Social Choice Session 3

21
Social Choice Session 3 Carmen Pasca and John Hey

description

Social Choice Session 3. Carmen Pasca and John Hey. Plan for this session. We start with a review of Arrow’s theorem – using now Jen’s preferences to give completeness and showing that this leads to her being the dictator. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Transcript of Social Choice Session 3

Page 1: Social Choice Session 3

Social ChoiceSession 3

Carmen Pasca and John Hey

Page 2: Social Choice Session 3

Plan for this session

• We start with a review of Arrow’s theorem – using now Jen’s preferences to give completeness and showing that this leads to her being the dictator.

• Then, within the same framework (ordinal preferences) we explore how we may weaken Arrow’s assumptions and possibly get some possibility.

• After a short break we will invite comments from you as to other ways to get possibility.

• (Note: in session 6 we explore the implications of cardinality/measurability of preferences – so we do not do this today.)

Page 3: Social Choice Session 3

Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem

• In social choice theory, Arrow’s impossibility theorem ... states that, when voters have three or more discrete alternatives (options), no voting system can convert the ranked preferences of individuals into a community-wide ranking while also meeting a certain set of criteria. These criteria are called unrestricted domain, non-dictatorship, Pareto efficiency, and independence of irrelevant alternatives. (Wikipedia)

• We remind you of Arrow’s famous result and explore more its implications.

• We again draw inspiration from John Bone at York and borrow some of his slides.

Page 4: Social Choice Session 3

Arrow

• Arrow’s conditions are these:• Universal Domain: is applicable to any profile.• Consistency: produces a complete, transitive ordering

of available alternatives.• Pareto: if everyone prefers x to y then so should

society.• Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives: orders x and

y on the basis only of individual preferences on x and y.• Can we replace/eliminate/weaken any of these?• This is the question we address today.

Page 5: Social Choice Session 3

Back to session 2 briefly

• We go back to where we had to assume some society’s preferences in order to get completeness...

• ...and we take an alternative way.• We go to slide number 12 of the PowerPoint

presentation of session 2...• ... after which we once again shamelessly use

John Bone’s thoughts and slides.

Page 6: Social Choice Session 3

Universal Domain: is applicable to any profile

Can we plausibly relax Arrow’s conditions?

Perhaps there are some profiles at which we might not require a social ordering at all?

Especially for profiles of (e.g. malicious) preferences.

But perhaps also for profiles of welfare rankings.

For example if x and y are different allocations of economic goods, and J is allocated more of every good under x than under y,

then it might be reasonable to ignore any hypothetical profile in which J ranks y above x.

Might this be enough to escape the problem?

Page 7: Social Choice Session 3

Pareto: if everyone prefers x to y then so should society

Can we plausibly relax Arrow’s conditions?

Perhaps for similar reasons as with Universal Domain

A Sen, “The impossibility of a Paretian Liberal”,Journal of Political Economy, vol 78 (1970), 152-7

A single copy of Lady Chatterley’s Lover

a: Ken (Prude) reads it b: Jen (Liberal) reads it c: neither reads it

a b cJen

c a bKen

Pareto → aPb

Liberalism →bPc

cPa

Ignore “meddlesome” preferences? (We will return to Sen shortly.)

Page 8: Social Choice Session 3

Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives

Can we plausibly relax Arrow’s conditions?

Whatever determines the relative merits of x and y should not include individual welfare data regarding z …

... but should instead be intrinsic to x and y.

So at any two profiles in which the individual welfare data regarding (only) x and y is the same, the social ordering of x and y should also be the same.

This becomes problematic when the individual welfare data comprises only rankings

that is, comprises only ordinal welfare data

Page 9: Social Choice Session 3

Consistency: complete transitive ordering

Can we plausibly relax Arrow’s conditions?

So why require a complete, transitive social ordering of all available alternatives ?

We may only have to decide which of the available alternatives should be (socially) chosen.

This is equivalent to requiring the social choice to be consistent across different (hypothetical) sets of alternatives

Whatever determines the relative merits of x and y should not include the availability or otherwise of z …

... but should instead be intrinsic to x and y.

Page 10: Social Choice Session 3

A single copy of Lady Chatterley’s Lover

a: Ken reads it b: Jen reads it c: neither reads it

a b cJen

c a bKen choose: a from {a,b}

b from {b,c}

c from {a,c}

? from {a,b,c}

Whatever is the choice from {a,b,c}, there is inconsistency.

But so what?

Page 11: Social Choice Session 3

a b cJen

c a bKen choose: a from {a,b}

b from {b,c}

c from {a,c}

? from {a,b,c}

Whatever is the choice from {a,b,c}, there is inconsistency.

But so what?

b c aLen

Choose x from {x,y} iff more people prefer x to y than prefer y to x.

Majoritarianism

Page 12: Social Choice Session 3

Sen’s Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal

• The idea is that each individual has the right to determine things ‘locally’ – that is, those things that concern only him or her. So individuals are decisive over local issues.

• For example, I should be free to choose whether or not I read Lady Chatterley’s Lover.

• He gives a nice example, which we have already seen. Three alternatives, a, b and c, and two people A and B.

• a: Mr A (the prude) reads the book;• b: Mr B (the lascivious/liberal) reads the book;• c: Neither reads the book.

Page 13: Social Choice Session 3

Lady C.

• Mr A (the Prude): c > a > b• Mr B (the Lascivious): a > b > c • Now assume that Mr A is decisive over (a,c) and that

Mr B is decisive over (b,c).• So from A’s preferences c > a and from B’s

preferences b > c. From unanimity a > b. • Hence we have b > c (B) and c > a (A) and a > b (unanimity)!• WEIRD! (Intransitive).

Page 14: Social Choice Session 3

Sen’s Theorem

• Condition U (Unrestricted domain): The domain of the collective choice rule includes all possible individual orderings.

• Condition P( Weak Pareto): For any x, y in X, if every member of society strictly prefers x to y, then xPy.

• Condition L* (Liberalism): For each individual i, there is at least one pair of personal alternatives (x,y) in X such that individual i is decisive both ways in the social choice process.

• Theorem: There is no social decision function that satisfies conditions U, P and L*.

Page 15: Social Choice Session 3

Proof

• P indicates Society’s preference and Pi that of individual i.

• Suppose i is decisive over (x,y) and that j is decisive over (z,w). Assume that these two pairs have no element in common.

• Let us suppose that xPiy, zPjw, and, for both k=i,j that wPkx and yPkz.

• From Condition L* we obtain xPy and zPw.• From Condition P we obtain wPx and yPz.• Hence it follows that • xPy yPz zPw and wPx.• Cyclical.

Page 16: Social Choice Session 3

Gibbard’s Theory of Alienable Rights

• Background...• Going back to the Lady C example, Mr A may realise that

maintaining his right to decisiveness over (a,c) leads to an impasse/intransitivity.

• He cannot get c (his preferred option) because Mr B has rights over that and renouncing his right to decisiveness over (a,c), society will end up with a (which is preferred by Mr A to b – his least preferred).

• (Might Mr B think similarly (mutatis mutandis) and give up his right to decisiveness?)

Page 17: Social Choice Session 3

Gibbard’s own example

• Three persons: Angelina, Edwin and the ‘judge’.• Angelina prefers marrying Edwin but would marry the judge.• Edwin prefers to remain single, but would prefer to marry Angelina

rather than see her marry the judge.• Judge is happy with whatever Angelina wants.• Three alternatives:• x: Edwin and Angelina get married• y: Angelina and the judge marry (Edwin stays single)• z: All three remain single• Angelina has preference: x PA y PA z

• Edwin has preference: z PE x PE y

Page 18: Social Choice Session 3

The problem and its solution

• Angelina has a libertarian claim over the pair (y,z).• Edwin has a claim over (z,x).• Edwin and Angelina are unanimous in preferring x to y.• So we have a preference cycle: yPz, zPx, xPy.• If Edwin exercises his right to remain single, then Angelina

might end up married to the judge, which is Edwin’s least preferred option.

• ‘Therefore’ it will be in Edwin’s own advantage to waive his right over (z,x) in favour of the Pareto preference xPy.

Page 19: Social Choice Session 3

Gibbard’s Theory of Alienable Rights

• Condition GL: Individuals have the right to waive their rights.• Gibbard’s rights-waiving solution: There exists a collective

choice rule that satisfies conditions U, P and GL.

• The central role of the waiver is to break a cycle whenever there is one ...

• ... but the informational demands are high.

Page 20: Social Choice Session 3

Now a short break

• After the break we invite you to suggest other ways of breaking Arrow’s impossibility...

• ...within the ordinal preferences framework.• Note that we could dispense with the notion of trying

to find society’s preferences...• ... we could immediately think about a decision rule of

society which depends upon individual preferences....• ... Like doing something if a majority of the population

want to do it.• Problems with this? Intransitivity?

Page 21: Social Choice Session 3

Conclusions

• So what do we conclude from all of this?• Essentially that, whatever way we do the aggregation,

there is no method, that does not have objections, to aggregate individual preferences into a set of social preferences.

• Is this surprising?• What are its implications?• That we cannot leave a computer in charge of society.• We need decision-making bodies with flexibility and some

autonomy but also somehow under the control of the members of society.