The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

download The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

of 14

Transcript of The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    1/14

    1

    The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    Matt Bower

    Postdoctoral Researcher

    Ruhr-Universitt Bochum

    Institut fr Philosophie II

    GA 3/151

    Universittsstr. 150

    [email protected]

    Abstract: No commentator on Husserls later philosophy can present it without at some point

    touching on his theory of affection. While he had formulated the rudiments of the theory by

    1905, it does not feature prominently in early works like Ideas I. It is not until sometimebetween 1918 and 1920 that Husserl discovers its deep significance. When he comes to that

    realization, affection takes a life of its own, revolutionizing his phenomenology. I begin by

    describing the phenomenon of affection as understood by Husserl, piecing together both very

    early and late manuscripts to present the phenomenon in more complexity than is typically done.

    I show how the phenomenon of affection maps onto the foreground/background and

    intention/fulfillment structures of intentionality. I then move to discuss how that phenomenon

    revolutionizes Husserls philosophy. In his later work, he recasts affection as a ubiquitous

    feature of conscious life, a privileged status it has thanks to its function as a precondition for

    other forms of phenomenality. On the basis of that insight, he formulates a novel theory of the

    unity of conscious life rooted in affection. The unity of conscious life is explained by Husserl interms of his idea of a universal teleology. The latter, I show, is underwritten by the affective

    intentionality of instincts, which have the remarkable property of operating independently from

    objectivating intentionality.

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    2/14

    Bower | The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    2

    The nature of affective intentionality

    No commentator on Husserls later philosophy can present it without at some point

    touching on his theory of affection. While he had formulated the rudiments of the theory by

    1905, it does not feature prominently in early works like Ideas I. It is not until sometime

    between 1918 and 1920 that Husserl discovers its deep significance. When he comes to that

    realization, affection takes a life of its own, revolutionizing his phenomenology. After giving a

    summary account of what affection is for Husserl, I will discuss just how affection revolutionizes

    Husserls philosophy. Recasting affection as a ubiquitous feature of conscious life allows him to

    formulate a novel theory of the unity of conscious life rooted in affection and propose a solution

    to a special phenomenological version of the paradox of learning. Affection now appears

    everywhere in conscious life, holding it together and even giving meaning to its very beginning.

    Affection, as Husserl understands it is distinct from emotion and feeling. Emotions or

    feelings, such as pride or envy, are feelings about something (Goldie 2000, 16-17). More

    specifically, they are means of evaluating something, whether in the form of nondiscursively

    seeing something to be valuable (e.g., enjoying the pleasant character of a meal) or of

    discursively making an evaluative judgment about something (e.g., making the claim that the

    meal is a good meal). Those domains of mental life are of interest to Husserl (seeHua XXVIII

    andHua XXXVII), but affection is a distinct, sui generis form of intentionality (Husserl 1973, 85,

    Hua XXXI, 8-9/281). It has to do with how experience comes about and runs its course rather

    than what the experience is of. It accounts for our advertence (Zuwendung) to things and,

    moreover, sustains and modulates that advertence. These are the primary traits that we will have

    to consider in sketching Husserls phenomenological treatment of affection.

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    3/14

    Bower | The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    3

    Husserls theory of affection is inspired by the work of Carl Stumpf. Stumpf speaks of a

    theoretical interest, which he defines as a pleasure in noticing (Lust am Bemerken) (Hua

    XXXVIII, 103). Husserls advance over Stumpfs theory lies in his meticulous integration of the

    theory of affection into his general theory of intentionality (Hua XXXVIII, 160). There are two

    interrelated axes of intentionality into which affection is delicately woven. First, every

    intentional act has its background, context, or situation. An intentional act has its focal core,

    what is under immediate consideration, and its unthematic periphery. Following anothers

    argument in a conversation, for instance, involves focusing on particular phrases and statements,

    while retaining in the background the preceding statements that continue to play a marginal role

    in making sense of what currently dominates ones interest. Affection likewise admits of a

    distinction paralleling this foreground/background distinction.

    Affection and foreground/background

    There is an affective experience peculiar to what actually catches ones attention. It is an

    excitement or appeal (Reiz) to embark upon or continue some manner of responding to

    something (Hua XI, 148-149/196). It is the feeling that attends any particular transaction with

    the world. Consider, for instance, the feeling of shock and surprise spurring the jolt of interest

    with its corresponding shift of attention from ones work in the kitchen while cooking to the

    sounding of a smoke detector. Subtler affective undercurrents similarly mediate our involvement

    with things in more prosaic ways. It is with a certain feeling of engagement, however relaxed,

    that one listens to a piece of music or lecture.

    Alongside the prominent foreground affection is the sort of affection that pertains to what

    is of proximate and gradually decreasing interest (Hua Mat VIII, 340,Hua XXXIX, 42). Husserl

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    4/14

    Bower | The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    4

    calls all the affective shades besides the primary subject of ones attention tendencies (Hua XI,

    50-51/90-91). This turn of phrase is somewhat misleading. He maintains that tendencies do

    actually affect one despite how term tendency connotes something merely dispositional and

    not occurent. The two are conflated in Husserls use of the term.1

    A tendency actually affects

    one, and it simultaneously refers to further potential affective experiences (Hua XI, 167/216,Hua

    Mat VII, 191). It is the affective hold that a possible intentional act has on one, ones interest in

    that intentional act.

    The phases of an action currently underway still bear affectively on the present phase,

    comprising its affective context, just as the intentional content bound up with the preceding

    phases remain pertinent in a different respect to the action. Consider a transition to pianissimo

    in a piece of music (Hua XI, 153/200) or a suspenseful silence in a movie. In these cases one is

    confronted with something that would otherwise lack interest (very softly played notes, a scene

    with dead silence or perfect stillness) but for the fact that its affective circumstances, the

    lingering feeling of what has just taken place, live on and animate it. Similarly, future

    possibilities germane to the action also have an affective allure. One is drawn into one direction

    rather than another. And even beyond past or future phases of a present undertaking, there is a

    peculiar affection pertaining to alternative competing undertakings, an allure to take part in them,

    although perhaps not compelling enough to change ones present course.

    All of these forms of affection together make up an affective vantage point, an affective

    perspective on ones present situation, possessing a prominent foreground and a background with

    distinct affective contours (the past, the future, the possible). As the preceding remarks indicate,

    1Husserl is of the somewhat non-standard view that dispositions are not merely inferred from their effects, but are

    available to consciousness in their effects.

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    5/14

    Bower | The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    5

    the affective perspective is not necessarily autonomous, but is integrated with, for instance, the

    perspective of an agent undertaking an action and the moments of that action.

    Affection and intention/fulfillment

    The second sense in which affection is interwoven with other forms of intentionality is

    more dynamic. A synchronic snapshot of affection reveals a complex affective vantage point

    that is structurally analogous to the vantage points of diverse forms of intentionality. A

    diachronic (although not yet genetic (Hua XVII, 276/315, Welton 2000, 218-219)) analysis

    takes into account in addition the modifications of this affective vantage point as an intention

    passes from a mere (empty) intention to a fulfilled one, a distinction familiar from the Logical

    Investigations.

    Intention and fulfillment together form a whole, an act of identification. The intention

    singles some item out and makes a supposition about it. This spurs an act, a synthesis leading,

    ideally, toward fulfillment, the culmination of that synthesis being an intuitive experience, a

    confirmation of the initial supposition. For instance, I might read about the awe of being in the

    presence of some great monument or natural formation (e.g., the Grand Canyon), and consider

    what that would be like for me. The supposition sets up a potential chain of experiences

    terminating (if all goes well) in an experience of fulfillment, where the supposition is confirmed,

    i.e., where I confront the item or state of affairs in the flesh, perceptually. This

    intention/fulfillment distinction is a feature of every form of intentionality governed by norms

    (i.e., epistemic, axiological, practical).

    Parallel to this transition from intention to fulfillment there is a determinate series of

    affective states. At one end, there is a feeling of tension related to the pertinent supposition, and,

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    6/14

    Bower | The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    6

    at the other, there is a feeling of resolution corresponding to the fulfillment (Hua XXXVIII, 104-

    105).2 These dynamics give a much clearer picture of the phenomenon in question. The feeling

    of affection, with its hedonic character, is a class including experiences of unease, tension,

    relaxation, satisfaction, dissatisfaction, strain, exertion, release, and the like.3

    Thefunction of affection is to condition or motivate the concatenation of intention and

    fulfillment. For instance, I might decide to take a trip to see for myself some great monument or

    natural formation Ive heard about. My supposition creates a tension in me, perhaps the unease

    of curiosity. When I am actually face to face with it, then I am, certainly among other things,

    relieved of my tensed expectations, whether in the satisfaction of enjoyment or the letdown of

    frustration. It is also a familiar device in television to exploit the affective states of viewers by

    creating tension at the end of a program (a cliffhanger) so that the viewer is inclined to tune in

    for the next episode for some resolution. Essentially the same thing takes place in the ordinary

    case of perceptual experience or logical argumentation, to mention Husserls standard examples

    (Hua XXXVIII, 112-114). The feelings present in all these instances do not merely accompany

    the event as it unfolds. They motivate the sequence, they are its lifeblood (Hua X, 146/150).4

    The affective turn

    While Husserl wavered at least until the early 1920s, he eventual comes to the conclusion

    that the form of intentionality just described, affection, is a universal feature of intentionality in

    all its varieties. In the notes for his 1904/1905 lectures on perception and attention, Husserl,

    2In his earliest manuscripts ranging from 1893 to 1906 (in Hua XXXVIII) Husserl hesitates to call these feelings, but

    in later texts (for instance, Husserl 1973, 20 and Hua XXXI, 16-17/189) he clearly resolves to understand them as

    feelings or affective states.3Husserl does not take these to be feelings of the body, as one might naturally suppose ( la William James). He

    views them solely in terms of their function in the economy of lived-experience. A feeling of tension is localizable,

    but it is a feeling whose primary function is quite different from informing one of the ongoings of ones body.4

    In this, Humes legacy is palpable, undoubtedly mediated by Brentano.

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    7/14

    Bower | The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    7

    following the lead of Carl Stumpt and Anton Marty (Hua X, 145-156/149-150,Dwyer 2007, 87-

    88), without hesitation claims that an intentional act fixing reference to some content is

    necessarily distinct from and precedes any affective act (Gemtsakt) of interest (Hua XXXVIII,

    117-118). A decade and a half later, we find Husserl wrestling with himself on the issue in the

    lectures on passive synthesis from the early 1920s (Hua XI, 34). But, as Mensch (2010, 216-

    219) and Steinbock (1995, 153-156) persuasively argue, in that text Husserl ultimately comes

    down in favor of the view that affection is necessary for any intentional act whatsoever. By the

    time of the C-Manuskripte, Husserl explicitly disavows his earlier stance as expressed in a

    manuscript from 1917/1918 collected in the Bernauer Manuskripte where he argues that

    affection cannot be a necessary feature of intentional acts generally (Hua XXXXIII, 285). Now in

    the C-Manuskripte he states categorically that every lived experience has both an affective

    form and an intentional content (a Was)(Hua Mat VIII, 189; 252).

    This claim about the universality of affection displays the centrality of that phenomenon for

    Husserls later philosophy. We can get some indirect insight into Husserls rationale for that by

    considering his appeal to affection to account for the unity of conscious life. Around the same

    time as Husserl alters his view on affection he also alters his view on the ego. InIdeas Ihe

    maintains that phenomenologically we are only justified in a very minimal, formal conception of

    subjectivity as an executor of intentional acts possessing no determinate properties itself and

    only evidenced in the intentional acts it carries out (Hua III, 80). Shortly after writingIdeas I,

    in the manuscripts ultimately published asIdeas II, Husserl asserts that self-reflection can reveal

    properties belonging to the subject, namely, its dispositions. All of the habits, convictions,

    abilities, and character traits one can acquire as well as natural temperament or any other non-

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    8/14

    Bower | The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    8

    acquired idiosyncrasies are genuine, phenomenologically describable features of who one is

    (Hua IV, 57, 59-60). One is in principle a pure ego and in fact a personal ego.

    These considerations spur the much-discussed (Donohoe 2004, 30-36, Welton 2000, 228-

    237, Steinbock 1995, 33-37) turn of Husserls focus to the concreteness of life, a concreteness

    that bespeaks not only the complex character one inevitably has as a person, but also the unity of

    conscious life in terms of its various traits. The realization that subjectivity has content allows

    him to think of the unity of consciousness as a history, since ones subjective constitution

    refers implicitly to ones history. A persons idiosyncrasies, habits, convictions, and so on are

    the relatively stable characters that give unity to a mass of disparate experiences undergone or

    actions undertaken. Husserl displays his fundamentally post-Kantian philosophical orientation in

    appealing to the phenomenon of affection to give his own phenomenological twist to the idea of

    the unity of apperception.

    The affective unity of conscious experience

    Kant supposes, roughly, that the possible addition of an I think to any mental event or

    series of mental events is the basis for their continuity. In other words, the unity of experience is

    due to the synthetic activity of a cognitive agent whose a priori forms of intuition and concepts

    are applied to the material of experience to give it coherence. The unity is a result of that

    activity. On Husserls view, the unity of experience is also a matter of synthesis, but in two

    forms, namely, active and passive (Hua IV, 56,Hua I, 38). These are not heterogeneous

    factors, as they both have the common form of what Husserl calls motivation. The higher-order

    unifying principle depends essentially on a lower passive form of motivation that is ubiquitous in

    a way that active motivation could never be (Hua XXXI, 49, Hua Mat VIII, 183). It is prima

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    9/14

    Bower | The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    9

    facie implausible and phenomenologically false to say that all experience depends on deliberate,

    rational activity for its unity.

    The more likely candidate is passive synthesis, whose motive force is affection. Recalling

    the analysis of affection that this paper began with, it should not be difficult to see how

    intimately related this phenomenon is to the problem of the unity of conscious experience. This

    relationship is especially evident in the way that affection fits into and spurs on the flow of

    conscious experience in terms of intention and fulfillment. It is not incidental that affection

    parallels the intention/fulfillment structure of intentionality as though it could be sloughed off

    and done without at any time. The universality of affection in conscious life is, in fact, largely

    due to its motivational relation, driving the transition from intention to fulfillment and then

    restlessly stirring up yet further intentions calling out for fulfillment.

    This last remark brings us closer to a new plane of analysis concerning the phenomenon of

    affection. For affection to have explanatory power for the whole of conscious life and its

    phenomenal unity, it must concern more than this or that conscious experience, and it must even

    have significance beyond the simple repeated arousal of new conscious experiences just

    mentioned. Following this line of thought, Husserl comes upon what he refers to as universal

    teleology (Hua XV, Nos. 22, 34, Hua Mat VIII, 260). In speaking of a universal teleology,

    Husserl intends to advance a theory about the unity of conscious life in terms of its overarching

    structure.

    In a certain way, this universal teleology is like the intention/fulfillment transition writ

    large, set over the course of a life (although, in truth, extending as well to intersubjective and

    generative life (Hua XV, 381)). Life begins as an empty intention, and aims at a kind of grand

    fulfillment, the perhaps unattainable ideal of becoming a fully rational, responsible person.

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    10/14

    Bower | The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    10

    While, naturally much more could and must be said to concretize a notion that is supposed to

    give form to a whole life, I only want to emphasize here the role affection plays within universal

    teleology. Affection appears in this context in the form of instinct.5

    Instinct, as Husserl

    understands it, is a way of elaborating and clarifying affective intentionality.

    Instinct is, in its raw form, affection unburdened by objective intentionality. I mean by the

    expression objective intentionality any intentional experience or moment thereof that targets

    transcendent reality in such a way that the subject is conscious of the acts goal and the

    appropriate way of achieving that goal. An intentional act exhibits objective intentionality by

    virtue of its focal directedness, whereby it grasps the thing itself, and its horizonal directedness

    to other aspects of the object or state of affairs. Consider an illustration. When one gets in the

    car to drive somewhere, one has in mind where one wants to go, and also the better or worse

    ways of getting there.

    In describing the parallelism of affection and typical intentional acts above in terms of

    foreground/background and intention/fulfillment, I left aside the possible decoupling of the

    parallel intentionalities, which we can now call the affective and the objective dimensions of

    intentionality. Now, given the universality of affective intentionality, there is no possibility for

    an autonomously operating objective intentionality. It would be without motivation, without its

    very life-blood. But that does not yet rule out the possible independent operation of affective

    intentionality, which is exactly what we are now considering.

    This possibility is actual in raw instinct. Husserl captures this idea in his repeated

    description of instinct as blind, a term which he glosses by saying instincts lack the

    presentation of a goal (Hua Mat VIII, 225-226, 326-327; Hua XV, 329-330, 511, 593). In

    instinct, one finds oneself caught up in an act, drawn into some engagement with the world and,

    5On the notion of instinct in Husserl, see Lee (1992), Khn (1998), and Mensch (2010).

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    11/14

    Bower | The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    11

    of course, with other people (Hua XIII, 107; Hua XIV, 165-166, 178-179; Hua XV, 593, 599,

    601-602, 611-612; Hua XXXIX, 476, 582).6 Importantly, this blind affective intentionality

    differs from the so-called empty presentation of protentional consciousness (Hua XIV, 333-

    335, Hua XXXIX, 317-318). The latter may be empty, but only relatively so, since it still

    predelineates in at least a very general way the future course of experience, namely, in terms of

    the terminus of the intentional act and the phases remaining for its full execution. Raw instinct

    lacks even the slightest hint of predelineation.7

    The possibility and reality of independent affective intentionality is not only an interesting

    feature of the phenomenon of affection, it is crucial for understanding the unfolding of universal

    teleology. The indeterminacy of the instinctive affection pertains both to particular episodes, but

    also to a long-term trajectory of conscious life. That is, one may on the one hand find oneself, by

    instinct, interested in, say, food when one is hungry. But one can also be driven to more

    sophisticated forms of an experience or even to new dimensions of conscious life. This may

    happen, for instance, in a personal crisis, where one finds oneself called to lead a life of ethical

    self-responsibility (Hua XV, 379).

    Indeed, Husserl conceives of the major twists and turns of life as being guided by instinct,

    which is thus what pushes us to develop ever new abilities (Hua XXXIX483). That means that

    every novel way of experiencing the world, every new form of constitution, is first instigated by

    a novel affection (Hua Mat VIII, 324). These events, the emergence of new dimensions of

    conscious life, are not ruptures with instinct, but its transformation, so that Husserl will even say

    6For discussion of intersubjective instincts, see Yamaguchi (1982), Iribarne (1994), and Khn (1998).

    7Husserl makes it exceedingly clear (Hua XIV, 335) that this is his position by contrasting it with the vulgar

    nativism of Schelers postulation of innate representations [Vorstellungen,] which he rejects as the contrary of a

    genuine phenomenological theory. At issue is how to account for the intentional constitution of this basement level

    of conscious life in its earliest moments. As Husserl sees it, his own view of the instincts tries to account for this

    constitution, whereas Scheler takes the existence of innate representations as a given and only subsequently

    introduces intentionality into the picture.

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    12/14

    Bower | The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    12

    that instinct is immortal (Hua Mat VIII, 258). Even when autonomous instinct gives way to

    intentional acts and the normative strictures of full-fledged rationality, it is still at bottom the

    instinct that governs and sustains ones interest. If one goes from being a culinary philistine to

    being an epicure, the original impulse is sustained. It simply finds a new way of being

    conducted, namely, deliberately, with a firmer normative grip on the activity.

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    13/14

    Bower | The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    13

    References

    Bejarano, J. Vargas (2006). Phnomenologie des Willens: Seine Struktur, sein Ursprung und

    seine Funktion in Husserls Denken. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.

    Donahoe, J. (2004). Husserl on Ethics and Intersubjectivity: From Static to Genetic

    Phenomenology. Amherst, NY: Humanity Books.

    Dwyer, D. (2007). Husserls appropriation of the psychological concepts of apperception and

    attention. Husserl Studies. Vol. 23, 2. 83-118.

    Goldie, P. (2000). The Emotions: A Philosophical Account. New York: Oxford University

    Press.

    Hua I. Husserl, E. Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology. D. Cairns

    (Trans.). Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1999.

    Hua III. Husserl, E. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological

    Philosophy, First Book. F. Kersten (Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers,1983.

    Hua IV. Husserl, E. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological

    Philosophy, Second Book. R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer (Trans.). Dordrecht, the

    Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989

    Hua XI. Husserl, E. Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis: Lectures on

    Transcendental Logic. A. Steinbock (Trans.). Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2001.

    Hua XV. Husserl, E. Zur Phnomanologie der Intersubjektivitt: Texte aus dem Nachlass,

    Dritter Teil (1929-1935). I. Kern (Ed.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973.

    Hua XVII. Husserl, E. Formal and Transcendental Logic. D. Cairns (Trans.). The Hague:

    Martinus Nijhoff, 1969.

    Hua XXVIII. Husserl, E. Vorlesungen ber Ethik und Wertlehre (1908-1914). Ullrich Melle

    (Ed.). The Hague: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1988.

    Hua XXXI. Husserl, E. Aktive Synthesen: Aus der Vorlesung Transzendentale Logik 1920/21.

    R. Breeur (Ed.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2000.

    Hua XXXIII. Husserl, E. Die Bernauer Manuskripte ber das Zeitbewusstsein (1917/18). R.

    Bernet and D. Lohmar (Eds.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2001.

    Hua XXXVII. Husserl, Edmund. Einleitung in der Ethik: Vorlesungen Sommersemester 1920und 1924. H. Peucker (Ed.). Dordrecht: Springer, 2004.

    Hua XXXVIII. Husserl, E. Wahrnehmung und Aufmerksamkeit: Texte aus dem Nachlass (1893-

    1912). T. Vongehr and R. Giuliani (Eds.). Dordrecht: Springer, 2004.

  • 7/27/2019 The Affective Revolution in Husserls Phenomenology

    14/14

    Bower | The affective revolution in Husserls phenomenology

    14

    Hua XXXIX. Husserl, E. Die Lebenswelt: Auslegungen der vorgegebenen Welt und ihrer

    Konstitution, Texte aus dem Nachlass (1916-1937). R. Sowa (Ed.). Dordrecht: Springer,

    2008.

    Hua Mat VIII. Husserl, E. . Spte Texte ber Zeitkonstitution (1929-1934): Die C-Manuskripte.

    D. Lohmar (Ed.). Dordrecht: Springer, 2006.Husserl, E. (1973). Experience and Judgment:Investigations in a Genealogy of Logic. J. S.

    Churchill, K. Ameriks and L. Eley (Trans.). Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Iribarne, J. (1994). Husserls Theorie der Intersubjektivitt. Munich: Karl Alber Publishing.

    Khn, R. (1998). Husserls Begriff der Passivitt. Munich: Karl Alber Publishing.

    Lohmar, D. (2003). Husserls Type and Kants Schemata. In The New Husserl: A Critical

    Reader(93-124). D. Welton (Ed.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Mensch, J. (2010). Husserls Account of Our Consciousness of Time. Milwaukee: Marquette

    University Press.Steinbock, A. (1995). Home and Beyond: Generative Phenomenology after Husserl. Evanston,

    IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Welton, D. (2000). The Other Husserl: The Horizons of Transcendental Phenomenology.

    Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Yamaguchi, I. (1982). Passive Synthesis und Intersubjektivitt bei Edmund Husserl. The

    Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.