Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

download Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

of 29

Transcript of Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    1/29

    http://stx.sagepub.com/Sociological Theory

    http://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326Theonline version of this article can be found at:

    DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9558.2010.01378.x

    2010 28: 326Sociological TheoryMarc Garcelon

    The Missing Key: Institutions, Networks, and the Project of Neoclassical Sociology

    Published by:

    http://www.sagepublications.com

    On behalf of:

    American Sociological Association

    can be found at:Sociological TheoryAdditional services and information for

    http://stx.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts:

    http://stx.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions:

    http://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326.refs.htmlCitations:

    What is This?

    - Sep 1, 2010Version of Record>>

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://www.asanet.org/http://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326http://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326http://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326http://stx.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://www.sagepublications.com/http://www.sagepublications.com/http://www.asanet.org/http://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326.full.pdfhttp://stx.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326.full.pdfhttp://stx.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://stx.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326.refs.htmlhttp://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326.refs.htmlhttp://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326.full.pdfhttp://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326.full.pdfhttp://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326.full.pdfhttp://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326.full.pdfhttp://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326.refs.htmlhttp://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326.refs.htmlhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://stx.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://stx.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://stx.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://stx.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://www.asanet.org/http://www.asanet.org/http://www.sagepublications.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/content/28/3/326http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    2/29

    The Missing Key: Institutions, Networks, and the Project

    of Neoclassical Sociology*

    MARC GARCELON

    Yeshiva University

    The diversity of contemporary capitalisms underscores the need to supplant the

    amorphous concept of structure with more precise concepts, particularly institutions

    and networks. All institutions entail both embodied and relational aspects. Insti-

    tutions are relational insofar as they map obligatory patterns of getting by and

    getting alonginstitutional ordersthat steer stable social fields over time. In-

    stitutions are simultaneously embodied as institutional paradigms, part of a larger

    bodily agency Pierre Bourdieu called habitus. Institutions are in turn tightly cou-

    pled to networks between various people based on, but not reducible to, strategic

    interests. Yet social interaction sometimes exceeds institutional boundaries, giving

    rise to disjunctive fields and underscoring the prominence of institutional failures in

    the unfolding of antagonistic relations such as warfare. Such disjunctive fields can

    be tracked in relation to some transnational networks at the global level without

    assuming developmental convergence. This last point underscores the meaning of

    neoclassical sociology, which eschews assumptions of developmental convergence at

    the global level.

    Institution stands among the most widely used concepts in sociology today, yet para-

    doxically remains underdeveloped. Lack of clarity conceptualizing institutions closely

    links with chronic overburdening of the concept of structure. Overcoming this theo-retical Gordian knot requires integrating a reconstructed concept of institution with

    network theory in ways useful for empirical analysis. Such a conceptual reframing

    in turn enables a regionally specific mapping of the diversity of contemporary capi-

    talisms, socialisms, democracies, civil societies, authoritarianisms, imperi-

    alisms, and aspects of premodern societiespeasantries, kinship groups, mythical

    and religious beliefs, and so onthat continue in todays global order without be-

    ing reducible to effects of modern tendencies. For the diversity of the contemporary

    worldand by extension, its institutions and networkshas confounded earlier mod-

    ernist expectations of developmental convergence despite real degrees of global-scale

    enmeshment of aspects of regional human societies with one another and their co-evolutionary developmental history since the emergence of a world-scale economy in

    the 1500s and 1600s. Indeed, development and convergence are not synonyms. Take

    the failure of capitalist-style economic policies to generate representative democracy

    in China over the last 30 years, or the failure of the Washington consensusthe

    prescriptive model of neoliberal development adopted widely in the developing world

    in return for foreign aid and loans from the United States, its allies, the World Bank

    Address correspondence to: Marc Garcelon, Department of Sociology, Yeshiva University, 500 W.185th St., New York, NY 10033. Tel: 212-960-5400 x6982; E-mail: [email protected]. I would like to

    thank Robert N. Bellah, Jim Stockinger, commentators from Sociological Theory, the Politics and ProtestWorkshop at the CUNY Graduate Center in New York, and an ASA Annual Meeting for helpfulsuggestions on earlier versions of this article.

    Sociological Theory 28:3 September 2010C 2010 American Sociological Association. 1430 K Street NW, Washington, DC 20005

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    3/29

    THE MISSING KEY 327

    and the International Monetary Fund for nearly 30 yearsto effect the envisioned

    patterns of economic growth in developing nations adopting it since the early 1980s.

    Such examples underscore paradoxes and contradictions behind assumptions of

    developmental convergence across different states in the contemporary global order.

    Avoiding such assumptions entails avoiding conflation of educated guesses about the

    future direction of social change with sociological hypotheses per se. Two theoreticalmoves guard against such conflation. The first involves rethinking what a sociological

    paradigm might look like given recognition of the historical irreducibility of social

    development. The second involves some rethinking of the most general concepts

    used in sociology, together with their articulation in models of social reproduction,

    incremental change, and institutional collapse on the level of states.

    In the first subsection below, I develop alternatives to action/structure binaries

    through refinement and synthesis of the concepts of institutions, fields, habitus, legit-

    imacy, and reflexive action. I then propose a new concept of institutional paradigms

    analytically distinct from institutional orders, differentiating embodied from

    relational aspects of institutions and underscoring the misleading nature of in-dividualistic assumptions of [American] culture [that] lead us to believe . . . we can

    live as we choose, using the big institutions . . . for our own ends, without being fun-

    damentally influenced by them (Bellah et al. 1992:19). Those aspects of institutions

    embodied as institutional paradigms manifest as dispositions that become routine

    taken for grantedby agents in their daily lives as they get by and get along in

    social interactions. Institutional paradigms develop as regions of a broader habitus,

    Pierre Bourdieus concept for the array of dispositions that individuals embody and

    display in everyday practices (Bourdieu 1984:16975). Institutional paradigms are

    key to explaining how institutional ordersthe relational aspects of institutions

    stabilize. Crucially, habitus and its core institutional paradigms highlight the distinc-tion between a broader agency and instances of reflexive action involving conscious

    deliberation and choice.

    I next show how this conceptual array enables a robust and empirically useful

    specification of networks and how they mediate between individual agency, patterns

    of social order, and dynamics of social change. From there, I move to topics of insti-

    tutional change and disintegration, as well as noninstitutional networking common

    in diverse social situations from social movements to criminal activity. These argu-

    ments culminate in a warrant for the project of neoclassical sociology (Eyal et al.

    1998) with its recognition of the contingency of global order and the multiplicity of

    regional variants of capitalisms, socialisms, democracies, authoritarianisms,and the like. In a sentence, neoclassical sociology abandons the assumption ofneces-

    sary developmental convergence at a global scale. If such a convergence happens at

    some point in the future, it will be the consequence of complex strings of historically

    unique contingencies.

    INSTITUTIONS, FIELDS, AND AGENCY

    An institution can initially be conceptualized as an obligatory form of getting by

    and getting along in social routines, a pattern of expected action of individuals

    or groups enforced by social sanctions, both positive and negative (Bellah et al.1992:10). Institutions may be either customary or formal. In a customary institution,

    no written rules steer people toward expected ways of behaving, yet rituals may serve

    as equivalents to formal sanctions. Individuals in such customary situations develop

    an intuitive sensea feel for the gameof how to behave in situations. In peasant

    villages prior to literacy, for example, failure to show proper respect to a village elderat UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    4/29

    328 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

    may have resulted in a peasants exclusion from public festivities, and was enforced

    in a ritual manner by collective shunning and spontaneous eviction of the offender

    from festivities by fellow villagers. Some customary institutions may have entailed

    death, liminal conditions such as temporary banishment,1 or other harsh sanctions,

    so customary here does not serve as a synonym for informal.

    Formal institutions, on the other hand, presuppose some degree of literacy for theyentail the codification of expected conventions of behaviorstabilizing what sociol-

    ogists often call roles and positionsin laws or corporate handbooks given

    to employees. For instance, wageworkers who violate such codes may be fired, a

    consequence that strips workers of the benefits of inclusion. Since workers remain

    dependent on wages for livelihood, such a sanction serves as a powerful incentive to

    conform to managerial rules. All formal organizations involve institutional steering

    by means of rules and codes, and this codification in turn entails bureaucratization,

    a relatively late historical development (Weber 1978:956). Indeed, bureaucratization

    builds on a web of formal laws associated with the rise of civil societies in the early

    modern West that have since spread around the globe, albeit unevenly and oftencoexisting with other, sometimes antithetical tendencies such as political authoritar-

    ianism.

    Institutions stabilize fields, social spaces that Pierre Bourdieu described as arena[s]

    in which people play a game which has certain rules (Bourdieu 1991b:215). Game

    as a metaphor here should be taken in contextafter all, institutional patterns

    in fields involve aspects beyond strategic considerations such as normative beliefs,

    ethical expectations, and the like. Regardless, institutions form the core of such fields

    by giving them order and meaning for agents (Bourdieu 1981; Fuchs 2001b:28492),

    steering adaptation to power relations within them. Such adaptation shows that

    power entails more than top-down authority, but also what Michel Foucault calledthe micro-physics of power (Foucault 1978), a bottom-up process in which the

    capillaries and synapses of power connect with the central circulatory and nervous

    system of the state (Gorski 2003:2324).

    Institutions are key to discerning how everyday practicesthe capillaries and

    synapses of powerlink with social authority. Customary institutions tend toward

    what Durkheim (1964) called segmental patterns, insofar as they may segment off

    across regions even where they share common origins and help bring about similar

    social orders. But formal institutions, rooted in the innovation of bureaucracy and

    the generalization of literacy across populations,2 enabled both the development of

    many modern legal practices, as well as new types of organization, specifically formalorganizations. Among the latter, we see a diverse range of distinctively modern forms,

    from nation-states to political parties to unions to corporations to nongovernmental

    associations.

    The differentiation of organizational forms co-evolved with the differentiation of

    fields, and when combined in the early modern West with legal limitations on the

    state to interfere with some practices in these fields, gave rise to the concept of

    civil society as a means of tracing such differentiation in terms of legal regulations

    restraining the exercise of political authority. Crucially, such legal limitations must

    be effective in practice to some degree for the concept of civil society to have much

    1In oral societies, liminal states between inclusion and exclusion often figured as central markers ofsocial life: Thus, liminality is frequently likened to death, to being in the womb, to invisibility, todarkness, to bisexuality, to the wilderness, and to an eclipse of the sun or moon (Turner 1969:95).

    2For thousands of years, literacy remained confined to narrow elites in tributary states, a conditionJack Goody and Ian Watt termed oligoliteracy (Goody and Watt 1968:36).

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    5/29

    THE MISSING KEY 329

    analytical use. The Soviet Constitution of 1936the so-called Stalin Constitution

    granted extensive rights in theory, rights that had no practical bearing in Soviet life,

    rendering application of the term civil society to the Soviet Union highly misleading

    (Garcelon 1997). Moreover, no single pattern of civil society has emerged in moder-

    nity; rather, a variety of civil societies described in terms of the legal, political, and

    social practices that augment co-evolutionary patterns of institutional differentiationof fields and formal organizations.3

    Diverse formal organizations in turn enable geographically extensive networks,

    many of whose members never know each other personally but remain loosely

    connected through extensive chains, such as corporate networks. Through such

    networks . . . small-scale interaction becomes translated into large-scale patterns,

    and . . . these, in turn, feed back into small groups (Granovetter 1973:1360).

    Of course, institutional obligations do not guarantee compliance between practices

    and institutions, so degrees of conformity to obligations must be assessed probabilis-

    tically in particular instances. This converges with the wide use of statistical analysis

    as a primary source of evidence in contemporary sociology, as during the last cen-tury the study of probabilities more and more displaced attempts to generalize the

    concept of scientific law from the physical into the social sciences.4 Rather than

    invariant properties mapped as algorithms across different societies, sociology deals

    with social realities through specific cases, comparative-historical models, and prob-

    abilistic assessments (Steinmetz 2004:394). The probabilistic character of institutions

    points to their historical irreducibility, as the concept of institution tells us little

    concerning the relative degree of institutional observance in particular settings.

    Conceiving institutions as probabilistic social phenomena differentiates them from

    invariant regularities. Here, objects of algorithmic analysis give way to the modeling

    of contingent institutions and networks. To be sure, distinctions between algorithmicregularities across cases and modeling of particular cases occur across the sciences.

    When scientists encounter historical irreducibility in the physical world, for example,

    they switch from explaining phenomena in terms of algorithmic regularities and

    instead use such algorithms to map the boundary conditions of chaotic phenomena.5

    Institutional disintegration on the scale of a state itself epitomizes chaos in the

    technical sense, that is, the historical contingency of the processes it unleashes.

    For instance, once the probability of observance of ostensibly obligatory ways of

    getting by and getting along in a given society declines past a certain point

    which varies across casesinstitutions may undergo sudden bouts of rapid change

    or even disintegrate outright, in the process destroying the coherence of previ-ously stable fields. Relatively long periods of institutional equilibrium are thus

    3This is only the briefest of treatments of the concept of civil society, which has a rich pedigree inboth Western and, more recently, global history. See the collection Civil Society and the State (Keane1988), and Jeffrey Alexanders recent The Civil Sphere to get a sense of this. Alexander argues that acivil sphere, that is, a civil society, ensures that conflicts are more than simple battles whose outcomedepends only on instrumental power (Alexander 2006:266). Detailing how Alexanders approachnot tomention more than two previous centuries of writings on civil societyboth converges and diverges fromneoclassical sociology lies beyond the scope of this article.

    4Weber emphasized the centrality of probabilistic analysis to sociology in his methodological writings,

    often with the phrase objective possibility (Weber 1949:18182). Fritz Ringer points out Weber literallyrefers to objective possibility in German; but probability nevertheless seems the better translation(Ringer 1997:65).

    5In the physical sciences, chaos theory provides us with understanding that is holistic, historical, andqualitative, eschewing deductive systems (Kellert 1993:114). This does not mean nonmathematical, aschaos theorya relatively new brand of physicsuses among the most sophisticated mathematics in allthe empirical sciences (pp. 2328).

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    6/29

    330 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

    punctuated by relatively rapid bouts of institutional disintegration, reformation,

    and generation.6 Historical irreducibility takes on a specific sociological weight in

    cases of institutional disintegration because historical modeling of such disintegra-

    tion must account for meaning. Meaning figures prominently in assessing patterns

    of rapid institutional change where social movements, invading military forces, or

    other protoinstitutions or counterinstitutions organize preinstitutional, extrain-stitutional, and postinstitutional networks in ways that may both exacerbate insti-

    tutional collapse or in rarer cases stimulate development of alternative institutions

    themselves.

    All of this indicates a range of conceptual problems that have tortured sociology

    since its origin. Chief among these is how to conceptualize relations between so-

    ciety, on the one hand, and individual agentshuman personalitieson the other.

    Alongside the failure to generalize an empirically intelligible concept of social law

    congruent with the concept of law in the physical sciences, the social sciences have

    been plagued by persistent conceptual dualisms between individual and society, per-

    sonality and social structure, subjectivity and objectivity, and so forth. Here, Bour-dieus distinction between relational and embodied aspects of social lifepositions

    and dispositionsprovides a perceptive alternative for the embodied and the rela-

    tional avoids dualisms between self and society (Bourdieu 1990a:54). This has several

    benefits.

    First, such a distinction allows us to conceptualize institutions as both embodied

    and relational. Institutions are relational insofar as they stabilize patterns of interac-

    tion over time within geographically and temporally limited fields, conceived simply

    as the social spaces ordered by institutions (Bourdieu and Wacquant 1992:105). Thus,

    agents perceive social order as centered upon prestigious positions sanctified through

    taboo, ritual, custom, and in more complex societies, legality, formal codes, and ide-ologies as well. Social relations often appear hierarchically organized as status and

    class in what Weber called legitimate orders (Weber 1978:3138, 94145). At the

    heart of such orders lie the institutions that cohere and stabilize patterns of author-

    ity within them. Relational aspects of institutions form the epicenter of patterns of

    power, inequality, and social change.

    At the same time, institutions are embodied insofar as sufficient convergence

    among individual practices inclines agents toward reproduction of social routines

    over time. Degrees of convergence in turn can sometimes be mapped probabilisti-

    cally, through electoral outcomes, surveys, and the like. Such mappings show how

    concatenations of individual practices generate institutions over time. [I]nstitutedhistorythe institutionbecomes historical action, i.e., enacted, active history, only

    if it is taken in charge by agents whose own history predisposes them to do so

    (Bourdieu 1981:306). Institutions combine authority as a relational pattern observ-

    able over time with an embodied sense of legitimacy, what Weber called a voluntary

    willingness to comply with authoritative expectations and directions (Weber 1978:37).

    In this sense, the relational aspects of institutions can be conceptualized as in-

    stitutional orders, while the embodied aspects of institutions can be conceptualized

    6The borrowing from Stephen Jay Gould and Niles Eldredges (1977) neo-Darwinian theory of punc-tuated equilibrium in patterns of biological evolution is explicit. Punctuated equilibrium emphasizes longperiods of relative equilibrium in biological evolution, punctuated by historically contingent episodes ofecological upheaval that trigger relatively rapid clusters of extinctions, followed by relatively rapid periodsof evolutionary differentiation until the full house of the ecology again tips the balance into relativestasis (Gould 1989:283, 1995, 1997).

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    7/29

    THE MISSING KEY 331

    as institutional paradigms.7 Institutional paradigmsthe embodied dispositions that

    form as a psychological sensibility of legitimacy incrementally shifts from conscious

    cognition to habitual routine among particular networks of agentssteer various

    practices that reproduce institutional orders, with incremental change, over time. By

    emphasizing how institutional paradigms routinize a sense of legitimacy among par-

    ticular individuals, we see how rough convergences between paradigms among groupsof such individuals establish institutional orders as the cores of fields.

    Institutional paradigms should be seen as a crucial aspect of a larger bodily

    agency, habitus, an agents cluster of dispositions always marked by its (social)

    conditions of acquisition and realization (Bourdieu 1990a:65). Habitus designates

    an agglomeration of capacities that an individual does not have to consciously think

    about in order to engage in a practice, such as pressing a brake while driving a car. A

    lack of conscious deliberation in performing such activities is an accomplishment of

    habitusto be judged a good driver, for instance, a person must develop capacities

    to spontaneously react well to ongoing events without thinking much about them.

    Habitus clarifies why agency entails more than reflexive action (Bourdieu1990c:131). Indeed, reflexive action represents a special case emerging from more

    habitual practices, a conception that converges with empirical findings in recent neu-

    rophysiology.8 As an amalgam of dispositions unique to each person at a given

    time and place, habitus nevertheless entails limited aspects shared among individ-

    uals across different fields, namely, institutional paradigms. As convergent aspects

    of otherwise distinct, embodied conglomerations of individual dispositions, such in-

    stitutional paradigms generate stable patterns of practices across networks and in

    various fields. This highlights networks as key causal linkages between institutional

    paradigms as aspects of broader embodied dispositions, on the one hand, and power,

    status, and class in various fields, on the other.Conceptually distinguishing institutional paradigms, a broader habitus, and a sen-

    sibility of legitimacy that can either be consciously adopted or serve as a preconscious

    habitus (and in fact can shift and change from one to the other at different times

    of an agents life) clarifies relations between agents, institutions, and as we shall

    see, networks. In so doing, it avoids the chronic overburdening of the concept of

    structure in contemporary sociology. Whether structure is identified as one end of a

    continuum along with agency at the other end (Fuchs 2001a), with the parameters of

    inequality (Blau and Duncan 1978), or with social patterns per se (Mohr and White

    2008:490), the variability of its use to cover just about anything creates obstacles to

    seeing how social order is embodied as institutional paradigms that steer patterns ofsocial stability.

    The embodiment of institutional paradigms as cores of habitus in turn routinizes

    legitimacy as a sensibility, showing how such a sensibility moves from conscious

    adoption to preconscious disposition. All of this underscores that agency per se

    refers not to the intentions people have in doing things but to their capacity of

    doing those things in the first place, refining action proper as a special case of a

    broader agency presupposing reflexive monitoring (Giddens 1984:9). The distinc-

    tion between agency as practical activity, on the one hand, and reflexive action as an

    emergent property mediating practices through conscious deliberation, on the other,

    7This develops Nicos Mouzeliss distinction between the paradigmatic level of institutions and thesyntagmatic level of actual relationships of cooperation/conflict (1995:78) as explained below.

    8P. Read Montague and Gregory S. Berns argue identifiable neural substrates . . .may support sophis-ticated economic evaluations of diverse stimuli, in other words, economic evaluations are often tied tononconscious neural patterns (Montague and Berns 2002:281).

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    8/29

    332 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

    separate[s] out what an agent does from what is intended or the intentional as-

    pects of what is done (Giddens 1984:10).9 This clarifies relations between broader

    practices of agency generated through habitus, and more restricted instances of re-

    flexive action that constitute a smallthough often causally significantfraction of

    agents practices (Lakoff and Johnson 1999:51338).

    Conceiving agency in this way facilitates rethinking Webers four ideal typesof action: instrumentally rational, value-rational, affective, and traditional action

    (Weber 1978:2426). The most problematic of these is traditional action that

    Weber called borderline between action proper and behavior, collapsing habit, and

    routine into complex variants of reflexive fidelity to, and development of, cultural

    traditions. First, in light of distinguishing reflexive action as an emergent property

    of agency, the habitual aspects of traditional action can be more clearly speci-

    fied as habitual practices not entailing reflexive agencyat least after learning such

    practicesthat generate routines through habitus, a process that begins in early child-

    hood. Habitus in turn enables a potentially widening scope of reflexive action among

    maturing individuals. Webers three remaining ideal types of action can then be seenas denoting regions along a broad continuum of patterns of reflective action ranging

    from instrumentally rational to value-rational to affective actions. The complex vari-

    ants of reflexive fidelity to, and development of, traditions that Weber collapsed into

    habit and routine thus appear among the diverse variety of value-rational actions

    proper.10

    Key here is recognition that embodiment of habitus results from protracted pro-

    cesses of socialization during which simplified stories presented to children of

    the good and the bad, the right and the wrong, and so on generate institutional

    paradigms that change incrementally over time as the capacity of deliberative action

    develops over childhood and adolescence. Weber nowhere dealt with socialization andin fact presumed his interpretive sociology always in relation to adults, a significant

    shortcoming.

    Routinized legitimacylegitimacy fossilized in institutional paradigms as aspects

    of a larger habitusin turn helps reproduce patterns of domination in social relations

    among large enough numbers of individuals sufficient to render opposition risky to

    some degree by those who do not embody such legitimacy (Weber 1978:946). We

    can distinguish a solidaristic variant of legitimacy derived from an agent reflexively

    adopting the norms of legitimacy for his or her own sakeas exemplified in maxims

    such as the duty of citizens is to support their country, moral people dont break

    laws, etc.from expedient variants of legitimacy that agents develop to get by andget along in the absence of strong convictions of the rightness or justness of

    said institutional order.11

    9Emergent properties conceptualize relations between elements that cannot be explained by the prop-erties of the elements themselves. Thus, at each level of complexity entirely new properties appear, andthe understanding of the new behaviors requires research which I think is as fundamental in its nature asany other (Anderson 1972:393).

    10The above develops comments made on an earlier draft of this article by Robert N. Bellah regardingthe problematic aspects of Webers concept of traditional action.

    11

    Weber distinguished these types in terms of pure and expedient variants of legitimacy (Weber1978:3133). By replacing the term pure with solidaristic, we can differentiate more precisely betweenconvergence around a social core of beliefs among some agents, and expedient compliance among others,in the process outlining a key aspect of how social hierarchies form. The term solidaristic is adaptedfrom Durkheim, who conceptualized solidarity as a moral disposition: The functions of assistance aresuch that . . .they demand feelings of solidarity . . .a certain intellectual and moral homogeneity such asthe same occupation produces (Durkheim 1964:26).

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    9/29

    THE MISSING KEY 333

    an institutional field

    legitimacy

    (as sensibility) (as social relation)

    legitimate authority

    institutional paradigms institutional orders

    norms embodied by patterns of

    individuals as aspects obligation stable

    of a larger habitus in fields over time

    institutionally

    enmeshed networks

    Figure 1. Mapping embodied and relational aspects of institutions in fields.

    Solidaristic legitimacy renders durable the social cores of institutional orders, while

    expedient legitimacy reinforces strategic adjustment to institutional orders in navi-

    gating relations of power, status, and class in various fields. Reproduction of both

    solidaristic and expedient legitimacy fosters routinizationhabitualizationof le-

    gitimacy as an embodied institutional paradigm among agents. Conformity to rou-

    tines stabilizes this virtuous circle, rendering institutions natural to many agents.

    Formal legality in contemporary capitalist democracies, for instance, facilitates com-

    mercial activity by routinizing respect for laws governing property and contractual

    obligations. In this way, institutional paradigms serve both as primary generators

    of institutional orders, and causal influences shaping institutionally bound networks

    that form, change, and disintegrate within and across various fields. All of this can

    be mapped, starting with the case of stable institutional fields as in Figure 1.

    Figure 1 clarifies how overburdening the concept of structureusing a single

    concept to describe institutional order, institutional paradigms, fields, habitus, le-

    gitimacy, reflexive action, and networksobscures how institutional paradigms are

    embodied as part of a larger suite of dispositionshabitusroutinizing a sense of

    legitimacy and stabilizing institutional orders and institutionally embedded networks.

    This closely relates to actor/structure binaries, for if institutional paradigms are em-

    bodied in agency, conceiving structures as external to such agency is a conceptual

    error generating additional errors. Certainly, Bourdieu had a chronic tendency to

    overuse the term structure, but mitigated this by describing social phenomena with

    more precise concepts such as habitus.

    Of course, variation in senses of legitimacy among agents presents difficulties in

    empirically mapping degrees of conformity to institutional authority among pop-

    ulations, whether through surveys, various administrative records, or other types

    of evidence. Surveys, for instance, present methodical difficulties pertaining to the

    framing of questions, the representativeness of the survey sample, and, in some

    cases, the degree to which respondents answer sincerely.12 Moreover, such surveys

    12A 75 percent disparity between men and women aged 1859 in reporting number of heterosexualacts in the five years prior to the question marred the results of a series of surveys on sexual behaviordesigned as the most rigorous taken on the subject prior to 1994. In presenting this discrepancy in thesurvey data, the researchers list seven different possibilities, most highly unlikely, except for the sixth:Either men may exaggerate, or women underestimate (Laumann et al. 1994:185).

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    10/29

    334 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

    IOt0 IOt1 IOt2 IOt3 IOt4

    IPt0 IPt1 IPt2 IPt3 IPt4

    IO = institutional order

    IP = institutional paradigms, aspects of a larger habitust = particular times

    Figure 2. The trajectory adjustment model of institutional reproduction and incre-

    mental social change in a stable social field. Adapted from Eyal et al. (1998:45).

    are impossible for historical cases, as well as difficult to impossible in situations

    such as state collapse, authoritarian regimes, and regions such as contemporary

    Afghanistan.

    Degrees of social reproduction and incremental social change across a variety of

    fields can be assessed in terms of consonance and dissonance between habitus andfield. Consonance between habitus and field signals relative institutional stability,

    mapped as a pattern of trajectory adjustment in Figure 2 as first proposed by Gil

    Eyal, Ivan Szelenyi, and Eleanor Townsley (Eyal et al. 1998:45).

    Note that Figure 2 represents institutions as a whole, that is, their embodied and

    relational aspects. The diagonal up from institutional paradigms at time x to insti-

    tutional order at time y captures the generative role of such paradigms in stabilizing

    relative social stability over time. Habitual expectation of a future institutional order

    at time y by a person at preceding time x entails no teleology, as the expectation

    may not be realized.

    Inter alia, the above arguments enable refinement of the concept of economicinterest. Weber distinguished cases of pure self-interesteconomic interest in a

    narrow sensewhich did not entail any sense of legitimacy (Weber 1978:2931). But

    self-interested practices frequently occur in the context of specific fields. Markets

    presuppose institutional recognition of a means of exchange, some rules regarding

    property, and the like, though the causality of actual transactions cannot be reduced

    to such initial conditions. It would thus be more precise to track a continuum

    of economic interestspursued by individuals, groups of organized individuals, or

    aggregates of these such as classesthat generate aggregate effects irreducible to

    institutional routines. With this model, economic innovations and conflicts can be

    accounted for as emergent properties of stable institutional orders that sometimeslead to institutional change or in rarer cases institutional disintegration.

    The irreducibility of economic activity to stable institutions underscores an irony

    of classical social science. For generalization of utilitarian calculations in classical

    economics turned social theory on its head by assuming the special case of reflexive

    action rooted in economic interests as a sufficient model of agency. Such reflexive

    action, of course, presupposed a historically specific institutional background in

    regions of the early modern West. Though Adam Smith recognized this background

    as forming the moral presuppositions of market economies (Smith [1797] 2002),

    most of economics has since neglected his insight. Instead, sociology and political

    science developed it by situating economic interests in relation to historical patternsof institutional development (Janos 1986:730).

    The continuum running from reflex behavior to habitus to reflexive action

    including rational action in the sense of conscious deliberation of alternativesin

    turn allows us to situate more precisely reflexive action as an emergent property of

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    11/29

    THE MISSING KEY 335

    agency per se (Elder-Vass 2007:341). Given that institutional paradigms are embod-

    ied as aspects of habitus, to presume institutions as external to agency is an error.

    Overcoming this error facilitates a more precise concept of networks.

    NETWORKS

    What, then, is a social network? Initially, I define a network as some array of

    ties between individuals linked bybut not always reducible tostrategic agency

    over time.13 By this definition, many interactionsfrom incidental contacts between

    individuals in crowds, on the one hand, to people passively watching a televised

    speech by a politician, on the otherdo not count as examples of network relations.

    Network linkages can be further differentiated in terms of hierarchies between net-

    work cores, their extended connections, and outliers or more marginal individuals

    in terms of power dynamics within networks. Moreover, the cores of some networks

    are deeply institutionalized, such as networks of employees in public corporations, or

    in authoritarian political parties such as the former Communist Party of the SovietUnion. Networks may be hierarchal as well as institutionalized.

    On the opposite end of the continuum, we find highly egalitarian networks, from

    such trivial examples as networks of neighbors informally organizing reciprocal baby-

    sitting patterns, to relatively egalitarian networks among, for instance, some Native

    Americans surviving in marginalized positions on reservations, networks that per-

    sist as highly modified aspects of earlier hunter-gatherer patterns in a surrounding

    industrial environment. All of this emphasizes the contingent nature of relations be-

    tween institutions and networks, with some networks co-evolutionary aspects of the

    same process that generates a modern, formal group of institutionsfrom corpora-

    tions to political parties to representative democracy as a state form in the currentUnited Stateswhile other networks develop in more peripheral relation to institu-

    tions proper. Such networks are thus the key linkage between embodied institutional

    paradigms and patterns of institutional order across various fields.

    Take the example of Al Qaeda as a terrorist network forming out of extremist

    Islamic movements in parts of the Middle East, Africa, and Central Asia. Al Qaeda

    exemplifies apparent paradoxes when it comes to usage of the network concept:

    from the perspective of the U.S. government today, Al Qaeda is an anti-institutional

    network, and yet internally Al Qaeda benefits from institutional support from some

    puritanical mosques of Sunni Islam. The paradox, though, is only apparent, as Al

    Qaeda-aligned networksinstitutionalized to various degrees internally and bene-fiting from support from some religious institutionsare in strong conflict with

    hegemonic global networks and institutions, including other religious institutions,

    aligned with U.S. foreign policies.

    Other examples, such as the emergence of pro-democracy networks into a broader

    social movement during the last years of the Soviet Union, underscore how institu-

    tional paradigms may aid network innovationpeople can become reflective about

    that which they may have hitherto taken for granted. In late-communist Russia,

    13

    This formalizes a definition often implicitly worked with but rarely explicitly defined, as in DiMaggio(1986). See, especially, Figure 2 on p. 340, where DiMaggio maps a hypothetical interorganizationalnetwork in terms of arrows between members of different organizational cliques. Such commonworking definitions are compatible with the formalization introduced here. An influential early articleemphasizing the need to conceptualize relations between networks and institutions (Mitchell 1973) uses ageneric conception of networks as linkages between individuals (1973:22, 3233), though at one pointmentions a network as an action set (1973:31) without clarifying what this entails.

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    12/29

    336 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

    networks of agents holding institutionally sanctioned positionssuch as profession-

    als in academic bodiescould simultaneously organize informal networks against

    the very authorities who controlled the organizations of which they remained nomi-

    nally a part (Garcelon 2005). Many other examples of people informally networking

    in ways risky for their positions in established institutional networks can be found:

    from networks fusing into the civil rights movement in the American deep south inthe late 1950s, to pro-democracy networks among intellectuals in todays Iran where

    such intellectuals have become targets of repression since the disputed presidential

    election in June 2009.

    Such considerations lead to adjusting common sociological concepts of networks.

    Some wish to distinguish networks from groups and formal organizations (Fuchs

    2001b:191292). While restricting the concept of group to agents who know one

    another makes analytic sense, such a definition simply renders strategically oriented

    groups as one pole along a continuum of networks, namely, the pole of discrete

    networks. On the other hand, Fuchs correctly distinguishes formal organizations

    from networks, as such organizations entail more than networks per se, such aslegal recognition, organizational property, and the like. But networks nevertheless

    remain central to organizations, as networked agents create, reform, and disband such

    organizations and their internal hierarchies, making clear that networks are vectors

    through which agency drives organizational behavior. That formal organizations are

    more than networks shows the need to differentiate what too often are simply called

    structures.

    More problematic is Fuchss and others analysis of networks in ways that method-

    ologically exclude the potential causal significance of reflexive action for their devel-

    opment. This reifies empirical study of networks by treating agents linked through

    them as nodes without recognizing that such nodes always have agentic potentials toengage in reflexive action of possible causal significance. Consider Fuchss argument

    that a person might be a node in a network, but what the network does cannot

    be explained as the result of individual actions and intentions (Fuchs 2001a:29

    30). This raises two problems. First, a network per se does not do anything, only

    its nodesits networked agentsdo things. Second, this comes close to eliding the

    possible causal significance of human deliberation, such as the causal significance of

    decisions made by the cell of hijackers linked through the Al Qaeda network who

    carried out the September 11 attacks.

    The tendency to reify networks and their nodes as if they were causally indepen-

    dent of agents reflexive action is an influential tendency in American sociologicalconceptions of networks. But this is more a philosophical than a sociological posi-

    tion justified in terms of empirical evidence, as Fuchs demonstrates in the following

    statement.

    We might summarize sociologys approach to person, personhood, and agency

    in three serious, all-too-serious, methodological rules of thumb. First, nothing

    is ever anyones fault in particular. Second, no one can do all that much about

    anything. And third, fewer people actually care about anything you say or do

    than your vanity is willing to consider. (Fuchs 2001a:30)

    So by inference, dictators are not really dictators as their reflexive action has no

    causal effects, etc. Fuchss subsequent description of his sociological position as anti-

    humanism (Fuchs 2001b:63) further conflates a methodological with a philosophical

    position that a prioriassumes agency as always an effect, not a cause.

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    13/29

    THE MISSING KEY 337

    Mustafa Emirbayer and Jeff Goodwin expand this criticism of reification in net-

    work theory by delineating three common methodological approaches to networks:

    structural determinism, structural instrumentalism, and structural constructionism

    (1994:142436). As Emirbayer and Goodwin stress, two of these three method-

    ological strategies either conceptualize segments of networks frozen analytically

    at a given time (structural determinism), or assume ahistorical rationalthat is,economicinterests linking such moments at all times (structural instrumentalism),

    thus failing to provide a coherent model for how networks change over time. The

    third strategythe structural constructionism of Doug McAdams work on the civil

    rights movementpartially avoids this by questioning rational-action assumptions,

    though without developing a more systematic account of agency. As Emirbayer and

    Ann Mische argue (1998:99, 1012), developing a relational pragmatics of agency

    and deliberationreflexive actionis central to social theory.

    Problems of ahistoricity and absence of accounts of agency common in network

    theory are tightly coupled to exactly what structure is supposed to mean.14 For

    instance, Centola and Macy argue that the structural strength of a tie refers to theability of the tie to facilitate diffusion, cohesion, and integration of a social network

    by linking otherwise distant nodes (2007:70304). Here, structural refers to the

    capacities of institutions and networks, a contingent, historically irreducible question

    that must account empirically to what degree a network forms within or outside

    of institutional orders. And yet they obscure this by describing social normsthat

    is, central aspects of institutional paradigmsas social contagions, right alongside

    technological innovations and (inherently noninstitutional) social movements. From

    the emergence of social norms . . . to the adoption of technological innovations . . . to

    the growth of social movements . . . social networks are the pathways along which

    these social contagions propagate (Centola and Macy 2007:702).Reflecting on this in light of what has been stated above, however, shows that

    norms embodied as institutional paradigms by agents enable much of social net-

    working in the first place, and thus networks are not necessarily prior to institutions.

    Rather, agents bring to preinstitutional networks practical capacities enabled by em-

    bodied institutional paradigms formed within different institutional orders, orders

    distinct from preinstitutional networks. Specifically, such agents may improvise us-

    ing such institutional paradigms as practical models for developing an initial sense

    of protolegitimacy for potential supporters in expanding preinstitutional networks,

    consolidating organizations, and in some cases, changing institutional orders as such.

    It remains an empirical question whether networks can in fact also spread suchinstitutional norms through social contacts, as they sometimes do, thus serving as

    possible vectors for diffusing institutions from core to more peripheral agents who

    come under their influence and become new nodes in the network. This observation

    converges with the fact that preinstitutional, noninstitutional, and postinstitutional

    networks can play key causal roles in the generation, change, and collapse of insti-

    tutions, as discussed above. But there can be no a priori relation between particular

    concatenations of institutional paradigms, institutional orders, and networks, on the

    one hand, and the question of whether a particular institution temporally preceded,

    co-evolved with, or came about after the development of a particular network, on

    14The chemist James Lovelock and the microbiologist Lynn Margulis used the term tightly coupled tomap systemic relations between organisms and their environments on the surface of the Earth as a whole:The evolution of organisms and their material environment proceeds as a single tight-coupled processfrom which self-regulation of the environment at ahabitable state, appears as an emergent phenomenon(Lovelock 2001:1).

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    14/29

    338 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

    the other. This is, and must remain, an empirical question whose answer remains

    contingent on evidence.

    Some network theorists have already shifted from an overburdened concept of

    structure to an explicit concept of institutions. Peng, for instance, states how his

    research draws insights from two theoretical traditions: one is new institutional-

    ism that emphasizes the role of institutions, both formal and informal, in economicgrowth; the other is social network analysis, which highlights the role of interper-

    sonal relations in producing and enforcing informal norms (Peng 2004:1045). He

    then argues that analysis of the developmental history of institutions and informal

    networks in the situations he examines turns on:

    the relative strength of the normative capacity of the formal organizations (the

    state apparatus) vis-a-vis the informal social networks. When formal institutions

    are vague and ineffective, informal rules do not supplement but substitute for

    formal rules, and the normative capacity of social relations not only subsumes

    the costs of formal sanctioning but takes its place. . .

    If the normative capacityof the social networks is strong, then spontaneous social order may emerge to

    reduce uncertainty. (Peng 2004:1070)

    We can now circle back to our reconstructed concept of institutions to show

    why such order is not spontaneous, but the result of embodiment of customary

    institutional paradigms among unofficial networks. Note also that Peng refers to

    informal institutions whenas stressed abovethese are customary, congealing in

    this case outside of official Chinese law and politics but still rendering obligations

    on those who rely on them.

    A final difficulty in network theory links to a persistently reified use of the micro-macro distinction. For instance, Mohr and White (2008:495) recognize the centrality

    of the concept of institution to network theory, but struggle to trace how this can be

    used in empirical analysis after positing institutions as above the analytical level of

    conventions and social rules. This fragments aspects constitutive of institutions into

    distinct analytical levels and places institutions above the level of agency. Mouzelis

    is critical of such assumptions, assumptions that actors and face-to-face interac-

    tions belong to the micro, and institutional structures to the macro level (Mouzelis

    1995:20). Such a bifurcation of agency and institutions obscures how agents con-

    tribute to the reproduction, change, dissolution, and generation of institutional orders

    through embodied institutional paradigms. I do not reject the use of analytical levelshere, just the assignment of agency to a micro level and structure to a macro level.

    The difficulty disappears once one recognizes how habitus carries institutional

    paradigms, as the followings examples show. Take the Mormon sect in Texas recently

    broken up by Texas state agents. Within a small, discrete network of sect members

    all of whom knew each other on a face-to-face basissect routines were powerfully

    institutionalized in a customary fashion overseen by sect leaders (all of whom were

    male polygamists) on the basis of their interpretation of the Book of Mormon.15

    Where is the macro level here? Everything was micro in the sense that all of

    the sect knew and interacted with each other on a daily basis within a compound

    15See 52 Girls Are Taken from Polygamist Sects Ranch in Texas, The New York Times, April5 2008, http://www.nytimes.com/2008/04/05/us/05jeffs.html?_r=1&oref=slogin, retrieved July 8, 2008;and Texas Wrong to Take Fundamentalist Mormon Sect Kids, The Australian, May 31 2008,http://www.theaustralian.news.com.au/story/0,25197,23785647-26397,00.html, retrieved July 8, 2008.

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    15/29

    THE MISSING KEY 339

    of a few buildings, yet it would be absurd to claim that the sect had no internal

    institutions.

    Now reverse the situation by taking several discrete meetings between American

    President Bush and British Prime Minister Blair in 2002 that secured Bushs launch-

    ing of the second Iraq war in March 2003. These face-to-face meetings took place at

    a macro level, if what you mean is the level of structures such as the state. More-over, understanding how the U.S. military and some of its allies entered the war at

    all entails unraveling the activities of a small network of persons at the most senior

    level of the Bush White House throughout 2002 and early 2003. Such a relatively

    micro network at the very top of the macro state worked to discredit, marginalize,

    or silence some of the findings of U.S. intelligence agencies, as documented at length

    by Johnson (2004:21753). Micro-macro problems of this variety are an artifact of

    a mistaken conceptualization.16

    Mouzelis suggests an alternative. By reframing both institutions and networks as

    entailing embodied aspects, micro, meso, and macro distinctions become strictly spa-

    tial. Some network analysts have already begun such a spatial redefinition. TakeHedstrom, Sandell, and Stern, who argue that mesolevel network[s] had a consid-

    erable influence on both the pattern and the speed at which the Social Democratic

    Party diffused through Sweden (Hedstrom et al. 2000:169).

    In summary, networks can be mapped in three principal ways. First, we can track

    their spatial extensiveness. Again, a more discrete network remains a strategically

    related group, that is, remains localized in the sense of most people in it know-

    ing one another. But many networks in more complex societiesand even across

    several such societies, such as in transnational corporations or transnational terror-

    ist networksextend diversely in terms of both geography and social ties between

    people only connected indirectly through the chain.Second, networks can be differentiated in terms of both degrees of institutional

    embeddedness and internal institutionalization. Such factors tie closely to how net-

    works develop polyglots of relative hierarchy and equality that Weber distinguished

    in terms of closed and open social relations (Weber 1978:4346). The degree to

    which networks are embedded in institutions remains empirically contingent, with

    some networks forming largely outside institutional channels, such as the networking

    patterns of social movements. Sometimes, of course, such movements trigger changes

    in institutions they challenge, pointing to the need to avoid reifying the boundary

    between institutionalized and noninstitutionalized politics (McAdam et al. 2001:6).

    Thus, even noninstitutional networks remain tightly coupled to institutions and va-rieties of legitimacy within them.

    Finally, networks remain tightly coupled with status and class. If status maps pat-

    terns of hierarchy embedded in cultural sensibilities of honor and the like, class maps

    commonalities of market situations. Thus, class differentiated from status as market

    relations spread in the modern period, though class relations appeared occasionally

    and secondarily in some premodern societies, often around trading towns.17 And, the

    differentiation of networks in terms of status and class in distinct historical periods

    and regions intertwines with the history of institutions and varieties of assets that

    developed with such institutions and enabled various patterns of networking.

    16For elaborations of this argument, see Mouzelis (1995:1527, 12324) and Garcelon (2006:26567).17This remains a Weberian conception of status and class (Weber 1978:30207). For a more Marxian

    alternative, see Eyal et al. (1998:6670).

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    16/29

    340 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

    = network node, i.e., individual agent

    = network linkage between individuals

    = incidental linkage across networks

    Figure 3. Initial mapping of a network.

    Figure 3 summarizes the concept of network introduced here. This converges with

    detailed maps of particular networks available in sociological literature.18

    MAPPING DISJUNCTIVE SOCIAL RELATIONS: OF FIELDS,

    FIGURATIONS, AND EXPLANATORY NARRATIVES

    How can the concepts and models developed so far be expanded to account for

    bouts of social change entailing degrees of institutional disintegration, as well as the

    generation of alternative institutions from social movements, military occupations,

    coup detats, and the like? The protracted conflict since 2001 between representa-

    tive democracies and Sunni Islamic-fundamentalist movements either sympathizing

    with, or actually carrying out, terrorist tactics, illustrates the prominence of dis-

    junctive social relations across human societies. For though this conflict involves

    institutionsfrom governments in Western nation-states to terrorist networks linkedto some Sunni mosques in different regions of the worldsuch institutions have not

    only failed to constrain the many complex networks involved in the conflict as a

    whole, but have often fed their antagonism. Mass media sometimes exacerbate this.

    Because acts of violence and terrorism grab the headlines, we seem to know a lot

    more about Islamic advocates of a clash, the militant jihadists, than about those

    who are working toward a peaceful revolution and civilizational dialogue (Esposito

    2002:133). Such media tendencies contribute, in turn, to intensifying antagonisms

    between representative democracies, on the one hand, and regional populations of

    Sunnis in the Islamic world more or less susceptible to the influence of Sunni Islamist

    terrorist networks, on the other.Norbert Elias stressed the importance of recognizing patterns of interdependent

    conflict between distinct societies. Characterized by a lack of what Elias called in-

    tegration, shared antagonism for others or their hatred and enmity towards each

    other mark such relations (Elias 1978:175). However, Eliass insight remains un-

    derappreciated in part due to his imprecise use of the term structure, such as his

    description of relations between antagonists lacking overarching patterns of insti-

    tutional mediation simply as structures formed between antagonistically related

    substructures, that is, societies (Elias 1978:24).

    By introducing a more differentiated range of concepts instead of asking struc-

    ture to describe most everything, we can clarify causal factors in conflicts. Forinstance, once we have specified institutional orders as the cores of fields, we

    18See, for instance, Armando Razos finely detailed maps of both Overlapping Protection of PublicOfficials (Fig. 6.4) and Pimentel y Fagoagas Political Connections (Fig. 6.6) in the study of networksand political power in Porfirio Dazs prerevolutionary Mexico (Razo 2008:146, 148).

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    17/29

    THE MISSING KEY 341

    aggregate effects ------------------------------aggregate effects

    emergent

    properties

    disjunctive fields

    aggregate effects ------------------------------aggregate effects

    institutional fields

    Figure 4. The emergent properties of disjunctive fields and aggregate effects.

    can differentiate disjunctive fields as emergent properties of institutional fieldsthat serve as their initial conditions. Disjunctive fields entail relations between

    mutually antagonistic institutional fieldssuch as colonial conflicts between the

    Spanish conquest of the Americas and the end of the colonial era, or inter-

    mittent patterns of exploration or trade that developed alongside colonial con-

    flicts in this periodas well as gray areas emerging alongside institutional

    fields such as social movements, criminal networks, and the like, as shown in

    Figure 4.

    In the case of transnational conflicts, disjunctive fields emerge as consequences of

    relations between institutional fields that lack an overarching, shared institutional

    framework. In this sense, a world-system formed many years prior to the creationof global-scale institutions such as the United Nations, the International Monetary

    Fund, and the like in the wake of World War II.19 Yet such global-scale institu-

    tions remain weaker than many states, and disjunctive global fields coexist alongside

    them in historically irreducible patterns, ranging from spaces partially controlled

    by criminal transnational networks such as the illicit drug trade to transnational

    terrorist networks. Such coexistence is often highly complex, as the simultaneous in-

    ternational and unilateralist policies of the United States in recent years exemplifies.

    Moreover, analysts must simultaneously factor in both transnational institutional

    isomorphismsas global-scale corporate organization exemplifies (DiMaggio and

    Powell 1991)as well as patterns of regional institutional collapse, as in parts of thecontemporary Middle East, Central Asia, and sub-Saharan Africa.

    Distinguishing the international from the transnational clarifies how disjunctive

    relations may coexist and interpenetrate institutional orders. The absence of in-

    stitutional order in disjunctive fields themselves deserves particular attention. On a

    transnational level, for instance, we can map transnational demonstration effects

    the selective mimicking of things from technologies to institutional design in law

    operating in both institutionally and disjunctively isomorphic patterns.20 Within

    19Caution is used here with the concept of world-system introduced by Wallerstein (1976). So long assystem simply designates causal interrelations, this term remains compatible with the argument developedhere. But locating causal priority at the world-system as a whole is problematic from a perspective thatboth recognizes a multiplicity of regional capitalisms, as well as insists on the historical contingencyof global-scale development as a whole. Moreover, Wallersteins perspective excludes a range of potentialcausal factors such as meanings.

    20The concept of transnational demonstration effect slightly modifies Bendix (1984) and Janos (1986:8495) by substituting transnational for international in order to capture such effects as emergent properties

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    18/29

    342 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

    institutions, such effects at times spur change among international organizations

    such as the United Nations, as well as patterns of institutional isomorphism within

    groups of regional states, within a state itself, and in more geographically restricted,

    substate regions. But other transnational demonstration effects operate across situ-

    ations of antipathy with little or no overall institutional regulation, such as Cold

    War-era competition between the Western and Soviet blocs leading to isomorphicpatterns of weapons design.

    Here, the role of transnational networks must figure in analyses of how such

    demonstration effects actually operate across disjunctive fields. Of course, there are

    open transnational networks linking phenomena as diverse as corporations, social

    movements, and nongovernmental organizations across national spaces, and their

    role in spurring transnational isomorphism is obvious. But other types of transna-

    tional networks coexisting or even quietly encouraged by more open networks can

    figure prominently in such causal dynamics, such as covert transnational networks

    connected in surreptitious ways to states, corporations, and the like. Other examples

    such as organized crime and terrorist cells operate almost exclusively from highlyopaque transnational networks. All of these came together in the case of the North

    Korean regimes opportunistic adaptation of military technologies across disjunctive

    fields that led to detonation of a nuclear weapon based on technologies gleaned

    indirectly from Western powers through the mediation of the Khan network in Pak-

    istan (Corera 2006:86102). Here, we see linkages between transnational networks

    operating with connections to state intelligence services, corporations, and organized

    crime, on the one hand, and transnational demonstration effects, on the other.

    Elias additionally developed the concept of figuration to introduce the perspective

    of agents to such fields: for him, a structure from the vantage point of the social

    sciences appeared as a figuration from the perspective of an agent living her orhis life in relation to other situated agents. What we call structure is, in fact,

    nothing but the pattern or figuration of interdependent individual people who form

    the group or, in a wider sense, the society. What we term structures when we

    look at people as societies, are figurations when we look at them as individuals

    (Elias 1998a:101). Bourdieus distinction between habitus and fieldrefined here

    to encompass the duality of institutions as embodied institutional paradigms and

    relational institutional ordersaccomplishes much the same thing. This leaves us free

    to modify the concept of figuration to specify patterns of representation generated

    by agents, everything from informal conversations to more elaborate discourses such

    as texts, ideologies, and speeches.A huge continuum of such figurations are bound by the doxa of a given culture,

    Bourdieus adaptation (1991a:16370) of an ancient Greek term for current opinion

    (Goody and Watt 1968:53) to map conventional frames of discourse that order

    everyday speech in particular societies. Such doxa constitute figurational aspects of

    a broader life world, a phenomenological concept postulated by Alfred Schutz and

    developed by Jurgen Habermas (1987:11952) to trace a horizon of relevance

    (1987:12122) orienting everyday practices in a given social group at a given time.

    Within this broader boundary of intelligibility, a doxa emerges as a more limited

    conversational boundary of convention.21

    operative in both institutional and disjunctive fields. Bendix and Janos, in turn, reconstructed the economicconcept of international demonstration effect in more sociologically diverse ways.

    21An exchange with Robert N. Bellah inspired the synthesis of Bourdieu and Habermas proposed here.

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    19/29

    THE MISSING KEY 343

    From a doxa, in turn, emerge various orthodoxies and what Bourdieu in his

    later writings called allodoxia (Bourdieu 1996a:7475), patterns of misrecognition

    that sometimes serve as ideologies in Marx and Engelss early sense in The German

    Ideology. Heterodoxies, in turn, form as either unconventional or oppositionaland

    sometimes bothfigurations to orthodoxies and allodoxia.

    Empirical criteria thus need to be developed on a case-by-case basis to establishwhether a figuration functions as an orthodox, allodoxic, or heterodox tendency in

    a particular time and place. Not all orthodoxies are ideologies by any meanstake,

    for example, instances of religious orthodoxy motivating highly risky human rights

    work against certain states. We have thus developed a suite of concepts for mapping

    continuums running from various orthodoxies through various allodoxia to various

    heterodoxies, facilitating robust analyses of how terms like common sense function

    practically.

    Institutions order the diverse array of figurations outlined here both in terms

    of class, status, and power, and more broadly in terms of simply enabling conven-

    tional patterns of speech. Specifically, institutional paradigms enable such figurationsas the syntagmatic telling of stories that make conventional sense across time

    in various fields. This clarifies the relation between paradigmatic and syntagmatic

    (story telling) levels introduced by Mouzelis (1995:6980), insofar as institutional

    paradigms enable the emergence of figurations coherent in a social group.

    The recursive effects (Giddens 1984) of figurations as various patterns of nar-

    rative help regenerate institutions on an ongoing basis. We thus refine our analytic

    model of how the virtuous circle of stability in institutional orders works. Yet

    such narratives also emerge from antagonistic relations and aggregate effects within

    disjunctive fields. Distinguishing disjunctive from institutional fields clarifies how fig-

    urations may order regional perceptions of both cooperation and antagonism withinand between various geographic regions. Understanding how such perceptions de-

    velop in turn is key to reconstructing the history of various networks. Conceiving

    various narrativesfrom skeins of common sense to journalistic discourse to ide-

    ological pronouncements to academic writing and so onas figurations of both

    institutional and disjunctive fields clarifies patterns of recognition and misrecogni-

    tion across them.22

    Projects to create and stabilize international institutions since the end of World

    War II, for instance, have simultaneously entailed attempts by the very agents in

    dominant states engineering them to curtail their reach and steer them in ways that

    maintain national hegemony within them. Tensions between figurations released byU.N.s officials, and actual U.N. practices constrained by dominant powers such as

    the United States, mark the U.N.s institutional history, a clear example of how

    misrecognition unfolds in international institutions. Moreover, hysteresis effects

    time lags between patterns of rapid institutional change and individual adjustment

    to such change generated in part through conventions of habitusappear often in

    history (Bourdieu and Wacquant 1992:130).

    The complex intertwining of institutions, institutional fields, disjunctive fields,

    agents, networks, and figurations indicates the sometimes importance of noninsti-

    tutional relations in patterns of social change. Indeed, differentiation of institutional

    and disjunctive fields, and discourses within and across them, creates social spaces

    22The regime of reproduction would thus be under constant threat . . . if this threat were not counter-balanced by . . .misrecognition of the arbitrary nature of the established order and its perpetuation, andhence in the recognition granted to such an order (Bourdieu 1996b:375).

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    20/29

    344 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

    TI t4

    IOt1 IOt2 IOt3 OSt4 IOt5

    INt4

    IP t1 IPt2 IPt3 IPt4 IPt5

    IO = institutional order

    IP = institutional paradigms, aspects of a larger habitus

    IN = informal networks

    OS = organizational shells of formerly stable institutional organizations

    TI = truncated institutional orders

    t = particular times

    Figure 5. Mapping processes of trajectory improvisation at the level of states.

    Source: Garcelon (2005:23, 2006:263).

    for noninstitutional networking over a period of time, as with social movements.

    Such movements may have significant consequences for institutional stability, for the

    power of nonviolent disruption comes mainly from its uncertainty as disorganizer

    of institutional routines (Tarrow 1994:109). By extension, such movements generate

    counterinstitutional figurations contesting authoritative figurations in official state

    discourses. Figurations can thereby have powerful causal effects in processes of state

    breakdown. Take the role of pro-democracy figures in the Soviet media in rapidly

    undermining the authority of the briefly existing Soviet State Committee for the

    State of Emergency (GKChP)the committee that tried to suppress perestroika in

    August 1991by broadcasting things out of synch with the GKChP during its failedattempt to seize power between August 18 and 20, 1991 (Bonnell and Freidin 1993).

    In the modern period, we can describe state breakdown as rapid slippage of

    hitherto stable institutional patterns of trajectory adjustment into patterns of trajec-

    tory improvisation, in which a relative handful of political entrepreneurs (Garcelon

    2006:26265) may mobilize everything from social movements to alliance with oc-

    cupying military forces in attempting to generate alternatives to disintegrating insti-

    tutions. In more authoritarian societies, state decline involving even partial loss of

    control over the mass media aggravates the process by opening the political field to

    alternative figurations. When state institutions disintegrate entirely, we see how such

    political entrepreneurs may fashion what can eventually consolidate as alternativeinstitutions, though this may be a very protracted and traumatic process, as seen in

    the cases of the Soviet collapse and the occupation of Iraq starting in 2003. Figure 5

    graphs processes of trajectory improvisation in a preliminary fashion.

    All of this gives us a way of historicizing the empirical study of social change

    across the widest range of cases. Rather than assumptions of institutional con-

    vergence around an assumed end point in the future, we now have concepts for

    analyzing regional and historical variants of capitalisms, socialisms, democra-

    cies, and authoritarianisms. Sociologyindeed all of the social sciences, includ-

    ing economicsshould focus on developing historically irreducible causal accounts

    of particular skeins of developmental history, rather than attempting to generatealgorithmic generalizations across cases.

    Indeed, due to the nature of the object of knowledge in the social sciences, such

    generalizations often prove impossible. The sciences in general are only beginning

    to come to terms methodologically with the preponderance of historical explanation

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    21/29

    THE MISSING KEY 345

    in biology, and its growing importance in the physical sciences as well, such as in

    the study of atmospheric dynamics, planetary surfaces, geological formations, ocean

    currents, and so on. In the social sciences, little can be generalized in an explanatory

    sense beyond boundary disciplines like neuropsychology and physical anthropology.

    Rather, generalization is largely conceptual in the social sciences for all the reasons

    discussed above, and recognition of this stands as a sine qua non for consolidatingtheoretical coherence across sociology.

    What forms, then, do viable explanations take in sociology? One of the most

    important such forms develops narratives that identify causally significant junctures

    in historically irreducible sequences. Andrew Abbott (1988, 1991, 1992, 2004) calls

    such explanations exercises in narrative positivity. Here, the moniker explanatory

    narrative is used, as it better captures what Abbott is driving at, for he means

    by narrative positivity not so much a philosophical as a methodological position.

    Such explanatory narratives grapple with the empirical problem of how to factor

    multiple perspectives of various agents into a broader narrative sequence focused on

    key causal links in the chain.Explanatory narrative does not abandon an alternative explanatory strategy, the

    variables paradigm (Abbott 1992). It simply shifts it to an available auxiliary mode

    of analysis useful for isolating and clarifying key aspects of sociohistorical pro-

    cesses. For instance, geology used variables analysis in formulating the historically

    irreducible hypothesis that identified a meteorite as the key causal initiator of a

    planet-wide sequence of events we know as the Cretaceous extinction 65 million

    years ago (Alvarez 1998). Explanatory narratives are thus common across the sci-

    ences, and such a strategy of causal analysis should be predominant in the social

    sciences.

    We thus see how distinctions between institutional paradigms, institutional orders,institutional fields, disjunctive fields, habitus, legitimacy, reflexive action, networks,

    and figurations can be used to supplant overburdened concepts of structures and con-

    struct explanatory narratives of differing outcomes in differing regions at different

    times without assuming cross-case algorithmic generalizations. Such explanatory nar-

    ratives can use both cross-case models and variables analysisand very usefullyas

    auxiliary methods so long as they avoid positing cross-case algorithmic uniformities

    as empirical theories per se. The recognition of the irreducible historicity of trajecto-

    ries of relative social stability and social change converges with an ongoing attempt

    in recent years to initiate a paradigm shift in sociology called neoclassical sociology

    by Eyal, Szelenyi, and Townsley (1998).

    WHAT IS NEOCLASSICAL SOCIOLOGY?

    Over the last 30 years, Karl Marxs historical materialism, Emile Durkheims struc-

    tural functionalism, and Max Webers interpretive sociology have emerged as the

    cornerstones of classical sociology. Marx, Durkheim, and Weber all conceived social

    science as the project of the universal theory of modernity, and all referenced what

    we now call classical economics in doing so. Starting in the 1930s, Talcott Parsons

    attempted to unify sociology theoretically by both marginalizing historical materi-

    alism and incorporating psychoanalysis, but his project evinced strong oppositionfrom within the discipline and collapsed in the late 1970s. With the eclipse of Par-

    sonss project, sociology fell into protracted disagreement over its theoretical core.

    Nonetheless, the drive to achieve a unified disciplinary matrixThomas Kuhns

    at UNICAMP /BIBLIOTECA CENTRAL on February 11, 2014stx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/http://stx.sagepub.com/
  • 7/22/2019 Sociological Theory 2010 Garcelon 326 53

    22/29

    346 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

    modification of what he earlier called a paradigm 23persisted, gaining momentum in

    the last 15 years. Sometimes this appears as a generic project to reunify sociological

    theory (Mouzelis 1995), and sometimes as the more specific project of neoclassical

    sociology (Eyal et al. 1998).

    Consolidating a neoclassical disciplinary matrix entails recognizing and avoiding

    the conundrums that undermined the various classical projects. In particular, the col-lapse of a universal theory of modernity into the generation of empirical hypotheses

    proved the Achilles heel of the classical theorists otherwise distinct projects, bring-

    ing the classical period to grief. Neoclassical sociology revives the project of unifying

    theory through generalizable concepts and heuristic models, but organizes research

    around the comparative study of a multiplicity of socially and geographically dis-

    tinct historical outcomes within a larger patter