, simplicity is not an attribute of a being with no distinctions. It is the necessity of denying that any of the distinctions that help us discern created realities can possibly help us when our subject is the One who is the cause of all being. Again, simplicity is a way of ensuring that the One of whom we speak is indeed the prima causa of all things. Something that does not exist, that is not "in act", cannot bring anything about. Thus, what is only "potential" cannot bring itself about, but must be brought about by some­thing in act. If God has any potency, God would need to be acted on by some other agent, and so would not be the ultimate cause of which Thomas is trying to speak.16 If this notion of actus purus in all simplicity does help us speak properly of God, then we certainly must confess that everything that is in God is God. But this is, again, simply to guarantee the proper distinc­tion between God and the world, a distinction that reminds us that how our language refers to God remains a mystery to us.

This way of thinking about God is central to Aquinas's whole discussion of the one God. Beginning with the treatment of simplicity, Aquinas dis­cusses many predications that can be made of God, and each of them is described according to its ability to point to some aspect of God's full actu­ality. If perfection is predicated of God, as it must be according to the scrip­tures, Aquinas relates perfection to the lack of any potency, i.e., the full

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 6: The Simplicity of the Living God

280 Christopher A. Frante

actuality, of God.17 If immutability is predicated of God, again as the scrip­tures demand, Thomas shows how mutability would imply potency, and hence not full actuality, in God.18 It is the fully actual God who is the central referent of all these predications. Every question, therefore, reflects that reversal whereby God is acknowledged as cause of being and creatures in turn are recognized as contingent and dependent. It is God's Life that is determinate and uncontradictable, while our lives hang on the participation in Life granted us by God.

Since God's essence is simply esse, "to be", all other things have being by participation in God. Thomas likens God's esse to fire. "Just as that which has fire but is not itself fire is on fire by participation, so that which has being but is not being, is a being by participation."19 This is not to say that God is simply that "being in general" that is predicated of all things.20 God is dis­tinct from such diffused "being". God is self-subsistent. But God is that primary actus purus, so as to be the source of existence for all other things. Thus, existence belongs to other things by participation, but it is said of God essentially. So "every being that is in any way is from God".21 The universe utterly depends on God for its existence. The fullness of God's action in this respect just is God's simplicity. God is simple in God's uniqueness as the one on whose unchanging activity everything else depends.

The notion of "unchanging activity" must not be misunderstood. God's unchangeableness for Aquinas is not some static prison that makes attribut­ing "activity" to God paradoxical. Rather, he connects mutability with the possibility of going from not existing to existing and back again.22 It is pre­cisely this mutability that God does not have, for rather than depending on existence coming to him from some other agent, God is the source of exis­tence, with the power of bestowing it or withdrawing it from all beings. So God's immutability is a function of God's fully actual power of existence. In contrast, creatures are totally dependent on God for their existence, so that "if He took away His action from them, all things would be reduced to nothing".23 The fullness of this activity just is God's changelessness and God's simplicity.

Since we will see how Stump and Kretzmann find an intransigent tension between God's simplicity and God's freedom to create, it is important to note at this point that the changelessness of God's creating activity does not mean for Thomas that God cannot be God without creation. Indeed, God would be no different had God not created. God's activity is fully realized as it is, and is unchangeable. It is no different activity for God if existence is partic­ipated by creatures, for willing creatures is simply another way of willing Godself ,24 Thus, God's simplicity, the unity of God's uncontradictable action, the identity of God's action whether creation is or not, is exactly what guar­antees God's freedom with respect to creation.

It should be evident that Thomas's Christian account of the doctrine of creation is behind his discussion of simplicity, but it is perhaps not quite

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 7: The Simplicity of the Living God

The Simplicity of the Living God 281

evident how this discussion is conditioned by the doctrines of Trinity and Incarnation. But the relation between creature and Creator that Thomas assumes is precisely an articulation of the creature-Creator relation that the church worked out in the course of its reflections on Trinity and Incarnation. The notion that the three divine persons are one God involved the confes­sion over against various sorts of Arians that there are no gradations and distinctions within the divine, but rather there is only divinity with no gra­dation and distinctions on the one side and creatures on the other.25 As Aquinas summarized this conclusion centuries later: "Everything which is not the divine essence is a creature."26 In this way Trinitarian debates fos­tered the sort of creature-Creator distinction we see worked out in Thomas. There is the one, uncreated, simple God, and there is everything that is not that one, simple essence, which is created.

Not only does the church's confession of the unity of the three sharpen the distinction between creature and Creator, but so does the confession of the triplicity of the one as well. According to Thomas, that God acts in cre­ation and redemption through the missions of the Son and Holy Spirit is pre­cisely what demonstrates the gratuity of creation.27 For God uttered rather than emanated the Word, reaching out in Love rather than from necessity. But this awareness of the non-necessity of creation deepens our grasp of what it means for God to be the cause of being, to be the simple actus purus, to be the fully Living One. If God did not have to create, our own contin­gency and fragility stand forth all the more. Of course, just because God is Trinity, it is truly appropriate to God's character to create, for God is Word and Love. God goes forth in self-communication among the three persons, and so it is perfectly fitting for such a God to seek, through creating and redeeming others, "to communicate by likeness its own good to others as much as is possible".28 But just because that self-communicating impulse already finds a terminus within the divine life, God's character does not dictate creation. Although the connection is not explicitly drawn in the Summa Theologiae, in his commentary on the Lombard's Sentences Thomas suggests that God's will to communicate Godself would be fulfilled without creatures exactly because of the intra-Trinitarian relations.29 It is important to remember that such Trinitarian reflections are behind Thomas's talk of God willing creation by willing Godself as participatable. Such talk easily calls to our minds a lonely monad contemplating itself. But when Aquinas speaks of God knowing all by knowing Godself and willing all by willing Godself, he is speaking of the same knowing that is God's Word, the Son, and of the same willing that is God's love, the Holy Spirit.30

If Trinitarian reflections stand in the background of Thomas's account of the God-world relation, so do reflections on Christ's person. The church's Christological discussions concerning the unity of the two natures bring out especially starkly the radical otherness of God. Within the distinctions that define for us the essences of things in the world, a thing is what it is pre-

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005

Page 8: The Simplicity of the Living God

282 Christopher A. Frante

cisely by its not being something else. A man is a man partially in virtue of not being a horse. Mixing a man and a horse can only destroy the essences that define "man" and "horse", and so we have a centaur, neither man nor horse. In rejecting various attempts at truncating Christ's essence as a man or limiting the extent of his essential divinity, the church determined that divinity is not something that must destroy earthly natures to make a place for itself. Indeed, God can join in such intimate union with the creature exactly because God is simply not part of the order of beings. God is differ­ent from creation—so different, that God can unite with the creature without losing that difference. In this way "the denial that God in his divinity is part of or dependent on the world, was brought forward with greater clarity through the discussion of the way the Word became flesh".31 These lessons are evident in Thomas's teaching on the creature-Creator relation. They are especially clear in that Thomas takes God's radical otherness to be a neces­sary part of the confession that God enters into unions with the creature, either at the most intimate level, in the incarnation, in a lesser way in the grace of union, or even in that lesser intimacy God shares with all that is sus­tained in being.32 The unfathomable intimacy of God with creation, wit­nessed supremely in the Incarnation, proclaims how radically discontinuous God is with creatures, as the source of their being.33

Thomas's discussion of simplicity is thoroughly dependent on reflections stemming from the revelation of God in Christ. Those reflections press toward the radical otherness of God—so great an otherness that the great­est intimacy with creation is possible—and toward the determinateness of God's uncontradictable Life—so great a determinateness that creation can only be a radically free and gratuitous act. It is just that fully actual Life, that free and unchangeable Life, hinging on God's "already fulfilled activity", that is God's simplicity. Thus, simplicity as Thomas sees it is a pivotal aspect of a fully Christian account of God. And this is a notion of simplicity that, as Barth rightly points out, must be distinguished from any human idea of "the simple".

Stump and Kretzmann on Simplicity

I contend that the crucial features of the understanding of simplicity out­lined above are generally missing from discussions of divine simplicity among philosophers of religion. If theologians by and large accept the philo­sophically debated concept of simplicity as the genuine article, it is no wonder that they tend to reject it. For it bears the marks of what Barth called the consideration of an "ens vere unum". As such it does not reflect the sense of the radical distinction between God and the world I have been develop­ing. And perhaps we should not expect it to, because the notion of simplic­ity is intentionally treated in abstraction from doctrines like Trinity and Incarnation, the very doctrines that helped to refine the church's under-

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 9: The Simplicity of the Living God

The Simplicity of the Living God 283

standing of simplicity as referring to God's determinate and uncontradicat-able Life. Yet Stump and Kretzmann in particular claim to be following at least the spirit of Aquinas, and exegesis of Aquinas forms a standard mode of operating for them. But absent the relation between God and creation worked out above, their treatment fails to grasp what Aquinas means by "simplicity".

None of this is to say that Stump and Kretzmann do not get many things right about Aquinas. They offer many thoughtful and more or less Thomistic considerations to show how simplicity has been misunderstood by many of its modern critics. They offer compelling and useful arguments to show that the notion of divine simplicity is not necessarily incompatible with God acting in history, with divine perfection, and with divine freedom. The result is a notion of simplicity that has much in common with that of Thomas. But while adequately sketching some of the outlines of Aquinas's notion of sim­plicity, they miss its heart and center.

At this juncture let me recount briefly what Stump and Kretzmann do in the article in question.34 They begin by characterizing divine simplicity as a denial of distinctions in God. They then point out three sorts of difficulties entailed in predicating such simplicity of a God who is believed to have acted in history and to have freely created the world. First, a simple God acting in history appears nonsensical because simplicity would require that God's act at one time in history be identical with God's essence, which would also be identical with God's act at another time in history. Thus, acts at two different times would have to be essentially identical. Stump and Kretzmann resolve the difficulty by referring to the notion of pure act. There is no con­tradiction, they say, in claiming that God as an eternal, unchanging act can have various temporal manifestations or effects. The same logic helps them to resolve the apparent difficulty in asserting that two of God's attributes, for example omnipotence and omniscience, are identical. These various predications simply describe God differently according to God's various manifestations and effects.

Second, even if a simple God acting in history is not nonsensical, such a God must not be free, since what this God does is identical with God's essence. The key to the resolution here is how "will" is understood. A simple God acting in history is not free if will is understood as the neutral capacity to choose. But Stump and Kretzmann propose, following Aquinas, to think of will as a "self-directed rational wanting of the good".35 Thus, the possi­bility of doing otherwise than one does is not the criterion of true freedom. Instead, freedom means facing no obstacles in one's pursuit of the good. God cannot do other than God does only because nothing can frustrate God's goodness. God's simplicity, then, is perfect freedom.

Third, even if God's simplicity can be squared with God's acting in history and with those acts being understood as free, it apparently cannot be squared with God's freedom to create. Traditionally, neither God's creating nor God's

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 10: The Simplicity of the Living God

284 Christopher A. Frante

abstaining from creating would frustrate God's goodness. Therefore, the freedom operative here is of a fundamentally different order. That is to say, when we consider God's creating activity—unlike God's acts in history— God's acting otherwise than God does must be a real possibility. To preserve God's simplicity, apparently the creating God and the (possible) non-creating God would have to be identical. Here Stump and Kretzmann concede that a strong version of simplicity is impossible to mesh with a freely creating God. But they refuse to abandon their defense of simplicity alto­gether. They claim that divine simplicity can be thought of in a "weakened sense". God's simplicity could mean not that God is the same in all possible worlds, but that given a creating God, God is the same in all time-lines pos­sible under such circumstances. This seems to mean that although God could have not created (and so is not simple in the "strong sense"), God might still be simple (in a "weakened sense") if beyond that there are no further dis­tinctions in God. Stump and Kretzmann conclude their article by suggesting some tricky issues in theology that might be helped if the doctrine of divine simplicity were available.

This summary is necessarily sketchy, and leaves out several important moves Stump and Kretzmann make. But it is enough to give the reader a sense of the interests that animate the article and to hint at some of the assumptions at work in it. In what follows, I hope to make clear how some of those assumptions separate Stump and Kretzmann from the notion of divine simplicity espoused by Aquinas. Specifically, they neglect the partic­ular (Christian) shape of the discontinuity between the radically contingent creation and the uncontradictably Living God, and hence proceed too uni-vocally and end up parsing not the Living God but a human idea of "the simple".

Following Aquinas, Stump and Kretzmann do acknowledge that the doc­trine of divine simplicity derives from the notion of God as pure actuality.36

But they do not seem to recognize just what this notion of "pure actuality" is supposed to accomplish, or its place in the whole structure of Thomas's doctrine of God. Indeed, they appear to miss that structure altogether. As we have seen, the idea of "pure act" has a central place in Aquinas's explication of God since every predication retrains our thinking in light of the confes­sion of the ultimate source of being. This construal of the distinction between the completely living God and the determined and contingent creation is exactly what Stump and Kretzmann miss.37 They talk about a God one of whose aspects is to be "entirely actual, or in act",38 but without attention to how that full actuality places all of our talk about God on this side of a great apophatic divide; they fail to point to the Living God and instead end up explicating a human concept of a being with no potency. Thus they approach much more closely to what Barth derides as the ens vere unum implied by many discussions of divine simplicity.

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 11: The Simplicity of the Living God

The Simplicity of the Living God 285

Analogy The most obvious indication of this failure to grasp what actus purus means for Aquinas is the excessively univocal approach Stump and Kretzmann take toward God's predicates. If they had recognized the extent to which God as actus purus means radical discontinuity between God and creation, then they would have appreciated (but in fact do not) how analogical language follows. For example, consider how Stump and Kretzmann approach the problem of identifying both "perfect power" and "perfect knowledge" with God. They appeal to a time/eternity distinction to reconcile these concepts. While no distinctions apply in God's eternal being, God may have different temporal manifestations that lead us to identify God alternatively as "power" or as "knowledge". This time/eternity distinction has the potential to support the radical otherness between God and creation. But Stump and Kretzmann actually intimate a great deal of continuity between the eternal and temporal realms. The simile Stump and Kretzmann employ likens the distinction between power and knowledge in the temporal realm to the dis­tinction between opposite slopes of a mountain, and likens the identity between perfect power and perfect knowledge to the one summit that com­pletes both slopes.39

The trouble here is the suggestion of an unbroken continuity between where we creatures are, near the bottom of the slope, and where God is at the top of it. Such continuity betrays any possibility of the sort of radical dis­continuity between God and creatures expounded by Thomas. The image of two slopes leading to one summit suggests a spectrum of degrees of power on which God has the same thing we have, but God has more of it. It also suggests that if "power" is understood in a high enough degree it is identi­cal to an equally high degree of knowledge. This approach to God's predi­cates Aquinas would call univocal.40

Of course, this image of the mountain slopes is only a simile, and if pressed, we might expect Stump and Kretzmann to reply that it is not meant to convey just how power and knowledge coincide in God as res significata, but only to evoke the imaginative possibility for us that such a coincidence need not be judged incoherent. Indeed, in later work Kretzmann in particu­lar has paid a good deal of attention to the way our language falls short of reaching God. In The Metaphysics of Theism, a reading of Summa contra Gentiles I, Kretzmann highlights Thomas's repeated statements about the limitations of our speech about God.41 Yet, even here the full meaning of Aquinas's insistence on analogical language remains in the dark. For Kretzmann our language is limited because of our cognitive constraints and because of the way "Alpha" (his generic term for whatever is prima causa) so transcends all our experience. But these limitations are limitations the Greeks knew, and limitations that philosophy since Scotus has known. They are the limitations of earthly beings trying to account for the highest being.

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 12: The Simplicity of the Living God

286 Christopher A. Frante

These limitations do not yet approach the limitations involved in discussing the very source of being who is not part of the order of beings. Thus, even if Kretzmann can say that none of our language actually reaches God, that what is appropriate predication according to our modus significandi must be distinguished from the res significata, nevertheless the only possible horizon envisioned for that res is still the horizon of being. So it fits with their neglect of the full range of the creature-Creator distinction that Stump and Kretzmann give us metaphors that suggest a shared horizon between humans and God. The problem is related to Kretzmann's assumption that there is a tradition connecting him with Aquinas that can be called a tradition of "perfect-being theism".42 For Aquinas, God is precisely not a being. God's simplicity, then, is not the simplicity of a perfect being. So illustrations that fail to undermine the assumption that God is a being will necessarily be too univocal, regard­less of disclaimers about the limitations of our language.

If, as Thomas believes, we know God through creatures, then in order to understand God we must form "conceptions proportional to the perfections flowing from God to creatures, which perfections pre-exist in God unitedly and simply, while in creatures they are received divided and multiplied".43

This does not mean that we predicate things of God by looking at the mul­tiple perfections of creatures and intensifying them until we have a concep­tion of a being who unites all those perfections. If we do that we arrive at Barth's ens vere unum. On the contrary, Aquinas says that the perfection in the effect (the creature) may not even be in the cause (the creator) in the same manner. As an example of how predications we make of creatures might signify differently when predicated of God, Thomas points to the difference between what "healthy" means when predicated of medicine versus what "healthy" means when predicated of an animal.44 The term applies to animals because they have health, but it applies to medicine because it is the cause of such health. "Healthy" is predicated of medicine and of animals in ways that are only analogous. In no way is there a spectrum of healthiness that includes the animal at one point and medicine at a much higher degree of the same thing. So Thomas suggests that, although the use of the term is not completely equivocal, the sort of continuity between the two predica­tions evoked by the slope analogy cannot be presumed between creatures and God.

Yet, neither is our language about God wholly misleading, for God not only causes our perfections, but causes them precisely as One in whom those perfections pre-exist in a higher way. So when we call God the Living God, we do not merely mean that God causes life in us. Rather, we mean that life pre-exists in God in a preeminent way.45 Still, such preeminence does not mean that God has a higher degree of the same thing we have. It means that what we have is an effect that falls short of fully representing its cause, even though it derives "some kind of likeness to it, even as the forms of inferior bodies represent the power of the sun".46 Although such

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 13: The Simplicity of the Living God

The Simplicity of the Living God 287

terms are certainly not totally equivocal, God is far enough above continuity with creatures that the same term applied to both cannot be used univo-cally. A term that is

applied to man in some degree circumscribes and comprehends the thing signified; but this is not the case when (the term) is applied to God, but it leaves the thing signified as incomprehended, and as exceeding the signification of the name.47

Another way to say this is that "life" is in fact more properly said of God, according to the res significata, because God lives more fully and determi-nately and perfectly than we do; but according to our modus significandi "hie" does not appropriately refer to God, for we understand "life" from our knowledge of creatures, which fails as a basis for grasping what "life" is in God.48 The fully Living One cannot be circumscribed or comprehended, even by calling God the Living One. Predications like "perfect knowledge" and "perfect power" must be attributed analogically, and thus we cannot pin down precisely how they refer to God. Much less, then, can we employ similes suggesting that "perfect power equals perfect knowledge" is a propo­sition we might be able to make sense of without reference to our inability to comprehend the Living God.49

The Puzzle of Simplicity and Freedom Stump and Kretzmann deal not with the Living God but with an idea of "the simple" as it might apply within the order of beings. This appears most cru­cially in the way their univocal treatment leads them to see divine simplic­ity as a threat to God's freedom rather than the guarantee of it.50 We have seen how for Aquinas the affirmation of God's simplicity lives from the con­fession of God as the fully determinate Living One who is the same with or without creation and on whom creation utterly depends. This approach roots simplicity in the understanding of who God is gleaned from the church's reflection on the Trinity and Incarnation. Stump and Kretzmann, on the other hand, work from ideas of "the simple", of "eternity", and "freedom" con­ceived without recourse to the church's deliberations, and hope to pry from them some understanding of God. It turns out that these versions of "simplicity" and "freedom" are only compatible if simplicity is truncated.

Had they truly followed Aquinas, Stump and Kretzmann would have seen that God's simplicity is exactly what guarantees that God's creative activity is totally free. God has no need to create, but neither is God bound not to create. Indeed, God's simplicity means that creating fits God's character, as it were, even though God's character would be no different had God not created. Aquinas's explication of God's simplicity in terms of God's full actu­ality does nothing if not preserve God's freedom. The ungraspable cause of all being knows and loves Godself, and thereby knows and loves whatever

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 14: The Simplicity of the Living God

288 Christopher A. Frante

participates in being. Whether anything participates in being is thus a matter of sheer gratuity. This construal of simplicity preserves God's freedom insep­arably from preserving God's mystery and incomprehensibility. It means that humans can place no limits on the ability of God, as the fully living, determinative, uncontradictable one, to be who God will be. Not that there are no limits on who God will be. In sacra doctrina, God has certainly revealed to faith who God is and who God will be. But our faith does not "give us a handle" on God. Through faith we know God, and precisely in that faith we know God's incomprehensibility. God's simplicity, freedom, and incompre­hensibility all hang together. If faith offers no handle on God, a fortiori neither does an exhaustive analysis of the conceptual possibilities of a human idea of the "simple". Following such a methodology, unlike Aquinas's procedure, loses the coordination of simplicity, freedom, and incomprehensibility. Indeed, Stump and Kretzmann come up with an idea of the simple that is all too comprehensible and for that reason is difficult to square with God's freedom.

The question that troubles Stump and Kretzmann is how an agent can have real freedom without positing a distinction in the agent between what is willed necessarily and what could be willed differently; yet the very neces­sity of that distinction seems to threaten the agent's simplicity. What has been said is sufficient to indicate why Aquinas was never troubled by this question. Stump and Kretzmann come up with an answer, but it is an answer that manifests the univocity of their approach and ends with a simplicity that is no simplicity at all (at least in any theologically fruitful sense).

The simplicity Stump and Kretzmann investigate is the simplicity of a simple being. A simple being must dwell in a static eternity. Of course, this threatens God's freedom, since a being of static simplicity cannot be or do other than it is and does. Our authors resolve the tension by proposing that God could have chosen a different static eternity in place of the creating static eternity God has in fact chosen. God's act of creating is therefore free, but simplicity applies only in a "weakened sense", in that it does not hold together who God is as creator and who God would be without creation. In other words, God is simple relative to the circumstance that does obtain (cre­ation exists), but God's decision to create forms the boundary of God's simplicity.

The main threat to this solution is the distinction between God's necessary willing of Godself and God's contingent willing of other things. Stump and Kretzmann elide the gap between willing necessarily and willing contin­gently by showing how what God wills contingently already involves a sort of necessity. Even what God wills most freely, i.e., the existence of other things, is tinged with a sort of necessity insofar as it is willed eternally by God, so that there is no part of that eternity where God's willing to create is contradicted or uncertain. This observation does not give God's willing of creation logical necessity, but it does make it necessary in a significant sense.

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 15: The Simplicity of the Living God

The Simplicity of the Living God 289

Once we see that God's willing of creation has this sort of necessity, there is no reason to posit a distinction between God's willing of the contingently necessary and the absolutely necessary. It is all one act of willing in God's eternity.

Here Stump and Kretzmann's misunderstanding of Thomas on simplicity finds support in their misunderstanding of eternity Of course, for Thomas there is no need to posit a real distinction in God between God's willing of Godself and God's willing of contingent things. But that has to do with the mysterious and gratuitous confession that creatures can and do participate in the God who is actus purus. Since they miss this radical construal of the creature-Creator distinction, Stump and Kretzmann conceive not the source of being, but a being who wills two things. They turn to a static eternity as the setting for all God's willing to make the two willings compatible.

Thomas's account of eternity does agree that what God wills God eter­nally wills. But the same reversal of our normal assumptions about being by which Thomas renders God as the determinative, Living One in whom we participate is reflected also in the discussion of eternity, where Thomas reverses our assumptions about time to render God as the ultimate source of all times, in whom our times participate. For Thomas, describing God as "eternal" is a way to ensure that we are discussing the fully actual, living God—to ensure that there is no potency in God. Thus Aquinas explicates eternity in terms of immutability, which earlier he had described with ref­erence to God as pure actuality.51 That God is eternal means that God is too fully actual to be contradictable or changeable. God's eternity is not a prison that keeps God alienated from time or from action. On the contrary, God is so fully in act that no time is only potentially related to God. Rather, God holds all times together. Scripture can apply past, present, and future time to God because God's "eternity includes all times".52 Nor is eternity a measure that bounds or circumscribes God. We do not learn about God by understanding eternity and then subsequently fitting our idea of God into that description. Instead, "eternity is nothing else but God Himself".53 So if we would grasp anything about eternity, we must first know something of the Living God.54

Stump and Kretzmann's characterization of eternity as a static, timeless present builds on their work in an earlier essay.55 There the focus is the def­inition of eternity presented by Boethius, defended by Aquinas, "the com­plete possession all at once of illimitable life".56 Yet their treatment of God as if God were a being is evident in the first problem the essay tackles. The conundrum is how a being existing in an eternal "present", who is thus simultaneous with each temporal moment, can have this simultaneity with such a diversity of moments. They investigate this question in terms of various species of simultaneity all of which fall under the one genus of things that "exist at once (together)".57 Here we see that God, conceived as a being, albeit an eternal being, can fall under a shared genus with other beings. In

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 16: The Simplicity of the Living God

290 Christopher A. Frante

contrast to Aquinas, eternity means that God enters along with creatures into the realm of things that can be measured.58 Although Stump and Kretzmann stress the difference between eternal and temporal simultaneity, they discuss not the incomparable Living God but a being continuous with creatures. Simultaneity, as Stump and Kretzmann point out, is a relative term. Events are simultaneous only relative to a certain observer. For an event in the tem­poral realm to be simultaneous with an eternal present, the event must be present relative to observers in both the eternal and the temporal frames of reference.59 Now, the notion of God as an "observer" may be just a figure of speech. But it is a misleading one, especially since our authors do not point out the crucial difference—that God is causing the created realities that God "sees". So they liken God to the temporal observer, noting that God must discern whether events are present to God eternally or temporally.60 Here God is a being, who senses the presence of events similarly to the way crea­tures do. God becomes one more character in Stump and Kretzmann's drama, rather than the actus purus on which all creatures, all temporal events, and all dramas depend.

This eternal observer's simultaneity with all times becomes a straitjacket, locking him into a "static instant". Again beginning with human assump­tions about what eternity must be like, Stump and Kretzmann explicate a view of eternity identified with atemporality. Temporality involves past, present, and future, so atemporality is understood only as a constant present. Since a human understanding of what it means to be "in the present" governs their view of God's eternal present, they think that the idea of eter­nity as an isolated static instant is "not so far off the mark" as the idea of eternity as limitless duration.61 For Aquinas, God is simultaneously whole and perfect, but is not therefore closer to being an instant than a duration. In fact, God exceeds duration: God "endures beyond every age, that is, beyond every kind of duration".62 But for Stump and Kretzmann the key to God's eternity is not God's full actuality. Eternity thus becomes a prison that locks God into doing whatever God does. That is how God's willing of cre­ation acquires the sort of necessity that makes any distinction between that willing and God's willing of Godself superfluous.

Clearly, Stump and Kretzmann have missed Aquinas's notion of sim­plicity. For Aquinas, God's simplicity means that God is the completely Living One, the One who alone can share life with what does not exist by granting a participation in God's own existence. Simplicity, then, is exactly what obviates any need for a distinction between God's willing of creation and God's willing of Godself. That Stump and Kretzmann resort to eliding the distinction by attributing necessity to creation bears witness to the fact that Aquinas's notion of simplicity is beyond their metaphysical imaginings.

The prison-like view of eternity presented in their earlier article is also behind the relevant moves in "Absolute Simplicity". Here they explain

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 17: The Simplicity of the Living God

The Simplicity of the Living God 291

further why a static instant view of eternity entails such a strong sense of necessity. It may seem that God's eternity only entails a suppositional neces­sity to what God does. Of course, if God is creating, God must be creating. But our authors distinguish God's creating from the merely suppositional necessity that if Socrates is running, he must be running.63 The claim about Socrates, while necessary, does not appear to impinge on Socrates's freedom to run or not to run. This is because "before the time of his running Socrates could have brought it about that he not be running at that later time".64 There is no such antecedent time of decision for God, whose act of creating is "a timeless action in the eternal present."65 This gives the conditional necessity of creation a stronger sense than the suppositional necessity of Socrates's running, so that God's willing of it can sit more neatly in one act of will with what God wills with absolute necessity.

The univocity in their idea of eternity is here supported by a univocal view of freedom. Just as what we are doing is free because determined by a prior free choice, so what God is doing cannot be truly free unless preceded by a time of decision. But with God there is no preceding time, so what God is doing is not really free, but simply given. Unlike the God of Aquinas, an "eternal being" must in a sense merely receive the way things are. Consider Stump and Kretzmann's comparison between God's act of willing and a woman named Monica's act of looking into a mirror.66 God can will Godself and other things in one act, just as Monica can see herself and other things in one act. The illustration suggests that just as Monica receives what she sees in the mirror—her looking is not creating what she sees—so God receives what God wills. But they neglect to point out the crucial difference: that God's willing of other things is the very source of those things. Here God's action of creating, though willed by God, seems mysteriously to be treated as part of the way things are, a given that God must receive but never had time to choose. This procedure is supposed to demonstrate a certain necessity to God's creating activity in order to preserve the simplicity of God's eternal willing. The cost, though, is the loss of Aquinas's living actus purus and its replacement with a human idea of the simple.

The foregoing arguments sketch the main elements of Stump and Kretz­mann's defense of simplicity. We see that it differs greatly from Aquinas's discussion. It is the static simplicity of an eternal being, not the living activ­ity of the simple cause of being. Furthermore, it is a simplicity that only obtains within the creating eternity that God has chosen. When they turn to the possibility that God might not have created, Stump and Kretzmann show how the simplicity they have defended is a truncated simplicity.

After associating God's willing of creation so closely with God's necessary willing of Godself, they are concerned to present God's will to create as nevertheless not absolutely necessary. In order to do this after having put God in such a box of necessity on account of God's eternity, Stump and Kretzmann point out that creating is not logically entailed by God's nature.

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 18: The Simplicity of the Living God

292 Christopher A. Frante

Thus God's eternity could have been a non-creating eternity rather than a creating eternity. Consequently, God is not the same "in all possible worlds". In view of this distinction, Stump and Kretzmann admit that they can only weaken "the claims basic to the doctrine of simplicity".67 Freedom and simplicity are finally incompatible, and they save simplicity by narrowing its applicability.

Stump and Kretzmann refuse to admit defeat. They claim that something really worthy of the name "simplicity" can still be salvaged. In place of a simplicity implying sameness through all possible worlds, they advocate a divine simplicity understood as sameness through all possible time-lines emanating from a single initial world-state. But this would seem not to "weaken" the notion of simplicity, but to abandon it. Divine simplicity, however it is construed, would seem to require that God is the same no matter what God might do. Claiming that God is simple, excepting consid­eration of God's decision to create, abandons the doctrine of simplicity. Nor can this quasi-simplicity accomplish even the modest uses for which Stump and Kretzmann themselves commend it. For example, they suggest that the doctrine of simplicity overcomes the nominalist-realist dilemma with regard to morality.68 God's goodness need not be an arbitrary divine invention nor an extrinsic measure that limits God, since God simply is God's goodness. But this use of the doctrine of simplicity shows that simplicity is not sim­plicity unless God's simplicity and the standards by which God judges are identical. It is precisely that identity that Stump and Kretzmann have already abandoned. If God's decision to create is excluded from the understanding of God's simplicity, then God's simplicity is not identical to the standards by which God determined to create—indeed, those standards are totally exter­nal to God's simplicity. Stump and Kretzmann thus end up calling some­thing simplicity that is no simplicity at all.

The truth of the matter is that Stump and Kretzmann explicate not the sim­plicity of the Living God of Aquinas, but the notion of a being who is simple. Their neglect of the radical distinction between creature and Creator that characterizes Thomas's account of simplicity leaves them imagining God as a being within the order of beings. The limits of their horizon within the order of beings is especially evident in their language of various "possible worlds". They quite naturally render the difference between God-with-creation and God-without-creation as a difference between various possible worlds. What could be more intuitive from a human perspective than to describe the way things are, including even the way God is, as "the world"? But following such natural and intuitive leadings of our normal speech is precisely what throws us off the track of speaking about God. For in God we learn that the way things are is not the ultimate horizon. Rather, "all worlds" have their condition of possibility in the God who is other than all worlds. This God alone is the only final horizon. Thus, it would never occur to Thomas to describe the-way-things-would-be-if-God-had-not-created as

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 19: The Simplicity of the Living God

The Simplicity of the Living God 293

a "possible world". That is not a possible world, but the possible absence of any world. Our authors can say, "although there are possible worlds in which God wills not to create, none of those worlds lies along any branches of the time-line of the actual world".69 Aquinas could only say, "There are possible worlds which God wills not to create." There are no worlds in which God wills not to create, for if God wills not to create, there is no world and no time-line. Further, since God is radically other from creation, God is not in any world. But the thought of Stump and Kretzmann begins not with the Living God who is other than the world or any possible world, but with con­ceptions of the divine abstracted from any dependence on revelation and therefore dependent solely on reasoning for which the world itself must be the broadest possible horizon.

Barth on Simplicity

If at the beginning of this essay my claim that Barth is the true heir in modern theology of Thomas's account of divine simplicity seemed dubious, perhaps by now its pertinence is more evident. The human concept of "the simple" that Barth derides is far from Aquinas's discussion, and is much closer to the subject of the investigations of Stump and Kretzmann. While Stump and Kretzmann claim to continue a tradition that includes Aquinas, their treat­ment of simplicity differs drastically from his. This is partly due to their neglect of the church's reflections on the Trinity and the Incarnation that bring out in all its sharpness the radical distinction between contingent crea­tures and the Living God on whom they depend.

Unlike Thomas, Barth is not one to leave the precise significance of the Trinity implicit. He insists that the doctrine of the Trinity must determine a Christian understanding of divine simplicity. Thus, he attacks those "older" theologians who treat simplicity at the very beginning of their discussion of the doctrine of God. The trouble is that by putting simplicity first, they

give the impression that what is argued and considered is the general idea of an ens vere unum and not the God of the doctrine of the Trinity and of Christology—although this is in flat contradiction to the way in which this recognition originally forced itself on the Church.70

Barth clearly applies his wariness of human religion to the issue of divine simplicity. Humans extrapolate from their own composition to an idea of the uncomposite, and when that idea comes first in the doctrine of God, undis­ciplined by specifically Christian conceptions of God, the door to idolatry is opened. The way to close that door is to keep talk of God's simplicity tied to the doctrines of Trinity and Incarnation. The simplicity of God is nothing other than "the unity of the triune God and of the Son of God with man in Jesus Christ".71 Barth may have included Thomas among those who had

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 20: The Simplicity of the Living God

294 Christopher A. Frante

been misleading about this but, as we have seen, the character of Thomas's treatment of simplicity is no less conditioned by these confessions.

Precisely because he refuses any human idea of "the simple", Barth manages to repeat many of the lessons about the distinction between God and the world that we saw in Thomas. It is exactly this sort of difference between God and creation that Barth underscores with his talk of God as "wholly other". In his explication of how it is that we humans participate in the truth of God's revelation, Barth emphasizes the "general incongruence between God and man".72 Humans are by nature not fit for the knowledge of God, and it is this lack of fit that induces awe in the human knower when she finds herself possessed of knowledge of God. But the incongruity is not only between human minds and knowledge of God. If Barth left us think­ing that the incongruity was only there, we might think it due to the fact that our minds use words to think and thus are tied to the sensuousness of human speech, while God is not sensuous, but spiritual. Then we might seek to overcome the disparity through some process of spiritualization. But this incongruence, between the sensuous and the spiritual, is not the incongru­ence between God and the world, for it "exists within the world and can therefore be overcome within the world".73 The incongruity to which Barth points is that between the world with all its internal incongruities, on the one hand, and the God who stands over against the world, on the other. As Barth says elsewhere, God cannot be compared with any creature, for "God is an instance outside every genus."74

Not only is the distinction between God and creation radical in a way that recalls Aquinas but also, like Aquinas, Barth renders God as the ultimately determinate term in this distinction. It is God whose activity is full and un-withstandable. This unchangeable fullness of action reflects God's simplic­ity. God's action is crucial for Barth, because given the "otherness" of God, we need God's action if we are to come to know God. "God is the One whose being can be investigated only in the form of a continuous question as to His action."75 And God's action displays the simplicity of God, for in all God does, God is "wholly and undividedly Himself".76 Because of the lack of divi­sion or contradiction within God, nothing can contradict or withstand God's action. Thus, in the incongruity between God and creation, it is God who is determinate and un-contradictable. The world is incongruous with God insofar as it is determinable and contradictable by God. It is the world which cannot withstand God, and not vice versa.

Characteristically, Barth draws out the importance of this fullness of God's activity through reflection on how we are able to know God. Of course, the world cannot by its nature know God or lift itself up to God. But God's activity is so determinate that it is not confined to some divine realm on the far side of the discontinuity between God and creation. Rather, God's activity can even make us know what we are not fit to know. Indeed, although human knowledge works through created objects, such as signs

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 21: The Simplicity of the Living God

The Simplicity of the Living God 295

and concepts, and God is no object, God in fact deigns to make Godself an object to be known by humans. That we may really know God, God becomes a real object, like other objects of our consideration and concep­tion. Yet even here, when it seems that we have found God within the created world, God distinguishes Godself. The same human activity of knowing happens, but it happens in a different way, by the "union of man with God". So this is special knowledge, and though God has become an object for us, God is not "considered and conceived as one in a series of like objects".77 The distinction that remains corresponds to the veiling in every act of revelation, a veiling that requires our language about God to be ana­logical.78 Even the mode of our knowledge of God, then, teaches us that God is not a fixture among the world's furnishings, and that for our knowledge of God we are constantly at the mercy of the un-contradictable activity of this "wholly other".

This dependence on the determinate activity of God is not only episte­mologica!, but also ontological. The event of revelation binds us to God with clarity and certainty. So clear and certain is this binding that "our own exis­tence stands or falls with the existence of God. In the light of the existence of God it is less—infinitely less—clear and certain to us than His existence."79

This binding of our existence to God's more certain existence points to the notion that whatever certainty our existence has, it has by participation in God. God is the one who truly exists; we (and indeed the whole universe) exist only secondarily, as it were by participation. As Barth says in his dis­cussion of God's eternity, our time is "not merely apparent but real time" only because it is really in God's hands.80

The incongruity between God and creation goes even further, in a way that again echoes Aquinas. Not only does creation utterly depend on God's determinate activity, but also that activity is so full and free that God has no need of creation in order to be God. We have seen that for Barth God is fully Godself in God's actions. But that does not mean that God is not God without the particular action of allowing creatures a participation in time and exis­tence. It is true that God's unchanging action is at the "very deepest depths (of) God's Godhead",81 and that that action is the love that reaches out in fel­lowship. But that love needs no object outside God.82 Indeed, already in Godself God "has that which He seeks and creates between Himself and us".83 That is why God can truly do without creation:

He is the same even in Himself, even before and after and over His works, and without them. They are bound to Him, but He is not bound to them. They are nothing without Him. But He is who He is without them.84

Further, God's Life is so full and free that although God can do without creation, God does not need to do without it to be who God is. Barth claims that what is most revealing of God's freedom is the freedom God has not to

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 22: The Simplicity of the Living God

296 Christopher A. Frante

be bound by that freedom. God is free "not to surrender Himself to it, but to use it to give Himself to this communion (with the creation) and to prac­tice this faithfulness in it, in this way being really free, free in Himself".85

Barth characteristically links this assertion to the Trinity, for God's activity of reaching out in loving fellowship is already fulfilled in Godself, with or without creation.86 So God's creating and loving of the world fits the char­acter of God's activity, but is not the necessary upshot of that activity. God's freedom, in God's simplicity, to be for the universe or to do without it shows the radical contingency of it. In light of this understanding of the relation between God and creation, divine simplicity is seen to entail both that God is simply and wholly "other" from the world and that God, in God's un­contradictable activity, is the simply unchangeable and determinate one on whom the complex but fragile universe depends. In comparison with the opposition between freedom and simplicity that we saw in Stump and Kretzmann, a much more "Thomistic" position is articulated by Barth when he asserts that "God's freedom and therefore His simplicity are the freedom and simplicity of His love".87

And of course, Barth is not reticent about showing the importance of the Incarnation for his understanding. Thus, the same lessons we saw in Thomas about how the Incarnation manifests that radical otherness of a God who could join creation in such union while remaining God appear as well in Barth. In that union of God and creature, "God does not cease for a moment or in any regard to be the one, true God".88 If such a distinction can remain even in the union of God and creature, God must be radically different from us. God is so different from us even to be capable of this "inconceiv­able act".

The inconceivable fact in it is that without ceasing to be God the Word of God is among us in such a way that He takes over human being, which is His creature, into His own being and to that extent makes it His own being. As His own predicate along with His original predicate of divinity, He takes over human being into unity with Himself It is not the act of the human being and nature. How can it be capable of such an act?89

If God is able to overcome the discontinuity in such a way as to leave it intact, an overcoming that is inconceivable to us, the difference between God and creatures must be greater than we could have previously thought. Indeed, instead of God standing on the far side of a chasm running through the order of being, the Incarnation suggests that God is somehow other than the whole order of being itself, capable of presence in that order in such a way that no corresponding absence of created being is required.90

Barth's concurrence with Thomas on these issues is nicely captured in a comment he makes about Thomas's notion of actus purus. He notes the idea with approval, even intensifying it to actus purissimus,91 and he suggests that

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005

Page 23: The Simplicity of the Living God

The Simplicity of the Living God 297

what Thomas means by it is finally this: "Life is in the highest degree prop­erly in God."92 As Barth emphasizes, the focus of the divine simplicity is on God as the Living One, as the one who possesses life to the fullest. It is God who is Life in Godself, fully and completely, with or without creatures. It is God who lives, totally independent of the world, but who is free to create the world, granting it a share of life. It is the completeness and full actual­ity of this Life that is the divine simplicity.

Conclusion

I have sought to suggest that standard assumptions about the traditional doctrine of simplicity, assumptions reflected in the notion of simplicity dis­cussed by Stump and Kretzmann, fail to do justice to the role of simplicity in the thought of Aquinas. While the common concept of simplicity is typi­cally understood to be Thomas's concept as well, that common concept as presented by Stump and Kretzmann is marked especially by an innocence of the full implications of the creature-Creator distinction, implications that simplicity for Aquinas is supposed to protect. Abstracting from the Christ­ian sources and doctrines that stand behind Thomas's teaching on simplic­ity, they end up describing not the Living God but a divine being who seems really like a very strange human being.

Aquinas's view is unlike Stump and Kretzmann's exactly because it bears the marks of the early church's investigation into the Trinity and Incarna­tion. That is why it is not surprising that it bears such similarity to Barth's view, and that is why theologians who dismiss simplicity out of hand would do well to take another look. The view of simplicity outlined here is not only a useful tool for the theologian. It is crucial for conforming our speech about God to what we learn about God and the world from reflection on the Trinity and Incarnation. The simple God is radically other—so other that the great­est intimacy with the creature is possible—and determinately Living—so determinate that creation must be a radically free and gratuitous act. That fully actual, free, and unchanging Life just is God's simplicity, and that is why simplicity is such a crucial aspect of a fully Christian account of God.93

NOTES

1 Robert Jenson, "The Triune God/' in Christian Dogmatics, ed. Robert Jenson and Carl Braaten, 2 vols. (Philadelphia, PA: Fortress Press, 1984), Vol. 1, p. 166.

2 See, for example, Eleonore Stump and Norman Kretzmann, "Absolute Simplicity", Faith and Philosophy Vol. 2 (1985), pp. 353-382; and W. E Vallicella, "Divine Simplicity: A New Defense", Faith and Philosophy Vol. 9 (1992), pp. 508-525.

3 Katherin Rogers attests that among the religious philosophers, Stump and Kretzmann "do offer the correct analysis of the traditional view of divine simplicity". Katherin Rogers, "The Traditional Doctrine of Divine Simplicity", Religious Studies Vol. 32 (1996), pp. 165-186.

4 Karl Barth, Church Dogmatics 11/\ (New York: Scribner's, 1957), p. 329. Hereafter referenced as CD.

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005

Page 24: The Simplicity of the Living God

298 Christopher A. Frante

5 Stephen R. Holmes, " 'Something Much Too Plain to Sa/: Towards a Defence of the Doc­trine of Divine Simplicity", Neue Zeitschrift ßr Systematische Theologie Vol. 43 Bd. S (2001), pp. 137-154.

6 Ibid., p. 154. 7 Ibid.,p.l52í. 8 Ibid., p. 138. 9 CD Π/1, p. 447.

10 Josef Pieper anticipated some of these themes in Philosophia negativa: zwei Versuche über Thomas von Aquin (Munich: Kösel-Verlag, 1953). Other important texts include Victor Preller, Divine Science and the Science of God: A Reformulation of Thomas Aquinas (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1967); David Burrell, Aquinas: God and Action (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1979); and Robert Sokolowski, The God of Faith and Reason: Foun­dations of Christian Theology (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982).

11 Preller, Divine Science, p. 180. 12 Herbert McCabe, O. P., "Aquinas on the Trinity", New Blackfriars Vol. 80 (1999), pp. 268-283,

here p. 269. Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae 113.7; 3.5; 6.2 ad 3. 13 Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae I 3.4. Passages from the Summa Theologiae are taken

from the translation by the English Dominican Fathers. Hereafter referenced as ST. 14 David Burrell, Knowing the Unknowable God: Ibn-Sina, Maimonides, Aquinas (Notre Dame, IN:

University of Notre Dame Press, 1986), p. 45. 15 Carlo Leget, Living with God: Thomas Aquinas on the Relation between Life on Earth and "Life"

after Death (Leuven: Peeters, 1997), p. 34. 16 For this way of describing Thomas's teaching, I am indebted to Herbert McCabe, "Aquinas

on the Trinity", p. 272. 17 ST I 4.1. 18 STI 9.1. 19 ST I 3.4. 20 ST I 3.4 adi. 21 STI 44.1. 22 ST I 9.1. 23 ST I 9.2. 24 ST 119.2 ad 2. 25 See, for example, Gregory of Nyssa, "On 'Not Three Gods' ", trans. William Moore and

Henry Austin Wilson, in The Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, Second Series (Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, reprint 1976), Vol. V, pp. 331-336.

26 ST I 28.2, sed contra. 27 ST 132.1 ad 3. For more on Trinity and creation in Thomas, see Gilles Emery, O. P., Trinity

in Aquinas (Ypsilanti, MI: Sapientia Press, 2003). 28 Sril9.2. 29 Thomas Aquinas, Scriptum super IV libros Sententiarum, I, d. 2, q. 1, a. 4, sed contra, quoted

in Norman Kretzmann, "Goodness, Knowledge, and Indeterminacy in the Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas", The Journal of Philosophy Vol. 80 (1983), pp. 631-649, here p. 634.

30 ST I 27.3. 31 Sokolowski, The God of Faith and Reason, p. 37. 32 Henk J. M. Schoot, Christ the "Name" of God: Thomas Aquinas on naming Christ (Leuven:

Peeters, 1993). See also the very helpful article by Michael J. Dodds, O. P., "Ultimacy and Intimacy: Aquinas on the Relation between God and the World", in Ordo Sapientiae et Amoris, ed. Carlos-Josaphat Pinto de Oliveira, O. P. (Fribourg: Éditions Universitaires, 1993), pp. 211-227.

33 The coincidence of intimacy and otherness, of immanence and transcendence, is nicely traced by Kathryn Tanner in God and Creation in Christian Theology: Tyranny or Empower­ment? (Oxford and New York: Blackwell, 1988).

34 Stump and Kretzmann have co-authored other things since this article in 1985, but this is their definitive statement on simplicity. Further, a perusal of their more recent work shows that the issues I address here largely apply to their later work as well. I will, on occasion, refer to such later work to clarify their position.

35 Stump and Kretzmann, p. 362. 36 Ibid., p. 353.

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 25: The Simplicity of the Living God

The Simplicity of the Living God 299

37 This lacuna relates to a misunderstanding of the nature of "activity". On God's intending of the world as a sort of practical reasoning, see Thomas S. Hibbs, Virtue's Splendor: Wisdom, Prudence, and the Human Good (New York: Fordham University Press, 2001), p. 24.

38 Stump and Kretzmann, p. 355. 39 Ibid., p. 357. 40 Among the many important works on analogy, let me mention Gregory P. Rocca, O.P.,

Speaking the Incomprehensible God (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1994).

41 Norman Kretzmann, The Metaphysics of Theism: Aquinas's Natural Theology in Summa contra gentiles I (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997), esp. pp. 147-157.

42 For more on the difference between Kretzmann's theism and Thomas's, see Thomas S. Hibbs, "Kretzmann's Theism vs. Aquinas's Theism: Interpreting the Summa Contra Gen­tiles", The Thomist Vol. 62 (1998), pp. 603-622.

43 ST 113.4. 44 ST 113.5. 45 ST 113.6. 46 ST 113.2. 47 ST 113.5. 48 Leget, Living with God, p. 39. 49 In footnote 9, Stump and Kretzmann acknowledge that power is predicated differently of

God than of creatures (p. 379). But they clearly do not apprehend this difference in the radical way Thomas does. In fact, their clarifying example seems to indicate only a differ­ence of the means by which this power is exercised. In short, they seem to proceed in a thoroughly univocal manner when predicating "power" of God and of humans.

50 For them the problem of God's freedom to create is "the hardest of the problems for the doctrine of simplicity". Stump and Kretzmann, p. 367.

51 ST 110.1, 2. On immutability interpreted in terms of pure actuality, see Leget, Living with God, p. 42.

52 ST 110.2 ad 4. 53 ST 110.2 ad 3. 54 Thomas's view of eternity is not dissimilar to Barth's view. For Barth also, we learn about

eternity not by abstracting from time, but by gaining knowledge of God (CD II/l, p. 609). Eternity is not a prison, nor does it keep God alienated from time (Ibid., p. 610). Rather, eter­nity is predicated of God exactly because God is so fully actual that no time is only poten­tial to God. God holds all times together. Indeed, eternity includes all of being (Ibid.). Regarding how eternity is seen in terms of God's full actuality and how it points to the radical distinction between God and creatures, Aquinas and Barth are quite close, although Aquinas does not seem to invoke Trinitarian modes of thought to clarify eternity, as Barth does. Cf. George Hunsinger, "Mysterium Trinitatis: Karl Barth's Conception of Eternity", in Disruptive Grace: Studies in the Theology of Karl Barth (Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2000), pp. 186-209, and CD II/l, p. 639. It should be noted that Aquinas does not advocate what Hunsinger calls the nunc starts view of eternity. Cf. ST 110.2 ad 1.

55 Eleonore Stump and Norman Kretzmann, "Eternity", The Journal of Philosophy Vol. 78 (1981), pp. 429-458.

56 Ibid., p. 431. 57 Ibid., p. 435. 58 Ibid.,p.U3. 59 Ibid., ρΛ39. 60 Humans must do the same, although just how a temporal observer is to observe an event

as eternally present is not explained. 61 Stump and Kretzmann, "Eternity", p. 430. 62 ST 110.2 ad 2. 63 Interestingly, Thomas uses a similar illustration to argue that God's eternal willing of con­

tingent things is only suppositional. Cf. ST 119.3 and ad 1. 64 Stump and Kretzmann, "Absolute Simplicity", p. 368. 65 Ibid. 66 Ibid., p. 372. 67 Ibid., p. 369.

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 26: The Simplicity of the Living God

300 Christopher A. Franks

68 Ibid., p. 375Í. 69 Ibid., p. 368. 70 CD II/l, p. 447. 71 Ibid., p. 446. 72 Ibid., p. 220. 73 Ibid., p. 223. 74 Ibid., p. 447; cf. p. 83. 75 Ibid., p. 61. 76 Mi., p. 445. 77 Ibid., p. 15. 78 M*., p. 240. 79 Ibid., p. 39. 80 M*., pp. 613f. 81 Μί.,ρ.263. 82 Ibid., p. 282. 83 IM., p. 273. 84 Mi., p. 260. 85 Jb/d.,p. 303. 86 Ibid., p. 275. 87 Ibid.,p.A57. 88 IM., p. 446. 89 CD 1/1, pp. 160f. 90 I owe my understanding of this link between the implications of the Incarnation and the

distinctively Christian view of the distinction between God and creation to Robert Sokolowski. See his The God of Faith and Reason, especially chap. 4, "The Incarnation and the Christian Distinction".

91 CD II/l, p. 263. 92 ST 118.3. 93 I would like to express my gratitude to Reinhard Hütter for his encouragement and to the

anonymous readers appointed by this journal for their helpful comments.

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2005

Page 27: The Simplicity of the Living God

^ s

Copyright and Use:

As an ATLAS user, you may print, download, or send articles for individual use according to fair use as defined by U.S. and international copyright law and as otherwise authorized under your respective ATLAS subscriber agreement.

No content may be copied or emailed to multiple sites or publicly posted without the copyright holder(s)' express written permission. Any use, decompiling, reproduction, or distribution of this journal in excess of fair use provisions may be a violation of copyright law.

This journal is made available to you through the ATLAS collection with permission from the copyright holder(s). The copyright holder for an entire issue of a journal typically is the journal owner, who also may own the copyright in each article. However, for certain articles, the author of the article may maintain the copyright in the article. Please contact the copyright holder(s) to request permission to use an article or specific work for any use not covered by the fair use provisions of the copyright laws or covered by your respective ATLAS subscriber agreement. For information regarding the copyright holder(s), please refer to the copyright information in the journal, if available, or contact ATLA to request contact information for the copyright holder(s).

About ATLAS:

The ATLA Serials (ATLAS®) collection contains electronic versions of previously published religion and theology journals reproduced with permission. The ATLAS collection is owned and managed by the American Theological Library Association (ATLA) and received initial funding from Lilly Endowment Inc.

The design and final form of this electronic document is the property of the American Theological Library Association.