The Introduction to the Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

25
The Introduction to the Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

description

The Introduction to the Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom. 1. What is ‘right’? Hegel speaks of ‘right’ ( Recht ) not ‘rights’ or ‘a right’ – cf. French droit and Latin ius - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Transcript of The Introduction to the Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

Page 1: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

The Introduction to the Elements of the Philosophy of Right: Right, Will and

Freedom

Page 2: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

1. What is ‘right’?

Hegel speaks of ‘right’ (Recht) not ‘rights’ or ‘a right’ – cf. French droit and Latin ius

A right = a claim to something that one holds can be legitimately made in relation to others or in relation to the state and that typically ought to be legally protected and enforced

Right (justice or law) = whole system and foundation of law as distinct from specific legal statutes

Hegel is not directly concerned with ‘positive’ right – a particular, given body or system of laws

The ‘philosophical science of right’ (§ 1) is not to be confused with ‘the positive science of right’ (i.e. study of law, legal history) (§ 3)

Page 3: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

The basis of right is the realm of spirit [Geist] in general and its precise location and point of departure is the will; the will is free, so that freedom constitutes its substance and destiny [Bestimmung; also definition, determination, vocation, DJ] and the system of right is the realm of actualized freedom, the world of spirit produced from within itself as a second nature. (§ 4)

Page 4: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

(1) ‘Right’ is to be explained in terms of ‘spirit’

(2) More specifically, the form of ‘spirit’ designated by the term ‘will’

(3) The ‘will’ is essentially free; freedom is not a contingent property of the will

(4) The will must in some sense actualise or realise its freedom if it is to be what it essentially is

(5) It does this in the form of ‘the system of right’

(6) This system is some kind of ‘second’ nature’

Clearly, we must first look at Hegel’s theory of the will so as to explain what he means by the term ‘right’

Page 5: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

2. Hegel’s theory of the will

Hegel rejects view of will as separate faculty that mediates between thought and action

Any act of willing necessarily involves both thought and action and cannot, therefore, be considered as separate from them

Since freedom is the essence of the will, freedom must manifest itself in all the moments of the will

The concept of the will

The essential structure common to each and every individual will in which this structure is instantiated

This will is therefore universal or ‘general’ in the sense of applying to all willing whatsoever

Page 6: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

(1) Moment of abstract universality or ‘pure indeterminacy’ (§ 5)

One can conceive of oneself in abstraction from any given content (one’s needs, desires, drives etc.)

I encounter myself as a concrete self with certain needs, desires, drives etc.

I can, however, consider these given features as external to myself, in the sense of being able either to identify myself with them or to choose to renounce them

Second-order desires – desires relating to other desires - I may or may not desire to act on a desire that I happen to have

Hegel’s position is more radical than this – I can renounce all desires – a human being can commit suicide, whereas an animal cannot

Page 7: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

‘Negative’ freedom

Not in liberal sense – sphere free from interference by others, including the state, in which individuals may do as they please

(Hegel recognises the importance of such freedom, while providing a far more complex account of freedom)

In so far as I possess the capacity to abstract from all given determinations, I am a ‘pure’ self (or ‘I’) identical to all other such selves (at least in thought)

We can abstract from the particular differences that distinguish us from others and thereby think of ourselves as essentially equal as belonging to the same general type as them – abstract equality

Although an essential component (condition) of freedom, this conception of freedom is too abstract

Page 8: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

(2) The ‘finitude or particularization’ of the will (§ 6)

Willing always involves the willing of something

The will must have a determinate content or object

In having such a determinate content or object, the will becomes limited

By willing a determinate content or object, I subject myself to certain constraints (e.g. the means of realising an end)

(For Hegel something is finite when it finds its limit in something external to itself)

Page 9: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

(3) Will as unity of previous two moments – concrete universal – a universal that contains the particular within itself (§ 7)

The universal and the particular are not externally related to each other

Rather, the will remains ‘with itself’ (bei sich) in its object or the ‘other’ which limits it

The will is only truly will when it realises its essence or concept

It is itself essentially activity (i.e. the act of producing itself as will) as opposed to something already given

It does not, therefore, exist independently of this activity

Emphasis on self-activity and self-actualisation

Page 10: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

3. Freedom as ‘being with oneself in the other’

Form of freedom which already manifests itself in certain forms of human association based on feeling (e.g. friendship and love)

Objective aspect - I am subject to constraints that my relation to another imposes on me (e.g. the duty to be a good friend or spouse)

Thus my own will is limited

Yet I do not experience these constraints as something external

Subjective aspect - I experience, rather, a sense of absence of constraint in relation to them

Compatibility of freedom and constraint

Page 11: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

Unfreedom would be when I am subject to purely external constraints

Freedom as independence – I am not free when I am dependent on something external to me over which I have no control, while it may control or dominate me

Freedom is not, therefore, simply the absence of direct forms of interference and being able to do what one wants to do

This liberal freedom would seem to increase the more physically isolated one becomes - an essentially asocial conception of freedom

Given existence of constraints in a condition of interdependence, ideal condition would surely be one in which the constraints to which people are subject as social beings are not experienced as external constraints, because they can in some sense identify themselves with them – social freedom

Page 12: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

4. Levels of the will’s freedom (‘forms of the will’)

Increasingly complex and more adequate ways in which the will remains with itself in its object or ‘other’

(1) ‘Immediate or natural’ will (§ 11)

The will as determined by given desires, drives and inclinations etc.

These desires etc. are mine but without having been determined as mine by me – I just happen to have them

They are biologically, culturally and socially determined and thus not the product of my own will

Page 13: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

These desires, drives and inclinations etc. are indeterminate:

(i) There is an indeterminate multiplicity of them

(ii) They do not have a specific object (for example, the desire to eat, not the desire to eat some bread)

(2) The ‘resolving’ will (§§ 12-13)

Indeterminacy in senses (i) and (ii) is removed by

(i) willing to pursue one desire, drive or inclination rather than another one (e.g. the desire to work, rather than the desire to sleep)

(ii) willing one object rather than another as means (e.g. desiring to work on a Hegel essay rather than on a Kant essay)

Page 14: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

The capacity of the will to resolve presupposes that:

[T]his content is only a possible one for the reflection of ‘I’ into itself; it may or may not be mine; and ‘I’ is the possibility of determining myself to this or to something else; of choosing between these determinations which the ‘I’ must in this respect regard as external. (§ 14)

(3) Arbitrary will (freedom of choice, being able to do what one wants to do)

Capacity to objectify one’s given desires, drives and inclinations etc. and to choose among them

It remains, however, a contingent matter what one actually chooses

Page 15: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

(4) Happiness

The idea of happiness provides some kind of ordering principle

One’s various drives, desires and inclinations must be organised in a certain way, with some being subordinated to others

If two desires are incompatible, one must choose to act on the basis of one of them at the expense of the other

Such choices take place in the broader context of the plans and projects that we have

These plans and projects are themselves determined by what we think will make us happy

Page 16: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

The idea of happiness functions as a universal by means of which our given desires, drives etc. are consciously organised

But there is no independent standard to determine what the content of happiness itself should be

This content will therefore ultimately depend on what each individual takes happiness to be

In this respect, the content of happiness remains contingent and particular

Page 17: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

(5) Autonomy

When the will has universality, or itself as infinite form, as its content, object, and end, it is free not only in itself but also for itself. (§ 21)

The actualisation or realization of the concept of the will consists in the will making what it essentially is (in itself) into an object of consciousness (for itself)

Implicit → explicit

Hegel identifies ‘the will which is free in and for itself’ with ‘right, or ethics [Sittlichkeit]’ (§ 15R)

Page 18: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

This will is characterised by

(1) Universality – ‘the being which has being in itself and for itself has as its object the will itself as such, and hence itself in its pure universality’ (§ 21R)

(2) Necessity – ‘This self-consciousness which comprehends itself as essence through thought and thereby divests itself of the contingent and the untrue constitutes the principle of right, of morality, and of all ethics’. (§ 21R)

Autonomy = being subject to laws (principles of action characterised by universality and necessity) that are in some sense self-imposed

Page 19: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

Kant on autonomy:

[T]he will is not merely subject to the law but subject to it in such a way that it must be viewed as also giving the law to itself and just because of this as first subject to the law. (Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals)

For Kant, the mark of law is

(1) universality (something that is valid for all moral agents)

(2) necessity (it ought to be unconditionally obeyed - it is a matter of duty)

The rational will is subject to a law that it gives itself in the sense that this law conforms to agent’s own essential (rational) nature

Page 20: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

This identity of the will and the constraints to which it is subject in virtue of their common rationality means that the will is not subject to purely external constraints

The will which has being in and for itself is truly infinite, because its object is itself, and therefore not something which its sees as other or as a limitation. (§ 22)

(Infinity = not being limited by something external)

Only in this freedom is the will completely with itself [bei sich], because it has reference to nothing but itself, so that every relationship of dependence on something other than itself is thereby eliminated. (§ 23)

A form of freedom in which being subject to limitations need not be experienced as mere constraint

Page 21: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

5. Right

Right is any existence [Dasein] in general which is the existence of the free will (§ 29).

The forms of right outlined in PR are all ways in which the free will objectifies itself while remaining with itself in various entities:

(1) External objects or things (abstract right)

(2) External and internal actions, including their consequences (morality)

(3) Social and political institutions (ethical life)

Page 22: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

Institutions provide an objective guide to action in two senses:

(i) They exist in the world

(ii) They are objectively valid in relation to one’s own will – one has the duty to act in accordance with them

Norms derive from the relation of our own wills to such institutions

On the other hand, these institutions actualise certain rights that we have in the sense of being enabling conditions of freedom

The justification of these institutions lies in being such conditions of freedom

Page 23: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

As conditions of freedom, these institutions and the practices associated with them have a justified claim to be maintained by individuals and by society as a whole (a right to exist)

Freedom through institutions rather than freedom defined in opposition to institutions

The Structure of Hegel’s Theory of Right

The stages of right are increasingly adequate objectifications of all the moments of freedom (1) – (5) described above:

Each stage in the development of the Idea of freedom has its distinctive right, because it is the existence of freedom in one of its own determinations … Morality, ethics, and the interest of the state – each of these is a distinct variety of right, because each of them gives determinate shape and existence to freedom. (§ 30R)

Page 24: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

Abstract → concrete

A later stage is more concrete than an earlier one, in the sense that it more fully actualises freedom

An earlier one is subordinate to a later one (§ 30, including R)

A later stage cannot be adequately explained in terms of a lower one

A later stage in some sense completes and limits the claims of an earlier one

The development that the concept of right undergoes is conceptual not temporal (§ 32)

Page 25: The Introduction to the  Elements of the Philosophy of Right : Right, Will and Freedom

Right as ‘second’ nature

(1) Right is not something given but a human construct that depends on consciousness and will for its existence

(2) It nevertheless concerns the essence or nature of human freedom and reason

(3) People typically obey laws and conform to institutional demands unreflectively, that is, as a matter of habit