The Constitutional Right to Community Services

41
Georgia State University Law Review Volume 26 Issue 3 Spring 2010 Article 8 March 2012 e Constitutional Right to Community Services David Fergleger Follow this and additional works at: hps://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr Part of the Law Commons is Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Publications at Reading Room. It has been accepted for inclusion in Georgia State University Law Review by an authorized editor of Reading Room. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Recommended Citation David Fergleger, e Constitutional Right to Community Services, 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. (2012). Available at: hps://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

Transcript of The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Georgia State University Law ReviewVolume 26Issue 3 Spring 2010 Article 8

March 2012

The Constitutional Right to Community ServicesDavid Fergleger

Follow this and additional works at: https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr

Part of the Law Commons

This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Publications at Reading Room. It has been accepted for inclusion in Georgia StateUniversity Law Review by an authorized editor of Reading Room. For more information, please contact [email protected].

Recommended CitationDavid Fergleger, The Constitutional Right to Community Services, 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. (2012).Available at: https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TOCOMMUNITY SERVICES

David Ferleger*

INTRODUCTION

"[1Institutional placement of persons who can handle and benefitfrom community settings perpetuates unwarranted assumptionsthat persons so isolated are incapable or unworthy ofparticipating in community life."'

"Pennhurst provides confinement and isolation, the antithesis ofhabilitation."

2

"Institutions, by their very structure a closed and segregatedsociety founded on obsolete custodial models[,] can rarelynormalize and habilitate the mentally retarded citizen to theextent of community programs created and modeled upon thenormalization and developmental approach components ofhabilitation."3

Twenty-one years before the Supreme Court in Olmstead v. L. C.(Olmstead)4 held that unjustified institutionalization is discriminationforbidden by the Americans with Disabilities Act, a court issued thelandmark decision that all institutionalization of people with mentalretardation violates the United States Constitution and that stateshave an obligation to provide community services to the

* University of Pennsylvania Law School, J.D., 1972. The author has a national litigation andconsulting practice in disability law. He filed, litigated, and argued the Pennhurst case, discussed below.He was special master for a federal court for nine years in a case involving a state developmentaldisabilities institution, and was a court-appointed monitor in similar litigation.

1. Olmstead v. L.C., 527 U.S. 581, 600 (1999).2. Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 446 F. Supp. 1295, 1318 (E.D. Pa. 1978). For

subsequent history, see infra note 5.3. Halderman, 446 F. Supp. at 1318 (E.D. Pa. 1978).4. Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581, 587 (1999).

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 763 2009-2010

THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES

David Ferleger *

INTRODUCTION

"[I]nstitutional placement of persons who can handle and benefit from community settings perpetuates unwarranted assumptions that persons so isolated are incapable or unworthy of participating in community life.")

"Pennhurst provides confinement and isolation, the antithesis of habilitation. ,,2

"Institutions, by their very structure a closed and segregated society founded on obsolete custodial models[,] can rarely normalize and habilitate the mentally retarded citizen to the extent of community programs created and modeled upon the normalization and developmental approach components of habilitation. ,,3

Twenty-one years before the Supreme Court in Olmstead v. L. C. (Olmsteadt held that unjustified institutionalization is discrimination forbidden by the Americans with Disabilities Act, a court issued the landmark decision that all institutionalization of people with mental retardation violates the United States Constitution and that states have an obligation to provide community services to the

* University of Pennsylvania Law School, J.D., 1972. The author has a national litigation and consulting practice in disability law. He filed, litigated, and argued the Pennhurst case, discussed below. He was special master for a federal court for nine years in a case involving a state developmental disabilities institution, and was a court-appointed monitor in similar litigation.

\. Olmstead v. L.C., 527 U.S. 581, 600 (1999). 2. Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 446 F. Supp. 1295, 1318 (E.D. Pa. 1978). For

subsequent history, see infra note 5. 3. Halderman, 446 F. Supp. at 1318 (E.D. Pa. 1978). 4. Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581, 587 (1999).

763

1

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

institutionalized.5 The first quotation above is from Olmstead in 1999and the second two are from Halderman v. Pennhurst State Schooland Hospital (Pennhurst) in 1978.

United States District Judge Raymond J. Broderick, author ofPennhurst, was a conservative Republican jurist and formerLieutenant Governor of Pennsylvania. He was not a judicial activist.Those words did not come easily but after thoughtful consideration. 6

He was stirred in Pennhurst by the same considerations which shapedCongress' findings in the Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990 onsegregation and discrimination against people with disabilities. 7

5. Halderman, 446 F. Supp. at 1318 (E.D. Pa. 1978). The subsequent history of the case includestwo Supreme Court decisions and numerous other rulings. See, e.g., Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch.& Hosp., 465 U.S. 89 (1984); Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp. v. Halderman, 451 U.S. 1 (1981);Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 49 F.3d 939 (3rd Cir. 1995); Halderman v. Pennhurst StateSch. & Hosp., 901 F.2d 311 (3d Cir. 1990); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 707 F.2d 702(3d Cir. 1983); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 673 F.2d 645 (3d Cir. 1982) (on remand);Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 673 F.2d 628 (3d Cir. 1982); Halderman v. Pennhurst StateSch. & Hosp., 673 F.2d 647 (3d Cir. 1982); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 612 F.2d 84(3d Cir. 1979); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 612 F.2d 84 (3d Cir. 1979) (affirmed in partand reversed in part); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 612 F.2d 131 (3d Cir. 1979);Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 446 F. Supp. 1295 (E.D. Pa. 1977) (original trial courtdecision).For first-hand analysis of the case, see generally David Ferleger & Patrice McGuire, Rights and Dignity:Congress, the Supreme Court, and People with Disabilities After Pennhurst, 5 W. NEW ENG. L. REV.327 (1983); David Ferleger, Anti-Institutionalization and the Supreme Court, 14 RUTGERS L. REV. 595(1983); David Ferleger & Penelope A. Boyd, Anti-Institutionalization: The Promise of the PennhurstCase, 31 STAN. L. REV. 717 (1979); David Ferleger, The Right to Community Care for the Retarded, inNORMALIZATION, SOCIAL INTEGRATION AND COMMUNITY SERVICES (Robert J. Flynn & Kathleen E.Nitsch, eds., 1980).

6. Judge Broderick interrogated witness after witness on the need for institutions:"Would you agree with the other witnesses I've heard that it is time to sound the deathknell for institutions for the retardedT' Thus spoke United States District Judge RaymondJ. Broderick in the sixth week of trial. These words-soon to be echoed emphatically inthe court's unprecedented opinion-did not come easily. The judge had studied hard andlearned well. He spent the early days of trial listening to and interrogating expert afterexpert to find out whether an institution was not in fact needed in the southeast comer ofPennsylvania to serve 400 people. The answer was no. For 350 people? No. Oneinstitution for the entire state? No. An institution for the most profoundly retarded withphysical handicaps? Again, the answer was no. Even the superintendent of the institutiontold the court that there was no need to continue incarceration of the retarded atPennhurst.

David Ferleger & Penelope A. Boyd, Anti-Institutionalization: The Promise of the Pennhurst Case, 31STAN. L. REV. 717, 718 (1979).

7. In adopting the ADA, Congress recognized that "historically, society has tended to isolate andsegregate individuals with disabilities, and, despite some improvements, such forms of discriminationagainst individuals with disabilities continue to be a serious and pervasive social problem," and that"individuals with disabilities continually encounter various forms of discrimination, including outright

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 764 2009-2010

764 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 26:3

institutionalized.5 The first quotation above is from Olmstead in 1999 and the second two are from Halderman v. Pennhurst State School and Hospital (Pennhurst) in 1978.

United States District Judge Raymond J. Broderick, author of Pennhurst, was a conservative Republican jurist and former Lieutenant Governor of Pennsylvania. He was not a judicial activist. Those words did not come easily but after thoughtful consideration.6

He was stirred in Pennhurst by the same considerations which shaped Congress' findings in the Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990 on segregation and discrimination against people with disabilities.7

5. Halderman, 446 F. Supp. at 1318 (E.D. Pa. 1978). The subsequent history of the case includes two Supreme Court decisions and numerous other rulings. See, e.g., Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 465 U.S. 89 (1984); Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp. v. Halderman, 451 U.S. I (1981); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 49 F.3d 939 (3rd Cir. 1995); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 901 F.2d 311 (3d Cir. 1990); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 707 F.2d 702 (3d Cir. 1983); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 673 F.2d 645 (3d Cir. 1982) (on remand); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 673 F.2d 628 (3d Cir. 1982); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 673 F.2d 647 (3d Cir. 1982); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 612 F.2d 84 (3d Cir. 1979); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 612 F.2d 84 (3d Cir. 1979) (affirmed in part and reversed in part); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 612 F.2d 131 (3d Cir. 1979); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 446 F. Supp. 1295 (E.D. Pa. 1977) (original trial court decision). For first-hand analysis of the case, see generally David Ferleger & Patrice McGuire, Rights and Dignity: Congress, the Supreme Court, and People with Disabilities After Pennhurst, 5 W. NEW ENG. 1. REv. 327 (1983); David Ferleger, Anti-Institutionalization and the Supreme Court, 14 RUTGERS 1. REv. 595 (1983); David Ferleger & Penelope A. Boyd, Anti-Institutionalization: The Promise 0/ the Pennhurst Case, 31 STAN. 1. REv. 717 (1979); David Ferleger, The Right to Community Care/or the Retarded, in NORMALIZATION, SOCIAL INTEGRATION AND COMMUNITY SERVICES (Robert J. Flynn & Kathleen E. Nitsch, eds., 1980).

6. Judge Broderick interrogated witness after witness on the need for institutions: "Would you agree with the other witnesses I've heard that it is time to sound the death knell for institutions for the retarded?" Thus spoke United States District Judge Raymond J. Broderick in the sixth week of trial. These words-soon to be echoed emphatically in the court's unprecedented opinion-did not come easily. The judge had studied hard and learned well. He spent the early days of trial listening to and interrogating expert after expert to find out whether an institution was not in fact needed in the southeast comer of Pennsylvania to serve 400 people. The answer was no. For 350 people? No. One institutinn for the entire state? No. An institution for the most profoundly retarded with physical handicaps? Again, the answer was no. Even the superintendent of the institution told the court that there was no need to continue incarceration of the retarded at Pennhurst.

David Ferleger & Penelope A. Boyd, Anti-Institutionalization: The Promise 0/ the Pennhurst Case, 31 STAN. 1. REv. 717, 718 (1979).

7. In adopting the ADA, Congress recognized that "historically, society has tended to isolate and segregate individuals with disabilities, and, despite some improvements, such forms of discrimination against individuals with disabilities continue to be a serious and pervasive social problem," and that "individuals with disabilities continually encounter various forms of discrimination, including outright

2

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 765

Pennhurst foreshadowed the Supreme Court's identification inOlmstead v. L.C., of the profound negative impact of institutions onthose confined 8 and its holding that the ADA proscribes"[u]njustified isolation of individuals with disabilities." 9

With a satisfied grin, whether in public or private, Judge Broderickoften observed that his decision recognizing the constitutional right tocommunity services was never reversed. 10 Indeed, while the 1978decision precipitated two Supreme Court decisions on other grounds,and a myriad of rulings on related issues, the constitutional holdingswere not questioned on appeal or certiorari. 1 The commitment toalternatives to institutions, premised on constitutional rights,espoused in Pennhurst was the groundwork for much other litigation,became support for various states' policies, and a rallying point forinstitutional residents, professionals in the field, and advocates. 1 2

It was not until Olmstead, however, that the Supreme Courtweighed in on the institutionalization issue and this time, unlikePennhurst, there was a federal statutory ground for the decision. 13

The emergence of the "integration mandate" of the ADA, and the

intentional exclusion, . . . failure to make modifications to existing facilities and practices .... [and]segregation." 42 U.S.C. § 12101(a)(2), (5) (2006) (emphasis added).

8. The Court stated the following:Recognition that unjustified institutional isolation of persons with disabilities is a form ofdiscrimination reflects two evident judgments. First, institutional placement of personswho can handle and benefit from community settings perpetuates unwarrantedassumptions that persons so isolated are incapable or unworthy of participating incommunity life. [citations omitted] Second, confinement in an institution severelydiminishes the everyday life activities of individuals, including family relations, socialcontacts, work options, economic independence, educational advancement, and culturalenrichment. [citation omitted] Dissimilar treatment correspondingly exists in this keyrespect: In order to receive needed medical services, persons with mental disabilitiesmust, because of those disabilities, relinquish participation in community life they couldenjoy given reasonable accommodations, while persons without mental disabilities canreceive the medical services they need without similar sacrifice.

Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 600-01 (1999).9. Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 582 (1999).

10. Judge Broderick made the comment to the author and in various speeches and interviews, alwayswith the same confidence in the original constitutional grounding of his 1978 decision.

11. See supra note 5.12. See E.g., MARTHA MINOW, MAKING ALL THE DIFFERENCE: INCLUSION, EXCLUSION, AND

AMERICAN LAW 140-45 (1991); Samuel R. Bagenstos, Abolish the Integration Presumption? Not Yet,156 U. PA. L. REV. 157 (2007).

13. See Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581 (1999). Contra Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 446 F.Supp. 1295, 1318 (E.D. Pa. 1978).

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 765 2009-2010

2010) THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 765

Pennhurst foreshadowed the Supreme Court's identification in Olmstead v. L. c., of the profound negative impact of institutions on those confined8 and its holding that the ADA proscribes "[ u ]njustified isolation of individuals with disabilities.,,9

With a satisfied grin, whether in public or private, Judge Broderick often observed that his decision recognizing the constitutional right to community services was never reversed. lo Indeed, while the 1978 decision precipitated two Supreme Court decisions on other grounds, and a myriad of rulings on related issues, the constitutional holdings were not questioned on appeal or certiorari. II The commitment to alternatives to institutions, premised on constitutional rights, espoused in Pennhurst was the groundwork for much other litigation, became support for various states' policies, and a rallying point for institutional residents, professionals in the field, and advocates. 12

It was not until Olmstead, however, that the Supreme Court weighed in on the institutionalization issue and this time, unlike Pennhurst, there was a federal statutory ground for the decision. 13

The emergence of the "integration mandate" of the ADA, and the

intentional exclusion, . . . failure to make modifications to existing facilities and practices, ... [and] segregation." 42 U.S.C. § 12101(a)(2), (5) (2006) (emphasis added).

8. The Court stated the following: Recognition that unjustified institutional isolation of persons with disabilities is a form of discrimination reflects two evident judgments. First, institutional placement of persons who can handle and benefit from community settings perpetuates unwarranted assumptions that persons so isolated are incapable or unworthy of participating in community life. [citations omitted] Second, confmement in an institution severely diminishes the everyday life activities of individuals, including family relations, social contacts, work options, economic independence, educational advancement, and cultural enrichment. [citation omitted] Dissimilar treatment correspondingly exists in this key respect: In order to receive needed medical services, persons with mental disabilities must, because of those disabilities, relinquish participation in community life they could enjoy given reasonable accommodations, while persons without mental disabilities can receive the medical services they need without similar sacrifice.

Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 600-01 (1999). 9. Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 582 (1999).

10. Judge Broderick made the comment to the author and in various speeches and interviews, always with the same confidence in the original constitutional grounding of his 1978 decision.

II. See supra note 5. 12. See E.g., MARTHA MINOW, MAKING ALL THE DWFERENCE: INCLUSION, EXCLUSION, AND

AMERICAN LAW 140-45 (1991); Samuel R. Bagenstos, Abolish the Integration Presumption? Not Yet, 156 U. PA. L. REv. 157 (2007).

13. See Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581 (1999). Contra Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 446 F. Supp. 1295, 1318 (E.D. Pa. 1978).

3

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

Supreme Court's emphatic recognition in Olmstead of the benefits ofcommunity services for people who are institutionalized hasdiminished discussion of the constitutional inquiries which are thefocus of this article.

This is a moment for a "necessary and overdue"' 14 return toconstitutional principles as a means both to support the integrationmandate and to surmount some of the weaknesses of a purely ADAand Olmstead approach.

I propose that involuntary institutionalization of people withintellectual disabilities is unconstitutional on due process and equalprotection grounds. 15 Due process precludes needless curtailment ofpersonal liberty. Equal protection forbids discrimination against suchindividuals unless necessitated by a compelling state interest, aninterest absent in non-criminal institutionalization. On groundworklanguage in Olmstead, I suggest that the narrow class of involuntarilyinstitutionalized individuals with intellectual disabilities is a suspector quasi-suspect class under the Equal Protection Clause.

14. The phrase is from Dr. Morton Birnbaum whose writings inspired the call for recognition of aright to treatment for people in institutions fifty years ago; he termed it a "necessary and overduedevelopment of our present concept of due process of law." Morton Birnbaum, The Right to Treatment,46 A.B.A. J. 499, 503 (1960). The right to treatment did achieve recognition. For an early decision, seeRouse v. Cameron, 373 F.2d 451, 455 (D.C. Cir. 1966). For the early development of the right, seeDevelopments in the Law: Civil Commitment of the Mentally 111, 87 HARv. L. REV. 1190 (1974); RussellJackson Drake, Enforcing the Right to Treatment: Wyatt v. Stickney, 10 AM. CRIM. L. REv. 587 (1972);Stanley Herr, Civil Rights, Uncivil Asylums and the Retarded, 43 U. CIN. L. REv. 679 (1974).

15. The caselaw is often imprecise in defining the individuals involved in the litigation discussed inthis article. What had been called "Mental Retardation" is currently defined as "Intellectual Disability"by the American Association on Intellectual and Developmental Disabilities (formerly, the AmericanAssociation on Mental Retardation). ROBERT L. SCHALOCK ET AL., INTELLECTUAL DISABILITY:

DEFINITION, CLASSIFICATION, AND SYSTEMS OF SUPPORTS (lth ed. 2010). "Developmentaldisabilities" is a broader category than mental retardation is statutorily (not clinically) defined. Seegenerally Developmental Disabilities Assistance and Bill of Rights Act Amendments of 1994, Pub. L.No. 103-230, 108 Stat. 284 (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C.A. § 15002 (2000)).

Where contextually appropriate, I have chosen to use the term current in the field, that is,"intellectual disability," to refer to what was formerly called "mental retardation." Although stillunfamiliar in the legal literature, and not yet adopted in the caselaw, intellectual disability will becomethe norm in short order. However, where I refer to history, reported cases, or the published literature, Isometimes use the original source's terminology. It should be kept in mind that, while the categoriesoverlap, there is a difference between developmental disabilities and intellectual disability with regard totheir clinical, social, and functional features. However, for the purposes of this article, the applicablelegal principles are the same.

While much of the analysis in this article might also apply to "mental illness," the discussion islimited to the rights of people with intellectual disabilities.

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 766 2009-2010

766 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 26:3

Supreme Court's emphatic recognition in Olmstead of the benefits of

community services for people who are institutionalized has

diminished discussion of the constitutional inquiries which are the

focus of this article.

This is a moment for a "necessary and overdue,,14 return to

constitutional principles as a means both to support the integration

mandate and to surmount some of the weaknesses of a purely ADA

and Olmstead approach.

I propose that involuntary institutionalization of people with

intellectual disabilities is unconstitutional on due process and equal

protection grounds. 15 Due process precludes needless curtailment of

personal liberty. Equal protection forbids discrimination against such

individuals unless necessitated by a compelling state interest, an

interest absent in non-criminal institutionalization. On groundwork

language in Olmstead, I suggest that the narrow class of involuntarily

institutionalized individuals with intellectual disabilities is a suspect

or quasi-suspect class under the Equal Protection Clause.

14. The phrase is from Dr. Morton Birnbaum whose writings inspired the call for recognition of a right to treatment for people in institutions fifty years ago; he termed it a "necessary and overdue development of our present concept of due process of law." Morton Birnbaum, The Right to Treatment, 46 A.B.A. J. 499, 503 (1960). The right to treatment did achieve recognition. For an early decision, see Rouse v. Cameron, 373 F.2d 451, 455 (D.C. Cir. 1966). For the early development of the right, see Developments in the Law: Civil Commitment of the Mentally Ill, 87 HARv. L. REV. 1190 (1974); Russell Jackson Drake, Enforcing the Right to Treatment: Wyatt v. Stickney, 10 AM. CRIM. L. REv. 587 (1972); Stanley Herr, Civil Rights. Uncivil Asylums and the Retarded, 43 U. CIN. L. REv. 679 (1974).

15. The caselaw is often imprecise in defining the individuals involved in the litigation discussed in this article. What had been called "Mental Retardation" is currently defined as "Intellectual Disability" by the American Association on Intellectual and Developmental Disabilities (formerly, the American Association on Mental Retardation). ROBERT L. SCHALOCK ET AL., INTELLECTUAL DISABILITY: DEFINITION, CLASSIFICATION, AND SYSTEMS OF SUPPORTS (11th ed. 2010). "Developmental disabilities" is a broader category than mental retardation is statutorily (not clinically) defined. See generally Developmental Disabilities Assistance and Bill of Rights Act Amendments of 1994, Pub. L. No. 103-230, 108 Stat. 284 (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C.A. § 15002 (2000».

Where contextually appropriate, I have chosen to use the term current in the field, that is, "intellectual disability," to refer to what was formerly called "mental retardation." Although still unfamiliar in the legal literature, and not yet adopted in the caselaw, intellectual disability will become the norm in short order. However, where I refer to history, reported cases, or the published literature, I sometimes use the original source's terminology. It should be kept in mind that, while the categories overlap, there is a difference between developmental disabilities and intellectual disability with regard to their clinical, social, and functional features. However, for the purposes of this article, the applicable legal principles are the same.

While much of the analysis in this article might also apply to "mental illness," the discussion is limited to the rights of people with intellectual disabilities.

4

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

20101 THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 767

Restoration of constitutional rights to the conversation cures someof the deficits in the Olmstead statutory construct. In addition, thejudicial armamentarium available to enforce constitutional rightsmakes techniques available to enforce a broader and more powerfulresponsibility on the part of the state to eliminate unnecessaryinstitutionalization through the expansion of quality communityservices.

In this article, I briefly outline the Olmstead decision and thendiscuss its limitations. I assume some familiarity with the history ofinstitutional and community care, and the litigation which precededOlmstead.16

I. THE AMERICANS WITH DISABILITIES ACT

A. Olmstead: A "Qualified Yes " to Community Services

In Olmstead v. L.C., the United States Supreme Court held thatTitle II of the Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990 (ADA) 17

requires the placement of persons with mental disabilities incommunity settings, rather than in institutions, when: (1) the state's

16. See generally Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581 (1999). The work of Jacobus tenBroek is groundbreakingbut often unacknowledged, Jacobus tenBroek, The Right to Live in the World: The Disabled in the Lawof Torts, 54 CAL. L. REV. 841 (1966); Jacobus tenBroek & Floyd W. Matson, The Disabled and the Lawof Welfare, 54 CAL. L. REV. 809 (1966); see also, e.g., Samantha A. DiPolito, Olmstead v. L.C.-Deinstitutionalization and Community Integration: An Awakening of the Nations' Conscience?, 58MERCER L. REV. 1381, 1382-88 (2007) (nature and effects of institutionalization, and history ofcommunity services); Jefferson D.E. Smith & Steve P. Callandrillo, Forward to FundamentalAlteration: Addressing ADA Title Il Integration Lawsuits After Olmstead v. L.C., 24 HARV. J. L. & PUB.POL'Y 695, 703-05 (2001) (harms of institutionalization and benefits of community services); Mark C.Weber, Home and Community-Based Services, Olmstead, and Positive Rights: A PreliminaryDiscussion, 39 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 269, 273-77 (2004) (history and nature of institutionalization).On disability discrimination, see generally Samuel R. Bagenstos, Subordination, Stigma, and"Disability, " 86 VA. L. REV. 397, 418 (2000) ("subordinated status" of persons with a disability); PaulaE. Berg, Ill/Legal: Interrogating the Meaning and Function of the Category of Disability inAntidiscrimination Law, 18 YALE L. & POL'Y REV. 1, 9 (1999); Jonathan C. Drimmer, Comment,Cripples, Overcomers, and Civil Rights: Tracing the Evolution of Federal Legislation and Social Policyfor People with Disabilities, 40 UCLA L. REV. 1341, 1357-58 (1993) (civil rights model of disability);Michael L. Perlin, "Their Promises of Paradise ": Will Olmstead v. L.C. Resuscitate the Constitutional"Least Restrictive Alternative" Principle in Mental Disability Law?, 37 Hous. L. REV. 999, 1005-10(2000); Peter Blanck, "The Right to Live in the World": Disability Yesterday, Today, and Tomorrow, 13TEx. J. C.L. & C.R. 367 (2008).

17. Americans with Disabilities Act, 42 U.S.C. § 12132 (1990).

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 767 2009-2010

2010) THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 767

Restoration of constitutional rights to the conversation cures some of the deficits in the Olmstead statutory construct. In addition, the judicial armamentarium available to enforce constitutional rights makes techniques available to enforce a broader and more powerful responsibility on the part of the state to eliminate unnecessary institutionalization through the expansion of quality community services.

In this article, I briefly outline the Olmstead decision and then discuss its limitations. I assume some familiarity with the history of institutional and community care, and the litigation which preceded Olmstead. 16

I. THE AMERICANS WITH DISABILITIES ACT

A. Olmstead: A "Qualified Yes" to Community Services

In Olmstead v. L. c., the United States Supreme Court held that Title II of the Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990 (ADA)17 requires the placement of persons with mental disabilities in community settings, rather than in institutions, when: (1) the state's

16. See generally Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581 (1999). The work of Jacobus tenBroek is groundbreaking but often unacknowledged. Jacobus tenBroek, The Right to Live in the World: The Disabled in the Law of Torts, 54 CAL. L. REv. 841 (1966); Jacobus tenBroek & Floyd W. Matson, The Disabled and the Law of Welfare, 54 CAL. L. REv. 809 (1966); see also, e.g., Samantha A. DiPolito, Olmstead v. L.C.­Deinstitutionalization and Community Integration: An Awakening of the Nations' Conscience?, 58 MERCER L. REv. 1381, 1382-88 (2007) (nature and effects of institutionalization, and history of community services); Jefferson D.E. Smith & Steve P. Callandrillo, Forward to Fundamental Alteration: Addressing ADA Title II Integration Lawsuits After Olmstead v. L.C., 24 HARv. J. L. & PUB. POL'y 695, 703-{)5 (2001) (hanns of institutionalization and benefits of community services); Mark C. Weber, Home and Community-Based Services, Olmstead and Positive Rights: A Preliminary Discussion, 39 WAKE FOREST L. REv. 269,273-77 (2004) (history and nature of institutionalization). On disability discrimination, see generally Samuel R. Bagenstos, Subordination, Stigma, and "Disability," 86 VA. L. REv. 397,418 (2000) ("subordinated status" of persons with a disability); Paula E. Berg, Ill/Legal: Interrogating the Meaning and Function of the Category of Disability in Antidiscrimination Law, 18 YALE L. & POL'y REv. I, 9 (1999); Jonathan C. Drimmer, Comment, Cripples, Overcomers, and Civil Rights: Tracing the Evolution of Federal Legislation and Social Policy for People with Disabilities, 40 UCLA L. REv. 1341, 1357-58 (1993) (civil rights model of disability); Michael L. Perlin, "Their Promises of Paradise": Will Olmstead v. L.C. Resuscitate the Constitutional "Least Restrictive Alternative" Principle in Mental Disability Law?, 37 Hous. L. REv. 999, 1005-10 (2000); Peter Blanck, "The Right to Live in the World": Disability Yesterday, Today, and Tomarrow, 13 TEx. J. C.L. & C.R. 367 (2008).

17. Americans with Disabilities Act, 42 U.S.C. § 12132 (1990).

5

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

treatment professionals determine that such a placement isappropriate, (2) the transfer is not opposed by the individual, and (3)the placement can be reasonably accommodated given the resourcesavailable to the state and its obligation to provide for the needs ofothers with mental disabilities. 18 A five justice majority held that afailure to provide care for individuals with mental disabilities in themost integrated setting appropriate to their needs may be viewed asdiscrimination, in violation of the ADA, unless the state or otherpublic entity can demonstrate an inability to provide less restrictivecare without "fundamentally alter[ing]" the nature of its programs.19

Congress passed the Americans with Disabilities Act in 1990.20

Designed as a comprehensive statutory scheme, the ADA seeks toeliminate disability discrimination on three fronts: employment;public services offered by public; and public services andaccommodations offered by private entities.

Prior to the ADA,2' Section 504 of the Rehabilitation Act of 197322was the major statutory ground for challenge to discriminationagainst people with disabilities.23 Section 504 provides relief when aprogram or service receives federal funds and, thus, affects residentsof virtually all public institutions.24 Section 504 had been on thebooks for years but it had proven of limited utility in affectingdeinstitutionalization, despite a regulatory integration requirement.25

18. Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581, 607 (1999).19. Id. at 592; 28 C.F.R. § 35.130(b)(7) (1998).20. Americans with Disabilities Act, 42 U.S.C. §§ 12101-12213 (1990).21. Id. § 12132.22. 29 U.S.C. § 794 (1973).23. Although Section 504 has been called "the cornerstone of the civil rights movement of the

mobility-impaired," its shortcomings and deficiencies quickly became apparent. ADAPT v. Skinner, 881F.2d 1184, 1205 (3d Cir. 1989) (Mansmann, J., concurring). See, e.g., Timothy Cook, The Americanswith Disabilities Act: The Move to Integration, 64 TEMP. L. REv. 393, 394-408 (1991) (theRehabilitation Act and its regulations have been practically a dead letter as a remedy for segregatedpublic services). One commentator has written that the weaknesses of section 504 arise from its statutorylanguage, "the limited extent of their coverage, inadequate enforcement mechanisms, and erratic judicialinterpretations." Robert L. Burgdorf Jr., The Americans with Disabilities Act: Analysis and Implicationsof a Second-Generation Civil Rights Statute, 26 HARv. C.R-C.L. L. REv. 413, 431 (1991).

24. 29 U.S.C. § 794 (1973).25. See 29 U.S.C. § 794; 28 C.F.R. § 41.51(d) (2001) (providing that programs and activities shall be

administered "in the most integrated setting appropriate"). A number of courts held that the denial ofcommunity based habilitation services to mentally disabled individuals does not constitute a viablecause of action under section 504. E.g., Ky. Ass'n for Retarded Citizens, Inc. v. Conn, 674 F.2d 582,

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 768 2009-2010

768 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 26:3

treatment professionals determine that such a placement is appropriate, (2) the transfer is not opposed by the individual, and (3) the placement can be reasonably accommodated given the resources available to the state and its obligation to provide for the needs of others with mental disabilities. 18 A five justice majority held that a failure to provide care for individuals with mental disabilities in the most integrated setting appropriate to their needs may be viewed as discrimination, in violation of the ADA, unless the state or other public entity can demonstrate an inability to provide less restrictive care without "fundamentally alter[ing]" the nature of its programs. 19

Congress passed the Americans with Disabilities Act in 1990?0 Designed as a comprehensive statutory scheme, the ADA seeks to eliminate disability discrimination on three fronts: employment; public services offered by public; and public services and accommodations offered by private entities.

Prior to the ADA,21 Section 504 of the Rehabilitation Act of 197322

was the major statutory ground for challenge to discrimination against people with disabilities?3 Section 504 provides relief when a program or service receives federal funds and, thus, affects residents of virtually all public institutions?4 Section 504 had been on the books for years but it had proven of limited utility in affecting deinstitutionalization, despite a regulatory integration requirement.25

18. Olmstead, 527 U.s. 581, 607 (1999). 19. /d. at 592; 28 C.F.R. § 35. 130(b)(7) (1998). 20. Americans with Disabilities Act, 42 U.S.C. §§ 12101-12213 (1990). 21. Id. § 12132. 22. 29 U.s.C. § 794 (1973). 23. Although Section 504 has been called "the cornerstone of the civil rights movement of the

mobility-impaired," its shortcomings and deficiencies quickly became apparent. ADAPT v. Skinner, 881 F.2d 1184, 1205 (3d Cir. 1989) (Mansmann, J., concurring). See, e.g., Timothy Cook, The Americans with Disabilities Act: The Move to Integration, 64 TEMP. L. REv. 393, 394-408 (1991) (the Rehabilitation Act and its regulations have been practically a dead letter as a remedy for segregated public services). One commentator has written that the weaknesses of section 504 arise from its statutory language, "the limited extent of their coverage, inadequate enforcement mechanisms, and erratic judicial interpretations." Robert L. Burgdorf Jr., The Americans with Disabilities Act: Analysis and Implications o/a Second-Generation Civil Rights Statute, 26 HARv. C.R-C.L. L. REV. 413, 431 (1991).

24. 29 U.S.C. § 794 (1973). 25. See 29 U.S.C. § 794; 28 C.F.R. § 41.51(d) (2001) (providing that programs and activities shall be

administered "in the most integrated setting appropriate"). A number of courts held that the denial of community based habilitation services to mentally disabled individuals does not constitute a viable cause of action under section 504. E.g., Ky. Ass'n for Retarded Citizens, Inc. v. Conn, 674 F.2d 582,

6

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 769

The ADA differs from the Rehabilitation Act and other earlierstatutes in that it explicitly recognizes "institutionalization" and"segregation" as forms of discrimination against disabledindividuals. 26 Also, the ADA required adoption of implementingregulations.27 There are two regulations most relevant to theOlmstead decision; together they comprise the "integration mandate"of the ADA. The first is the integration regulation, which states: "Apublic entity shall administer services, programs and activities in themost integrated setting appropriate to the needs of qualifiedindividuals with disabilities. 28 The second is the reasonablemodifications regulation, which provides: "A public entity shall makereasonable modifications in policies, practices, or procedures whenthe modifications are necessary to avoid discrimination on the basisof disability, unless the public entity can demonstrate conclusivelythat making the modifications would fundamentally alter the natureof the service, program, or activity., 29

Delivering the Court's Olmstead decision, Justice Ginsburg framedthe issue as "whether the [ADA's] proscription of discrimination mayrequire placement of persons with mental disabilities in communitysettings rather then in institutions." 30 She expressed the Court'sanswer conspicuously as "a qualified yes." 31

While the majority concluded that unnecessary institutionalization32 3violated the ADA, Justice Ginsburg spoke for a plurality of four.33

Justices O'Connor, Souter and Breyer joined her opinion as to thefundamental alteration defense. 34 Justice Stevens would have

585 (6th Cir. 1982); Conner v. Branstad, 839 F. Supp. 1346, 1346 (S.D. Iowa 1993); Sabo v. O'Bannon,586 F. Supp. 1132, 1137 (E.D. Pa. 1984); Manecke v. Sch. Bd., 553 F. Supp. 787, 790 n. 4 (M.D. Fla.1982), aftd in part and rev'd in part, 762 F.2d 912 (11th Cir. 1985); Garrity v. Gallen, 522 F. Supp.171, 213 (D.N.H. 1981). These holdings, however, do not necessarily exclude application of Section 504to egregious discrimination in a particular individual case.

26. 42 U.S.C. §§ 12101(a)(2), (3), (5) (2006).27. 42 U.S.C. § 12134 (2006) (attorney general to promulgate regulations).28. 28 C.F.R. § 35.130(d) (2001).29. 28 C.F.R. § 35.130(b)(7) (2001).30. Olmstead v. L.C., 527 U.S. 581, 587 (1999).31. Id. (emphasis added).32. Id. at 587-603.33. Id. (O'Connor, Souter, and Breyer, JJ., concurring with respect to Part I1I-B).34. Id. at 603-07.

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 769 2009-2010

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 769

The ADA differs from the Rehabilitation Act and other earlier statutes in that it explicitly recognizes "institutionalization" and "segregation" as forms of discrimination against disabled individuals?6 Also, the ADA required adoption of implementing regulations.27 There are two regulations most relevant to the Olmstead decision; together they comprise the "integration mandate" of the ADA. The first is the integration regulation, which states: "A public entity shall administer services, programs and activities in the most integrated setting appropriate to the needs of qualified individuals with disabilities.,,28 The second is the reasonable modifications regulation, which provides: "A public entity shall make reasonable modifications in policies, practices, or procedures when the modifications are necessary to avoid discrimination on the basis of disability, unless the public entity can demonstrate conclusively that making the modifications would fundamentally alter the nature of the service, program, or activity.,,29

Delivering the Court's Olmstead decision, Justice Ginsburg framed the issue as "whether the [ADA's] proscription of discrimination may require placement of persons with mental disabilities in community settings rather then in institutions.,,30 She expressed the Court's answer conspicuously as "a qualified yes." 31

While the majority concluded that unnecessary institutionalization violated the ADA,32 Justice Ginsburg spoke for a plurality of four. 33

Justices O'Connor, Souter and Breyer joined her opinion as to the fundamental alteration defense.34 Justice Stevens would have

585 (6th Cir. 1982); Conner v. Branstad, 839 F. Supp. 1346, 1346 (S.D. Iowa 1993); Sabo v. O'Bannon, 586 F. Supp. 1132, 1137 (E.D. Pa. 1984); Manecke v. Sch. Bd, 553 F. Supp. 787, 790 n. 4 (M.D. Fla. 1982), affd in part and rev'd in part, 762 F.2d 912 (11th Cir. 1985); Garrity v. Gallen, 522 F. Supp. 171,213 (D.N.H. 1981). These holdings, however, do not necessarily exclude application of Section 504 to egregious discrimination in a particular individual case.

26. 42 U.S.C. §§ 12 101 (a)(2), (3), (5) (2006). 27. 42 U.S.C. § 12134 (2006) (attorney general to promulgate regulations). 28. 28 C.F.R. § 35.130(d) (2001). 29. 28 C.F.R. § 35.130(b)(7) (2001). 30. Olmstead v. L.C., 527 U.S. 581, 587 (1999). 31. Id. (emphasis added). 32. Id. at 587-603. 33. Id. (O'Connor, Souter, and Breyer, JJ., concuning with respect to Part III-B). 34. !d. at 603-07.

7

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

affirmed the judgment of the court of appeals. 35 Justice Kennedy,concurring separately, was concerned that the decision mightpressure the states into "attempting compliance on the cheap, placingmarginal patients into integrated settings devoid of the services andattention necessary for their condition., 36

The Court based its decision that unnecessary institutionalization isa form of discrimination on two rationales. First, placing people withdisabilities who are capable of living in the community in institutionsperpetuates the stereotypes that such individuals are unworthy orincapable of participating in community life.37 Second, confinementin an institution deprives the individual of participation in a broadspectrum of important activities, such as "family relations, socialcontacts, work options, economic independence, educationaladvancement, and cultural enrichment." 38 The Court recognized thatinstitutionalization implies discrimination: "[T]o receive neededmedical services, persons with mental disabilities must, because ofthose disabilities, relinquish participation in community life theycould enjoy given reasonable accommodations, while personswithout mental disabilities can receive the medical services they needwithout similar sacrifice." 39

Olmstead was heralded as a potentially "revolutionary" advancefor people with disabilities. Although other courts had previouslyfound the same protections in the ADA,4 1 Olmstead's conclusion thatTitle II of the ADA forbids "[u]njustified isolation" of people withdisabilities was a defining moment.42

35. Id. at 607-08.36. Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 610.37. Id. at 600.38. Id. at 601.39. Id.40. "Olmstead potentially has the capacity to transform and revolutionize mental health law."

Michael L. Perlin, "I Ain't Gonna Work on Maggie's Farm No More," Institutional Segregation,Community Treatment, the ADA, and the Promise of Olmstead v. L.C., 17 T.M. COOLEY L. REV. 53, 56(2000); see also Mary C. Cerreto, Olnstead: The Brown v. Board of Education for Disability Rights:Promises, Limits, and Issues, 3 LoY. J. PUB. INT. L. 47 (2001).

41. E.g., Helen L v. DiDario, 46 F.3d 325, 333 (3d Cir. 1995) ("[T]he ADA and its attendantregulations clearly define unnecessary segregation as a form of illegal discrimination against thedisabled.").

42. Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 582.

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 770 2009-2010

770 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW (Vol. 26:3

affirmed the judgment of the court of appeals.35 Justice Kennedy, concurring separately, was concerned that the decision might pressure the states into "attempting compliance on the cheap, placing marginal patients into integrated settings devoid of the services and attention necessary for their condition.,,36

The Court based its decision that unnecessary institutionalization is a form of discrimination on two rationales. First, placing people with disabilities who are capable of living in the community in institutions perpetuates the stereotypes that such individuals are unworthy or incapable of participating in community life.37 Second, confinement in an institution deprives the individual of participation in a broad spectrum of important activities, such as "family relations, social contacts, work options, economic independence, educational advancement, and cultural enrichment.,,38 The Court recognized that institutionalization implies discrimination: "[T]o receive needed medical services, persons with mental disabilities must, because of those disabilities, relinquish participation in community life they could enjoy given reasonable accommodations, while persons without mental disabilities can receive the medical services they need without similar sacrifice. ,,39

Olmstead was heralded as a potentially "revolutionary" advance for people with disabilities.4o Although other courts had previously found the same protections in the ADA,41 Olmstead's conclusion that Title II of the ADA forbids "[u]njustified isolation" of people with disabilities was a defining moment.42

35. Id. at 607-08. 36. Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 610. 37. Id. at 600. 38. Id. at 601. 39. Id. 40. "Olmstead potentially has the capacity to transform and revolutionize mental health law."

Michael L. Perlin, "I Ain't Gonna Work on Maggie's Farm No More," Institutional Segregation, Community Treatment, the ADA, and the Promise o/Olmstead v. L.C., 17 T.M. COOLEY L. REv. 53, 56 (2000); see also Mary C. Cerreto, Olmstead: The Brown v. Board of Education/or Disability Rights: Promises, Limits, and Issues, 3 loY. J. PuB. INT. L. 47 (2001).

41. E.g., Helen L v. DiDario, 46 F.3d 325, 333 (3d Cir. 1995) ("[T]he ADA and its attendant regulations clearly define unnecessary segregation as a form of illegal discrimination against the disabled.").

42. Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 582.

8

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

20101 THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 771

B. Olmstead's Shortcomings

Legal advocates and scholars are perhaps prone to overstate theimpact of particular cases on the world generally, as well as on thelaw. That has been Olmstead's fortune. 43 While one might haveexpected that the Olmstead decision would have acceleratedcommunity placement, this has not been the case. In addition, thedecision is fraught with deficiencies which thwart achievement of theright articulated by the Court, that is, to the right to be free fromunjustified isolation.

1. Movement from Institutions Has Slowed

Since the Olmstead decision, there has been a slowing of themovement of residents from both public and private institutions,according to an analysis marking the case's tenth anniversary.44

Between June 30, 1990 and June 30, 1999, public institutionpopulations decreased by about 30,300 residents or 38.2%. 41 Privateinstitution residents decreased by about 13,700 persons or about28.6%.46 These numerical and rate decreases were actually greaterfor public institutions than those that followed Olmstead,47 which wasdecided at the end of this ten year period.48 "Between June 30, 1999and June 30, 2008, public institution populations decreased by about14,100 people, or 28.6%, and private institution populationsdecreased by about 10,400 people, or 30 .5%.'49 "Although there wasa modestly increased rate of private institution depopulation

43. Within two years of his hailing Olmstead, Professor Perlin was questioning its impact. Olmstead,527 U.S. at 582. Professor Perlin asks, "Has Olmstead, so far, really made a difference? Or, are personsinstitutionalized because of mental disability, still 'on the bottom?' Michael L. Perlin, "What's GoodIsBad, What's Bad Is Good, You '11 Find Out When You Reach the Top, You're on the Bottom ": Are theAmericans with Disabilities Act (and Olnstead v. L.C.) Anything More Than "Idiot Wind?", 35 U.MICH. J.L. REFORM 235, 241 (2002).

44. K. Charlie Lakin, Naomi Scott, Sheryl Larson & Patricia Salmi, Marking the 10th Anniversary ofthe Olmstead: Has It Made a Difference for People with Developmental Disabilities, 47 INTELL. &DEVELOPMENTAL DISABILrrTEs, Oct. 2009, at 406.

45. Id. at 404.46. Id.47. See generally Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581.48. Lakin et al., supra note 44, at 404-06.49. Id. at 406.

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 771 2009-2010

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 771

B. Olmstead's Shortcomings

Legal advocates and scholars are perhaps prone to overstate the impact of particular cases on the world generally, as well as on the law. That has been Olmstead's fortune.43 While one might have expected that the Olmstead decision would have accelerated community placement, this has not been the case. In addition, the decision is fraught with deficiencies which thwart achievement of the right articulated by the Court, that is, to the right to be free from unjustified isolation.

1. Movement from Institutions Has Slowed

Since the Olmstead decision, there has been a slowing of the movement of residents from both public and private institutions, according to an analysis marking the case's tenth anniversary.44 Between June 30, 1990 and June 30, 1999, public institution populations decreased by about 30,300 residents or 38.2%.45 Private institution residents decreased by about 13,700 persons or about 28.6%.46 These numerical and rate decreases were actually greater for public institutions than those that followed Olmstead,47 which was decided at the end of this ten year period.48 "Between June 30, 1999 and June 30, 2008, public institution populations decreased by about 14,100 people, or 28.6%, and private institution populations decreased by about 10,400 people, or 30.5%.'.49 "Although there was a modestly increased rate of private institution depopulation

43. Within two years of his hailing Olmstead, Professor Perlin was questioning its impact. Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 582. Professor Perlin asks, "Has Olmstead, so far, really made a difference? Or, are persons institutionalized because of mental disability, still 'on the bottom?'" Michael L. Perlin, "What's Good Is Bad, What's Bad Is Good, You'll Find Out When You Reach the Top, You're on the BOllom": Are the Americans with Disabilities Act (and Olmstead v. L.C.) Anything More Than "/diot Wind? ", 35 U. MICH. J.L. REFORM 235, 241 (2002).

44. K. Charlie Lakin, Naomi Scott, Sheryl Larson & Patricia Salmi, Marking the 10th Anniversary of the Olmstead: Has It Made a Difference for People with Developmental Disabilities, 47 INTELL. & DEVELOPMENTAL DISABILITIES, Oct. 2009, at 406.

45. Id. at 404. 46. Id. 47. See generally Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581. 48. Lakin et aI., supra note 44, at 404-06. 49. Id. at 406.

9

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

following Olmstead,50 among public and private institutionscombined, the rates of depopulation were slightly lower after[Olmstead] than before (36.9% and 29.4%, respectively)." 51

Why did this occur? Statistically, it was "because of the slowingrate within public institutions" "driven by low rates ofdeinstitutionalization in relatively few states." 52 The states slowest incommunity movement are increasing the proportion of publicinstitution residents which they house.53 In 1990, the 10 sloweststates had 34% of the total public institution residents. 54 At the timeof the Olmstead decision, they had 43%, and by 2008, they had52%. 5 Since Olmstead, these 10 states decreased their total publicinstitution populations by about 15% as compared with a 42%reduction in the other states.56

While these numbers cannot demonstrate an Olmstead cause-and-effect, the researchers did find it "[more] evident.., that the effectsof Olmstead in the future, if any, will depend on the internal orexternal motivation of a relatively small number of states to operatein more consistent compliance with it." 57 This raises the question ofwhether Olmstead alone is sufficient to provide a significant piece ofthat motivation.

2. Olmstead Suffers from Internal Deficiencies

Apart from its lack of constitutional teeth, Olmstead58 suffers fromseveral internal deficiencies which weaken the force of its integrationmandate. These include a government-friendly fundamental alterationdefense and an effectively non-accountable "working plan" option todemonstrate compliance.59

50. See generally Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 587.51. [akin et al., supra note 44, at 406.52. Id.53. Id.54. Id.55. Id.56. Id. The public institutions' population was 84,239 in 1990, 49,105 in 1999, and 35,051 in 2008.

[akin et al., supra note 44, at 404.57. Id. (emphasis added).58. See generally Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581 (1999).59. Id. at 584.

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 772 2009-2010

772 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 26:3

following Olmstead,50 among public and private institutions combined, the rates of depopulation were slightly lower after [Olmstead] than before (36.9% and 29.4%, respectively).,,51

Why did this occur? Statistically, it was "because of the slowing rate within public institutions" "driven by low rates of deinstitutionalization in relatively few states.,,52 The states slowest in community movement are increasing the proportion of public institution residents which they house.53 In 1990, the 10 slowest states had 34% of the total public institution residents.54 At the time of the Olmstead decision, they had 43%, and by 2008, they had 52%.55 Since Olmstead, these 10 states decreased their total public institution populations by about 15% as compared with a 42% reduction in the other states. 56

While these numbers cannot demonstrate an Olmstead cause-and­effect, the researchers did find it "[more] evident ... that the effects of Olmstead in the future, if any, will depend on the internal or external motivation of a relatively small number of states to operate in more consistent compliance with it. ,,57 This raises the question of whether Olmstead alone is sufficient to provide a significant piece of that motivation.

2. Olmstead Suffers from Internal Deficiencies

Apart from its lack of constitutional teeth, Olmsteacf8 suffers from several internal deficiencies which weaken the force of its integration mandate. These include a government-friendly fundamental alteration defense and an effectively non-accountable "working plan" option to demonstrate compliance. 59

50. See generally Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 587. 51. Lakin et aI., supra note 44, at 406. 52. Id. 53. Id. 54. Id. 55. Id. 56. Id. The public institutions' population was 84,239 in 1990,49,105 in 1999, and 35,051 in 2008.

Lakin et aI., supra note 44, at 404. 57. Id. (emphasis added). 58. See generally Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581 (1999). 59. Id. at 584.

10

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 773

a. "Fundamental Alteration"

The obligation of public entities to make reasonable modificationsof their policies, practices and procedures to avoid the discriminationof unjustified segregation is limited by the "fundamental alteration"defense. The entity is relieved of its obligation if "the public entitycan demonstrate that making the modifications would fundamentallyalter the nature of the service, program, or activity."60 Courts mustconsider whether "in the allocation of available resources, immediaterelief for the plaintiffs would be inequitable, given the responsibilitythe State has undertaken for the care and treatment of a large anddiverse population of persons with.., disabilities." 61 Additional cost,however, alone does not constitute a fundamental alteration.62 Theanalysis is not limited to comparing institutional to community cost;if that were the case, plaintiffs would generally always prevail.

The fundamental alteration defense may result in bizarreacceptance of discrimination to the detriment of individuals deeply inneed. In Townsend v. Quasim,63 it was contended that the state's useof community-based nursing services to provide essential long termcare to some disabled Medicaid recipients but not others violatesTitle II of the ADA.64 The plaintiff, a man in his eighties withmedical and physical disabilities, was told by the Washington State'sDepartment of Social and Health Services that, based on newdefinitions of services, he would have to move to a nursing home orlose Medicaid benefits which provided him with community care.65

The Ninth Circuit agreed that the state's action was discriminatorybut declined to provide relief, remanding because providing

60. 28 C.F.R. § 35.130(b)(7) (2001) (emphasis added).61. Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 604. The section of Justice Ginsburg's opinion describing the standards to

be employed when analyzing a cost-based defense was joined by only four members of the Court.Justice Kennedy's concurring opinion supported a state's discretion to adopt its own systems of costanalysis. Id at 615 (Kennedy, J., concurring).

62. Fisher v. Okla. Health Care Auth., 335 F.3d 1175, 1183 (10th Cir. 2003) (citing H.R. REP. No.101-485, at 50 (1990), reprinted in 1990 U.S.C.C.A.N. 445, 473 ("While the integration of people withdisabilities will sometimes involve substantial short-term burdens, both financial and administrative, thelong-range effects of integration will benefit society as a whole." ).

63. See generally Townsend v. Quasim, 328 F.3d 511 (9th Cir. 2003).64. Id. at 518.65. ld. at514.

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 773 2009-2010

2010) THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 773

a. "Fundamental Alteration"

The obligation of public entities to make reasonable modifications of their policies, practices and procedures to avoid the discrimination of unjustified segregation is limited by the "fundamental alteration" defense. The entity is relieved of its obligation if "the public entity can demonstrate that making the modifications would fundamentally alter the nature of the service, program, or activity.,,60 Courts must consider whether "in the allocation of available resources, immediate relief for the plaintiffs would be inequitable, given the responsibility the State has undertaken for the care and treatment of a large and diverse population of persons with ... disabilities.,,61 Additional cost, however, alone does not constitute a fundamental alteration.62 The analysis is not limited to comparing institutional to community cost; if that were the case, plaintiffs would generally always prevail.

The fundamental alteration defense may result in bizarre acceptance of discrimination to the detriment of individuals deeply in need. In Townsend v. Quasim,63 it was contended that the state's use of community-based nursing services to provide essential long term care to some disabled Medicaid recipients but not others violates Title II of the ADA.64 The plaintiff, a man in his eighties with medical and physical disabilities, was told by the Washington State's Department of Social and Health Services that, based on new definitions of services, he would have to move to a nursing home or lose Medicaid benefits which provided him with community care.65

The Ninth Circuit agreed that the state's action was discriminatory but declined to provide relief, remanding because providing

60. 28 C.F.R. § 35.130(b)(7) (2001) (emphasis added). 61. Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 604. The section of Justice Ginsburg's opinion describing the standards to

be employed when analyzing a cost-based defense was joined by only four members of the Court. Justice Kennedy's concurring opinion supported a state's discretion to adopt its own systems of cost analysis. Id. at 615 (Kennedy, J., concurring).

62. Fisher v. Okla. Health Care Autb., 335 F.3d 1175, 1183 (10th Cir. 2003) (citing H.R. REp. No. 101-485, at 50 (1990), reprinted in 1990 U.S.C.C.A.N. 445, 473 ("While the integration of people with disabilities will sometimes involve substantial short-term burdens, both fInancial and administrative, the long-range effects of integration will benefIt society as a whole." ).

63. See generally Townsend v. Quasim, 328 F.3d 511 (9th Cir. 2003). 64. Id. at 518. 65. Id. at 514.

11

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

community services "would fundamentally alter" the State'sMedicaid programs.66

A fundamental alteration might involve program integrity(modification of the fundamental nature of the program, for example)or magnitude (changes in the extent or cost of the system). 67 "Noclear statutory limits give guidance, and in the end any limits,however vague, may have to come from courts. 68 Olmstead's impactis "diluted by the Court's failure to provide meaningful parametersfor the defense" of fundamental alteration.69

b. "Effectively Working Plan"

Justice Ginsburg's plurality gives states "leeway" to adopt a plan,apparently in the context of a fundamental alteration defense:

To maintain a range of facilities and to administer services withan even hand, the State must have more leeway than the courtsbelow understood the fundamental-alteration defense to allow. If,for example, the State were to demonstrate that it had acomprehensive, effectively working plan for placing qualifiedpersons with mental disabilities in less restrictive settings, and awaiting list that moved at a reasonable pace not controlled by theState's endeavors to keep its institutions fully populated, thereasonable-modifications standard would be met.70

Each piece of this operational test-a "comprehensive, effectivelyworking plan," 71 a waiting list moving "at a reasonable pace notcontrolled" by a State's effort to keep institutions filled72 raises

66. Id. at 520.67. For a detailed discussion of the various flavors which might comprise "fundamental alteration,"

see Jefferson D.E. Smith & Steve P. Callandrillo, Forward to Fundamental Alteration: Addressing ADATitle II Integration Lawsuits after Olmstead v. L.C., 24 HARv. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 695, 723-24 (2001).

68. Id. at 769.69. Rosemary L. Bauman, Disability Law-Needless Institutionalization of Individuals with Mental

Disabilities as Discrimination Under the ADA -Olmstead v. L.C., 30 N.M. L. REv. 287, 287 (2000).70. Olmstead v. L.C., 527 U.S. 581,605-06 (1999).71. Id. at584.72. Id.

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 774 2009-2010

774 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW (Vol. 26:3

community services "would fundamentally alter" the State's Medicaid programs.66

A fundamental alteration might involve program integrity (modification of the fundamental nature of the program, for example) or magnitude (changes in the extent or cost of the system).67 "No clear statutory limits give guidance, and in the end any limits, however vague, may have to come from COurtS.,,68 Olmstead's impact is "diluted by the Court's failure to provide meaningful parameters for the defense" of fundamental alteration.69

b. "Effectively Working Plan"

Justice Ginsburg's plurality gives states "leeway" to adopt a plan, apparently in the context of a fundamental alteration defense:

To maintain a range of facilities and to administer services with an even hand, the State must have more leeway than the courts below understood the fundamental-alteration defense to allow. If, for example, the State were to demonstrate that it had a comprehensive, effectively working plan for placing qualified persons with mental disabilities in less restrictive settings, and a waiting list that moved at a reasonable pace not controlled by the State's endeavors to keep its institutions fully populated, the reasonable-modifications standard would be met.70

Each piece of this operational test-a "comprehensive, effectively working plan,,,71 a waiting list moving "at a reasonable pace not controlled" by a State's effort to keep institutions filled72-raises

66. Id. at 520. 67. For a detailed discussion of the various flavors which might comprise "fundamental alteration,"

see Jefferson D.E. Smith & Steve P. Callandrillo, Forward to Fundamental Alteration: Addressing ADA Title II Integration Lawsuits after Olmstead v. L.C., 24 HARv. J.L. & PuB. POL'y 695, 723-24 (2001).

68. /d. at 769. 69. Rosemary L. Bauman, Disability Law-Needless Institutionalization of Individuals with Mental

Disabilities as Discrimination Under the ADA-Olmstead v. L.C., 30 N.M. L. REV. 287, 287 (2000). 70. Olmstead v. L.C., 527 U.S. 581,605--06 (1999). 71. Id. at 584. 72. Id.

12

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 775

difficult interpretive questions. It is a challenge to put meaning intothese terms. "The standards established under the majority decisionfor measuring when statutory violations under the ADA occur in thecontext of health services for persons with disabilities are, in fact,quite murky; furthermore, the powers granted to States to determinethe scope of their own obligations, as well as the affirmative defensesthey are accorded, are extensive." 73

Of course, any test of compliance would raise definitional andinterpretive questions. Here, however, where the State's "leeway"allows it to put its thumb on the scale, one is hard put to expect courtsto require meaty and prompt implementation of Olmstead plans.

All changes to complex systems, when done well, necessitatecareful planning. Planning will typically include analysis,development of a mission, goals and objectives, expected outcomes,tasks and timelines, deadlines, identification of persons responsible,quality assurance and accountability mechanisms, and evaluation.Consequently, a self-adjusting system will be in place, with sufficientfeedback and flexibility to adapt to changing conditions. A plan formovement from institutions would be expected to encompass theseelements.

Enforcement of civil rights, especially class-wide enforcement,often requires a change of complex systems. Courts, however, look toresults. Judicial orders require compliance. An unimplemented plan isinsufficient to satisfy the court that its involvement must come to anend.

The plurality opinion in Olmstead invites a "plan" which itself

would satisfy the integration mandate announced in the decision.74

Devoid of mention of compliance or enforcement, the Olmstead planhas such scant required content that it has been characterized as a

73. Sara Rosenbaun, Joel Teitelbaum & Alexandra Stewart, Olmstead v. L.C.: Implications for

Medicaid and Other Publicly Funded Health Services, 12 HEALTH MATRIx 93, 94 (2002). For example,the authors point out the vagueness in the "reasonable pace" piece of the puzzle; "there are no generalstandards for measuring what constitutes a 'reasonable pace' for purposes of Olmstead-related planning,

nor is there an explanation regarding how the reasonable pace standard might vary depending on thenature of the condition or service need at issue." Id. at 137.

74. See generally Olnstead, 527 U.S. 581.

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 775 2009-2010

2010) THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 775

difficult interpretive questions. It is a challenge to put meaning into these terms. "The standards established under the majority decision for measuring when statutory violations under the ADA occur in the context of health services for persons with disabilities are, in fact, quite murky; furthermore, the powers granted to States to determine the scope of their own obligations, as well as the affirmative defenses they are accorded, are extensive." 73

Of course, any test of compliance would raise definitional and interpretive questions. Here, however, where the State's "leeway" allows it to put its thumb on the scale, one is hard put to expect courts to require meaty and prompt implementation of Olmstead plans.

All changes to complex systems, when done well, necessitate careful planning. Planning will typically include analysis, development of a mission, goals and objectives, expected outcomes, tasks and timelines, deadlines, identification of persons responsible, quality assurance and accountability mechanisms, and evaluation. Consequently, a self-adjusting system will be in place, with sufficient feedback and flexibility to adapt to changing conditions. A plan for movement from institutions would be expected to encompass these elements.

Enforcement of civil rights, especially class-wide enforcement, often requires a change of complex systems. Courts, however, look to results. Judicial orders require compliance. An unimplemented plan is insufficient to satisfy the court that its involvement must come to an end.

The plurality opinion in Olmstead invites a "plan" which itself would satisfy the integration mandate announced in the decision. 74

Devoid of mention of compliance or enforcement, the Olmstead plan has such scant required content that it has been characterized as a

73. Sara Rosenbaum, Joel Teitelbaum & Alexandra Stewart, Olmstead v. L.C.: Implications for Medicaid and Other Publicly Funded Health Services, 12 HEALTH MATRIX 93, 94 (2002). For example, the authors point out the vagueness in the "reasonable pace" piece of the puzzle; "there are no general standards for measuring what constitutes a 'reasonable pace' for purposes of Olmstead-related planning, nor is there an explanation regarding how the reasonable pace standard might vary depending on the nature of the condition or service need at issue." Id. at 137.

74. See generally Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581.

13

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

"get out of jail free" card for states otherwise in violation of thedecision's integration mandate." 75

Some courts have held that a mere history of deinstitutionalization,even absent stated goals or guidelines, satisfies Olmstead, whileothers have accepted as satisfactory mere confirmation that a planexists.76 Even a "successful record" and a plan "to continue andincrease" unspecific programs were held sufficient. 7

Courts are certainly limited in ability and resources to shepherd allthe details of compliance,78 but they are competent to ensurecompliance, even in the most complex situations.79 A case in point isUnited States v. State of Connecticut in which Senior U.S. DistrictJudge Ellen Bree Bums found the state in contempt of a consentdecree intended to reform a large mental retardation institution,Southbury Training School (STS). 80 The court found deficiencies insuch areas as medical care, psychiatric services, psychologicalprograms, physical therapy, injuries, and protection from harm,concluding that "STS's systemic flaws have caused many residents tosuffer grave harm, and, in several instances, death., 81 The courtappointed a special master to review "all aspects" of STS's care,"determine the changes needed," "formulate specific methods to

75. John F. Muller, Olmstead v. L.C. and the Voluntary Cessation Doctrine: Toward a More HolisticAnalysis of the "'Effectively Working Plan," 118 YALE L.J. 1013,1014 (2009).

76. In Muller, supra note 75, the following "working plan" cases are discussed: Arc of Wash. StateInc. v. Braddock, 427 F.3d 615 (9th Cir. 2005); Sanchez v. Johnson, 416 F.3d 1051, 1068 (9th Cir.2005); Frederick L. v. Dep 't of Pub. Welfare (Frederick L. 11), 422 F.3d 151 (3d Cir. 2005); Pa. Prot. &Advocacy, Inc. v. Pa. Dep't of Pub. Welfare, 402 F.3d 374, 377 (3d Cir. 2005); Frederick L. v. Dep't ofPub. Welfare (Frederick L. 1), 364 F.3d 487 (3d Cir. 2004); Bryson v. Stephen, No. 99-CV-558-SM,2006 WL 2805238, at *4 (D.N.H. Sept. 29, 2006); Williams v. Wasserman, 164 F. Supp. 2d 591 (D. Md.2001); Kathleen S. v. Dep 't of Pub. Welfare, No. 97-6610, 1999 WL 1257284 (E.D. Pa. Dec. 23, 1999);Makin ex rel. Russell v. Hawaii, 114 F. Supp. 2d 1017 (D. Haw. 1999). See Melody M. Kubo,Implementing Olmstead v. L.C.: Defining "Effectively Working" Plans for "Reasonably Placed" WaitLists for Medicaid Home and Community-Based Services Waiver Programs, 23 U. HAW. L. REV. 731(2001).

77. Sanchez v. Johnson, 416 F.3d 1051, 1068 (9th Cir. 2005).78. See Samuel R. Bagenstos, Justice Ginsburg and the Judicial Role in Expanding "We the

People": The Disability Rights Cases, 104 COLUM. L. REV. 49, 58 (2004).79. See generally David Ferleger, Special Master Rules: Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 53, The

Role of Special Masters in the Judicial System, 2004 Special Masters Conference: Transcript ofProceedings, 31 WM. MITCHELL L. REV. 1193 (2005).

80. United States v. Connecticut, 931 F. Supp. 974, 974 (D. Conn. 1996), appeal dismissed, UnitedStates v. Connecticut, 116 F.3d 466 (2d Cir. 1997), cert. denied sub nom., 522 U.S. 1045 (1998).8 1. Connecticut, 931 F. Supp. at 984.

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 776 2009-2010

776 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 26:3

"get out of jail free" card for states otherwise in violation of the decision's integration mandate.,,75

Some courts have held that a mere history of deinstitutionalization, even absent stated goals or guidelines, satisfies Olmstead, while others have accepted as satisfactory mere confirmation that a plan exists.76 Even a "successful record" and a plan "to continue and increase" unspecific programs were held sufficient.77

Courts are certainly limited in ability and resources to shepherd all the details of compliance,78 but they are competent to ensure compliance, even in the most complex situations.79 A case in point is United States v. State of Connecticut in which Senior U.S. District Judge Ellen Bree Bums found the state in contempt of a consent decree intended to reform a large mental retardation institution, Southbury Training School (STS).80 The court found deficiencies in such areas as medical care, psychiatric services, psychological programs, physical therapy, injuries, and protection from harm, concluding that "STS's systemic flaws have caused many residents to suffer grave harm, and, in several instances, death.,,81 The court appointed a special master to review "all aspects" of STS's care, "determine the changes needed," "formulate specific methods to

75. John F. Muller, Olmstead v. L.C. and the Voluntary Cessation Doctrine: Toward a More Holistic Analysis of the "Effectively Working Plan," 118 YALE LJ. 1013, 1014 (2009).

76. In Muller, supra note 75, the following "working plan" cases are discussed: Arc of Wash. State Inc. v. Braddock, 427 F.3d 615 (9th Cir. 2005); Sanchez v. Johnson, 416 F.3d 1051, 1068 (9th Cir. 2005); Frederick L. v. Dep 't of Pub. Welfare (Frederick L.Il), 422 F.3d 151 (3d Cir. 2005); Pa. Prot. & Advocacy, Inc. v. Pa. Dep't of Pub. Welfare, 402 F.3d 374, 377 (3d CiT. 2005); Frederick L. v. Dep't of Pub. Welfare (Frederick L. I), 364 F.3d 487 (3d Cir. 2004); Bryson v. Stephen, No. 99-CV-558-SM, 2006 WL 2805238, at *4 (D.N.H. Sept. 29, 2006); Williams v. Wasserman, 164 F. Supp. 2d 591 (D. Md. 2001); Kathleen S. v. Dep't of Pub. Welfare, No. 97-6610, 1999 WL 1257284 (E.D. Pa. Dec. 23, 1999); Makin ex reI. Russell v. Hawaii, 114 F. Supp. 2d 1017 (D. Haw. 1999). See Melody M. Kubo, Implementing Olmstead v. L.C.: Defining "Effectively Working" Plans for "Reasonably Placed" Wail Lists for Medicaid Home and Community-Based Services Waiver Programs, 23 U. HAw. L. REv. 731 (2001).

77. Sanchez v. Johnson, 416 F.3d 1051, 1068 (9th Cir. 2005). 78. See Samuel R. Bagenstos, Justice Ginsburg and the Judicial Role in Expanding "We the

People": The Disability Rights Cases, 104 COLUM. L. REv. 49,58 (2004). 79. See generally David Ferleger, Special Master Rules: Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 53, The

Role of Special Masters in the Judicial System, 2004 Special Masters Conference: Transcript of Proceedings, 31 WM. MITCHELL L. REv. 1193 (2005).

80. United States v. Connecticut, 931 F. Supp. 974, 974 (D. Conn. 1996), appeal dismissed, United States v. Connecticut, 116 F.3d 466 (2d Cir. 1997), cerro denied sub nom., 522 U.S. 1045 (1998).

81. Connecticut, 931 F. Supp. at 984.

14

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

20101 THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 777

implement the required changes," and help "effectuate thosechanges." 82 The special master actively oversaw a detailed remedialplan, holding hearings where necessary, and after nine years, the stateachieved compliance at the institution and was purged of contempt.83

The Olmstead "working plan" option is problematic. It does notdescribe the minimum elements of such a plan and does not requiretimely outcomes and compliance. Most importantly, its emphasis onstates' "leeway" discourages the lower courts from mandating andenforcing full-bodied plans, and ensuring that desired outcomes areachieved before the court bows out of involvement.

c. Absence of Guidance on Standard of Care

The Olmstead Court stated in footnote 14, "We do not in thisopinion hold that the ADA imposes on the States a 'standard of care'for whatever medical services they render, or that the ADA requiresStates to 'provide a certain level of benefits to individuals withdisabilities., 84 Justice Kennedy's concurrence is stronger. Heconcluded that, given states' need to weigh their priorities, "[i]tfollows that a State may not be forced to create a community-treatment program where none exists." 85 He did not, however,explain how one distinguishes between "creation" and "expansion" ofcommunity programs.

The multiplicity of opinions and the weak language cited aboveopens the possibility that Olmstead's reach may be cut short in future

82. Id.83. This article's author was the special master. The court described the success of this judicial

oversight in a parallel case involving the same institution:In a process of evaluation lasting almost a decade, the Special Master, with the assistanceof experts commissioned by him and the parties, measured improvements at STS againstthe standards set forth in the Court Requirements. Periodically, when the Special Masterconcluded that the defendants had demonstrated compliance with a particular CourtRequirement, he recommended that the court release STS from oversight for that CourtRequirement. Finally, in 2006, after the Special Master found STS to be in compliancewith all remaining requirements of the Remedial Plan, the court released STS fromjudicial oversight and purged the defendants of contempt. See Order Purging Defendantsof Contempt and Ending Active Judicial Oversight, US. v. Connecticut, (Mar. 24, 2006).

Messier v. Southbury Training Sch., 562 F. Supp. 2d 294, 299-300 (D. Conn. 2008).84. Olmstead v. L.C., 527 U.S. 581, 603 n.14 (1999) (Thomas, J., dissenting).85. Id. at 613.

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 777 2009-2010

2010) THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 777

implement the required changes," and help "effectuate those changes.,,82 The special master actively oversaw a detailed remedial plan, holding hearings where necessary, and after nine years, the state achieved compliance at the institution and was purged of contempt.83

The Olmstead "working plan" option is problematic. It does not describe the minimum elements of such a plan and does not require timely outcomes and compliance. Most importantly, its emphasis on states' "leeway" discourages the lower courts from mandating and enforcing full-bodied plans, and ensuring that desired outcomes are achieved before the court bows out of involvement.

c. Absence of Guidance on Standard of Care

The Olmstead Court stated in footnote 14, "We do not in this opinion hold that the ADA imposes on the States a 'standard of care' for whatever medical services they render, or that the ADA requires States to 'provide a certain level of benefits to individuals with disabilities.,,84 Justice Kennedy's concurrence is stronger. He concluded that, given states' need to weigh their priorities, "[i]t follows that a State may not be forced to create a community­treatment program where none exists.,,85 He did not, however, explain how one distinguishes between "creation" and "expansion" of community programs.

The multiplicity of opinions and the weak language cited above opens the possibility that Olmstead's reach may be cut short in future

82. Id. 83. This article's author was the special master. The court described the success of this judicial

oversight in a parallel case involving the same institution: In a process of evaluation lasting almost a decade, the Special Master, with the assistance of experts commissioned by him and the parties, measured improvements at STS against the standards set forth in the Court Requirements. Periodically, when the Special Master concluded that the defendants had demonstrated compliance with a particular Court Requirement, he recommended that the court release STS from oversight for that Court Requirement. Finally, in 2006, after the Special Master found STS to be in compliance with all remaining requirements of the Remedial Plan, the court released STS from judicial oversight and purged the defendants of contempt. See Order Purging Defendants of Contempt and Ending Active Judicial Oversight, US. v. Connecticut, (Mar. 24, 2006).

Messier v. Southbury Training Sch., 562 F. Supp. 2d 294, 299-300 (D. Conn. 2008). 84. Olmstead v. L.C., 527 U.S. 581, 603 n.l4 (1999) (Thomas, J., dissenting). 85. Id. at 613.

15

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

rulings. The language does not appear to support even the minimallyadequate level of habilitation which Youngberg v. Romeo8 6 held isrequired.

d Silence on the Respective Roles of the Legislature and Courts

Constrained perhaps by internal divisions, the Court was muted inits endorsement of vigorous efforts to move to a fully community-oriented system. Institutional settings may be "terminated" but not forpeople "unable to handle or benefit" thereby. 87 Institutions may be"phased out" so long as this does not place "patients in need of closecare at risk.",88 These qualifications meet the concerns expressed inJustice Kennedy's opinion.

This limited closure mandate appears calculated to appeal both tothose who disfavor institutions as well as to those concerned thatsome residents may not be well served in the community. While noone would intentionally adopt a "phase out" effort, or place even asingle person into the community, if it would predictably cause harm,analysis of risk and benefit is a complex calculus in human services.Missing from the Court's brief "yes, but. . . "discussion is the natureof the balance in this sensitive arena between the legislative policy-setting role and the judicial role in the definition and enforcement ofrights. Also missing is the question of what weight to give theconstitutional liberty interests of the individual and his or her desires,or that of parents or guardians. One wishes for clearer guidance fromthe Court on these issues.

II. THE CONSTITUTION

A. The Parameters of a Constitutional Right to Community Services

As recently as 2000, a scholar in the field correctly characterizedthe constitutional dimensions of a right to community treatment as "a

86. Youngberg v. Romeo, 457 U.S. 307 (1982).87. Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 602.88. Id. at 583.

[Vol 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 778 2009-2010

778 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW (VoL 26:3

rulings. The language does not appear to support even the minimally adequate level of habilitation which Youngberg v. Rome086 held is required.

d Silence on the Respective Roles of the Legislature and Courts

Constrained perhaps by internal divisions, the Court was muted in its endorsement of vigorous efforts to move to a fully community­oriented system. Institutional settings may be "terminated" but not for people "unable to handle or benefit" thereby.87 Institutions may be "phased out" so long as this does not place "patients in need of close care at risk.,,88 These qualifications meet the concerns expressed in Justice Kennedy's opinion.

This limited closure mandate appears calculated to appeal both to those who disfavor institutions as well as to those concerned that some residents may not be well served in the community. While no one would intentionally adopt a "phase out" effort, or place even a single person into the community, if it would predictably cause harm, analysis of risk and benefit is a complex calculus in human services. Missing from the Court's brief "yes, but ... "discussion is the nature of the balance in this sensitive arena between the legislative policy­setting role and the judicial role in the definition and enforcement of rights. Also missing is the question of what weight to give the constitutional liberty interests of the individual and his or her desires, or that of parents or guardians. One wishes for clearer guidance from the Court on these issues.

II. THE CONSTITUTION

A. The Parameters of a Constitutional Right to Community Services

As recently as 2000, a scholar in the field correctly characterized the constitutional dimensions of a right to community treatment as "a

86. Youngberg v. Romeo, 457 U.S. 307 (1982). 87. Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 602. 88. Id. at 583.

16

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 779

mostly-moribund body of law."'8 9 With the Olmstead statutory

holding, 90 constitutional analysis took a backseat to examination ofthe extent to which the ADA might afford relief to theinstitutionalized. As I explain below, a comprehensive legal theoryembodying both constitutional and statutory rights is more likely toserve private and public needs than a theory including just one or theother.91

I contend that institutionalization of individuals with intellectualdisabilities, without their consent, violates the Due Process and EqualProtection Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment to theConstitution92 where the person could "handle and benefit from" anend to confinement and the provision of habilitation and supports in acommunity placement.93 In addition, long term confinement, withouteffective periodic review of the justification for that confinement, is adue process violation.

For these individuals, institutionalization, as lived out in our times,is often a lifetime proposition. Institutional populations are aging onaccount of very low admissions and deaths. The few admissions sinceadoption in the 1970s of right to education laws and expansion ofcommunity services since that time have resulted in skewing theinstitutional census toward higher age groups. The institutions' agegroupings "reflect the aging of the US population but in anexaggerated way. E.g., in 1977, 22% were 40 years and older;

89. Michael L. Perlin, "Their Promises of Paradise": Will Olmstead v. L.C. Resuscitate theConstitutional "Least Restrictive Alternative" Principle in Mental Disability Law?, 37 HOUS. L. REV.999, 1022 (2000).

90. Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581, 607 (holding that states are required to provide community-basedtreatment for persons with mental disabilities when such placement is appropriate).

91. See infra Part 2.92. U.S. CONST. amend. XIV.93. The "handle and benefit from" standard is repeated twice in the Olmstead plurality opinion:

"First, institutional placement of persons who can handle and benefit from communitysettings perpetuates unwarranted assumptions that persons so isolated are incapable orunworthy of participating in community life." Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 600 (emphasisadded)."We emphasize that nothing in the ADA or its implementing regulations condonestermination of institutional settings for persons unable to handle or benefit fromcommunity settings." Id at 601-02 (emphasis added).

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 779 2009-2010

2010) THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 779

mostly-moribund body of law.,,89 With the Olmstead statutory holding,90 constitutional analysis took a backseat to examination of the extent to which the ADA might afford relief to the institutionalized. As I explain below, a comprehensive legal theory embodying both constitutional and statutory rights is more likely to serve private and public needs than a theory including just one or the other.91

I contend that institutionalization of individuals with intellectual disabilities, without their consent, violates the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment to the Constitution92 where the person could "handle and benefit from" an end to confinement and the provision of habilitation and supports in a community placement.93 In addition, long term confinement, without effective periodic review of the justification for that confinement, is a due process violation.

For these individuals, institutionalization, as lived out in our times, is often a lifetime proposition. Institutional populations are aging on account of very low admissions and deaths. The few admissions since adoption in the 1970s of right to education laws and expansion of community services since that time have resulted in skewing the institutional census toward higher age groups. The institutions' age groupings "reflect the aging of the US population but in an exaggerated way. E.g., in 1977, 22% were 40 years and older;

89. Michael L. Perlin, "Their Promises of Paradise": Will Olmstead v. L.C. Resuscitate the Constitutional "Least Restrictive Alternative" Principle in Mental Disability Law?, 37 Hous. 1. REv. 999,1022 (2000).

90. Olmstead, 527 U.S. 581, 607 (holding that states are required to provide community-based treatment for persons with mental disabilities when such placement is appropriate).

91. See infra Part 2. 92. U.S. CONST. amend. XIV. 93. The "handle and benefit from" standard is repeated twice in the Olmstead plurality opinion:

"First, institutional placement of persons who can handle and benefit from community settings perpetuates unwarranted assumptions that persons so isolated are incapable or unworthy of participating in community life." Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 600 (emphasis added). "We emphasize that nothing in the ADA or its implementing regulations condones termination of institutional settings for persons unable to handle or benefit from community settings." Id at 601--02 (emphasis added).

17

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

1987=33.3%; 1998=57.1%; 2006=72.1%.,, 94 By comparison to theinstitutionalized 72.1%, 45% of the United States population in 2006were 40 years and older.95 Residence in an institution for people withintellectual disabilities often lasts decades and can be commitmentfor the life of the individual.96

The Supreme Court has long recognized that civil confinemententails a "massive curtailment of liberty."97 The only permissiblejustifications for committing the mentally disabled are: (1) danger tothe individual, (2) danger to others, and (3) need for treatment.98 TheCourt enunciated the following principle in Jackson v. Indiana,striking down a state law that permitted the state to confineindefinitely a mentally deficient deaf mute adjudged incompetent tostand trial: "At the least, due process requires that the nature andduration of commitment bear some reasonable relation to the purposefor which the individual is committed." 99

Jackson's "nature, duration and purpose" criteria have become thetouchstone (often unacknowledged) for the development ofprocedural and substantive due process, and for equal protectionsafeguards of the rights of the institutionalized. It is to those rightsthat I now turn.

94. E-mail from R. Charlie Lakin, Institute on Community Integration, University of Minnesota, toauthor (Sept. 4, 2009) (on file with author).

95. United States Census Bureau, 2006 American Community Survey, S0101, Age and Sex,http://factfinder.census.gov/servlet/STTable? bm=y&-qrname=ACS_2006ESTGOO S0101&-geo_id=01000US&-dsname=ACS_2006_ESTG00_&-_lang--en (last visited Feb. 17, 2010).

96. Failure to provide adequate habilitation may well mean commitment for the life of the individual.Welsch v. Likins, 373 F. Supp. 487, 497 (D. Minn. 1974), aff'd in part, vacated, remanded in part, 550F.2d 1122 (8th Cir. 1977); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 446 F. Supp. 1295, 1315 (E.D.Pa. 1978).

97. Zinermon v. Burch, 494 U.S. 113, 131 (1990); Vitek v. Jones, 445 U.S. 480, 491-92 (1980)(commitment to mental hospital entails "'a massive curtailment of liberty,"' and requires due processprotection); Parham v. J.R., 442 U.S. 584, 600 (1979) (there is a "substantial liberty interest in not beingconfined unnecessarily for medical treatment"); Addington v. Texas, 441 U.S. 418, 425 (1979) ("[C]ivilcommitment for any purpose constitutes a significant deprivation of liberty that requires due processprotection."); Humphrey v. Cady, 405 U.S. 504, 509 (1972); Jackson v. Indiana, 406 U.S. 715, 738(1972).

98. Jackson, 406 U.S. at 737.99. Id.; see also McNeil v. Director, Patuxent Inst., 407 U.S. 245, 249-50 (1972).

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 780 2009-2010

780 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW (Vol. 26:3

1987=33.3%; 1998=57.1%; 2006=72.1%.,,94 By comparison to the institutionalized 72.1 %, 45% of the United States population in 2006 were 40 years and 01der.95 Residence in an institution for people with intellectual disabilities often lasts decades and can be commitment for the life of the individua1.96

The Supreme Court has long recognized that civil confinement entails a "massive curtailment of liberty. ,,97 The only permissible justifications for committing the mentally disabled are: (1) danger to the individual, (2) danger to others, and (3) need for treatment.98 The Court enunciated the following principle in Jackson v. Indiana, striking down a state law that permitted the state to confme indefinitely a mentally deficient deaf mute adjudged incompetent to stand trial: "At the least, due process requires that the nature and duration of commitment bear some reasonable relation to the purpose for which the individual is committed. ,,99

Jackson's "nature, duration and purpose" criteria have become the touchstone (often unacknowledged) for the development of procedural and substantive due process, and for equal protection safeguards of the rights of the institutionalized. It is to those rights that I now turn.

94. E-mail from R. Charlie Lakin, Institute on Community Integration, University of Minnesota, to author (Sept. 4, 2009) (on file with author).

95. United States Census Bureau, 2006 American Community Survey, S0101, Age and Sex, http://factfinder.census.gov/servletiSTIable?_bm=y&-qr_name=ACS _ 2006_ EST_GOO _SO 1 0 1 &­geo_id=OI 000US&-dsyame=ACS_2006_EST_GOO_&-_lang=en_(last visited Feb. 17,2010).

96. Failure to provide adequate habilitation may well mean commitment for the life of the individual. Welsch v. Likins, 373 F. Supp. 487, 497 (D. Minn. 1974), ajJ'd in part, vacated, remanded in part, 550 F.2d 1122 (8th Cir. 1977); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 446 F. Supp. 1295, 1315 (E.D. Pa.1978).

97. Zinermon v. Burch, 494 U.S. 113, 131 (1990); Vitek v. Jones, 445 U.S. 480, 491-92 (1980) (commitment to mental hospital entails "'a massive curtailment of liberty,'" and requires due process protection); Parham v. J.R., 442 U.S. 584,600 (1979) (there is a "substantial liberty interest in not being confmed unnecessarily for medical treatment"); Addington v. Texas, 441 U.S. 418, 425 (1979) ("[Clivi I commitment for any purpose constitutes a significant deprivation of liberty that requires due process protection."); Humphrey v. Cady, 405 U.S. 504,509 (1972); Jackson v. Indiana, 406 U.S. 715, 738 (1972).

98. Jackson, 406 U.S. at 737. 99. [d.; see also McNeil v. Director, Patuxent Inst., 407 U.S. 245, 249-50 (1972).

18

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 781

B. Due Process

1. Procedural Due Process

A procedural due process violation occurs when one is deprived ofa significant interest protected under the Constitution withoutappropriate procedures to protect against unfairness and error. 100 Thisinterest can arise either from the Constitution itself or from statelaw.'10 Post-Olmstead decisions have not generally required periodicreview in a formal sense. The model has been to require theinstitution to review and to "consider" each resident for possibleplacement i

02

A person confined in an institution who protests that confinementis entitled to a meaningful hearing-a periodic review-on theperson's continuing need for institutionalization. 10 3 The need forcommitment must be reviewed periodically by a neutral fact finder.'0 4

In concluding that a woman confined for decades at a state institutionfor people with mental retardation had a procedural due process rightto such reviews, the Third Circuit noted, "[t]he hearing tribunal musthave the authority to afford relief."10 5 Other courts agree. 10 6 Thereview must not be pro forma and must not be biased toward thestatus quo. It has been held that, while Due Process does not require a

100. Addington, 441 U.S. at 425 (1979); see generally Vitek, 445 U.S. at 480 (1980) (transfer ofprisoner to mental hospital); Goldberg v. Kelly, 397 U.S. 254 (1970).

101. Hewitt v. Helms, 459 U.S. 460, 466 (1983).102. See, e.g., Messier v. Southbury Training Sch., 562 F. Supp. 2d 294, 343 (D. Conn. 2008) ("The

evidence indicates that the defendants generally failed to exercise professional judgment in consideringcommunity placement for a large number of class members regardless of the degree of their disability,but the plaintiffs have not established that the defendants failed to consider more severely disabled classmembers for community placement.").

103. The need for review is implied in O'Connor v. Donaldson, 422 U.S. 563, 574-75 (1975) ("Nor isit enough that Donaldson's original confinement was founded upon a constitutionally adequate basis, ifin fact it was, because even if his involuntary confinement was initially permissible, it could notconstitutionally continue after that basis no longer existed.").

104. Parham v. J.R., 442 U.S. 584, 613 (1979) (requiring the periodic review implied in Donaldson v.O'Connor).

105. Clark v. Cohen, 794 F.2d 79, 86 (3d Cir. 1986) (citing Parham v. J.R., 442 U.S. 584, 607(1979)).

106. Doe ex rel. Doe v. Austin, 848 F.2d 1386, 1395-96 (6th Cir. 1988) ("Of course, becauseinvoluntary commitment cannot continue after the basis for that commitment ceases to exist, due processrequires that some periodic review take place during confinement."), cert. denied sub. nom., Cowherd v.Doe ex rel. Doe, 488 U.S. 967 (1988); Conner v. Branstad, 839 F. Supp. 1346,1353 (S.D. Iowa 1993).

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 781 2009-2010

2010) THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 781

B. Due Process

1. Procedural Due Process

A procedural due process violation occurs when one is deprived of a significant interest protected under the Constitution without appropriate procedures to protect against unfairness and error. 100 This interest can arise either from the Constitution itself or from state law.101 Post-Olmstead decisions have not generally required periodic review in a formal sense. The model has been to require the institution to review and to "consider" each resident for possible placement. 102

A person confined in an institution who protests that confinement is entitled to a meaningful hearing-a periodic review-on the person's continuing need for institutionalization.103 The need for commitment must be reviewed periodically by a neutral fact finder. 104 In concluding that a woman confined for decades at a state institution for people with mental retardation had a procedural due process right to such reviews, the Third Circuit noted, "[t]he hearing tribunal must have the authority to afford relief.,,105 Other courts agree. 106 The review must not be pro forma and must not be biased toward the status quo. It has been held that, while Due Process does not require a

100. Addington, 441 U.S. at 425 (1979); see generally Vitek, 445 U.S. at 480 (\980) (transfer of prisoner to mental hospital); Goldberg v. Kelly, 397 U.S. 254 (1970).

101. Hewitt v. Helms, 459 U.S. 460, 466 (1983). 102. See, e.g., Messier v. Southbury Training Sch., 562 F. Supp. 2d 294, 343 (D. Conn. 2008) ("The

evidence indicates that the defendants generally failed to exercise professional judgment in considering community placement for a large number of class members regardless of the degree of their disability, but the plaintiffs have not established that the defendants failed to consider more severely disabled class members for community placement.").

103. The need for review is implied in O'Connor v. Donaldson, 422 U.S. 563, 574-75 (1975) (''Nor is it enough that Donaldson's original confmement was founded upon a constitutionally adequate basis, if in fact it was, because even if his involuntary confinement was initially permissible, it could not constitutionally continue after that basis no longer existed.").

104. Parham v. JR, 442 U.S. 584,613 (\979) (requiring the periodic review implied in Donaldson v.

O'Connor). 105. Clark v. Cohen, 794 F.2d 79, 86 (3d Cir. 1986) (citing Parham v. J.R., 442 U.S. 584, 607

(1979». 106. Doe ex rei. Doe v. Austin, 848 F.2d 1386, 1395-96 (6th Cir. 1988) ("Of course, because

involuntary commitment cannot continue after the basis for that commitment ceases to exist, due process requires that some periodic review take place during confinement."), cert. denied sub. nom., Cowherd V.

Doe ex reI. Doe, 488 U.S. 967 (1988); Conner V. Branstad, 839 F. Supp. 1346, 1353 (S.D. Iowa 1993).

19

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

judicial fact finder for periodic review of commitment of personswith intellectual disabilities, Equal Protection requires judicialperiodic review of continuing need for institutionalization if peoplewith mental illness receive such review. 107

2. Substantive Due Process

Until its indirect evisceration in the Supreme Court's decisions inYoungberg v. Romeo (on Due Process) and Pennhurst State Schooland Hospital v. Halderman (on the Developmentally DisabledAssistance and Bill of Rights Act), "the concept of the leastrestrictive alternative-the idea that restrictivity of confinement canand must be calibrated and evaluated-ha[s] remained one of the corestaples of mental disability law.' 1 8 Youngberg focused oninstitutional treatment rights, and Pennhurst rejected a statutorycommunity services right. 10 9 There followed a line of cases in themid-to-late 1980s rejecting the "least restrictive" basis for communityservices. 110

What has survived the disfavor of the least restrictive analysis,however, is robust law on other grounds. Two conceptual strands

107. Doe ex rel. Doe, 848 F.2d at 1395-96.108. Michael L. Perlin, supra note 89, at 1000. For a review of the 1970s and early 1980s community

placement court decisions, see id. at 1022-25. See Dixon v. Weinberger, 405 F. Supp. 974, 980 (D.D.C.1975) (mental hospital must plan for treatment of plaintiff patients in "suitable residential facilitiesunder the least restrictive [alternative] conditions"); David Ferleger, Anti-Institutionalization and theSupreme Court, 14 RUTGERS L. J. 595, 598 & n. 12 (1983) (judicial action has provided thousands withmore humane services in community facilities); Melissa G. Warren & Robert R. Moon, Dixon: In theAbsence of Political Will, Carry a Big Stick, 18 LAW & PSYCHOL. REV. 329, 330 (1994) (mental healthde-institutionalization order); see generally Brewster v. Dukakis, 544 F. Supp. 1069 (D. Mass. 1982)(mem.), aff'das modified, 786 F.2d 16 (1st Cir. 1986) (mental health deinstitutionalization order).

109. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp. v. Halderman, 451 U.S. 1, 18 (stating that nothing in theDevelopmental Disabilities Act suggests Congress intended to require the states to provide 'appropriatetreatment' in the 'least restrictive environment"' to citizens with developmental disabilities); Youngbergv. Romeo, 457 U.S. 307 (1982).

110. See Lelsz v. Kavanagh, 807 F.2d 1243, 1248-49 (5th Cir. 1987); Soc'y for Good Will toRetarded Children v. Cuomo, 737 F.2d 1239, 1249 (2d Cir. 1984); Phillips v. Thompson, 715 F.2d 365,368 (7th Cir.1983); see Jackson v. Fort Stanton Hosp. & Training Sch., 964 F.2d 980, 992 (10th Cir.1992) ("Community placement is only one of various possible ways in which the state may comply withits constitutional obligations to adequately care for and train involuntarily committed individuals.");Hanson ex rel. Hanson v. Clarke County, 867 F.2d 1115, 1120 (8th Cir. 1989) (denying plaintiff'scontention that she had right to funding for placement in the "least restrictive environment consistentwith qualified professional judgment"); Conner v. Branstad, 839 F. Supp. 1346, 1351 (S.D. Iowa 1993).See generally Gieseking v. Schafer, 672 F. Supp. 1249 (W.D. Mo. 1987).

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 782 2009-2010

782 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 26:3

judicial fact finder for periodic review of commitment of persons

with intellectual disabilities, Equal Protection requires judicial

periodic review of continuing need for institutionalization if people

with mental illness receive such review. 107

2. Substantive Due Process

Until its indirect evisceration in the Supreme Court's decisions in

Youngberg v. Romeo (on Due Process) and Pennhurst State School and Hospital v. Halderman (on the Developmentally Disabled

Assistance and Bill of Rights Act), "the concept of the least

restrictive alternative-the idea that restrictivity of confinement can

and must be calibrated and evaluated-ha[ s] remained one of the core

staples of mental disability law.,,108 Youngberg focused on

institutional treatment rights, and Pennhurst rejected a statutory

community services right. 109 There followed a line of cases in the

mid-to-Iate 1980s rejecting the "least restrictive" basis for community

services. I 10

What has survived the disfavor of the least restrictive analysis,

however, is robust law on other grounds. Two conceptual strands

107. Doe ex rei. Doe, 848 F.2d at 1395-96. 108. Michael L. Perlin, supra note 89, at 1000. For a review of the 1970s and early 1980s community

placement court decisions, see id. at 1022-25. See Dixon v. Weinberger, 405 F. Supp. 974, 980 (D.D.C. 1975) (mental hospital must plan for treatment of plaintiff patients in "suitable residential facilities under the least restrictive [alternative] conditions"); David Ferleger, Anti-Institutionalization and the Supreme Court, 14 RUTGERS L. J. 595, 598 & n.12 (1983) (judicial action has provided thousands with more humane services in community facilities); Melissa G. Warren & Robert R. Moon, Dixon: In the Absence of Political Will, Carry a Big Stick, 18 LAW & PSYCHOL. REv. 329, 330 (1994) (mental health de-institutionalization order); see generally Brewster v. Dukakis, 544 F. Supp. 1069 (D. Mass. 1982) (mem.), affd as modified, 786 F.2d 16 (1st Cir. 1986) (mental health deinstitutionalization order).

109. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp. v. Halderman, 451 U.S. I, 18 (stating that nothing in the Developmental Disabilities Act suggests Congress intended to require the states to provide '''appropriate treatment' in the 'least restrictive environment'" to citizens with developmental disabilities); Youngberg v. Romeo, 457 U.S. 307 (1982).

110. See Lelsz v. Kavanagh, 807 F.2d 1243, 1248-49 (5th Cir. 1987); Soc'y for Good Will to Retarded Children v. Cuomo, 737 F.2d 1239, 1249 (2d Cir. 1984); Phillips v. Thompson, 715 F.2d 365, 368 (7th Cir.1983); see Jackson v. Fort Stanton Hosp. & Training Sch., 964 F.2d 980, 992 (10th Cir. 1992) ("Community placement is only one of various possible ways in which the state may comply with its constitutional obligations to adequately care for and train involuntarily committed individuals."); Hanson ex rei. Hanson v. Clarke County, 867 F.2d 1115, 1120 (8th Cir. 1989) (denying plaintiff's contention that she had right to funding for placement in the "least restrictive environment consistent with qualified professional judgment"); Conner v. Branstad, 839 F. Supp. 1346,1351 (S.D. Iowa 1993). See generally Gieseking v. Schafer, 672 F. Supp. 1249 (W.O. Mo. 1987).

20

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

20101 THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 783

form the basis for the substantive due process right to treatment forthe institutionalized. Although they are intertwined, they each havebeen considered to provide independent support for the right. Thequid pro quo approach considers that the massive curtailment ofliberty occasioned by involuntary civil institutionalization, for whichcriminal justice procedural safeguards are absent, cannot be justifiedunless the state gives to the institutionalized person something inexchange for the loss of liberty."' That "something" is habilitation.The parens patriae approach is that due process is violated when thestate fails to provide treatment to a person dependent on the state.There is no need for detailed analysis here of whether the right totreatment arises under the quid pro quo or the parens patriaetheory.

112

The quid pro quo position finds support in the Supreme Court'sruling in O 'Connor v. Donaldson that "a State cannot constitutionallyconfine without more a non-dangerous individual who is capable ofsurviving safely in freedom by himself or with the help of willing andresponsible family members or friends." ' 13 Absent treatment (orwhatever the Court meant by "more"), the deprivation of liberty isunjustified. Courts have applied this rationale to confinement ofpeople with retardation."14

Partaking of the parens patriae interest is the holding ofYoungberg v. Romeo,"15 and its progeny, that due process requiresthat an institution provide its residents with a minimal level oftraining or "habilitation." 116 In Youngberg, the Supreme Court

111. See O'Connor v. Donaldson, 422 U.S. 563, 576 (1975).112. See Bruce G. Mason & Frank J. Menolascino, The Right to Treatment for Mentally Retarded

Citizens: An Evolving Legal and Scientific Interface, 10 CREIGHTON L. REv. 124 (1976); Donald H.J.Hermann, Barriers to Providing Effective Treatment: A Critique of Revisions in Procedural,Substantive, and Dispositional Criteria in Involuntary Civil Commitment, 39 VAND. L. REV. 83, 85(1986).

113. O'Connor, 422 U.S. at 576.114. See United States v. Jackson, 553 F.2d 109, 119 (D.C. Cir. 1976); Welsch v. Likins, 373 F. Supp.

487, 496 (D. Minn. 1974) (relying on Robinson v. California, 370 U.S. 660 (1962), for holding that ifplaintiffs are subject to "detention for mere illness without a curative program," their confinement isunconstitutional).

115. Youngberg v. Romeo, 457 U.S. 307 (1982).116. A recent acknowledgement of this right is Judge Ellen Bree Bums' detailed decision in Messier

v. Southbury Training Sch., 562 F. Supp. 2d 294, 303 (D. Conn. 2008), finding that institutional

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 783 2009-2010

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 783

form the basis for the substantive due process right to treatment for the institutionalized. Although they are intertwined, they each have been considered to provide independent support for the right. The quid pro quo approach considers that the massive curtailment of liberty occasioned by involuntary civil institutionalization, for which criminal justice procedural safeguards are absent, cannot be justified unless the state gives to the institutionalized person something in exchange for the loss of liberty. III That "something" is habilitation. The parens patriae approach is that due process is violated when the state fails to provide treatment to a person dependent on the state. There is no need for detailed analysis here of whether the right to treatment arises under the quid pro quo or the parens patriae theory. 112

The quid pro quo position finds support in the Supreme Court's ruling in 0 'Connor v. Donaldson that "a State cannot constitutionally confine without more a non-dangerous individual who is capable of surviving safely in freedom by himself or with the help of willing and responsible family members or friends.,,113 Absent treatment (or whatever the Court meant by "more"), the deprivation of liberty is unjustified. Courts have applied this rationale to confinement of people with retardation. I 14

Partaking of the parens patriae interest is the holding of Youngberg v. Romeo,115 and its progeny, that due process requires that an institution provide its residents with a minimal level of training or "habilitation.,,116 In Youngberg, the Supreme Court

III. See O'Connor v. Donaldson, 422 U.S. 563, 576 (1975). 112. See Bruce G. Mason & Frank J. Menolascino, The Right to Treatment for Mentally Retarded

Citizens: An Evolving Legal and Scientific Interface, 10 CREIGHTON L. REv. 124 (1976); Donald H.J. Hermann, Barriers to Providing Effective Treatment: A Critique of Revisions in Procedural, Substantive, and Dispositional Criteria in Involuntary Civil Commitment, 39 VAND. L. REv. 83, 85 (1986).

113. O'Connor, 422 U.S. at 576. 114. See United States v. Jackson, 553 F.2d 109, 119 (D.C. Cir. 1976); Welsch v. Likins, 373 F. Supp.

487,496 (D. Minn. 1974) (relying on Robinson v. California, 370 U.s. 660 (1962), for holding that if plaintiffs are subject to "detention for mere illness without a curative program," their confmement is unconstitutional). 115. Youngberg v. Romeo, 457 U.S. 307 (1982). 116. A recent acknowledgement of this right is Judge Ellen Bree Burns' detailed decision in Messier

v. Southbury Training Sch., 562 F. Supp. 2d 294, 303 (D. Conn. 2008), fmding that institutional

21

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

concluded, first, that "[t]he mere fact that Romeo has been committedunder proper procedures does not deprive him of all substantiveliberty interests under the Fourteenth Amendment." 117 There areadditional liberty interests and they require the State to provideminimally adequate or reasonable training to ensure safety andfreedom from undue restraint."11 8 The treatment interests are not"absolute." Whether the constitutional rights have been violated mustbe determined by "balancing his liberty interests against the relevantstate interests. '119

These constitutional requirements are satisfied when there has beena "professional judgment" in determining what services and careshould be provided to residents of state-run institutions. 120 Aviolation of the professional judgment requirement may be shown inat least two ways:

a. Where no professional judgment has been exercised (includingsituations where a facility administrator ignoresrecommendations of professionals), 12' andb. Where the judgment made by a qualified professional was"such a substantial departure from accepted professionaljudgment, practice, or standards as to demonstrate that the person

conditions generally had been improved from its prior level of dangerousness and other deficiencies tosatisfy constitutional muster.

117. Youngberg, 457 U.S. at 315.118. Id. at 319 & n.24 (noting that, in the concurring opinion in the appellate court with which the

Supreme Court agreed, the concurring judge had "used the term 'treatment' as synonymous withtraining or habilitation"). Residents also have a constitutionally protected interest in medical care, safeconditions and in freedom from bodily restraint except to the extent that restraint must be used to assuresafety. Youngberg, 457 U.S. at 315-16.

119. Id. at 321.120. Id.121. Messier, 562 F. Supp. 2d at 300 (citing Valentine v. Strange, 597 F. Supp. 1316, 1318 (E.D.

Va. 1 984) (declining to dismiss complaint by patient who set fire to herself after hospital officials tookno action to confiscate her cigarettes and lighter despite unsuccessful effort to bum herself earlier in theday), and Cameron v. Tomes, 783 F. Supp. 1511, 1520-21 (D. Mass. 1992) (finding due processviolation where facility's administrator ignored recommendation of professionals and ordered a patientto be transported in shackles)).

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 784 2009-2010

784 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW (Vol. 26:3

concluded, first, that "[t]he mere fact that Romeo has been committed under proper procedures does not deprive him of all substantive liberty interests under the Fourteenth Amendment."I17 There are additional liberty interests and they require the State to provide minimally adequate or reasonable training to ensure safety and freedom from undue restraint.,,118 The treatment interests are not "absolute." Whether the constitutional rights have been violated must be determined by "balancing his liberty interests against the relevant state interests. ,,119

These constitutional requirements are satisfied when there has been a "professional judgment" in determining what services and care should be provided to residents of state-run institutions. 12o A violation of the professional judgment requirement may be shown in at least two ways:

a. Where no professional judgment has been exercised (including situations where a facility administrator ignores recommendations of professionals), 121 and

b. Where the judgment made by a qualified professional was "such a substantial departure from accepted professional judgment, practice, or standards as to demonstrate that the person

conditions general1y had been improved from its prior level of dangerousness and other deficiencies to satisfy constitutional muster.

117. Youngberg, 457 U.S. at 315. 118. /d. at 319 & n.24 (noting that, in the concurring opinion in the appel1ate court with which the

Supreme Court agreed, the concurring judge had "used the term 'treatment' as synonymous with training or habilitation"). Residents also have a constitutional1y protected interest in medical care, safe conditions and in freedom from bodily restraint except to the extent that restraint must be used to assure safety. Youngberg, 457 U.S. at 315-16.

119. Id.at321. 120. Id. 121. Messier, 562 F. Supp. 2d at 300 (citing Valentine v. Strange, 597 F. Supp. 1316, 1318 (E.D.

Va. 1984) (declining to dismiss complaint by patient who set fire to herself after hospital officials took no action to confiscate her cigarettes and lighter despite unsuccessful effort to burn herself earlier in the day), and Cameron v. Tomes, 783 F. Supp. 1511, 1520-21 (D. Mass. 1992) (fmding due process violation where facility's administrator ignored recommendation of professionals and ordered a patient to be transported in shackles».

22

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 785

responsible actually did not base the decision on such ajudgment.'

122

The issue is "not whether the optimal course of treatment asdetermined by some experts was being followed" but whetherprofessional judgment was exercised. 123 Where professionaljudgment establishes that provision of minimally adequate treatmentrequires community services, an institutionalized person'ssubstantive due process rights are violated. 124 Youngberg did notaddress institutional judgments favoring placement. 125

Youngberg requires balancing an institutionalized person's libertyinterests against the "relevant state interests", which the Courtidentified not as budgetary or administrative but rather as the state'sinterest in ensuring the exercise of professional judgment.126

For many individuals with intellectual disabilities in publicinstitutions, the judgment exercised by the institution's professionalsthemselves is that the confinement is not necessary and thatcommunity services would be beneficial. Therefore, not surprisingly,

122. Id. at 301. Youngberg, 457 U.S. at 323.123. Soc'y for Good Will to Retarded Children v. Cuomo, 737 F.2d 1239, 1248 (2d Cir. 1984); P.C.

v. McLaughlin, 913 F.2d 1033, 1043 (2d Cir. 1990) (courts do not determine that "the best course ofaction was taken"); Messier, 562 F. Supp. 2d at 301; Griffith v. Ledbetter, 711 F. Supp. 1108, 1110(N.D. Ga. 1989).

124. It is important to note that "[t]he decisions of the treating professionals are not conclusive," andthe opinions of experts at trial may be "relevant to whether the treating professionals' decisionssubstantially departed from accepted standards." Williams v. Wasserman, 164 F. Supp. 2d 591, 614 (D.Md. 2001) (citing Thomas S. v. Flaherty, 902 F.2d 250, 252 (4th Cir. 1990) (citation omitted)). Thiscase is the fourth in the "Thomas S." line of cases: Thomas S. v. Morrow (Thomas S. 1), 601 F. Supp.1055 (W.D.N.C. 1984); Thomas S. v. Morrow (Thomas S. 11), 781 F.2d 367 (4th Cir. 1986); Thomas S.v. Flaherty (Thomas S. 111), 699 F. Supp. 1178 (W.D.N.C. 1988); and Thomas S. v. Flaherty (Thomas S./M, 902 F.2d 250 (4th Cir. 1990).

125. Based on what turned out to be an incorrect premise, community placement was thought to bebeyond the facts of the case. The Court noted that, at oral argument, "Respondent, in light of the severecharacter of his retardation, concedes that no amount of training will make possible his release."Youngberg, 457 U.S. at 317. However, Nicolas Romeo was released from Pennhurst and moved to acommunity group home. E-mail from Edmund Tiryak, Romeo's counsel, to author (Sept. 10, 2009,08:21:30 EST) (on file with author).

126. Youngberg, 457 U.S. at 321 ("We think the standard articulated by Chief Judge Seitz affords thenecessary guidance and reflects the proper balance between the legitimate interests of the State and therights of the involuntarily committed to reasonable conditions of safety and freedom from unreasonablerestraints. He would have held that 'the Constitution only requires that the courts make certain thatprofessional judgment in fact was exercised. It is not appropriate for the courts to specify which ofseveral professionally acceptable choices should have been made."').

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 785 2009-2010

2010) THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES

responsible actually did not base the decision on such a judgment.,,122

785

The issue is "not whether the optimal course of treatment as determined by some experts was being followed" but whether professional judgment was exercised. 123 Where professional judgment establishes that provision of minimally adequate treatment requires community services, an institutionalized person's substantive due process rights are violated. 124 Youngberg did not address institutional judgments favoring placement. 125

Youngberg requires balancing an institutionalized person's liberty interests against the "relevant state interests", which the Court identified not as budgetary or administrative but rather as the state's interest in ensuring the exercise of professional judgment. 126

For many individuals with intellectual disabilities in public institutions, the judgment exercised by the institution's professionals themselves is that the confinement is not necessary and that community services would be beneficial. Therefore, not surprisingly,

122. Jd. at 301. Youngberg, 457 U.S. at 323. 123. Soc'y for Good Will to Retarded Children v. Cuomo, 737 F.2d 1239, 1248 (2d Cir. 1984); P.C.

v. Mclaughlin, 913 F.2d 1033, 1043 (2d Cir. 1990) (courts do not determine that "the best course of action was taken"); Messier, 562 F. Supp. 2d at 301; Griffith v. Ledbetter, 711 F. Supp. 1108, 1110 (N.D. Ga. 1989).

124. It is important to note that "[t]he decisions of the treating professionals are not conclusive," and the opinions of experts at trial may be "relevant to whether the treating professionals' decisions substantially departed from accepted standards." Williams v. Wasserman, 164 F. Supp. 2d 591, 614 (D. Md. 2001) (citing Thomas S. v. Flaherty, 902 F.2d 250, 252 (4th Cir. 1990) (citation omitted». This case is the fourth in the "Thomas S." line of cases: Thomas S. v. Morrow (Thomas S. J), 601 F. Supp. 1055 (W.D.N.C. 1984); Thomas S. v. Morrow (Thomas S. II), 781 F.2d 367 (4th Cir. 1986); Thomas S. v. Flaherty (Thomas S. III), 699 F. Supp. 1178 (W.D.N.C. 1988); and Thomas S. v. Flaherty (Thomas S. lV), 902 F.2d 250 (4th Cir. 1990).

125. Based on what turned out to be an incorrect premise, community placement was thought to be beyond the facts of the case. The Court noted that, at oral argument, "Respondent, in light of the severe character of his retardation, concedes that no amount of training will make possible his release." Youngberg, 457 U.S. at 317. However, Nicolas Romeo was released from Pennhurst and moved to a community group home. E-mail from Edmund Tiryak, Romeo's counsel, to author (Sept. 10, 2009, 08:21:30 EST) (on file with author).

126. Youngberg, 457 U.S. at 321 ("We think the standard articulated by Chief Judge Seitz affords the necessary guidance and reflects the proper balance between the legitimate interests of the State and the rights of the involuntarily committed to reasonable conditions of safety and freedom from unreasonable restraints. He would have held that 'the Constitution only requires that the courts make certain that professional judgment in fact was exercised. It is not appropriate for the courts to specifY which of several professionally acceptable choices should have been made. "').

23

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

Youngberg has been extended to embrace a due process right tocommunity services.'27

On the other hand, some courts (mostly before Olmstead) havedeclared that residents of state institutions for people with mentalretardation "have no right to community placement."' 28 Virtually inthe same breath, however, "no-right" courts have acknowledged thatstate decisions which deprive individuals of liberty, which result intheir institutionalization, are subject to scrutiny under Youngberg anddue process principles; confinement must be "rational., 129 We see inthese decisions a profound judicial disquiet with a constitutionalfabric which would uphold use of governmental power toinvoluntarily confine people when it is acknowledged thatconfinement is not justified by considerations of adequate care andtreatment. In considering the Youngberg balance between a person'sliberty interests and the state's interests, Olmstead's recognition thatthe ADA forbids unjustified institutionalization must be placed in thebalance.

127. See generally Clark v. Cohen, 794 F.2d 79 (3d Cir. 1986); Homeward Bound, Inc., v. HissomMemorial Ctr., No. 85-C-437-E, 1987 WL 27104, at *19 (N.D. Okla. July 24, 1987) ("Freedom frombodily restraint includes the right to be free from confinement in an institution where such confinementis shown on a factual basis to be unnecessary.").

128. Messier, 562 F. Supp. 2d at 319; Soc'y for Good Will, 737 F.2d at 1249; Phillips v. Thompson,715 F.2d 365, 368 (7th Cir. 1983); Garrity v. Gallen, 522 F. Supp. 171, 237-39 (D.N.H. 1981). Pre-Youngberg, there were cases which did not appreciate the significance of the liberty deprivation. E.g.,Ass'n for Retarded Citizens of N.D. v. Olson, 561 F. Supp. 473, 488 (D.N.D. 1982) (questioningwhether institutionalization "compromises a fundamental liberty interest" and suggesting that "the statemay have a compelling interest in just safekeeping-rather than habilitating-mentally retardedpersons").

129. "Community placement decisions are, however, subject to scrutiny under Youngberg. Like anyother decision to place restraints on a patient's freedom, the decision to keep a resident in an institutioninstead of placing the resident in a community setting must be 'a rational decision based on professionaljudgment."' Messier, 562 F. Supp. 2d at 319 (quoting Soc "yfor Good Will, 737 F.2d at 1249) (citationsomitted). As one court put it, if "a patient were being held against his will contrary to all the medicalevidence and expert medical opinion, there would clearly be a constitutional violation." Hughes v.Cuomo, 862 F. Supp. 34, 37 (W.D.N.Y. 1994).Some courts flatly disagreed pre-Olmstead that there is any due process right to community services.S.H. v. Edwards, 860 F.2d 1045, 1051-52 (11 th Cir. 1988) (Constitution does not bestow any "right" toreceive state-provided mental health treatment in a community setting rather than in an institutionalone); Soc 'y for Good Will, 737 F.2d at 1247 ("[M]ere residence in an institution or school for thementally retarded, without more, does not violate due process.").

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 786 2009-2010

786 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW (Vol. 26:3

Youngberg has been extended to embrace a due process right to

community services.127

On the other hand, some courts (mostly before Olmstead) have

declared that residents of state institutions for people with mental

retardation "have no right to community placement.,,128 Virtually in the same breath, however, "no-right" courts have acknowledged that

state decisions which deprive individuals of liberty, which result in

their institutionalization, are subject to scrutiny under Youngberg and

due process principles; confinement must be "rational.,,129 We see in

these decisions a profound judicial disquiet with a constitutional

fabric which would uphold use of governmental power to

involuntarily confine people when it is acknowledged that

confinement is not justified by considerations of adequate care and

treatment. In considering the Youngberg balance between a person's

liberty interests and the state's interests, Olmstead's recognition that

the ADA forbids unjustified institutionalization must be placed in the

balance.

127. See generally Clark v. Cohen, 794 F.2d 79 (3d Cir. 1986); Homeward Bound, Inc., v. Hissom Memorial Ctr., No. 85-C-437-E, 1987 WL 27104, at ·19 (N.D. Okla. July 24, 1987) ("Freedom from bodily restraint includes the right to be free from confinement in an institution where such confinement is shown on a factual basis to be unnecessary.").

128. Messier, 562 F. Supp. 2d at 319; Soc'y for Good Will, 737 F.2d at 1249; Phillips v. Thompson, 715 F.2d 365, 368 (7th Cir. 1983); Garrity v. Gallen, 522 F. Supp. l71, 237-39 (D.N.H. 1981). Pre­Youngberg, there were cases which did not appreciate the significance of the liberty deprivation. E.g., Ass'n for Retarded Citizens of N.D. v. Olson, 561 F. Supp. 473, 488 (D.N.D. 1982) (questioning whether institutionalization "compromises a fundamental liberty interest" and suggesting that ''the state may have a compelling interest in just safekeeping-rather than habilitating-mentally retarded persons").

129. "Community placement decisions are, however, subject to scrutiny under Youngberg. Like any other decision to place restraints on a patient's freedom, the decision to keep a resident in an institution instead of placing the resident in a community setting must be 'a rational decision based on professional judgment.'" Messier, 562 F. Supp. 2d at 319 (quoting Soc'y for Good Will, 737 F.2d at 1249) (citations omitted). As one court put it, if "a patient were being held against his will contrary to all the medical evidence and expert medical opinion, there would clearly be a constitutional violation." Hughes v. Cuomo, 862 F. Supp. 34, 37 (W.D.N.Y. 1994). Some courts flatly disagreed pre-Olmstead that there is any due process right to community services. S.H. v. Edwards, 860 F.2d 1045, 1051-52 (11th Cir. 1988) (Constitution does not bestow any "right" to receive state-provided mental health treatment in a community setting rather than in an institutional one); Soc'y for Good Will, 737 F.2d at 1247 ("[M]ere residence in an institution or school for the mentally retarded, without more, does not violate due process.").

24

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 787

C. Equal Protection

1. Introduction

The Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment

requires that similarly situated individuals should be treated similarly.When state law or practice do not employ suspect classifications orimpinge on fundamental rights, they are upheld when they are

rationally related to a legitimate public purpose.' 30

When the government acts on the basis of a suspect classification

or affecting a fundamental interest, the traditional rational basisstandard is abandoned in favor of what has been called "strictscrutiny." Strict scrutiny admits of little or no presumption of validity

of the challenged state action.An intermediate level of scrutiny is afforded classifications

involving "quasi-suspect" classes such as gender and illegitimacy.' 3 1

To withstand constitutional challenge, a classification disfavoring aquasi-suspect class must "serve important governmental objectives

and must be substantially related to achievement of thoseobjectives.,

132

I advance two arguments here. First, I propose that forcible and

unnecessary institutionalization of people with intellectual disabilitiesis irrational and therefore unconstitutional under the traditional equalprotection framework. Second, I conclude that a class definition for

equal protection purposes narrower than all "the disabled" is subjectto at least the intermediate degree of scrutiny. Rather than define theprotected group as "the disabled" generically, one would focus onthose among the disabled who are maximally deprived of liberty and

who are a close fit to the "special condition" class described infootnote 4 of United States v. Carolene Products,133 and its "strict

130. Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202, 216 (1982). See generally City of Clebume v. Clebume Living Ctr.,473 U.S. 432 (1985); Hodel v. Indiana, 452 U.S. 314 (1981); Schweiker v. Wilson, 450 U.S. 221 (1981);Personnel Adm'r of Mass. v. Feeney, 442 U.S. 256 (1979).13I. Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190, 197 (1976) (acknowledgement of middle tier scrutiny).132. Id.133. United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 153 n.4 (1938) ("Nor need we inquire

whether similar considerations enter into the review of statutes directed at particular religious, ornational, or racial minorities, whether prejudice against discrete and insular minorities may be a special

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 787 2009-2010

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 787

C. Equal Protection

1. Introduction

The Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment requires that similarly situated individuals should be treated similarly. When state law or practice do not employ suspect classifications or impinge on fundamental rights, they are upheld when they are rationally related to a legitimate public purpose. 130

When the government acts on the basis of a suspect classification or affecting a fundamental interest, the traditional rational basis standard is abandoned in favor of what has been called "strict scrutiny." Strict scrutiny admits of little or no presumption of validity of the challenged state action.

An intermediate level of scrutiny is afforded classifications involving "quasi-suspect" classes such as gender and illegitimacy.131 To withstand constitutional challenge, a classification disfavoring a quasi-suspect class must "serve important governmental objectives and must be substantially related to achievement of those objectives.,,132

I advance two arguments here. First, I propose that forcible and unnecessary institutionalization of people with intellectual disabilities is irrational and therefore unconstitutional under the traditional equal protection framework. Second, I conclude that a class definition for equal protection purposes narrower than all "the disabled" is subject to at least the intermediate degree of scrutiny. Rather than define the protected group as "the disabled" generically, one would focus on those among the disabled who are maximally deprived of liberty and who are a close fit to the "special condition" class described in footnote 4 of United States v. Carolene Products,133 and its "strict

130. Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202,216 (1982). See generally City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., 473 U.S. 432 (1985); Hodel v. Indiana, 452 U.S. 314 (1981); Schweiker v. Wilson, 450 U.S. 221 (1981); Personnel Adm'r of Mass. v. Feeney, 442 U.S. 256 (1979).

131. Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190, 197 (1976) (acknowledgement of middle tier scrutiny). 132. /d. 133. United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 153 n.4 (1938) ("Nor need we inquire

whether similar considerations enter into the review of statutes directed at particular religious, or national, or racial minorities, whether prejudice against discrete and insular minorities may be a special

25

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

scrutiny" progeny. This approach would bring to bear the protectionsof the suspect or quasi-suspect class analysis on the discriminationinherent in institutionalization.

2. Needless Institutionalization Is Irrational

Freedom from segregation has long been recognized as an interestprotected by the Equal Protection Clause.' 34 Where a state forciblyexcludes, separates and segregates people with mental retardationfrom the rest of society, and where equivalent or superior care (andquality of life) is available in a non-segregated setting, a seriousquestion arises whether such action is rationally related to alegitimate state interest.

Classifications impinging on fundamental rights have beeninvalidated as irrational. 135 One of the rare instances in which theSupreme Court held that discrimination (not on the basis of gender orrace) was irrational involved community living for individuals withretardation. Finding that a city's zoning exclusion of a communityhome was irrational, the Court found a violation of equalprotection. 136 Similarly, it is not rational, or logical or humane, tocompel institutional segregation where it is not necessary for theindividual. One can demonstrate that, for each person in theinstitution, there is a "twin" living successfully in the communitywith equivalent disabilities. The institution for these individuals isdefinitively "separate but not equal."'137

condition, which tends seriously to curtail the operation of those political processes ordinarily to berelied upon to protect minorities, and which may call for a correspondingly more searching judicialinquiry." (citations omitted)).

134. See generally Brown v. Board of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954).135. See e.g., Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438 (1972) (access by married and unmarried to

contraception).136. City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., 473 U.S. 432,432 (1985).137. See Homeward Bound, Inc., v. Hissom Memorial Ctr., No. 85-C-437-E, 1987 WL 27104, at *19

(N.D. Okla. July 24, 1987) (finding institutionalization of people with retardation to be an irrationaldiscrimination in violation of the Equal Protection Clause). Gieseking v. Schafer recognized that a statemay not treat a class of residents with developmental disabilities irrationally under the Equal ProtectionClause, finding it a question of fact which could not be decided on summary judgment. Gieseking v.Schafer, 672 F. Supp. 1249, 1264 (W.D. Mo. 1987).

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 788 2009-2010

788 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 26:3

scrutiny" progeny. This approach would bring to bear the protections of the suspect or quasi-suspect class analysis on the discrimination inherent in institutionalization.

2. Needless Institutionalization Is Irrational

Freedom from segregation has long been recognized as an interest protected by the Equal Protection Clause.134 Where a state forcibly excludes, separates and segregates people with mental retardation from the rest of society, and where equivalent or superior care (and quality of life) is available in a non-segregated setting, a serious question arises whether such action is rationally related to a legitimate state interest.

Classifications impinging on fundamental rights have been invalidated as irrational. 135 One of the rare instances in which the Supreme Court held that discrimination (not on the basis of gender or race) was irrational involved community living for individuals with retardation. Finding that a city's zoning exclusion of a community home was irrational, the Court found a violation of equal protection. 136 Similarly, it is not rational, or logical or humane, to compel institutional segregation where it is not necessary for the individual. One can demonstrate that, for each person in the institution, there is a "twin" living successfully in the community with equivalent disabilities. The institution for these individuals IS definitively "separate but not equal.,,137

condition, which tends seriously to curtail the operation of those political processes ordinarily to be relied upon to protect minorities, and which may call for a correspondingly more searching judicial inquiry." (citations omitted».

134. See generally Brown v. Board of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954). 135. See e.g., Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438 (1972) (access by married and unmarried to

contraception). 136. City ofClebume v. Cleburne Living Ctr., 473 U.S. 432,432 (1985). 137. See Homeward Bound, Inc., v. Hissom Memorial Ctr., No. 85-C-437-E, 1987 WL 27104, at *19

(N.D. Okla. July 24, 1987) (finding institutionalization of people with retardation to be an irrational discrimination in violation of the Equal Protection Clause). Gieseking v. Schafer recognized that a state may not treat a class of residents with developmental disabilities irrationally under the Equal Protection Clause, finding it a question of fact which could not be decided on summary jUdgment. Gieseking v. Schafer, 672 F. Supp. 1249, 1264 (W.O. Mo. 1987).

26

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

20101 THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 789

3. Institutionalized Individuals with Intellectual DisabilitiesConstitute a Quasi-suspect Class

The Supreme Court has not yet considered whether people withintellectual disabilities who are institutionalized constitute a suspector quasi-suspect class under the Equal Protection Clause. Twice, theCourt has dodged the issue; both occasions occurred after passage ofthe ADA.138 Perhaps the Court recognizes that post-ADA there ismore to be said on the issue.

The majority opinion in Olmstead evidences a leaning toward theposition I espouse here. Referencing the "unwarranted assumptionsthat persons so isolated are incapable or unworthy of participating incommunity life,"' 139 the Court cited two cases, one on racialclassification and one on gender discrimination: Allen v. Wright andLos Angeles Dept. of Water and Power v. Manhart. 140 Neither was anequal protection case; however, the comparison of the irrationalstereotyping and stigmatization of institutionalized people withdisabilities to treatment of race and gender discrimination is telling.

A number of commentators have argued with force that the ADAitself, with its Congressional findings echoing the well-known criteriain footnote four of United States v. Carolene Products,14 1 compels

138. The Supreme Court declined to address an argument for heightened scrutiny of claims by peoplewith mental retardation regarding commitment, finding that the issue had not been raised below. Hellerv. Doe, 509 U.S. 312, 321 (1993) (challenge by class of individuals with mental retardation toconstitutionality of Kentucky's involuntary commitment procedures and holding that procedures metrational basis test under Equal Protection Clause). In opening her opinion in Olmstead, Justice Ginsburgstated, "This case, as it comes to us, presents no constitutional question," and, citing Cleburne, notedthat "the courts below resolved the case solely on statutory grounds." Olmstead v. L.C., 527 U.S. 581,587 (1999).

139. Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 600.140. Allen v. Wright, 468 U.S. 737, 755 (1984) (race); Los Angeles Dep't of Water & Power v.

Manhart, 435 U.S. 702, 708 n.13 (1978).141. See Brown v. Board of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954). The ADA's findings, at 42 U.S.C. §

12101(a)(7) originally read-quoting Carolene virtually verbatim-, "individuals with disabilities are adiscrete and insular minority who have been faced with restrictions and limitations, subjected to ahistory of purposeful unequal treatment, and relegated to a position of political powerlessness in oursociety, based on characteristics that are beyond the control of such individuals and resulting fromstereotypic assumptions not truly indicative of the individual ability of such individuals to participate in,and contribute to, society .... This paragraph was removed by sections 3(2) and (3) of the Americanswith Disabilities Act Amendments Act of 2008, Pub. L. No. 110-325, 112 Stat. 3553, 110th Cong., 2dSess. (Sept. 25, 2008). This change does not alter the 1990 Congress' characterization of the status ofpeople with disabilities.

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 789 2009-2010

2010) THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES

3. Institutionalized Individuals with Intellectual Disabilities Constitute a Quasi-suspect Class

789

The Supreme Court has not yet considered whether people with

intellectual disabilities who are institutionalized constitute a suspect

or quasi-suspect class under the Equal Protection Clause. Twice, the

Court has dodged the issue; both occasions occurred after passage of

the ADA.138

Perhaps the Court recognizes that post-ADA there is

more to be said on the issue.

The majority opinion in Olmstead evidences a leaning toward the

position I espouse here. Referencing the "unwarranted assumptions

that persons so isolated are incapable or unworthy of participating in

community life,,,139 the Court cited two cases, one on racial

classification and one on gender discrimination: Allen v. Wright and

Los Angeles Dept. of Water and Power v. Manhart. 140 Neither was an

equal protection case; however, the comparison of the irrational

stereotyping and stigmatization of institutionalized people with

disabilities to treatment of race and gender discrimination is telling.

A number of commentators have argued with force that the ADA

itself, with its Congressional findings echoing the well-known criteria

in footnote four of United States v. Carolene Products, 141 compels

138. The Supreme Court declined to address an argument for heightened scrutiny of claims by people with mental retardation regarding commitment, finding that the issue had not been raised below. Heller v. Doe, 509 U.S. 312, 321 (1993) (challenge by class of individuals with mental retardation to constitutionality of Kentucky's involuntary commitment procedures and holding that procedures met rational basis test under Equal Protection Clause). In opening her opinion in Olmstead, Justice Ginsburg stated, ''This case, as it comes to us, presents no constitutional question," and, citing Cleburne, noted that ''the courts below resolved the case solely on statutory grounds." Olmstead v. L.C., 527 U.S. 581, 587 (1999).

139. Olmstead, 527 U.S. at 600. 140. Allen v. Wright, 468 U.S. 737, 755 (1984) (race); Los Angeles Dep't of Water & Power v.

Manhart, 435 U.S. 702, 708 n.13 (1978). 141. See Brown v. Board of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954). The ADA's findings, at 42 U.S.C. §

12101(a)(7) originally read-quoting Carolene virtually verbatim-, "individuals with disabilities are a discrete and insular minority who have been faced with restrictions and limitations, subjected to a history of purposeful unequal treatment, and relegated to a position of political powerlessness in our society, based on characteristics that are beyond the control of such individuals and resulting from stereotypic assumptions not truly indicative of the individual ability of such individuals to participate in, and contribute to, society .... " This paragraph was removed by sections 3(2) and (3) of the Americans with Disabilities Act Amendments Act of 2008, Pub. L. No. 110-325, 112 Stat. 3553, I 10th Cong., 2d Sess. (Sept. 25, 2008). This change does not alter the 1990 Congress' characterization of the status of people with disabilities.

27

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

courts to employ a "strict scrutiny" or "compelling state interest" test.Such an argument would be reasonable. 142 It is certainly within easyreach to find that, because "the mentally retarded still suffer fromsome discrimination that is not related to actual disabilities," stateaction "must be reviewed under a level of scrutiny higher than therational basis test.' 43 For example, Michael Perlin in the immediateaftermath of Olmstead, urged that an ADA violation is per se aFourteenth Amendment violation:

The law's invocation of the full "sweep of congressionalauthority, including the power to enforce the FourteenthAmendment" simply means that any violation of the ADA mustbe read in the same light as a violation of the Equal ProtectionClause of the Constitution, guaranteeing, for the first time, thatthis core constitutional protection will finally be made availableto persons with disabilities. 44

This view won wide support in the literature' 45 before the SupremeCourt's 2001 decision to the contrary in the Garrett case, discussedbelow.

142. The suspect class criteria are a) whether the class has a history of purposeful unequal treatment,b) whether the class has such political powerlessness as to require extraordinary protection from themajoritarian political process, and c) whether the class is generally denied legal benefits on the basis ofstereotyped characteristics not truly indicative of their abilities. San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v.Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1, 28 (1973); Mass. Bd. of Ret. v. Murgia, 427 U.S. 307, 313 (1976) (per curiam).Each of these criteria has support in both history and case law.

143. See Ass'n for Retarded Citizens of N.D. v. Olson, 561 F. Supp. 473, 490 (D.N.D. 1982)(requiring the "state to show that disparities in educational opportunity which exist between the mentallyretarded and other citizens substantially furthers important state interests").

144. Perlin, supra note 40, at 59-60.145. See Marcia Pearce Burgdorf & Robert Burgdorf, Jr., A History of Unequal Treatment: The

Qualifications of Handicapped Persons as a "Suspect Class " Under the Equal Protection Clause, 15SANTA CLARA L. REV. 855, 905 (1975). James B. Miller, The Disabled, the ADA, and Strict Scrutiny, 6ST. THOMAS L. REV. 393, 413 (1994); Leonard S. Rubenstein, Ending Discrimination Against MentalHealth Treatment in Publicly Financed Health Care, 40 ST. Louis U. L.J. 315, 339 (1996) (analyzingthe ADA's invocation of the Carolene Products footnote); William Christian, Note, Normalization as aGoal: The Americans with Disabilities Act and Individuals with Mental Retardation, 73 TEX. L. REV.409, 424 (1994) (stating that laws treating persons with disabilities differently should be subject toheightened scrutiny); Amy Lowndes, Note, The Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990: ACongressional Mandate for Heightened Judicial Protection of Disabled Persons, 44 FLA. L. REV. 417,446 (1992) (discussing Congress' ADA findings); Lisa Montanaro, Comment, The Americans withDisabilities Act: Will the Court Get the Hint? Congress' Attempt to Raise the Status of Persons with

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 790 2009-2010

790 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 26:3

courts to employ a "strict scrutiny" or "compelling state interest" test. Such an argument would be reasonable. 142 It is certainly within easy reach to find that, because "the mentally retarded still suffer from some discrimination that is not related to actual disabilities," state action "must be reviewed under a level of scrutiny higher than the rational basis test.,,143 For example, Michael Perlin in the immediate

aftermath of Olmstead, urged that an ADA violation is per se a Fourteenth Amendment violation:

The law's invocation of the full "sweep of congressional authority, including the power to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment" simply means that any violation of the ADA must be read in the same light as a violation of the Equal Protection Clause of the Constitution, guaranteeing, for the first time, that this core constitutional protection will finally be made available to persons with disabilities. 144

This view won wide support in the literaturel45 before the Supreme Court's 2001 decision to the contrary in the Garrett case, discussed below.

142. The suspect class criteria are a) whether the class has a history of purposeful unequal treatment, b) whether the class has such political powerlessness as to require extraordinary protection from the majoritarian political process, and c) whether the class is generally denied legal benefits on the basis of stereotyped characteristics not truly indicative of their abilities. San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1,28 (1973); Mass. Bd. of Ret. v. Murgia, 427 U.S. 307, 313 (1976) (per curiam). Each of these criteria has support in both history and case law.

143. See Ass'n for Retarded Citizens of N.D. v. Olson, 561 F. Supp. 473, 490 (D.N.D. 1982) (requiring the "state to show that disparities in educational opportunity which exist between the mentally retarded and other citizens substantially furthers important state interests").

144. Perlin, supra note 40, at 59-60. 145. See Marcia Pearce Burgdorf & Robert Burgdorf, Jr., A History of Unequal Treatment: The

Qualifications of Handicapped Persons as a "Suspect Class" Under the Equal Protection Clause, 15 SANTA CLARA L. REv. 855, 905 (1975). James B. Miller, The Disabled. the ADA. and Strict Scrutiny, 6 ST. THOMAS L. REv. 393,413 (1994); Leonard S. Rubenstein, Ending Discrimination Against Mental Health Treatment in Publicly Financed Health Care, 40 ST. loUIS U. L.J. 315,339 (1996) (analyzing the ADA's invocation of the Carolene Products footnote); WiIIiam Christian, Note, Normalization as a Goal: The Americans·with Disabilities Act and Individuals with Mental Retardation, 73 TEx. L. REv. 409, 424 (1994) (stating that laws treating persons with disabilities differently should be subject to heightened scrutiny); Amy Lowndes, Note, The Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990: A Congressional Mandate for Heightened Judicial Protection of Disabled Persons, 44 FLA. L. REv. 417, 446 (1992) (discussing Congress' ADA findings); Lisa Montanaro, Comment, The Americans with Disabilities Act: Will the Court Get the Hint? Congress' Attempt to Raise the Status of Persons with

28

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 791

There is no precedential obstacle to a conclusion that involuntarilyinstitutionalized individuals with intellectual disabilities (a classnarrower than simply "the disabled") are a quasi-suspect class underthe Equal Protection Clause, and that their confinement must besubject to heightened scrutiny. Where that confinement isunnecessary, and the person could benefit from community services,institutionalization - to use the test for analysis of quasi-suspectclassifications - does not "serve important governmental objectivesand [is not] substantially related to achievement of thoseobjectives.' 46

In Board of Trustees of University of Alabama v. Garrett,147 adamages case by disabled state employees, the Court held that theEleventh Amendment sovereign immunity protects the state fromdamages liability under Title 1 of the ADA. Relying on Cleburne v.Cleburne Living Center, Inc.,148 the Court concluded that "thedisabled" are not a quasi-suspect class under the FourteenthAmendment. 149 The petitioners in Garrett were a woman with breastcancer and a man with asthma. Cleburne's rejection of a quasi-suspect class approach for "the large and amorphous class of thementally retarded" was appealing to the Supreme Court in Garrett.The concern was that labeling the disabled a quasi-suspect classmight support similar labeling of such generic groups as "the aging,the disabled, the mentally ill, and the infirm."'1 50

Disabilities in Equal Protection Cases, 15 PACE L. REV. 621, 663 (1995) (in the ADA, Congressattempted to utilize Carolene Products findings to imply that a "heightened level of scrutiny" should beutilized under the ADA); see also Crowder v. Kitagawa, 842 F. Supp. 1257, 1264 (D. Haw. 1994)(assuming application of strict scrutiny level in ADA cases).

146. Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190, 197 (1976).147. Bd. of Trs. of Univ. of Ala. v. Garrett, 531 U.S. 356, 374 (2001).148. City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., Inc., 473 U.S. 432 (1985) (invalidating a zoning

regulation which precluded a community home for individuals with retardation).149. Garrett, 531 U.S. at 367.150. Id. at 366 (quoting Cleburne, 473 U.S. at 446). One commentator makes a cogent argument that

there is a tension between the Supreme Court's decision in Garrett (declining to find "the disabled" aquasi-suspect class) and CleburnelOlmstead. Sean Pevsner, Reasonable Accommodations asConstitutional Obligations, 7 TEx. F. ON C.L. & C.R. 317, 317 (2002) (suggesting that Olmstead andCleburne in essence, if not in haec verba, balance individual rights and state interests in a mannerconsistent with the quasi-suspect classification approach).

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 791 2009-2010

2010) THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 791

There is no precedential obstacle to a conclusion that involuntarily institutionalized individuals with intellectual disabilities (a class narrower than simply "the disabled") are a quasi-suspect class under the Equal Protection Clause, and that their confinement must be subject to heightened scrutiny. Where that confinement is unnecessary, and the person could benefit from community services, institutionalization - to use the test for analysis of quasi-suspect classifications - does not "serve important governmental objectives and [is not] substantially related to achievement of those objectives.,,146

In Board of Trustees of University of Alabama v. Garrett,147 a damages case by disabled state employees, the Court held that the Eleventh Amendment sovereign immunity protects the state from damages liability under Title 1 of the ADA. Relying on Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Center, Inc.,148 the Court concluded that "the disabled" are not a quasi-suspect class under the Fourteenth Amendment. 149 The petitioners in Garrett were a woman with breast cancer and a man with asthma. Cleburne's rejection of a quasi­suspect class approach for "the large and amorphous class of the mentally retarded" was appealing to the Supreme Court in Garrett. The concern was that labeling the disabled a quasi-suspect class might support similar labeling of such generic groups as "the aging, the disabled, the mentally ill, and the infirm.,,150

Disabilities in Equal Protection Cases, 15 PACE L. REv. 621, 663 (1995) (in the ADA, Congress attempted to utilize Carolene Products findings to imply that a "heightened level of scrutiny" should be utilized under the ADA); see also Crowder v. Kitagawa, 842 F. Supp. 1257, 1264 (D. Haw. 1994) (assuming application of strict scrutiny level in ADA cases).

146. Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190, 197 (1976). 147. Bd. ofTrs. ofUniv. of Ala. v. Garrett, 531 U.S. 356, 374 (2001). 148. City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., Inc., 473 U.S. 432 (1985) (invalidating a zoning

regulation which precluded a community home for individuals with retardation). 149. Garrett, 531 U.S. at 367. 150. Id. at 366 (quoting Cleburne, 473 U.S. at 446). One commentator makes a cogent argument that

there is a tension between the Supreme Court's decision in Garrett (declining to find ''the disabled" a quasi-suspect class) and Cleburne/Olmstead. Sean Pevsner, Reasonable Accommodations as Constitutional Obligations, 7 TEx. F. ON C.L. & C.R. 317, 317 (2002) (suggesting that Olmstead and Cleburne in essence, if not in haec verba, balance individual rights 'and state interests in a manner consistent with the quasi-suspect classification approach).

29

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

Cleburne, however, did not simply reject the zoning rule at issue asif it were an irrational commercial regulation. The scrutiny was moreintense than that under the traditional rational basis test. As JudgePosner in dissent observed in a case involving zoning regulation andchurches, "But one has only to read a little further in the Cleburneopinion to realize that the Court was not treating the zoningdiscrimination at issue there as it would have treated a discriminationin the taxation of railroads or the zoning of bowling alleys." 15' JudgePosner wisely urges a deeper reading of the case:

We should follow what the Supreme Court does and not justwhat it says it is doing. The Court rejects a "sliding scale"approach to equal protection in words but occasionally accepts itin deeds. Cleburne instantiates though it does not articulate theproposition that discrimination against sensitive uses is to begiven more careful, realistic, skeptical scrutiny by the courts thandiscrimination against purely commercial activities. 152

Indeed, a separate opinion in Cleburne joined by three of theJustices points out that the majority in fact employs, at the least, a"second order rational basis review," not the traditional deferentialtest:

The Court holds the ordinance invalid on rational-basis groundsand disclaims that anything special, in the form of heightenedscrutiny, is taking place. Yet Cleburne's ordinance surely wouldbe valid under the traditional rational-basis test applicable toeconomic and commercial regulation. In my view, it is importantto articulate, as the Court does not, the facts and principles thatjustify subjecting this zoning ordinance to the searching review-the heightened scrutiny-that actually leads to its invalidation....[T]he Court does not label its handiwork heightened scrutiny,

151. Civil Liberties for Urban Believers v. City of Chicago, 342 F.3d 752, 770 (7th Cir. 2003) (zoningrestrictions on churches).

152. Id. (citing Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 634-35, 116 S.Ct. 1620, 134 L.Ed.2d 855 (1996); cf.Lawrence v. Texas, supra, 123 S.Ct. at 2482).

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 792 2009-2010

792 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW (Vol. 26:3

Cleburne, however, did not simply reject the zoning rule at issue as if it were an irrational commercial regulation. The scrutiny was more intense than that under the traditional rational basis test. As Judge Posner in dissent observed in a case involving zoning regulation and churches, "But one has only to read a little further in the Cleburne opinion to realize that the Court was not treating the zoning discrimination at issue there as it would have treated a discrimination in the taxation of railroads or the zoning of bowling alleys.,,151 Judge Posner wisely urges a deeper reading of the case:

We should follow what the Supreme Court does and not just what it says it is doing. The Court rejects a "sliding scale" approach to equal protection in words but occasionally accepts it in deeds. Cleburne instantiates though it does not articulate the proposition that discrimination against sensitive uses is to be given more careful, realistic, skeptical scrutiny by the courts than discrimination against purely commercial activities. 152

Indeed, a separate opinion in Cleburne joined by three of the Justices points out that the majority in fact employs, at the least, a "second order rational basis review," not the traditional deferential test:

The Court holds the ordinance invalid on rational-basis grounds and disclaims that anything special, in the form of heightened scrutiny, is taking place. Yet Cleburne's ordinance surely would be valid under the traditional rational-basis test applicable to economic and commercial regulation. In my view, it is important to articulate, as the Court does not, the facts and principles that justify subjecting this zoning ordinance to the searching review­the heightened scrutiny-that actually leads to its invalidation .... [T]he Court does not label its handiwork heightened scrutiny,

151. Civil Liberties for Urban Believers v. City of Chicago, 342 F.3d 752, 770 (7th Cir. 2003) (zoning restrictions on churches).

152. Id. (citing Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 634-35, 116 S.Ct. 1620, 134 L.Ed.2d 855 (1996); cf. Lawrence v. Texas, supra, 123 S.Ct. at 2482).

30

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 793

and perhaps the method employed must hereafter be called'second order' rational-basis review rather than 'heightenedscrutiny.' But however labeled, the rational-basis test invokedtoday is most assuredly not the rational-basis test of Williamsonv. Lee Optical of Oklahoma, Inc., 348 U.S. 483, 75 S.Ct. 461, 99

L.Ed. 563 (1955), Allied Stores of Ohio, Inc. v. Bowers, 358 U.S.522, 79 S.Ct. 437, 3 L.Ed.2d 480 (1959), and their progeny. 153

A proper and Cleburne-Garrett consistent rule would define as aquasi-suspect (if not suspect) class those who are institutionalized.These are individuals deprived of liberty, excluded from thecommunity, and recognized as deserving of special protection bothunder general due process principles and the ADA's integrationmandate. 154 This cabined definition answers Cleburne's slipperyslope concern that those in the general populace like the aging andinfirm might be swept into a tight equal protection standard.

Cleburne's disquiet with designating the amorphous class of "thedisabled" a quasi-suspect or suspect class is warranted. "Although itis often expressed in medical or functional terms, "disability" is asocial construct and therefore is assigned different meanings indifferent contexts."' 55 For example, the 2000 United States Censususes a variety of definitions of disability, including sensory disability,physical disability, mental disability, self-care disability, "going-outside-the-home disability," and employment disability.'5 6 TheADA, the Fair Housing Act, the Rehabilitation Act, and lawsdistributing public benefits also have sui generis definitions ofdisability.'57

153. Cleburne, 473 U.S. at 458.154. See sources cited supra notes 150-52.155. Henry Korman, Clash of the Integrationists: The Mismatch of Civil Rights Imperatives in

Supportive Housing for People with Disabilities, 26 ST. LOUIS U. PUB. L. REv. 3, 7 (2007).156. QI WANG, U.S. CENSUS BUREAU, CENSUS 2000 SPECIAL REPORTS, DISABILrrY AND AMERICAN

FAMILIES: 2000, at 2 (2005), available at www.census.gov/prod/2005pubs/censr-23.pdf.157. Korman, supra note 155, at 8-9 (enumerating various disability definitions). The Americans with

Disabilities Act Amendments Act of 2008, Pub. L. No. 110-325, 112 Stat. 3553, 110th Cong., 2d Sess.

(Sept. 25, 2008), is mainly a re-definition of disabilities, as well as a refutation of certain Supreme Court

decisions which narrowed the class of people covered by the ADA.

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 793 2009-2010

2010) THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 793

and perhaps the method employed must hereafter be called 'second order' rational-basis review rather than 'heightened scrutiny.' But however labeled, the rational-basis test invoked today is most assuredly not the rational-basis test of Williamson

v. Lee Optical of Oklahoma, Inc., 348 U.S. 483, 75 S.Ct. 461, 99 L.Ed. 563 (1955), Allied Stores of Ohio, Inc. v. Bowers, 358 U.S. 522,79 S.Ct. 437, 3 L.Ed.2d480 (1959), and their progeny. 153

A proper and Cleburne-Garrett consistent rule would define as a quasi-suspect (if not suspect) class those who are institutionalized. These are individuals deprived of liberty, excluded from the community, and recognized as deserving of special protection both under general due process principles and the ADA's integration mandate. 154 This cabined definition answers Cleburne's slippery slope concern that those in the general populace like the aging and infirm might be swept into a tight equal protection standard.

Cleburne's disquiet with designating the amorphous class of "the disabled" a quasi-suspect or suspect class is warranted. "Although it is often expressed in medical or functional terms, "disability" is a social construct and therefore is assigned different meanings in different contexts.,,155 For example, the 2000 United States Census uses a variety of definitions of disability, including sensory disability, physical disability, mental disability, self-care disability, "going­outside-the-home disability," and employment disability.156 The ADA, the Fair Housing Act, the Rehabilitation Act, and laws distributing public benefits also have sui generis definitions of disability. 157

153. Cleburne, 473 U.S. at 458. 154. See sources cited supra notes ISO-52. ISS. Henry Konnan, Clash of the Integrationists: The Mismatch of Civil Rights Imperatives in

Supportive Housingfor People with Disabilities, 26 ST. loUIS U. PuB. L. REv. 3, 7 (2007). 156. QI WANG, U.S. CENSUS BUREAU, CENSUS 2000 SPECIAL REPORTS, DISABILITY AND AMERICAN

FAMILIES: 2000, at 2 (2005), available at www.census.gov/pr0dJ2005pubs/censr-23.pdf. 157. Konnan, supra note ISS, at 8-9 (enumerating various disability defmitions). The Americans with

Disabilities Act Amendments Act of 2008, Pub. L. No. 110-325, 112 Stat. 3553, I 10th Cong., 2d Sess. (Sept. 25, 2008), is mainly a re-definition of disabilities, as well as a refutation of certain Supreme Court decisions which narrowed the class of people covered by the ADA.

31

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

San Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez,158 theschool financing case, finding no fundamental right to education andno suspect class, does not negate a right to treatment in thecommunity. The Supreme Court made it quite clear in Rodriguez that,had there been an absolute deprivation of education, or had the classbeen defined in more explicit terms, the result could have beendifferent. My argument is that institutionalization is close enough toan absolute deprivation, especially where it is shown that there is nonecessity for the confinement. The limitations of the class definitionproposed here render the discrimination fit for intense FourteenthAmendment scrutiny.

4. Institutionalization Must Be Justified by a Compelling StateInterest

Discriminatory institutionalization is prohibited by the EqualProtection Clause's separate strand which subjects to searchingjudicial review state systems which systematically depriveindividuals of fundamental rights. The Supreme Court has held that"any classification which serves to penalize the exercise of [afundamental] right, unless shown to be necessary to promote acompelling governmental interest, is unconstitutional."' 59 There is nodoubt that there is a constitutional right to be free from unjustifiedinstitutionalization. 160

In Tennessee v. Lane, holding that Title II of the ADA is a validexercise under the Fourteenth Amendment as applied to casesimplicating the fundamental right of access to the courts, theSupreme Court observed that Title II of the ADA was enacted"against a backdrop of pervasive unequal treatment in theadministration of state services and programs, including systematicdeprivations of fundamental rights" and found that Title II addresses

158. Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202, 216 (1982) (minor alien children have right to education); SanAntonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1, 35 (1973) (education is not a fundamental right).

159. Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.S. 618, 634 (1969) (emphasis added); see Skinner v. Oklahoma exrel. Williamson, 316 U.S. 535, 541 (1942) (subjecting to strict scrutiny a law providing for compulsorysterilization of habitual criminals).

160. See sources cited supra notes 102-09.

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 794 2009-2010

794 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 26:3

San Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez,158 the school financing case, finding no fundamental right to education and no suspect class, does not negate a right to treatment in the community. The Supreme Court made it quite clear in Rodriguez that, had there been an absolute deprivation of education, or had the class been defined in more explicit terms, the result could have been different. My argument is that institutionalization is close enough to an absolute deprivation, especially where it is shown that there is no necessity for the confinement. The limitations of the class definition proposed here render the discrimination fit for intense Fourteenth Amendment scrutiny.

4. Institutionalization Must Be Justified by a Compelling State Interest

Discriminatory institutionalization is prohibited by the Equal Protection Clause's separate strand which subjects to searching judicial review sta~e systems which systematically deprive individuals of fundamental rights. The Supreme Court has held that "any classification which serves to penalize the exercise of [a fundamental] right, unless shown to be necessary to promote a compelling governmental interest, is unconstitutional.,,159 There is no doubt that there is a constitutional right to be free from unjustified institutionalization. 160

In Tennessee v. Lane, holding that Title II of the ADA is a valid exercise under the Fourteenth Amendment as applied to cases implicating the fundamental right of access to the courts, the Supreme Court observed that Title II of the ADA was enacted "against a backdrop of pervasive unequal treatment in the administration of state services and programs, including systematic deprivations of fundamental rights" and found that Title II addresses

158. Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202, 216 (1982) (minor alien children have right to education); San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1,35 (1973) (education is not a fundamental right).

159. Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.S. 618, 634 (1969) (emphasis added); see Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rei. Williamson, 316 U.S. 535, 541 (1942) (subjecting to strict scrutiny a law providing for compulsory sterilization of habitual criminals).

160. See sources cited supra notes 102--09.

32

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

20101 THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 795

the deprivation of certain "basic constitutional guarantees,infringements of which are subject to more searching judicialreview." 161 Among the examples cited are cases involvinginstitutional deprivation of liberty. 162 The Lane reasoning applieswith equal force to institutionalization. It is not subject to question,therefore, that needless institutionalization of people with intellectualdisabilities, as proscribed by Olmstead on statutory grounds, is anexercise of state power which constitutionally must be justified by acompelling state interest.

D. Subsidiary Questions

There are two subsidiary questions which are distinct from thethesis of this article but which are often enmeshed with communityservices litigation under the ADA and the Constitution. Thesequestions are alive at the periphery of the central issues discussedabove. They have substance. It is important to acknowledge them.

1. Does the Right to Community Services Protect People Not (Yet)Institutionalized?

This article highlights the constitutional rights of people ininstitutions. There are many other individuals who, living at home orelsewhere, are on the cusp of institutionalization. They may requireservices if institutionalization is to be avoided. Post-Olmstead, theseindividuals are protected by the statute and, I suggest, by theConstitution.

Courts have held that the integration mandate applies equally toindividuals already institutionalized and "at risk" ofinstitutionalization. 163 One court reached this conclusion on accountof the absence of language in the statute and regulations"suggest[ing] that a plaintiff must currently be institutionalized to

161. Tennessee v. Lane, 541 U.S. 509, 510, 522-23 (2004).162. Lane, 541 U.S. at 523-24.163. Fisher v. Okla. Health Care Auth., 335 F.3d 1175, 1181 (10th Cir. 2003); M.A.C. v. Betit, 284 F.

Supp. 2d 1298, 1309 (D. Utah 2003).

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 795 2009-2010

2010) THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 795

the deprivation of certain "basic constitutional guarantees, infringements of which are subject to more searching judicial review.,,161 Among the examples cited are cases involving institutional deprivation of liberty.162 The Lane reasoning applies with equal force to institutionalization. It is not subject to question, therefore, that needless institutionalization of people with intellectual disabilities, as proscribed by Olmstead on statutory grounds, is an exercise of state power which constitutionally must be justified by a compelling state interest.

D. Subsidiary Questions

There are two subsidiary questions which are distinct from the thesis of this article but which are often enmeshed with community services litigation under the ADA and the Constitution. These questions are alive at the periphery of the central issues discussed above. They have substance. It is important to acknowledge them.

1. Does the Right to Community Services Protect People Not (Yet) Institutionalized?

This article highlights the constitutional rights of people in institutions. There are many other individuals who, living at home or elsewhere, are on the cusp of institutionalization. They may require services if institutionalization is to be avoided. Post-Olmstead, these individuals are protected by the statute and, I suggest, by the Constitution.

Courts have held that the integration mandate applies equally to individuals already institutionalized and "at risk" of institutionalization.163 One court reached this conclusion on account of the absence of language in the statute and regulations "suggest[ing] that a plaintiff must currently be institutionalized to

161. Tennessee v. Lane, 541 U.S. 509, 510, 522-23 (2004). 162. Lane, 541 U.S. at 523-24. 163. Fisher v. Okla. Health Care Auth., 335 F.3d 1175, 1181 (i Oth Cir. 2003); M.A.C. v. Betit, 284 F.

Supp.2d 1298, 1309 (D. Utah 2003).

33

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

bring a claim under the ADA or Rehabilitation Act."' 164 The TenthCircuit reasoned that the integration mandate "would be meaninglessif plaintiffs were required to segregate themselves by entering aninstitution before they could challenge an allegedly discriminatorylaw or policy that threatens to force them into segregatedisolation."' 65 Olmstead's proscription of "unjustified isolation" isconsistent with this approach.

There is authority that neither due process nor equal protectionprinciples protect individuals living at home from government budgetcuts resulting in reduction of their services.1 66 However, with ananalysis informed by Olmstead, and a finely-tuned emphasis on thefactual "at risk" question, the result of similar litigation hasappropriately been different. 67

The rationale is straightforward and persuasive: restriction of theclaim to those already institutionalized would force communityplaintiffs to "choose between staying in the community without anyservices or entering an institution in order to receive services."' 168 Oneneed not be at the institution's door to be at risk. The fragility ofone's situation in the community is sufficient.

2. Does the Right to Community Services Protect People Who Are"Voluntarily " Institutionalized?

There is support in the case law for the notion that voluntariness inthe context of institutionalization of people with intellectualdisabilities is an illusory concept, and that therefore there is no basis

164. MA.C., 284 F. Supp. 2d at 1309.165. Fisher, 335 F.3d at 1181. The court also noted that there is nothing in Olmstead which requires

"pre-suit" institutionalization before bringing suit to enforce the ADA's integration requirement. Id.166. E.g., Phila. Police & Fire Ass'n for Handicapped Children, Inc. v. City of Philadelphia, 874 F.2d

156, 163 (3d Cir. 1989).167. Fisher, 335 F.3d at 1184 (three individuals with medical-physical handicaps at risk of nursing

home institutionalization on account of state decision to limit medically-necessary prescriptionmedications to five per month; "plaintiffs' precarious health and finances" triggers "substantial risk" ofharm of institutionalization); M.A.C., 284 F. Supp. 2d at 1309 (waiting list under Medicaid Waiver);Martin v. Taft, 222 F. Supp. 2d 940, 948 (S.D. Ohio 2002) (people with developmental disabilitieseligible to be moved from large private ICF/MR facilities to non-institutional, integrated community-based housing).

168. MA.C., 284 F. Supp. 2d at 1309.

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 796 2009-2010

796 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 26:3

bring a claim under the ADA or Rehabilitation ACt."I64 The Tenth Circuit reasoned that the integration mandate "would be meaningless if plaintiffs were required to segregate themselves by entering an institution before they could challenge an allegedly discriminatory law or policy that threatens to force them into segregated isolation.,,165 Olmstead's proscription of "unjustified isolation" is consistent with this approach.

There is authority that neither due process nor equal protection principles protect individuals living at home from government budget cuts resulting in reduction of their services. 166 However, with an analysis informed by Olmstead, and a finely-tuned emphasis on the factual "at risk" question, the result of similar litigation has appropriately been different. 167

The rationale is straightforward and persuasive: restriction of the claim to those already institutionalized would force community plaintiffs to "choose between staying in the community without any services or entering an institution in order to receive services.,,168 One need not be at the institution's door to be at risk. The fragility of one's situation in the community is sufficient.

2. Does the Right to Community Services Protect People Who Are "Voluntarily" Institutionalized?

There is support in the case law for the notion that voluntariness in the context of institutionalization of people with intellectual disabilities is an illusory concept, and that therefore there is no basis

164. MA.C., 284 F. Supp. 2d at 1309. 165. Fisher, 335 F.3d at 1181. The court also noted that there is nothing in Olmstead which requires

"pre-suit" institutionalization before bringing suit to enforce the ADA's integration requirement Id. 166. E.g., Phila. Police & Fire Ass'n for Handicapped Children, Inc. v. City of Philadelphia, 874 F.2d

156,163 (3dCir. 1989). 167. Fisher, 335 F.3d at 1184 (three individuals with medical-physical handicaps at risk of nursing

home institutionalization on account of state decision to limit medically-necessary prescription medications to five per month; "plaintiffs' precarious health and finances" triggers "substantial risk" of harm of institutionalization); MA.C., 284 F. Supp. 2d at 1309 (waiting list under Medicaid Waiver); Martin v. Taft, 222 F. Supp. 2d 940, 948 (S.D. Ohio 2002) (people with developmental disabilities eligible to be moved from large private ICFIMR facilities to non-institutional, integrated community­based housing).

168. MA.C., 284 F. Supp. 2d at 1309.

34

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

20101 THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 797

for treating them differently from those involuntarily civillycommitted. Residents of state mental retardation facilities havegenerally not consented to their institutionalization. As one courtexplained:

First, the plaintiffs who are residents of the Grafton state schoolhave not, in most cases, voluntarily consented to theirconfinement in any meaningful sense of the word "voluntary."North Dakota Century Code, Chapter 25-04, allows for the

admission of mentally deficient persons upon the application of aparent or guardian without the consent of the person involved.The statute in no way makes the consent of the person concerneda condition of admittance. Further, in the case of plaintiffs whoare severely retarded, informed consent is not even possible. Andeven in the case of the plaintiffs who are capable of givinginformed consent to admission, it may be questioned whether

such consent is voluntary in light of pressures from family andthe high cost and unavailability of alternative care. 169

Cases which superficially take the opposite position, that voluntarysubmission to state custody does not trigger constitutionalprotections, 170 concur: "Indeed, even commitments formally labeled

169. Ass'n for Retarded Citizens of N.D. v. Olson, 561 F. Supp. 473, 484 (D.N.D. 1982). AccordKentucky Ass'n for Retarded Citizens v. Conn, 510 F. Supp. 1233, 1248 (W.D. Ky. 1980); Haldermanv. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 446 F. Supp. 1295, 1311 (E.D. Pa. 1977) ("[T]he notion ofvoluntariness in connection with admission as well as in connection with the right to leave Pennhurst isan illusory concept. Few if any residents now have, nor did they have at the time of admission, anyadequate alternative to their institutionalization."); see, e.g., Clark v. Cohen, 794 F.2d 79, 93 n.7 (3d Cir.1986) (Becker, J., concurring); United States v. Pennsylvania, 832 F. Supp. 122, 124 (E.D. Pa. 1993)("[W]here the initial institutionalization of an individual is made pursuant to a 'voluntary' decision, suchinstitutionalization in its course may become one which necessarily curtails an individual's liberty...."); New York Ass'n for Retarded Children, Inc., v. Rockefeller, 357 F. Supp. 752, 762 (E.D.N.Y.1973); see Phyllis Podolsky Dietz, Note, The Constitutional Right to Treatment in Light of Youngberg v.Romeo, 72 GEO. L.J. 1785, 1791 (1984).

170. Torisky v. Schweiker, 446 F.3d 438, 446 (3d Cir. 2006) ("Thus, a custodial relationshipcreated merely by an individual's voluntary submission to state custody is not a 'deprivation of liberty'sufficient to trigger the protections of Youngberg.").

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 797 2009-2010

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 797

for treating them differently from those involuntarily civilly

committed. Residents of state mental retardation facilities have

generally not consented to their institutionalization. As one court

explained:

First, the plaintiffs who are residents of the Grafton state school have not, in most cases, voluntarily consented to their confinement in any meaningful sense of the word "voluntary." North Dakota Century Code, Chapter 25-04, allows for the admission of mentally deficient persons upon the application of a parent or guardian without the consent of the person involved. The statute in no way makes the consent of the person concerned a condition of admittance. Further, in the case of plaintiffs who are severely retarded, informed consent is not even possible. And even in the case of the plaintiffs who are capable of giving informed consent to admission, it may be questioned whether such consent is voluntary in light of pressures from family and the high cost and unavailability of alternative care.169

Cases which superficially take the opposite position, that voluntary

submission to state custody does not trigger constitutional

protections,170 concur: "Indeed, even commitments formally labeled

169. Ass'n for Retarded Citizens of N.D. v. Olson, 561 F. Supp. 473, 484 (D.N.D. 1982). Accord Kentucky Ass'n for Retarded Citizens v. Conn, 510 F. Supp. 1233, 1248 (W.D. Ky. 1980); Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 446 F. Supp. 1295, 1311 (E.D. Pa. 1977) ("[T]he notion of voluntariness in connection with admission as well as in connection with the right to leave Pennhurst is an illusory concept. Few if any residents now have, nor did they have at the time of admission, any adequate alternative to their institutionalization."); see, e.g., Clark v. Cohen, 794 F.2d 79, 93 n.7 (3d Cir. 1986) (Becker, J., concurring); United States v. Pennsylvania, 832 F. Supp. 122, 124 (E.D. Pa. 1993) ("[W]here the initial institutionalization of an individual is made pursuant to a 'voluntary' decision, such institutionalization in its course may become one which necessarily curtails an individual's liberty ... . "); New York Ass'n for Retarded Children, Inc., v. Rockefeller, 357 F. Supp. 752, 762 (E.D.N.Y. 1973); see Phyllis Podolsky Dietz, Note, The Constitutional Right to Treatment in Light o/Y oungberg v. Romeo, 72 GEO. L.l. 1785,1791 (1984).

170. Torisky v. Schweiker, 446 F.3d 438, 446 (3d Cir. 2006) ("Thus, a custodial relationship created merely by an individual's voluntary submission to state custody is not a 'deprivation of liberty' sufficient to trigger the protections of Youngberg.").

35

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

as 'voluntary' may arguably amount to de facto deprivations ofliberty from their inception."' 17 1

A reasonable framework is that adopted under the ADA in a recentdecision. 172 "The ADA's preference for integrated settings is notconsistent with a procedure in which remaining at STS is the defaultoption for residents. The defendants cannot establish compliance withthe integration mandate by showing that class members neverrequested community placement."' 173

Neither the lack of a request for placement, nor nominal voluntarystatus, should be determinative of whether a person in an institution iseligible to be provided community services.

E. The Benefits of Recognition of the Constitutional Right toCommunity Services

Recognition of the constitutional right to community servicesdescribed in this article would provide an "Olmstead Plus" footingfor analysis of the rights of the institutionalized. There would be areduction in reliance on other statutes. 174 The force inherent inenforcement of civil rights under the Constitution would augment theattention to detail found in the ADA statute and regulations. Certaindefenses would evaporate or be diminished.

States often assert some variation of 11 th Amendment sovereignimmunity in response to claims for expansion of community services

171. Torisky, 446 F.3d at 446 (citing case law and Sarah C. Kellogg, Note, The Due Process Right toa Safe and Humane Environment for Patients in State Custody: The Voluntary/Involuntary Distinction,23 AM. J.L. & MED. 339, 341-43 (1997)).

172. See generally Messier v. Southbury Training Sch., 562 F. Supp. 2d 294, 337 (D. Conn. 2008).173. Id.174. With an Olmstead-strengthened ADA augmented by constitutional rights to community services,

reference to Section 504 of the Rehabilitation Act, long on shaky ground, would be unnecessary in thisregard. A number of courts have held that the denial of community-based habilitation services tomentally disabled individuals does not constitute a viable cause of action under section 504. E.g., Sabov. O'Bannon, 586 F. Supp. 1132, 1137 (E.D. Pa. 1984); see Ky. Ass'n for Retarded Citizens, Inc. v.Conn, 674 F.2d 582, 585 (6th Cir. 1982), cert. denied, 459 U.S. 1041 (1982) (holding that section 504does not include a legislative mandate for deinstitutionalization); see also Manecke v. Sch. Bd., 553 F.Supp. 787, 790 n.4 (M.D. Fla. 1982), aff'd in part, rev'd in part, 762 F.2d 912 (11th Cir. 1985); Garrityv. Gallen, 522 F. Supp. 171, 213 (D.N.H. 1981). See generally Conner v. Branstad, 839 F. Supp. 1346(S.D. Iowa 1993). These holdings, however, do not necessarily exclude application of section 504 toegregious discrimination in a particular individual case.

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 798 2009-2010

798 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW (Vol. 26:3

as 'voluntary' may arguably amount to de facto deprivations of l·b fr h·· . ,,171 I erty om t elr mceptIon.

A reasonable framework is that adopted under the ADA in a recent decision.172 "The ADA's preference for integrated settings is not consistent with a procedure in which remaining at STS is the default option for residents. The defendants cannot establish compliance with the integration mandate by showing that class members never requested community placement.,,173

Neither the lack of a request for placement, nor nominal voluntary status, should be determinative of whether a person in an institution is eligible to be provided community services.

E. The Benefits of Recognition of the Constitutional Right to Community Services

Recognition of the constitutional right to community services described in this article would provide an "Olmstead Plus" footing for analysis of the rights of the institutionalized. There would be a reduction in reliance on other statutes.174 The force inherent in enforcement of civil rights under the Constitution would augment the attention to detail found in the ADA statute and regulations. Certain defenses would evaporate or be diminished.

States often assert some variation of 11 th Amendment sovereign immunity in response to claims for expansion of community services

171. Torisky, 446 F.3d at 446 (citing case law and Sarah C. Kellogg. Note, The Due Process Right to a Safe and Humane Environment for Patients in State Custody: The Voluntary/Involuntary Distinction, 23 AM. 1.L. & MED. 339, 341-43 (l997».

172. See generally Messier v. Southbury Training Sch., 562 F. Supp. 2d 294, 337 (D. Conn. 2008). 173. ld. 174. With an Olmstead-strengthened ADA augmented by constitutional rights to community services,

reference to Section 504 of the Rehabilitation Act, long on shaky ground, would be unnecessary in this regard. A number of courts have held that the denial of community-based habilitation services to mentally disabled individuals does not constitute a viable cause of action under section 504. E.g., Sabo v. O'Bannon, 586 F. Supp. 1132, 1137 (E.D. Pa. 1984); see Ky. Ass'n for Retarded Citizens, Inc. v. Conn, 674 F.2d 582, 585 (6th Cir. 1982), cert. denied, 459 U.S. 1041 (1982) (holding that section 504 does not include a legislative mandate for deinstitutionalization); see also Manecke v. Sch. Bd., 553 F. Supp. 787, 790 n.4 (M.D. Fla. 1982), affd in part, rev'd in part, 762 F.2d 912 (11th Cir. 1985); Garrity v. Gallen, 522 F. Supp. 171,213 (D.N.H. 1981). See generally Conner v. Branstad, 839 F. Supp. 1346 (S.D. Iowa 1993). These holdings, however, do not necessarily exclude application of section 504 to egregious discrimination in a particular individual case.

36

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 799

under the ADA. Regardless of their validity, 175 a constitutional basisfor community services eviscerates the sovereign immunity defense.For legislation enacted under Congress' spending power, the remedyfor violation is generally not a private right of action, but an action bythe federal government to terminate the funds provided to the state. 176

Internal deficiencies in Olmstead would be mitigated. 177 Thefundamental alteration defense would have less traction in the face ofassertion of constitutional rights. 178 An "effectively working plan"would need to satisfy standards for protection of fundamentalconstitutional rights, not simply statutory rights. The absence ofguidance on standard of care in Olmstead is a gap which may now befilled by Youngberg-based integration case law supplemented byOlmstead's "handle and benefit from" community services. Onanother deficiency, the lack of guidance on the future of institutionalcare, one may look to recent case law which establishes that eachresident must at least be considered for placement.

CONCLUSION

Challenges to institutionalization are high profile forunderstandable reasons including, for example, curtailment of liberty,high cost of services, deprivation of rights, a history of mistreatmentand lack of care, and intensity of public and judicial scrutiny.

175. The Supreme Court suggested in dicta that ADA claims which seek prospective injunctive relief

are not barred by the Eleventh Amendment. Bd. of Trs. of the Univ. of Ala. v. Garrett, 531 U.S. 356,374 n.9 (2001).

176. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp. v. Halderman, 451 U.S. 1, 28 (1981); M.A.C. v. Betit, 284 F.Supp. 2d 1298, 1302 (D. Utah 2003) (class action by individuals living in the community on waiting list

for Medicaid Waiver community services; rejecting challenge to cap on number of persons served).177. See Steven Schwartz, The Potential and Risks of Relying on Title I1's Integration Mandate to

Close Segregated Institutions, 26 GA. ST. U. L. REv. (forthcoming 2010) (critique and interpretation ofOlmstead).

178. See generally Olmstead v. J.C., 527 U.S. 581 (1999). Establishment of the suggested rights might

risk an inappropriate importing of the Olmstead limitations into constitutional analysis. The fundamentalalteration defense available under Olmstead has already affected (or infected) due process analysis. InWilliams v. Wasserman, 164 F. Supp. 2d 591, 627 (D. Md. 2001), the court found the fundamental

alteration limitation on the ADA's integration mandate to be acceptable under due process standards as a

basis to "confine patients to mental institutions who do not belong there" if the "state acts reasonably to

implement community placement, without arbitrary or undue delay in light of legitimate budgetconstraints and the competing demands of other disabled citizens."

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 799 2009-2010

2010) THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 799

under the ADA. Regardless of their validity,175 a constitutional basis for community services eviscerates the sovereign immunity defense. For legislation enacted under Congress' spending power, the remedy for violation is generally not a private right of action, but an action by the federal government to terminate the funds provided to the state. 176

Internal deficiencies in Olmstead would be mitigated. l77 The fundamental alteration defense would have less traction in the face of assertion of constitutional rightS. 178 An "effectively working plan" would need to satisfy standards for protection of fundamental constitutional rights, not simply statutory rights. The absence of guidance on standard of care in Olmstead is a gap which may now be filled by Youngberg-based integration case law supplemented by Olmstead's "handle and benefit from" community services. On another deficiency, the lack of guidance on the future of institutional care, one may look to recent case law which establishes that each resident must at least be considered for placement.

CONCLUSION

Challenges to institutionalization are high profile for understandable reasons including, for example, curtailment of liberty, high cost of services, deprivation of rights, a history of mistreatment and lack of care, and intensity of public and judicial scrutiny.

175. The Supreme Court suggested in dicta that ADA claims which seek prospective injunctive relief are not barred by the Eleventh Amendment. Bd. of Trs. of the Univ. of Ala. v. Garrett, 531 U.S. 356, 374 n.9 (2001).

176. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp. v. Halderman, 451 U.S. 1,28 (1981); M.A.C. v. Betit, 284 F. Supp.2d 1298, 1302 (D. Utah 2003) (class action by individuals living in the community on waiting list for Medicaid Waiver community services; rejecting challenge to cap on number of persons served).

177. See Steven Schwartz, The Potential and Risks of Relying on Title II's Integration Mandate to Close Segregated Institutions, 26 GA. ST. U. L. REv. (forthcoming 2010) (critique and interpretation of Olmstead).

178. See generally Olmstead v. lC., 527 U.S. 581 (1999). Establishment of the suggested rights might risk an inappropriate importing of the Olmstead limitations into constitutional analysis. The fundamental alteration defense available under Olmstead has already affected (or infected) due process analysis. In Williams v. Wasserman, 164 F. Supp. 2d 591, 627 (D. Md. 2001), the court found the fundamental alteration limitation on the ADA's integration mandate to be acceptable under due process standards as a basis to "confine patients to mental institutions who do not belong there" if the "state acts reasonably to implement community placement, without arbitrary or undue delay in light of legitimate budget constraints and the competing demands of other disabled citizens."

37

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

In Olmstead, the Supreme Court accepted the Nation's conclusionthat community services are superior to institutional services.Institutional administrators generally agree that, with appropriatesupport, their residents could be well served in the community. Thiswas the case for Pennhurst (decided in 1978) and for SouthburyTraining School (decided 30 years later in 2008). 179 In many ways,this diminishing group is a "Moses generation." Only a smallproportion of people with intellectual disabilities live in institutionsand the number has dropped significantly.' 80 Most of the residentsentered the institution before the explosion of community servicesover the last several decades, and many have not, or will not,experience personally the fruition of that community servicedevelopment.

This is a time to circle back to those constitutional principles onwhich the rights of people with disabilities were recognized decadesago. These principles both support the ADA's integration mandateand mitigate the weaknesses of a purely ADA approach.

The involuntary institutionalization of people with intellectualdisabilities is unconstitutional on due process and equal protectiongrounds where it is unjustified in the sense recognized in Olmstead,that is, when they can "handle and benefit from" community servicesbased on professional assessment. Periodic review of each person'sneed for institutionalization is required.

179. Compare Halderman v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 446 F. Supp. 1295, 1312 (E.D. Pa. 1978)("All the parties in this litigation are in agreement that given appropriate community facilities, all theresidents at Pennhurst, even the most profoundly retarded with multiple handicaps, should be living inthe community."), with Messier v. Southbury Training Sch., 562 F. Supp. 2d 294, 326 (D. Conn. 2008):

The defendants do not seem to dispute that many or all class members could be placed inthe community under the right circumstances. The defendants' witnesses, includingofficials at STS, rejected a so-called "readiness model" and testified that anyone currentlyplaced at STS could live in the community if provided with the appropriate "supports andservices."

180. Between 1990 and 2008, the number of individuals in public mental retardation institutions hasfallen 66% from 84,239 to 35,051. See Lakin supra at note 44. Fifteen years ago, there were anestimated 4,132,878 people in the United States with mental retardation or developmental disabilities.RESEARCH AND TRAINING CENTER ON COMMUNITY LIVING, INSTITUTE ON COMMUNITY INTEGRATION,

UNIVERSITY OF MINNESOTA, PREVALENCE OF MENTAL RETARDATION AND/OR DEVELOPMENTAL

DISABILITIES: ANALYSIS OF THE 1994/1995 NHIS-D (2000), available at http://rtc.umn.edu/docs/dddb2-I .pdf. At roughly the same time (1999), there were 49,105 people in public institutions. See Lakin et al.,supra note 44, at 406.

[Vol. 26:3

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 800 2009-2010

800 GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 26:3

In Olmstead, the Supreme Court accepted the Nation's conclusion that community services are superior to institutional services. Institutional administrators generally agree that, with appropriate support, their residents could be well served in the community. This was the case for Pennhurst (decided in 1978) and for Southbury Training School (decided 30 years later in 2008).179 In many ways, this diminishing group is a "Moses generation." Only a small proportion of people with intellectual disabilities live in institutions and the number has dropped significantly.180 Most of the residents entered the institution before the explosion of community services over the last several decades, and many have not, or will not, experience personally the fruition of that community service development.

This is a time to circle back to those constitutional principles on which the rights of people with disabilities were recognized decades ago. These principles both support the ADA's integration mandate and mitigate the weaknesses of a purely ADA approach.

The involuntary institutionalization of people with intellectual disabilities is unconstitutional on due process and equal protection grounds where it is unjustified in the sense recognized in Olmstead, that is, when they can "handle and benefit from" community services based on professional assessment. Periodic review of each person's need for institutionalization is required.

179. Compare Haldennan v. Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp., 446 F. Supp. 1295, 1312 (E.D. Pa. 1978) ("All the parties in this litigation are in agreement that given appropriate community facilities, all the residents at Pennhurst, even the most profoundly retarded with multiple handicaps, should be living in the community."), with Messier v. Southbury Training Sch., 562 F. Supp. 2d 294, 326 (D. Conn. 2008):

The defendants do not seem to dispute that many or all class members could be placed in the community under the right circumstances. The defendants' witnesses, including officials at STS, rejected a so-called "readiness model" and testified that anyone currently placed at STS could live in the community if provided with the appropriate "supports and services."

180. Between 1990 and 2008, the number of individuals in public mental retardation institutions has fallen 66% from 84,239 to 35,05\. See Lakin supra at note 44. Fifteen years ago, there were an estimated 4,132,878 people in the United States with mental retardation or developmental disabilities. REsEARCH AND TRAINING CENTER ON COMMUNITY LNING, INSTmITE ON COMMUNITY INTEGRATION, UNNERSITY OF MINNESOTA, PREVALENCE OF MENTAL RETARDATION AND/OR DEVELOPMENTAL DISABILITIES; ANALYSIS OF THE 1994/1995 NHlS-D (2000), available at http;lIrtc.urnn.eduldocsldddb2-l.pdf. At roughly the same time (1999), there were 49,105 people in public institutions. See Lakin et aI., supra note 44, at 406.

38

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8

20101 THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 801

Restoration of the constitutional dimension to the conversationencourages reasoned discussion of both the opportunities and thedeficits in the Olmstead statutory approach. Recognition of theconstitutional right to community services is an opening to movefurther toward an end to unjustified institutionalization.

Both the Constitution and the Americans with Disabilities Actadvance the integration of people with disabilities in our society. Theconstitutional scholar Jacobus tenBroek urged "integrationalism." He"called for the full and equal participation in society of persons withdisabilities.",181 "Without that right, that policy, that world, it is notliving.'

' 82

181. Jacobus tenBroek, The Right to Live in the World: The Disabled in the Law of Torts, 54 CAL. L.REV. 841, 843 (1966) (defining the policy of integrationism as "a policy entitling the disabled to fullparticipation in the life of the community and encouraging and enabling them to do so .... ).

182. Id. at 918, quoted in Peter Blanck, The Right to Live in the World: Disability Yesterday, Today,and Tomorrow, 13 TEX. J. C.L. & C.R. 367, 401 (2008).

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 801 2009-2010

2010] THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO COMMUNITY SERVICES 801

Restoration of the constitutional dimension to the conversation encourages reasoned discussion of both the opportunities and the deficits in the Olmstead statutory approach. Recognition of the constitutional right to community services is an opening to move further toward an end to unjustified institutionalization.

Both the Constitution and the Americans with Disabilities Act advance the integration of people with disabilities in our society. The constitutional scholar Jacobus tenBroek urged "integrationalism." He "called for the full and equal participation in society of persons with disabilities.,,181 "Without that right, that policy, that world, it is not living." I 82

181. Jacobus tenBroek, The Right to Live in the World: The Disabled in the Law of Torts, 54 CAL. L. REv. 841, 843 (1966) (defining the policy of integrationism as "a policy entitling the disabled to full participation in the life of the community and encouraging and enabling them to do so .... ").

182. Id. at 918, quoted in Peter Blanck, The Right to Live in the World: Disability Yesterday, Today, and Tomorrow, 13 TEx. J. C.L. & C.R. 367,401 (2008).

39

Fergleger: The Constitutional Right to Community Services

Published by Reading Room, 2010

HeinOnline -- 26 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 802 2009-201040

Georgia State University Law Review, Vol. 26, Iss. 3 [2010], Art. 8

https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/gsulr/vol26/iss3/8