Social Choices

download Social Choices

of 292

Transcript of Social Choices

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    1/292

    COLLECTIVE DECISION MAKING

    Pierre Dehez

    CORE

    University of Louvain

    [email protected]

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    2/292

    2

    Outline

    1. Preferences, utility and choices

    2. Cardinal welfarism distributive justice

    utilitarism vsegalitarism

    Nash bargaining

    social welfare orderings

    transferable utility games

    3. Ordinal welfarism the case of two alternatives

    social choice procedures

    impossibility theorems

    possibility theorems

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    3/292

    3

    References

    Austen-Smith D. and J. Banks,Positive political theory I: Collective preferences,

    University of Michigan Press, 1999.

    Austen-Smith D. and J. Banks,Positive political theoryII: Strategy and structure,

    University of Michigan Press, 2005.

    Brams S., Game theory and politics, Dover, 2004.

    Brams S.,Mathematics and democracy, Princeton University Press, 2008.

    Moulin H.,Axioms of cooperative decision making, Cambridge University Press, 1998.*

    Moulin H.,Fair division and collective welfare, MIT Press, 2003.*

    Taylor A.,Mathematics and politics, Springer-Verlag, 1995.

    Peyton Young H.,Equity. In theory and Practice, Princeton University Press, 1995.Handbook of social choice and welfare, Elsevier, 2002.

    * Moulin's monographies have inspired some of the material presented here.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    4/292

    4

    1.Preferences, utility and choices

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    5/292

    5

    Preferences

    Preferences over a setAof alternativesare defined by a (binary)

    relation overA:

    bis not preferred to a

    from which the strictpreference and indifferencerelations are deduced:

    ais preferred to b

    indifference between aand b

    a b

    a b

    a b

    [ and ]a b b a

    [ and ]a b b a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    6/292

    6

    Preferences arerational if they verify the following properties:

    - completeness:

    - reflexivity:

    - transitivity:

    Completeness is by far the most demanding assumption!

    A relation satisfying reflexivity and transitivity is apreorder.

    We denote byL(A) the set of preorders on a setA.

    [ or ] for all ,a b b a a b A

    [ and ]a b b c a c

    for alla a a A

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    7/292

    7

    Ordinal utilities

    A preference preorder carries no information on the intensity of

    preferences:

    if ais preferred to band cis preferred to d, we don't know

    whether ais "more preferred" to bthan cis preferred to d

    Under minimal assumptions, preferences can be represented by a

    utility function which associates a real

    number to each alternative, such that:

    : : ( )u A a A u a

    ( ) ( )u a u b a b

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    8/292

    8

    As such, this is an ordinalrepresentation of preferences:

    only the sign of the difference provides

    an information on the preferences between aand b

    As a consequence, u and where is an arbitrary

    increasing transformation, both represent the same preferences.

    T(u) = u3is the simplest nonlinear transformation with range

    ( ) ( )u a u b

    ( ) ( ) 0

    ( ) ( ) 0

    u a u b a b

    u a u b a b

    :T ( )v T u

    .

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    9/292

    9

    Choices

    Given a set of alternativesAand preferences a choice is a best

    element inA:

    ( ),L A

    *

    * for all

    a A

    a a a A

    There may be several best elements. The set of solutions is called the

    choice set.

    or

    * maximizes ( ) ona u a A

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    10/292

    10

    Let denote the choice set associated to a setAof alternatives

    and a preference relation Then:

    ( , )C A

    There is indifference between the elements of a choice set.

    In the multivalued case, a neutral mechanism is necessary to eventually

    retain a uniquealternative.

    For instance a random mechanism.

    , ( , )a b C A a b

    .

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    11/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    12/292

    12

    Collectivity: preference profiles

    Consider a setA of alternatives and nindividuals indexed by irunning

    from 1 to n, each having a preference relation

    Apreference profilePspecifies a preference relation for each member

    of the group:

    A utility profile can be associated to any alternative aA:

    ( ).i L A

    1( ,..., ) ( )n

    nP L A

    1( ) ( ),..., ( ) n

    nu a u a u a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    13/292

    13

    One of the questions addressed by social choice is the determination

    of a collectivepreference ordering for comparing utility profiles.

    There are several levels of independencethat collective preferences

    may satisfy:

    1. Ordinal, non-comparable: full independence

    2. Ordinal, comparable: independence of common utility space

    3. Cardinal, non-comparable: independence of utility scales

    4. Cardinal, partially comparable: independence of zero utilities

    5. Cardinal, comparable: independence of utility scales and zero utilities

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    14/292

    14

    Given a set of alternativeAand a preference profile onA

    represented by utility functions u1,,un we define the attainable

    utility set

    The problem is then to pick up a point in this set, possibly given the

    specification of a disagreement point din U(A).

    1( ,..., ) ( )n

    n L A

    1( ) ( ),..., ( ) ,n

    nU A u u u a u a a A

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    15/292

    15

    1. Ordinal, non-comparable: full independence

    This is the situation where each individual utility level is defined up toan arbitrary increasing transformation:

    where the Ti's are arbitrary increasing transformation

    1 1

    1 1 1 1

    ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )

    ( ( ),..., ( )) ( ( ),..., ( ))

    n n

    n n n n

    u u v v

    T u T u T v T v

    from into .

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    16/292

    16

    2. Ordinal, comparable: independence of common utility space

    This is the situation where individual utility levels are defined up to anarbitrary and commonincreasing transformation:

    where Tis an arbitrary increasing transformation

    1 1

    1 1

    ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )

    ( ( ),..., ( )) ( ( ),..., ( ))

    n n

    n n

    u u v v

    T u T u T v T v

    from into .

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    17/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    18/292

    18

    4. Cardinal, partially comparable: independence of zero utilities

    This is the situation where each individual utility level is defined up toan increasing and affine transformation:

    Alternatively:

    1 1

    1 1 1 1

    ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )

    ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )

    n n

    n n n n

    u u v v

    u b u b v b v b

    1for all , ..., .nb b

    1 1 1 1( ,..., ) ( ,..., ) ( ,..., ) (0,..., 0)n n n nu u v v u v u v

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    19/292

    19

    5. Cardinal, comparable: independence of utility scales and zero utilities

    This is the situation where individual utility levels are defined up to anincreasing and affine commontransformation:

    1 1

    1 1

    ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )

    ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )

    n n

    n n

    u u v v

    a u b a u b a v b a v b

    for all , , 0.a b a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    20/292

    20

    2.Cardinal welfarism

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    21/292

    21

    2.1Distributive justice

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    22/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    23/292

    23

    Liberalism: the social order emerges from the interaction of free wills.

    Methodological individualismis at the root of liberalism.

    Individuals are characterized by values, rightsand obligations.

    Distributive justice has two sides:

    - procedural justice: is the distribution of rights fair ?

    - end-state justice: is the outcome fair ?

    We start with a simple problem of sharing a resource.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    24/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    25/292

    25

    Principle 1: ex ante equality

    There arebasic rightslike freedom of speech, access to education,

    freedom of religion, equal political rights (one person, one vote),

    They induce ex ante equality: equal claim to the basic resources.

    Private ownership or differences in status (for instance seniority)are instances of unequalexogenous rights which justify unequal

    treatment.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    26/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    27/292

    27

    Principle 3: reward or penalize

    justifies unequal sharesyi's of resources to compensate

    for voluntary differencesin individuals' characteristics:

    - past sacrifies justify a larger share

    - past abuses justify a lesser share

    How to reward individual contributions ?

    The answer if difficult when there are externalities(extraction of

    exhaustible resources, division of joint costs or surpluses).

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    28/292

    28

    Principle 4: best use of the resources (fitness)

    resources must go to those that can make the best use them.

    Fitness justifies unequal treatment by differences in talent,

    independently of basic rights, needs or merits.

    Two definitions:

    sum-fitness: maximization of the sum of the individual utilities

    efficiency-fitness: Pareto optimality

    Sum-fitness implies efficiency fitness.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    29/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    30/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    31/292

    31

    Transplants

    exogeneous rights: strict equality (lottery) or priority ranking

    based on social status or wealth

    compensation: priority to those suffering most or whose life

    expectancy is the shortest

    reward: priority to seniority on the waiting list

    fitness: maximization of the chances of success

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    32/292

    32

    Seats: auctioning or queuing

    exogenous rights: only a lottery would induce a strict equality

    reward: queuing reward efforts while auctioning

    does not

    fitness: queuing meets sum-fitness but involves awaste of time auctioning is better if

    individuals are comparable, because otherwise

    it favors the rich

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    33/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    34/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    35/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    36/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    37/292

    37

    Assumption: equal exogenous rights

    the allocation depends only on the

    distribution of claims or liabilities

    An allocation methodis a rule that associates an allocation

    to any given allocation problem such that

    1 1( ,..., ) ( , ,..., )n nx x E d d

    1( , ,..., )nE d d ( ) .x N E

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    38/292

    x2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    39/292

    39

    0

    2

    x1

    d2

    d1

    PROP

    11

    1 2

    22

    1 2

    dx E

    d dd

    x Ed d

    22 1

    1

    dx xd

    1 2x x E

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    40/292

    x2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    41/292

    41

    0

    2

    x1

    d2

    d1

    ES

    SURPLUS: d1+d2 < E and d1 > d2

    d1d2

    2 1 2 1( )x x d d

    2 1x x

    1 21

    2 12

    2

    2

    E d d

    x

    E d dx

    x2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    42/292

    42

    0

    2

    x1

    d2

    d1

    ES

    SURPLUS: d1+d2 < E and d1< d2

    d2d1

    2 1 2 1( )x x d d 2 1x x

    1 21

    2 12

    2

    2

    E d d

    x

    E d dx

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    43/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    44/292

    x2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    45/292

    45

    0x1

    d2

    d1

    UG

    2 1x x

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    46/292

    Uniform gain rule (in case of a deficit)

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    47/292

    47

    Uniform gain rule(in case of a deficit)

    satisfies

    1

    ( , )

    where satisfies ( , )

    i i

    n

    ii

    x Min z d

    z E Min z d

    for all .i ix d i

    Herezcan be interpreted as the common gain.

    This rule is also called "constrained" egalitarian.

    y = f(z) 2y z y d z

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    48/292

    48

    0

    y f( )

    zd2 d1

    d1+d2

    y2y d z

    1 2( ) ( , ) ( , )f z Min z d Min z d

    1 2d d

    2d2

    d2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    49/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    50/292

    y = f(z) DEFICIT: d1+d2 > E

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    51/292

    51

    0zd2 d1

    d1+d2

    1y d z 1 2 2y d d z

    1 2( ) ( , 0) ( , 0)f z Max d z Max d z

    1 2d d

    d1d2

    d1

    DEFICIT: d1+d2 E

    x2DEFICIT: d1+d2 > E

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    52/292

    52

    0x1

    d2

    d1d1d2

    2 1 2 1( )x x d d

    DEFICIT: d1 d2 E

    1 21

    2 12

    2

    2

    E d dx

    E d dx

    2 1x x

    UL

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    53/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    54/292

    Proportional (surplus/deficit)( )

    i i

    Ex d

    d N

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    55/292

    55

    Proportional (surplus/deficit)

    Equal surplus (surplus)

    Uniform gain (surplus)

    Uniform gain (deficit)

    Uniform loss (deficit)( ,0)

    where is such that

    i i

    i

    x Max d z

    z x E

    ( )i i

    d N

    1( ( ))i ix d E d Nn

    ( , )

    where is such that

    i i

    i

    x Min z d

    z x E

    ( , )

    where is such that

    i i

    i

    x Max z d

    z x E

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    56/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    57/292

    Surplus: n= 5,E= 80 and d= (20, 16, 10, 8, 6)

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    58/292

    58

    1 216 20 and 165

    Ex x

    3 4 5

    3614.7 14.7

    3

    Ex x x

    ( ) 60d N E

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    59/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    60/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    61/292

    E= di= 20 16 10 8 6

    20 PRO 6 7 5 3 3 3 2 7 2

    60id

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    62/292

    62

    20 PRO 6.7 5.3 3.3 2.7 2

    UG 4 4 4 4 4

    UL 11.3 7.3 1.3 0 0

    40 PRO 13.3 10.7 6.7 5.3 4

    UG 8.7 8.7 8.7 8 6

    UL 16 12 6 4 2

    50 PRO 16.7 13.3 8.3 6.7 5

    UG 13 13 10 8 6UL 18 14 8 6 4

    80 PRO 26.7 21.3 13.3 10.7 8

    UG 20 16 14.7 14.7 14.7

    ES 24 20 14 12 10

    120 PRO 40 32 20 16 12

    UG 24 24 24 24 24

    ES 32 28 22 20 18

    deficit

    su

    rplus

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    63/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    64/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    65/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    66/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    67/292

    1. Invariance to transfers

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    68/292

    68

    if iandj"merge" into a single individual, is the resulting

    share equalto the sum of the individuals' shares ?

    Only theproportional ruleis invariant to transfers.

    The uniform gain ruleis not: merging leads to a smalleror equal share.

    The uniform loss ruleis not: merging leads to a higher

    or equal share.

    2. Truncation property

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    69/292

    69

    In case of a deficit, a solution satisfies the truncation property

    if truncating the claims toE

    does not affect the resulting allocation.

    The uniform gainrulesatisfies the truncation property.

    The uniform loss ruleand theproportional rule do not.

    ,i i id d Min d E

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    70/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    71/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    72/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    73/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    74/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    75/292

    1 2y y

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    76/292

    76

    y1

    y2

    0 t1

    t2

    FlatHead

    Levelling

    y1y2

    2 1 1 2( )t t y y 2 1t t

    22 1

    1

    yt t

    y

    1 2y y

    1 2y y

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    77/292

    77

    y1

    y2

    0 t1

    t2

    FlatHead

    Levelling

    y1y2

    2 1 1 2( )t t y y 2 1t t

    22 1

    1

    yt t

    y

    1 2y y

    Principles

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    78/292

    78

    1. Fair ranking

    A higher income justifies both a higher tax burden and a higher after-

    tax income :

    Under this principle, equal incomes are taxed equally.

    i ji j

    i i j j

    t ty yy t y t

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    79/292

    2. Progressive tax

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    80/292

    80

    A higher income justifies a higher the tax rate:

    3. Regressive tax

    A higher income justifies a lower the tax rate:

    orji i i

    i j

    i j j j

    tt t yy y

    y y t y

    jii j

    i j

    tty y

    y y

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    81/292

    progressive region: levelling tax

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    82/292

    82

    0

    progressive region: levelling tax

    is the most progressive method

    y1

    y2

    t1

    t2

    y1y2 T

    T

    2 2

    1 1

    t y

    t y

    The exponential methodis defined by:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    83/292

    83

    where is choosen such that

    It is progressive forp> 1and regressive forp< 1.

    It is the flat tax forp= 1.

    It is the head tax forp= 0.

    , for some 0pi i it Min y y p

    .it T

    t2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    84/292

    84

    y1

    y2

    0 t1y1y2

    Equal sacrifice

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    85/292

    85

    "Equality of taxation means equality of sacrifice.It means apportioning the contribution of each

    person towards the expenses of the government

    so that he shall feel neither more nor less incon-

    venience from his share of the payment than

    every other person experiences from his."

    John Stuart Mill,Principle of Economics, 1848

    Let ui(y) be the utility associated to incomeyby individuali.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    86/292

    86

    Equal sacrifice means choosing taxes in such a way that differences of

    utilities are equalized:

    To avoid interpersonal utility comparisons, we postulate a common

    utility function u (a kind of social norm):

    Mill proposed to use the Bernoulli utility function logy.

    ( ) ( ) for alli i i i iu y u y t z i

    ( ) ( ) for alli i iu y u y t z i

    yields theproportional tax:

    j jy ty t

    ( ) logu y y

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    87/292

    87

    Equal relativesacrifice means choosing taxes in such a way that ratios

    of utilities are equalized:

    It is merely equivalentto equal absolute sacrifice: the log of the ratio

    equals the difference of the log.

    j ji i

    i i j j i j

    y ty t

    y t y t y y

    ( )

    for all( )i i

    i

    u y t

    z iu y

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    88/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    89/292

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    90/292

    The solution can then be alternatively written as:

    1

    E Mi E d Mi E d

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    91/292

    91

    The contested garment rule satisfies both the truncation property and

    the concession property. Actually, it is the only 2-person rule satisfyingthese two properties. They define it.

    An allocation rule has the contested garment propertyif, when

    applied to a 2-person problem, it coincides with the contested garmentsolution.

    1 1 2

    2 2 1

    , ,2

    1, ,

    2

    x E Min E d Min E d

    x E Min E d Min E d

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    92/292

    92

    2.2 Egalitarism vsutilitarism

    Egalitarian vsutilitarian solutions

    egalitarian solution (compensation):

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    93/292

    93

    egalitarian solution(compensation):

    utilitarian solution(sum-fitness):

    1find ( ,..., ) such that ( ) ( ) for all , and ( )n i i j jx x u x u x i j x N E

    1find ( ,..., ) that maximizes ( ) subject to ( )n i ix x u x x N E

    The egalitarian solution solution may not be defined. The proper

    formulation should instead be the following:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    94/292

    94

    1find ( , ..., ) 0 such that ( )and

    0 ( ) ( )

    n

    i i i j j j

    x x x N E

    x u x Min u x

    Whether or not the utility function are concave (decreasing marginalutility) impacts the comparison of the two solutions.

    In the concave case, the two solutions are in some sense identical.

    Furthermore, the three solutions studied earlier turns out to be special

    cases.

    The link between the two solutions when utility functions are

    increasing and concave(and differentiable) appears by comparing

    the revised definition of the egalitarian solution and the first order

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    95/292

    95

    the revised definition of the egalitarian solution and the first order

    conditionassociated to the utilitarian solution:

    0 ( ) ( )i i i j j jx u x Min u x

    0 ( ) ( )i i i j j jx u x Max u x

    Hence, the utilitarian solution with utility functions uicorresponds to

    the egalitarian solution with utility functionsui'.

    If concavity is quite natural in a context of income distribution,

    convexity may be adequate in other context e.g. medical rationing.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    96/292

    The egalitarian solutionreads:

    0 ( ) ( )i i i j N j jx u x Min u x

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    97/292

    97

    becauseuis increasing. Hence

    We observe that this solution is equivalentto the uniform gain solutionapplied to the problem of dividing the amount

    with claims

    0 ( ) ( )

    ( )

    i i i j N j j

    i i j N j j

    x u x Min u x

    x Min x

    ' ( )E E N

    for all , .i i j jx x i j

    .i id

    The utilitarian solutionis the solution of the following maximization

    problem:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    98/292

    98

    Using the 1storder conditions, we have:

    because u'is decreasing. Hence

    0 ( ) ( )

    ( )

    i i i j N j j

    i i j N j j

    x u x Max u x

    x Max x

    ( ) subject to:

    0 1,...,

    j j j

    i

    Max u x x E

    x i n

    for all , .i i j jx x i j

    If now uis a strictly convexfunction, the egalitarian solution

    is unchanged. Being a uniform gain solution, it is independent

    of the choice of the base utility function that only needs to be

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    99/292

    99

    of the choice of the base utility functionthat only needs to be

    increasing.

    The utilitarian solution instead allocates all the resource to the

    richest individual!

    Indeed ifpositiveamountsxiandxjare allocated to the iandj

    such that strict convexity implies:

    i.e. transferringxjto i increases the sum of the utilities.

    i j

    ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )i i j j i i j ju x u x u x x u

    Another example

    Assume the utility functions are of the form

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    100/292

    100

    Assume the utility functions are of the form

    where the i's are positive "productivities" and uis some base

    and strictly concaveutility function such that u(0) = 0.

    Here the two principles give opposite recommendations.

    ( ) ( )i i i iu x u x

    The egalitarian solutionsimply equalizes utilities:

    ( ) ( ) for all ,i i j ju x u x i j

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    101/292

    101

    The utility function ubeing strictly increasing, shares and

    productivities are negatively correlated:

    The utilitarian solutionis defined by the 1storder conditions

    By strict concavity, shares and productivities are nowpositively

    correlated:

    ( ) ( ) for all ,i i j ju x u x i j

    i j i jx x

    i j i jx x

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    102/292

    102

    2.3Nash bargaining

    Consider a game in strategic (normal) form (S1, S2, u1, u2) involving two

    players.

    We de te b A the et f e e e ll i f el ted

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    103/292

    103

    We denote byAthe set of consequences, allowing for correlated

    strategies and we work directly on the expectedutility set

    Players may agree on a choice of strategies, knowing that incase of disagreement, they find themself in some situation that

    corresponds to a pair of utilities d = (d1,d2) U(A).

    One possibility is to refer to prudent (MaxMin) strategies in

    which case diis the security level of player i.

    2 1 2( ), ( ) ,U u u u a u a a A

    A bargaining problem is defined by pair (U,d) where

    Uis a subset of that is closed, convex and bounded above2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    104/292

    104

    dis a point in Usuch that there exists some uU, u>> d

    Example: the battle of sexes

    strategic form correlated strategiesa2 b2

    a1 2,1 0,0

    b1 0,0 1,2

    a2 b2

    a1 p1 p2

    b1 p3 p4

    0 1 and 1i ip p

    (1 2)

    u2battle of sexes

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    105/292

    105

    (1,2)

    (2,1)

    (0,0) u1

    U

    a2 b2

    a1 2,1 0,0

    b1 0,0 1,2

    In general, Uis the convex hull of the utility pairs corresponding

    topure strategies:

    u2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    106/292

    106

    u1

    C7

    C8

    U

    U

    Bargaining problem need not result from a game situation. This is the

    case of allocation problems like the bankcruptcy problem.

    u2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    107/292

    107d= (0,0)

    u1

    L

    L

    C2

    C1

    U

    C1+ C2>L

    A solution to a bargaining problem (U,d) is a point u* in Usatisfying the

    following minimalproperties:

    collective rationality: such that * and *u U u u u u

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    108/292

    108

    collective rationality:

    individual rationality:

    We look for a ruleassociating a solution to any bargaining problem

    (U,d).

    A bargaining problem (U,d) is symmetricif d1= d2and inter-changing

    the players results in the same set Ui.e. the 45line

    is a symmetry axis of U.

    such that and u U u u u u

    *u d

    u2

    individual + collective rationality

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    109/292

    109

    u1d1

    d2

    U

    d

    symmetric bargaining problem

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    110/292

    110

    45

    d

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    111/292

    These three axioms determine the solution of symmetric

    bargaining problems:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    112/292

    112

    (U,d)

    d

    (1,2)

    u2 battle of sexes

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    113/292

    113

    ( , )

    (2,1)

    (0,0) u1

    U

    3 3( , )2 2

    Because utilities are expected utilities we need the following

    further axiom.

    Independence with respect to preference representation (covariance)

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    114/292

    114

    p p p p ( )

    (U,d) (V,c) wherevi= ai+ biui (bi> 0)

    ci= ai+ bidi

    i(V,c) = a

    i+ b

    i

    i(U,d) (i = 1,2)

    Indeed we are in a cardinalframework with non comparable utilities

    (independence of utility scales).

    b 5

    i ii

    i i

    u dv

    b d

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    115/292

    115

    d1=2 b1=71

    1

    b2-d2=2

    b1-d1=5

    (4.5, 4)

    (2.5, 1)

    (0.5, 0.5)

    d2=3

    b2=5i i

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    116/292

    The following axiom extends the solution to all bargaining problems.

    Independence with respect to irrelevant alternatives:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    117/292

    117

    If (U,d) and (V,d) are such that

    UV and (V,d) U

    then (U,d) = (V,d).

    (V,d) U

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    118/292

    118

    (U,d) = (V,d)

    UV

    u2

    Here the bargaining problem (V,d) is defined by the line tangent to Uat its mid point:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    119/292

    119

    u1d

    U

    (U,d)

    this is theNash solution

    u2contour curves are

    rectangular hyperbolas

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    120/292

    120

    u1d

    (u1d1)(u2d2) = constantu*

    U

    Indeed the line segment tangent to a rectangular hyperbola and restricted

    to the axis is divided in its middle at the tangency point.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    121/292

    121

    Hence, the Nash solution is nothing but the solution of the maximizationof theproduct of the gains on U:

    MaxuU(u1d1)(u2d2)

    u2

    L Ci>L/2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    122/292

    122

    0 u1

    L

    C2

    C1

    u1* = u2* =L/2u*

    L/2

    L/2

    u2

    L

    C2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    123/292

    123

    0 u1

    L

    C2

    C1

    u1* =LC2u2* = C2

    u*L/2

    L/2

    u2

    Problem with the Nash solution: truncating the Uset leavesthe solution unchanged !

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    124/292

    124

    0 u1

    u*

    Relative utilitarism (Kalai et Smorodinsky)

    Each individual has an aspiration levelbi defined as the maximum utility

    level compatible with individual rationality

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    125/292

    125

    level compatible with individual rationality.

    Nash solution does not depend on individual aspirations.

    Relative utilitarism consists in satisfying individual in proportion

    to their aspirations.

    This solution relies on an monotonocity axiom replacing Nash's axiom of

    independence with respect to irrelevant alternatives.

    u2

    bu*

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    126/292

    126

    u1d1

    d2

    U

    d

    "idal" point

    u2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    127/292

    127

    0 u1

    u2

    L

    bi= Ci

    ui* =Ci L

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    128/292

    128

    0 u1L

    C2

    C1

    u*

    C1+ C2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    129/292

    129

    2.4 Social welfare orderings

    Welfarism postulates that the welfareof individuals is the only

    ingredient to be used to compare states of the world.

    Cardinal welfarismassumes that

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    130/292

    130

    - individual welfare utilities are measured by a utility index

    - utilities can be "compared"

    Because it concentrates exclusively on utility profiles, welfarism

    has no ethical content. For instance, the "non-envy" criterion doesnot enter into account.

    The task of the benevolent dictator is to compare utility profiles

    and to identify the best profile.1( ,..., )nu u

    Efficiency-fitnessis one of the basic concept of welfarism. It underlies

    utilitarism.

    LetAdenote the set of feasible states. A statex in APareto-dominates

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    131/292

    131

    a statex'inAif

    i.e. there is unanimityto move from statexto statex'.

    A feasible statexis Pareto optimalif it is notdominated by any

    feasible state.

    The other principle is compensation. It underlies egalitarism.

    with strict inequality( ) ( ') for all for at least on, ei iu x u x i i

    The preferences of the benevolent dictator are denoted by It is

    called social welfare ordering and it is assumed to be complete and

    transitive. The most widely used are:

    .

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    132/292

    132

    - utilitarian:

    - Nash:

    - egalitarian (leximin):

    1 1( ,..., ) ( ,..., )n n i iu u u u u u

    1 1 1 1( ,..., ) ( ,..., ) ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )n n n L nu u u u v v v v

    where is the applied to a reordering

    of the utility profile

    lexicographi

    s in an incr

    c

    e

    orderin

    asing .

    g

    way

    L

    1 1( ,..., ) ( ,..., )n n i iu u u u u u

    Lifeboat Consider the case of 5 individuals and the following feasible

    arrangments:

    {{1,2},{1,3},{1,4},{2,3,5}{3,4,5},{2,4,5}}A

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    133/292

    133

    Assume first that all individuals value equally being (10) and not being

    onboard (1).

    Utilitarismrecommends choosing one of the 3-person arrangments.

    Egalitarismrecommends the same solution:

    (1,1, ,10,10) (1,1, ,10,10)10 1L

    Assume now that utilities differ:

    1 2 3 4 5

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    134/292

    134

    Utilitarismnow recommends choosing either {1,2} or {1,3}. Theranking is given by:

    in 10 6 6 5 3

    out 0 1 1 1 0

    {1,2} {1,3} {1,4} {2,3,5} {2,4,5} {3,4,5}

    1 2 3 4 5

    in 10 6 6 5 3

    out 0 1 1 1 0

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    135/292

    135

    Egalitarismrecommends {2,3,5}.

    Indeed the corresponding ranking is:

    obtained from:

    (0,1, 3, 6, 6) (0,1, 3, 5, 6) (0,1,1, 6,10) (0,1,1, 5,10)L L L

    {2,3,5} {2,4,5} {3,4,5} {1,2} {1,3} {1,4}

    Collective utility function

    Most social welfare orderings can be represented by a collective utility

    function W(u1,,un).

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    136/292

    136

    A collective utility function Wis additiveif there exists some

    increasing functionfsuch that:

    for all (u1,,un).

    1( ,..., ) ( )n iW u u f u

    Additive collective utility functions

    Social welfare orderings are assumed to be complete and transitive.

    i ddi i l i

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    137/292

    137

    Five additional assumptions

    1. Monotonicity:

    2.Symmetry:

    1 1for all and ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )i i j j n nu u i j u u u u u u

    1 1

    1 1

    if ( ,..., ) is obtained from ( ,..., ) by permuting

    individuals, then ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )

    n n

    n n

    u u u u

    u u u u

    Monotonicity is compatible with Pareto optimality:

    1 1

    1 1

    if ( ,..., ) Pareto-dominates ( ,..., )

    then ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )

    n nu u u u

    u u u u

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    138/292

    138

    Hence, maximal elementson the set of feasible statesAof a monotonic

    social welfare ordering are Pareto-optimal.

    Symmetry is equivalent to "equal treatment of equals": only differences

    in utilities may justify discrimination.

    1 1n n

    3. Ignoring unconcerned individuals:

    ( , ) ( , ) ( , ) ( , ) for all ,i i i iu a u a u b u b a b

    where ( | ).i ju u j i

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    139/292

    139

    Hence social welfare orderings depends only on the welfare of the

    individuals who are affected.

    Proposition Any social welfare ordering represented by anadditivecollective utility function satisfies the above property.

    Under continuity, the converse is true: ignoringunconcerned

    individual implies additivity.

    4. Pigou-Dalton transfer principle: aversion for inequality

    If the utility profiles are such that:1 1( , ..., ) and ( , ..., )n nu u u u

    1 2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    140/292

    140

    then

    i.e. operating a transfer that reduces the inequality between any two

    individuals does not lead to a less preferred utility profile.

    1 2

    1 1 2 2

    for all 1,2

    and

    i i

    u uu u i

    u u a u u a

    1 1( ,..., ) ( ,..., ).n nu u u u

    5. Independence of common scale

    A common rescalingof every individual utility function leaves

    the social welfare ordering unaffected:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    141/292

    141

    Applied to an additive collective function, this property reads:

    Restricting to increasing and continuous functions f leads to

    1 1 1 1( ,..., ) ( ,..., ) ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )n n n nu u u u u u u u

    whenever 0 and 0 for all .i iu u i

    ( ) ( ) 0 ( ) ( ) 0i i i if u f u f u f u

    Proposition Any additive, increasing and continuous social welfare

    ordering satisfying the invariance property (5) can be represented by

    a collective utility function of one of the following three types:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    142/292

    142

    1

    1

    1

    ( ,..., ) for some 0 ( )

    ( ,..., ) log ( ) log

    1( ,..., ) for some 0 ( )

    p p

    n i

    n i

    p

    n p

    i

    W u u u p f u u

    W u u u f u u

    W u u p f u uu

    Maximizing is equivalent to maximizing Indeed,

    log is an increasing function and we have:

    log logi i

    u u

    .iulog iu

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    143/292

    143

    Hence, is called theNash collective utility function. It is the

    limit of the other two families of utility function forp 0.

    The classical utilitarian utilityfunction

    is obtained by settingp= 1 in the first family.

    i i

    log iu

    1( ,..., )n iW u u u

    Proposition An additive utility function

    meets the Pigou-Dalton transfer principle if and only if the functionf

    1( ,..., ) ( )n iW u u f u

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    144/292

    144

    is concave.

    For instance, the quadratic utility function

    promotes inequality. Indeed, because transferring

    utility to one individual is always preferable.

    21( ,..., )n iW u u u

    22

    i iu u

    Conclusion: if we impose the five requirements

    - monotonicity and symmetry

    - ignoring unconcerned individuals

    - aversion for inequality

    - independance of common scale

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    145/292

    145

    - independance of common scale

    we are left with the following family of utility functions:

    including their limits forp0.

    It is a one dimensional familydefined by a single parameter

    1

    1

    ( ,..., ) for some , 0 1

    ( ,..., ) for some 0

    p

    n i

    pn i

    W u u u p p

    W u u u p

    .p

    Leximinegalitarian social welfare ordering

    Equalization of utilities may not be possible because the ranges of

    the utility functions differ.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    146/292

    146

    Equalization of utilities may be incompatible with Pareto efficiency.

    The leximin social welfare orderingselects the most egalitarian among

    the Pareto optimal allocations.

    The leximin welfare ordering cannotbe represented by a collective

    utility function.

    However, it belongs to the family of additive concave collective utility

    f i i li i

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    147/292

    147

    functions in a limit sense.

    Proposition The social welfare ordering represented by the

    collective utility function

    converges to the leximin welfare ordering

    1( ,..., ) p

    n iW u u u

    for .p

    u2u1= u2

    UT

    no equalityefficiency trade-off

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    148/292

    148

    u1

    u1+ u2= constant

    EG = LEXU(A)

    u2u1= u2

    u1+ u2= constant

    no equalityefficiency trade-off

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    149/292

    149

    u1

    UT

    EG = LEXU(A)

    u2u1= u2

    UT

    LEX

    equalityefficiency trade-off

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    150/292

    150

    u1

    u1+ u2= constant

    U(A)

    u2u1= u2

    NASH

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    151/292

    151

    u1

    u1u2= constant

    U(A)

    Independence of the common utility space

    The leximin ordering is invariant with respect to a common

    transformationof the utilities:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    152/292

    152

    Proposition Leximin is the onlysocial welfare ordering satisfying the

    Pigou-Dalton transfer principle and the independence of the common

    utility space.

    1 1

    1 1

    ( , ..., ) ( ,..., )

    ( ( ),..., ( )) ( ( ),..., ( ))

    n L n

    n L n

    u u v v

    T u T u T v T v

    Independence of zero utilities

    The utilitarian social welfare ordering is invariant of zero utilities:

    1 1( ,..., ) ( ,..., )n nu u v v

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    153/292

    153

    1 1 1 1

    ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )

    ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )n n n n

    u u v v

    u w u w v w v w

    1for all ( ,..., ), ornw w

    1 1 1 1( ,..., ) ( ,..., ) ( ,..., ) (0,..., 0)n n n nu u v v u v u v

    Proposition The utilitarian social welfare ordering is the only social

    welfare ordering satisfying independence of zero utilities.

    Independence of utility scales

    The Nash social welfare ordering is independent of utility scales:

    1 1( ,..., ) ( ,..., )n nu u v v

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    154/292

    154

    1 1

    1 1 1 1 1 1

    ( , , ) ( , , )

    ( ,..., ) ( ,..., )

    n n

    n n n n n na u b a u b a v b a v b

    Proposition The Nash social welfare ordering is the only social welfare

    ordering satisfying independence of utility scales.

    for all 0 and .i ia b

    Example: location of a facility

    Consider the "linear" city represented by the interval [0,1] along which

    individuals are located:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    155/292

    155

    Ifxdenotes the location of the facility, the disutilityof agent iis

    measured by its distance to thex:

    ( )i iu x x t

    individual is located at [0,1]ii t

    If there are agents located at 0 or 1, the egalitarian solutionconsists in

    placing the facility in the middle: The corresponding ordered

    utility vector is of the form (1 /2,1/2,.).

    It differs from the utilitarian solution which picks the median

    1/ 2.x

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    156/292

    156

    d e s o e u so u o w c p c s e ed

    defined by:x

    1 1 { | } and { | }

    2 2i ii t x i t x

    This is indeed the point where total disutility is minimum: moving

    awayin any directionincreases the disutility of at least 1/2 of

    the individuals.

    Both solutions coincide when the individuals are uniformlydistributed

    on the interval [0,1].

    This is in particular the case of a continuum.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    157/292

    157

    The choice of the solution depends upon the kind of facility, in particular

    whether or not the facility is intented to meet basic needs (swimming

    pool vspost office).

    In some cases, the choice is difficult: where should a fire station

    be located ?

    Example: location of a noxiousfacility

    Now, the distance to the facility measures the utilityof agent i:

    ( )i iu x x t

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    158/292

    158

    In the extreme case of a continuum, the egalitarian solution consists in

    locating the facility anywherebecause there is an individual in any

    location.

    The utilitarian solution now picks one of the extreme points.

    The question is to compare the utilities at the end points.

    Indeed, iff denotes the density function and is the mean, we have:

    Hence, location at 1will be preferred if and only if

    1 1

    0 0( ) (1 ) ( ) 2 1x f x dx x f x dx

    1 .2

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    159/292

    159

    2

    f(x)

    x0 1

    UT

    Example: time sharing

    The problem is to share a given length of time between mradio

    programsto be broadcasted in a room where nindividuals work.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    160/292

    160

    Each individual is assumed to either like or dislikea program: utilities

    are then either 0 or 1. Each program is supported by at least one

    individual.

    The problem is to allocate time in proportions t1,,tmsuch that

    0 for all and 1k kt k t

    Assume first that each individual likes one and only oneprogram

    and let nkdenote the number of individuals who like program k:

    0 for all andk kn n k n n

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    161/292

    161

    Utilitarism implies majority: it picks the program supported by the

    largest group. In case where there is a tie, any combination is optimal.

    Egalitarism does the opposite: each program is broadcasted equallyi.e.

    1for allkt k

    m

    Assume now that individuals may be indifferentbetween radio

    programs. Consider the following case where n= m= 5:

    a b c d e

    1 1 0 0 0 02 0 1 0 0 0

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    162/292

    162

    2 0 1 0 0 0

    3 0 0 1 1 0

    4 0 0 0 1 1

    5 0 0 1 0 1

    So as to equalize the portion of time each individual listen to a given

    program, egalitarismsuggests the following allocation:

    2 2 1 1 1( , , , , )7 7 7 7 7

    x

    a b c d e

    1 1 0 0 0 0

    2 0 1 0 0 0

    3 0 0 1 1 0

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    163/292

    163

    4 0 0 0 1 1

    5 0 0 1 0 1

    Utilitarism instead suggest to forget about programs aand b, and to

    concentrate on programs c, dande, with an arbitrary allocation.

    a b c d e

    1 1 0 0 0 0

    2 0 1 0 0 0

    3 0 0 1 1 0

    If one particular program is supported by a majority, for instance:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    164/292

    164

    3 0 0 1 1 0

    4 0 0 0 1 1

    5 0 0 1 1 1

    utilitarism would simply suggest to concentrate on that program,

    without paying attention to those outside that majority.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    165/292

    165

    2.5 Transferable utility games

    TU-games

    Given a collectivityN= {1,,n}, a cooperative game with transferable

    utility is defined by a "characteristic function" vthat associates a real

    number to any "coalition" SN. Here v(S) is the worthof coalition S,understood as the minimum it can secure for itself, independently of

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    166/292

    166

    understood as the minimumit can secure for itself, independently of

    what the players outside Sdo.

    The set function vis assumed to be superadditive:

    a weaker requirement than convexity:

    ( ) ( ) ( )S T v S v T v S T

    , ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )S T N v S v T v S T v S T

    The problem is to share v(N) among the nplayers: findx= (x1,,xn)such that

    The minimum requirements is individual rationality:

    ( ) ( )x N v N

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    167/292

    167

    This defines the set imputations:

    ( ) for allix v i i N

    ( , ) { | ( ) ( ), ( ) for all }n iI N v x x N v N x v i i N

    The coreextends the rationality requirement from individuals tocoalitions:

    The core is the set, possibly empty, of allocations satisfying theseconditions:

    ( ) ( ) for allx S v S S N

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    168/292

    168

    It is the set of allocations against which there can be no objections

    from any coalition, including individuals. Hence

    ( , ) { | ( ) ( ), ( ) ( ) for all }nN v x x N v N x S v S S N

    ( , ) ( , )N v I N v

    The core is not as such a solution. It is the set of "stable" allocationsand there may be no such allocations except for some classes of games

    like for instance convex games.

    There are two "rules" that defines "fair" allocations.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    169/292

    169

    The Shapley value: it allocates v(N) on the basis of players marginal

    contributions to all coalitions they belong to:

    It defines an imputation that may not belong to the core.

    The nucleolus: it selects an allocation that is always defined and

    belongs to the core when this one is nonempty.

    ( ) ( \ )v S v S i

    Shapley value

    To each permutation = (i1,,in) Nof the players is associated a

    marginal contribution vector () defined by:

    1 1 1( ) ( ) ( ) ( )i v i v v i

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    170/292

    170

    The Shapley value is the averagemarginal contribution vector:

    1( , ) ( )

    !N

    N vn

    1

    1 1 1( ) ( ,..., ) ( ,..., ) ( 2,..., )ki k kv i i v i i k n

    Alternatively, the Shapley value can be written as:

    where the weights are given by

    ( )

    ( , ) ( ) [ ( ) ( \ )]i nS N

    S i

    N v s v S v S i

    ( 1)!( )!( )!

    n

    s n ss

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    171/292

    171

    The Shapley value is the unique allocation rule satisfying:

    - symmetry: players with identical marginalcontributions (substitute players) get the same (equal

    treatments of equals)

    - null player: players never contributing (null players) get nothing

    - additivity: (N,v+w) = (N,v) + (N,w)

    !n

    2 2

    3 3

    4 4

    1 12 ( , ) (1,1)

    2 2

    1 1 13 ( , , ) (1,2,1)

    3 6 3

    1 1 1 14 ( , , , ) (1,3,3,1)

    4 12 12 4

    1 1 1 1 1

    n

    n

    n

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    172/292

    172

    5 5

    6 6

    1 1 1 1 15 ( , , , , ) (1,4,6,4,1)

    5 20 30 20 5

    1 1 1 1 1 16 ( , , , , , ) (1,5,10,10,5,1)

    6 30 60 60 30 6

    n

    n

    1

    1

    1

    1

    ( )!where ( ) is the number of coalitions to which a given player belongs

    ( )!( )!

    1( ) ( ) for all

    s

    n n

    n n

    ns C

    n s s

    s s sn

    Least core and nucleolus

    The Shapley value is "fair" because it treats equal players equally and

    does not remunerate non-contributing players. The nucleolus instead is

    concerned with reducing the highest loss of the coalitions as measured

    by the difference between wath a coalition is worth and what it gets:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    173/292

    173

    is the "excess" associated to imputationxand coalition S.

    The least core is the set of imputations that minimize the largest excess:

    ( , ) ( ) ( )e x S v S x S

    ( , ),

    Min Max ( , )x I N v S NS N

    e x S

    This is typically a set. The nucleolus goes further to eventually retaina uniqueimputation:

    to each imputationxis associated the vector (x) of

    dimension 2n2 obtained by placing the excesses e(x,S)

    in a decreasing order

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    174/292

    174

    The nucleolus is then the unique imputations that minimizes

    lexicographicallythese vectors on the set of imputationsI(N,v):

    ( ) ( ) for all ( , )Lx x x I N v

    x

    Example: "market" game

    v(1) = v(2) = v(3) = v(23) = 0

    v(12) =p2 p3

    v(13) = v(123) =p3

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    175/292

    175

    The core is defined by:

    In particular, ifp3=p2, then

    3 2 3( , ) { ( ,0, ) }N v x p p p p p p

    3( , ) { ( ,0,0) }N v p

    1 2 3

    123 0 200 100

    132 0 0 300

    213 200 0 100

    231 300 0 0

    v(i) = 0

    v(12) =p2 = 200

    v(13) =p3 = 300

    v(23) = 0

    v(123) =p3 = 300

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    176/292

    231 300 0 0

    312 300 0 0

    321 300 0 0

    1/6 1100 200 500

    550 100 250( , ) ( , , ) (183,33,83)

    3 3 3N v

    each row corresponds

    to a permutation

    chaque column correspondsto a player

    176

    For any given coalition, the excess can be written as a fucntion ofp:

    3

    2

    ( , ) for {1}

    0 for {2} and {13}

    for {3} and {23}

    for {12}

    e p S p S

    S S

    p p S S

    p p S

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    177/292

    177

    For eachp, order the excesses in a decreasing way:

    2 3 3 2

    3 3 2 3

    (0, 0, , , , ) for [ , ]

    (0, 0, , , , ) for [ , ]

    p p p p p p p p p p

    p p p p p p p p p p

    2 3where2

    p pp

    pp3p20

    pp3

    p2

    2 3

    2

    p pp

    here the least core coincides with thecore and the nucleolus is its mid-point

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    178/292

    178

    - p3

    (p2-p3)/2

    p2

    -p3

    p

    p2p

    The nucleolus is the mid-point of the core:

    i e (250 0 50) in the case where p3 = 300 and p2 = 200

    3 2 3 2( , ) ,0,2 2

    p p p pN v

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    179/292

    179

    i.e (250, 0, 50) in the case wherep3 300 andp2 200.

    The nucleolus satisfies to two Shapley's axioms: symmetry and nulplayer.

    It does notsatisfy additivity.

    Example: crop game

    Imagine a landlord and m(identical) workers, and a technologydescribed by a production functiony=F(s) wheresis the numberof workers:

    v(S) = 0 if Sdoes not include the landlord

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    180/292

    180

    v(S) =F(s1) if Sincludes the landlord

    (he/she does not work)

    In particular, v(i) = 0 for all i and v(N) =F(m).

    We suppose thatFis increasingwithF(0) = 0, not more at this stage.

    The associated game is superadditive. It is convexif returns to scale are

    constant or increasing: linear or convex production function.

    We first observe that the extreme allocation (F(m), 0, ,0) always

    belongs to the core.

    Letxbe in the core. For allj1, we have:

    where

    ( \ ) ( \ ) ( 1)x N j v N j F m

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    181/292

    181

    where

    Hence,

    the most a worker can get within the core is

    the marginal product [F(m)F(m1)]

    ( \ ) ( ) ( )j jx N j x N x F m x

    ( ) ( 1)jx F m F m

    Workers are substitutes: they get the same wage under the Shapley value.

    We need only to compute what the value allocates to the landlord.

    In a given permutation, only thepositionof the landlord counts.

    if the landlord is in position k, he gets F(k-1)

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    182/292

    182

    if the landlord is in position k, he getsF(k1)

    and there are m + 1 positions possibles

    1

    1

    1 1

    1 11

    1 1( , ) ( ) ( )

    m m

    k k

    N v F k F km m

    F(m)

    F(k) 1xF(k)F(1) +F(2) + +F(m)

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    183/292

    183

    m0

    F(1)

    F(2)

    k k+1

    F(m)

    L > W

    decreasing

    returns

    Workers

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    184/292

    184

    m0

    L > W

    0

    ( )

    m

    k

    F k

    Landlord

    F(m)

    W = L

    constant

    returns

    Workers

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    185/292

    185

    m0

    W L

    Landlord

    F(m)

    T

    L < W

    increasing

    returns

    Workers

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    186/292

    186

    m0

    L < W

    Landlord

    F(m) mixed

    returns

    Workers

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    187/292

    187

    m0

    Landlord

    The Talmud example

    A man dies and his three wives have each a claim on his estate,

    following past promises. The value of the estate falls short of the

    total of the claims. Here is what a Mishnah suggests.

    d 100 d 200 d 300 EQUAL

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    188/292

    188

    d1=100 d2=200 d3=300

    E=100 33.3 33.3 33.3

    E=200 50 75 75

    E=300 50 100 150

    EQUAL

    UL

    ?

    Aumann and Mashler (1985) have shown that the nucleolus actuallyreproduces the Talmud figures for the following TU-game:

    Here v(S) represents the minimumcoalition Scan get:

    ( ) 0, ( \ )v S Max E d N S

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    189/292

    189

    it is the amount left once the outsiders have possibly

    got their claims

    In particular, v(N) =E.

    The above game is known as "bankcruptcy game".

    E= 200d= (100,200,300)

    v(i) = 0 i = 1,2,3

    v(12) = v(13) = 0v(23) = 100

    v(123) = 200

    ( ) 0, ( \ )v S Max E d N S

    1 2 3

    1 2 3 1

    2 3

    , , 0

    200 100

    100

    x x x

    x x x x

    x x

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    190/292

    190

    v(123) 200

    Here players 2 and 3 are substitutes.

    3

    1 2 3 1 2 3( , ) {( , , ) 0 , 200 , 0 100}N v x x x x a x x a a

    (200,0,0)

    x1

    x3x2

    0

    200

    200

    200

    ( , )I N v

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    191/292

    191

    (0, 200,0)

    x2+ x3=100

    (0,0, 200)x2+ x3=200 x1=0

    ( , )N v

    E= 200d= (100,200,300)

    v(1) = 0

    v(2) = 0v(3) = 0

    ( ) 0, ( \ )v S Max E d N S

    1 2 3

    123 0 0 200

    132 0 200 0

    213 0 0 200

    231 100 0 100

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    192/292

    192

    v(12) = 0

    v(13) = 0

    v(23) = 100

    v(123) = 200

    231 100 0 100

    312 0 200 0

    321 100 100 01/6 200 500 500

    200 500 500( , ) , , (33.7, 83.7, 83.7)

    6 6 6N v

    (200,0,0)

    (100 100 0)

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    193/292

    193

    (0, 200,0) (0,0, 200)

    Nucleolus

    Shapley

    Equal

    (100, 100, 0) (100, 0, 100)

    We observe that the four vertices of the core are precisely the fourmarginal contribution vectors:

    (0, 0, 200) with multiplicity 2

    (0, 200, 0) with multiplicity 2

    (100, 0, 100) with multiplicity 1(100, 100, 0) with multiplicity 1

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    194/292

    194

    This is actually a characteristic of convex games. Actually:

    the core of game is the convex hull of its marginal

    contribution vectors if and only if it is a convex game

    As a consequence, the Shapley value is in the core of convex games.

    The bankcruptcy game is convex.

    E = 200 d1 = 100 d2 = 200 d3 = 300

    EQUAL 66.6 66.6 66.6

    PROP 33.3 66.6 100

    UG 66 6 66 6 66 6

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    195/292

    195

    UG 66.6 66.6 66.6

    UL 0 50 150

    Nucleolus 50 75 75

    Shapley 33.3 83.3 83.3

    E= 100d= (100,200,300)

    v(i) = 0 i = 1,2,3

    v(12) = v(13) = v(23) = 0

    v(123) = 200

    ( ) 0, ( \ )v S Max E d N S

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    196/292

    196

    The game is symmetric: all players are substitutes.

    1 2 3

    1 2 3

    , , 0

    200

    x x x

    x x x

    ( , ) ( , )N v I N v

    200( , ) ( , )

    3i iN v N v

    E= 300d= (100,200,300)

    v(i) = 0 i= 1,2,3

    v(12) = 0

    v(13) = 100

    v(23) = 200

    ( ) 0, ( \ )v S Max E d N S

    1 2 3

    1 2 3

    1 3

    , , 0

    300100

    x x x

    x x xx x

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    197/292

    197

    ( )

    v(123) = 300 2 3 200x x

    (300,0,0)

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    198/292

    198

    (0, 300,0) (0,0, 300)

    x2

    + x3

    =200

    x1+ x3=100

    ( , )N v

    E= 300d= (100,200,300)

    v(i) = 0 i= 1,2,3

    v(12) = 0

    v(13) = 100

    v(23) = 200

    ( ) 0, ( \ )v S Max E d N S

    1 2 3

    123 0 0 300

    132 0 200 100213 0 0 300

    231 100 0 200

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    199/292

    199

    v(123) = 300231 100 0 200

    312 100 200 0

    321 100 200 0

    1/6 300 600 900

    300 600 900( , ) , , (50, 100, 150)

    6 6 6N v

    (300,0,0)

    + 100

    x1+ x3=200

    x1+ x2=150

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    200/292

    200(0, 300,0) (0,0, 300)

    Shapley = Nucleolus

    Equal

    x2

    + x3

    =200

    x1+ x3=100

    (300,0,0)

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    201/292

    201(0, 300,0) (0,0, 300)(0,200, 100)

    (100, 200, 0) (100, 0, 200)

    We observe again that the four vertices of the core are precisely

    the four marginal contribution vectors:

    1 2 3

    123 0 0 300

    132 0 200 100

    213 0 0 300

    231 100 0 200

    312 100 200 0

    321 100 200 0

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    202/292

    202

    (0, 0, 300) with multiplicity 2

    (0, 200, 100) with multiplicity 1

    (100, 0, 200) with multiplicity 1

    (100, 200, 0) with multiplicity 2

    confirming that the bankcruptcy game is convex.

    Assignment games (Shapley and Shubik)

    Consider a setN = {1,,n} of agents and a setM = {1,,m} (mn)

    of indivisible objects(say houses) to be allocated, one to each agent.

    Each agent attaches a "utility" to each house. These data are

    summarized in a utility matrix

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    203/292

    ui(h) is the reservation priceof agent i for house hi.e. the maximum

    price i is willing to pay for house h.

    It is the valuethat agent iattach to house hexpressed in monetary

    terms.

    [ ( ) | , ]iu h i N h M

    203

    Side payments being allowed, the associated TU-game is given by:

    whereFis the set of all functionsf:NMthat associates ahouse to each player.

    ( ) ( ( ))f F ii Sv S Max u f i

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    204/292

    Here v(S) is the cost of the houses that are optimally allocated to the

    members of coalition S.

    Consequently, (N,v)isa cost game. It is concaveand thereby also

    subadditive.

    204

    An optimal allocations of objects to players is associated to thedefinition of C(N)

    In the example below, it is (2,3,1): player 1 receives house 2, player 2

    receiveshouse3, and player 3 receives house 1.

    u1 u2 u3C(1) = 12

    C(2) 9

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    205/292

    1 2 3

    1 3 9 9

    2 12 6 6

    3 9 6 3

    C(2) = 9

    C(3) = 9

    C(12) = 21

    C(13) = 21

    C(23) = 15

    C(123) = 27

    205

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    206/292

    We observe that players 2 and 3 are substitute. The Shapley value isobtained from the following table which associates marginal cost

    vectors to players' permutations.

    1 2 3

    123 12 9 6

    132 12 6 9

    213 12 9 6

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    207/292

    213 12 9 6

    231 12 9 6

    312 12 6 9321 12 6 9

    1/6 72 45 45

    (N,C) = (12, 7.5, 7.5)

    207

    The core is defined by the allocations satisfying the followinginequalities:

    1 2 3

    1

    2

    3

    1 2

    27

    12

    99

    21

    y y y

    y

    yy

    y y

    y1= 12

    6 y29

    6 y39

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    208/292

    1 2

    1 3

    2 3

    21

    21

    15

    y y

    y y

    y y

    (12,6,9)(12,9,6)

    (12,7.5,7.5)

    optimal allocation before transfers

    the Shapley value is located at the center of the core

    208

    (27,0,0)

    x3= 9

    x2= 6x3= 6

    x2= 9

    set of

    imputations

    (9,9,9)

    (12,6,9)(12,9,6)

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    209/292

    (0,27,0) (0,0,27)

    x1= 12

    209

    3. Ordinal welfarism

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    210/292

    210

    A social choice procedureis a mappingFthat associates alternativesto preference profiles:

    : ( )nF L A A

    It associates to any profilepa subset of "winning" alternatives

    F(p) A.It is the collective choice set.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    211/292

    211

    : ( ) ( )nF L A L A

    A social welfare functionis a mappingFthat associates "collective"preferences to preference profiles:

    3.1 The case of two alternatives

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    212/292

    212

    Consider the case of 2 alternativesand nvoters:

    A= {0,1} andN= {1,,n}

    Assuming no indifference, apreference profileis a list of 0 and 1

    of length n:

    p= (p1,,pn) wherepiL(A) = {0,1}

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    213/292

    213

    where

    1 1 0

    0 0 1

    i

    i

    i

    i

    p

    p

    Example: n= 5 andp= (0,1,0,0,1) 3 in favour of 02 in favour of 1

    There are 2npossible profiles.

    The set of all possible preference profiles is {0,1}n.

    A voting procedureis a mapping

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    214/292

    214

    F:{0,1}n {0,1}

    It associates to any profilepa subsetF(p) {0,1}.

    F(p) is the "choice set".

    There are 4 possible outcomes:

    F(p) = {0}

    F(p) = {1}

    F(p) = {0,1}

    F( )

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    215/292

    215

    F(p) =

    So tiesare allowed.

    The natural neutral mechanism to break a tie is the flipping of a coin.

    Simple majority

    1

    1

    ( ) {1} if 2

    ( ) {0} if 2

    n

    i

    i

    n

    i

    i

    nF p p

    nF p p

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    216/292

    216

    1

    ( ) {0,1} if2

    n

    ii

    nF p p

    a tie is not a possible outcome of simple majority if nis odd

    Unanimity

    1

    1

    ( ) {1} if

    ( ) {0} if 0

    n

    i

    i

    n

    i

    i

    F p p n

    F p p

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    217/292

    217

    1

    ( ) if 0n

    ii

    F p p n

    A basic requirement to impose on a voting procedure is that itproduces a result:

    Decisiveness A voting procedure is decisiveif it never results

    in the empty outcome:

    ( ) for all {0,1}nF p p

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    218/292

    218

    Simple majority is always decisive. Unanimity is not.

    What would be a fairvoting procedure?

    What are desirable properties a voting procedure should have

    beyond decisiveness?

    The result of a voting procedure should not depend on the identity of

    the voters nor on the labelling of the alternatives:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    219/292

    219

    voters and alternatives should be treated equally

    Anonymity

    A voting procedureFis anonymousif it symmetric in its nvariables:

    for anyp , permuting the voters leavesF(p) unchanged

    For instance,

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    220/292

    220

    (0,1,1,0,1) (1,0,1,0,1) (1,1,1,0,0) ....F F F

    Anonymity clearly excludes dictatorship.

    It is actually a stronger form of non-dictatorship.

    Neutrality

    A voting procedureFis neutralif permuting the choice of every voter

    results in a permutation of the outcome:

    for anyp P, F(1p) = 1F(p)

    where 1= (1,1,,1).

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    221/292

    221

    For instance,

    (0,1,1,0,1) {1} (1,0,0,1,0) {0}F F

    Proposition: A voting procedure is anonymous and neutral

    if and only if it is the number of votes in favour

    of an alternative which determines whether he/she

    belongs to the choice set, i.e.

    1

    ( )n

    i

    i

    F p G p

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    222/292

    222

    for some increasing function G.

    Alone, anonymity and neutrality allow for many different votingprocedures, including those based on stupid rules like:

    1

    1 1 4( ) {1} if

    10 10( ) {0} otherwise

    n

    i

    i

    F p p

    nF p

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    223/292

    223

    If an alternative is elected and some voters change their minds in

    favour of that candidate, it may be that he/she is not elected any more.

    If, given the outcomeF(p) corresponding to a preference profilep,some voters change their mind in favourof a candidate who belongs

    to the choice setF(p), we would expect that the resulting choice set

    still includes that alternative.

    Monotonicity A voting procedure is monotonicif

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    224/292

    224

    1 ( ) and 1 ( )

    0 ( ) and 0 ( )

    F p p p F p

    F p p p F p

    where means for all .i ip p p p i

    An increased support for analternativeshould never hurt.

    An immediate consequence of monotonicity is strategyproofness:

    a voter has no incentive to be insincere by

    voting for the candidate he/she ranks second

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    225/292

    225

    Is it possible to characterize the procedures which satisfy these

    3 axioms simultaneously ?

    anonymity, neutrality and monotonicity

    A quota procedureis defined by an integer , , such that:2nq q n

    1

    1 1

    ( ) {1} if

    ( ) {0} if

    ( ) {0,1} otherwise

    n

    i

    i

    n n

    i i

    i i

    F p p q

    F p n p q p n q

    F p

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    226/292

    226

    Simple majority is defined by:

    1 if is odd2

    1 if is even2

    nq n

    nq n

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    227/292

    ( ) {0,1} and ( ) {1}

    ( ) {0,1} and ( ) {0}

    F p p p F p

    F p p p F p

    A stronger version of the monotonicity axiom is the following:

    Strict monotonicity A voting procedure isstrictly monotonic

    (positive responsiveness) if it monotonic and

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    228/292

    228

    means for all and for some .i i j jp p p p i p p j

    where

    If some voters change their mind in favour of a candidate who

    belongs to the initial choice set, then this alternative ends up

    being the only winner.

    In other words, either there was a tie and it disappears, or there

    was a unique winner and he/she remains the unique winner.

    Proposition Simple majority is the uniquevoting procedure which

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    229/292

    229

    p p j y q g p

    (May, 1952) is decisive, anonymous, neutral and strictlymonotonic.

    3.2 Social choice procedures

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    230/292

    230

    Borda method (1781)

    - each of the mposition is graded: m1 for the 1st,

    m2 for the 2nd, until 0 for the last

    - looking at the preference ordering of each voter,each alternative is graded accordingly

    - adding the grades, each alternative receives a score

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    231/292

    231

    adding the grades, each alternative receives a score

    ... the alternative(s) with the largest score wins.

    a a a c c b e

    b d d b d c c

    c b b d b d d

    d e e e a a b

    e c c a e e a

    n= 7

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    232/292

    232

    Bordaba b c d e

    14 17 16 16 7

    Condorcet has criticized Borda's method.

    Consider 3 alternatives and 30 voters,

    19 with preferences

    11 with preferences

    For Condorcet a should win while Borda assigns 41 to b against

    a b c

    b c a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    233/292

    233

    For Condorcet, ashould win while Borda assigns 41 to bagainst

    38 to a.

    Indeed ais preferred to b and cby 19 voters.

    An alternative isCondorcet winner if...

    ... confronted to any other alternative, it comes before in more

    than half of the orderings

    1 2 3 4 5 6 7a a a c c b e

    b b d b d c c

    d b d b d d

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    234/292

    234

    (This does not define a decisive rule !)

    c d b d b d d

    d e e e a a b

    e c c a e e a

    Hare method (1861) "single transferable voting system"

    - if an alternative comes on top of at least half of the orderings,

    he/she wins

    - if there is no such alternative, delete the alternative(s)that are on top of the fewest ordering

    - repeat the procedure with the remaining alternatives,...

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    235/292

    235

    repeat the procedure with the remaining alternatives,...

    a a a c c b e

    b d d b d c c

    c b b d b d d

    d e e e a a b

    e c c a e e a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    236/292

    236

    delete d

    a a a c c b e

    b b b b b c c

    c e e e a a b

    e c c a e e a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    237/292

    237

    delete b ande

    a a a c c c c

    c c c a a a a

    delete a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    238/292

    238

    Harec

    delete a

    Sequential pairwise voting (voting with an agenda)

    The idea is that a sequence of alternatives is determined and followed.

    For instance, dresults from the sequence (a,b,c,d,e) but bthat comes

    out from the reverse sequence:

    a a a c c b e

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    239/292

    239

    b d d b d c c

    c b b d b d d

    d e e e a a b

    e c c a e e a

    Pareto criteria

    If all voters preferxtoy, thenycannot be in the social choice set.

    a a a c c b e

    b d d b a c c

    c b b a b a a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    240/292

    240

    d e e e d d b

    e c c d e e d

    Condorcet criteria

    If there is a Condorcet winner, it must be in the social choice set.

    1 2 3 4 5 6 7

    a a a c c b e

    b b d b d c c

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    241/292

    241

    b b d b d c c

    c d b d b d d

    d e e e a a b

    e c c a e e a

    Monotonicity criteria

    Let the alternativexbe in the social choice set for a given preference

    profilep.

    If the preference profilepis modified by moving upxin the orderingof some voter,...

    ...xshould remain in the social choice set.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    242/292

    242

    Independence criteria(independence of irrelevant alternatives)

    Assume that the social choice set includesxbut noty.

    If the preference profilePis modified, without altering the preferences

    betweenxandy,...

    ... then the resulting choice set should still not includey.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    243/292

    243

    Pareto Condorcet Monotonicity Independance

    Plurality Yes No Yes No

    Borda Yes No Yes No

    Hare Yes No No No

    Agenda N Y Y N

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    244/292

    244

    Agenda No Yes Yes No

    Dictator Yes No Yes Yes

    Plurality satisfies Pareto

    If every voter prefersxtoy,ycannot come on top of any ordering.

    Borda satisfies Pareto

    Ifxcomes beforeyin all preference orderings, thenxhas more points

    thany.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    245/292

    245

    Hare satisfies Pareto

    If every voter prefersxtoy,yis not on top of any list.

    Then, either some alternative is on top of more than

    half of the orderings, it is the winner, noty,

    ory(being absent from the the first row) is among

    the alternatives to be deleted next.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    246/292

    246

    Dictatorship satisfies Pareto:

    if every voter prefersxtoy, it is also the case of the dictator...

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    247/292

    Sequential pairwise voting satisfies monotonicity

    Assumexis a social choice given a preference profile and

    an agenda.

    Movingxup in the preferences of some voter will certainly keepxin

    the social choice set (with a larger margin).

    Dictatorship satisfies monotonicity

    Ifxis the social choice, it is on top of the dictator's ordering...

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    248/292

    248

    x s e soc a c o ce, s o op o e d c a o s o de g...

    Dictatorship satisfies independence

    Ifxis the social choice but noty,xis on top of the dictator's ordering

    and will remain so...

    Plurality does not satisfy Condorcet

    1 to 4 5 to 7 8 and 9

    a b c

    b c b

    c a a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    249/292

    249

    ais plurality winner but bis Condorcet winner

    Borda does not satisfy Condorcet

    1, 2 and 3 4 and 5

    a b

    b c

    c a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    250/292

    250

    bis Borda winner but ais Condorcet winner

    Hare does not satisfy Condorcet

    1 to 5 6 to 9 10 to 12 13 to 15 16 and 17

    a e d c b

    b b b b cc c c d d

    d d e e e

    e a a a a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    251/292

    251

    bis Condorcet winner but it will be deleted first

    e a a a a

    Dictatorship does not satisfy Condorcet

    1 2 3

    a c c

    b b b

    c a a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    252/292

    252

    cis Condorcet winner while ais the "social"

    choice if voter 1 is the dictator.

    Hare does not satisfy monotonicity

    1 to 7 8 to 12 13 to 16 17

    a c b b

    b a c a

    c b a c

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    253/292

    253

    ais the social choice according to Hare

    If voter 17 moves aabove b, ...

    1 to 7 8 to 12 13 to 16 17

    a c b a

    b a c b

    c b a c

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    254/292

    254

    ...cbecomes the social choice

    Plurality does not satisfy independence

    a a b c

    b b c b

    c c a a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    255/292

    255

    ais the social choice and bis not

    If voter 4 moves cbetween band a, ...

    a a b b

    b b c c

    c c a a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    256/292

    256

    ... aand bare tied

    Borda does not satisfy independence

    1, 2 and 3 4 and 5

    a c

    b b

    c a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    257/292

    257

    ais the social choice

    If voters 4 and 5 move cbetween band a, ...

    1, 2 and 3 4 and 5

    a b

    b c

    c a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    258/292

    258

    ... bbecomes the social choice

    Hare does not satisfy independence

    a a b c

    b b c b

    c c a a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    259/292

    259

    ais the social choice according to Hare

    If voter 4 moves cbetween band a, ...

    a a b b

    b b c c

    c c a a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    260/292

    260

    ... aand bare tied

    Sequential pairwise voting does not satisfy Pareto

    a c b

    b a d

    d b cc d a

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    261/292

    261

    bdominates din the sense of Pareto: all voters prefer bto dbut dresults from the sequence (a,b,c,d) :

    adefeats b, cdefeats abut ddefeats c.

    Sequential pairwise voting does not satisfy Independance

    c a b

    b c aa b c

    The reverse sequence (c,b,a) produces aas social choice.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    262/292

    262

    Interchanging cand bin the first ordering results in bas social choice

    while no one has changed his/her mind about aand b.

    An illustration:Bonn, Berlin or both ?

    Bundestag, 20 June 1991

    659 representatives, 3 alternatives:

    a= government in Bonn and parliament in Berlin

    b= government and parliament in Berlin

    c= government and parliament in Bonn

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    263/292

    263

    A decision was eventually reached after a full day of debates.

    Bonn and Berlin

    Motion: NO to distinct locations

    No

    YesEnd

    340/657

    489/654

    147/654

    Procedure adopted by the Council of Elders and the results:

    Yes No 288/654

    Abstention

    Abstention

    18/654

    29/657

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    264/292

    264

    Bonn or Berlin

    Berlin338/659

    Bonn332/659

    Abstention

    1/659

    Questions:

    Which voting procedure should have been adopted ?

    Does the actual voting procedure produce enoughinformation to enable a reconstruction of the preferences

    of the 659 representatives ?

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    265/292

    265

    Would a different voting procedure have produceda different outcome ?

    Bonn-Berlin: Leininger's results* based on a clever

    reconstructedpreference profile:

    1. Majority would have been indecisive: 147/221/290.

    2. Bonn would have been the plurality winner.

    3. Berlin would have been the 2-step majority winner: 337/320.

    4. Berlin is Condorcet winner:B/A: 371/286

    B/C: 337/320

    A/C: 227/430A = 513

    B C A

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    266/292

    266

    5. Bonn would have been the Borda winner:

    6. Berlin and Bonn would have probably won under approval voting.

    *"The fatal vote: Bonn vs Berlin",Finanzarchiv,Neue Folge, Heft 1, 1993, 1-20

    B = 708C= 750

    Scoring rules like Borda can be characterized. A scoring rule is defined

    by a mapping that associates weights to alternatives (assuming strictpreferences) in terms of their positions in the preference lists.

    Consistency

    A social choice ruleFis consistent if, for any two disjoint sets of

    votersNandN',and preference profilespandp'on a common a

    setA of alternatives:

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    267/292

    267

    where is the combined preference profile ofNN'.

    ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )F p F p F p F p F p p

    p p

    Proposition (Young)

    A voting procedure is anonymous, neutral and consistent

    if and only if it is a scoring rule.

    Remark: The Borda scoring rule has been axiomatized as well.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    268/292

    268

    3.3 Impossibility theorems

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    269/292

    269

    Among the properties, the most desirable ones are certainly Pareto and

    monotonicity. Condorcet comes next.

    Independence appears as a strong requirement. It has indeed

    be the object of much discussion in the literature.

    We observe the following facts:

    - only dictatorship satisfies the independence axiom

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    270/292

    270

    - only sequential pairwise voting satisfies the Condorcet axiom

    Condorcet voting paradox

    h i h i l h i / f h h d

    a c b

    b a c

    c b a

    No Condorcet winner!

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    271/292

    271

    Whatever is the social choice, 2/3 of the voters are unhappy andmoreover, they agree on an other alternative !

    There is a transitivityproblem!

    The collective preferences built by saying that

    "xis preferred toy"

    if and only if"xis preferred toyby a majority of voters"

    are not transitive:

    x y

    d bb b

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    272/292

    272

    ... although individual preferences are.

    and buta b b c c a

    One implicit assumption is made:

    there is no retrictions on the preferences:

    social choice function are defined for any

    preference profile inL(A)n

    The only requirement is that individual preferences are preorders.

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    273/292

    273

    Impossibility theorem 1 (Taylor)

    There is no decisive social choice procedure satisfying

    both the Condorcet and the independence criteria.

    Proof: - assume there exists such a procedure

    - apply it to the preference profile underlying

    the Condorcet paradox

    h th t it d i f th th

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    274/292

    274

    - show that it produces no winner: none of the threealternatives can be winning

    Claim: acannot be winning

    Consider the profile obtained from the Condorcet profile by moving

    bdown in the third list:

    a c b

    b a c

    c b a

    a c c

    b a b

    c b a

    cis then Condorcet winner and must be in the choice set, not a.

    (same arguments forband c)

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    275/292

    275

    Going back to the Condorcet profile by moving bup in the third list

    should not affect the preferences between aand c.

    So ashould still be a non-winner.

    Impossibility theorem 2 (Arrow)

    Dictatorship is the only social welfare functionsatisfying the Pareto and independence criteria

    Impossibility theorem 3 (Gibbard)

    Dictatorship is the only social choice procedureti f i th P t d t i it

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    276/292

    276

    satisfying the Pareto and monotonicity

  • 7/26/2019 Social Choices

    277/292

    Strong monotonicity

    A social choice procedureFis strongly monotone if for all preference

    profilep andqin , and any alternative ainA:

    if qis obtained frompby lifting aup in some preference list,

    then eitherF(q) =F(p) or F(q) = a

    Pushing up an alternative can only help that alternative.

    Proposition (Muller and Satterthwaite)

  • 7/26/2019 Socia