Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper...

27
Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both proper and improper interpretations

description

The “improper interpretation” of an infinite set-theory structure founds the “proper interpretation” and thus that structure self-founds itself as the one interpretation of it can found the other

Transcript of Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper...

Page 1: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground:

The mutual foundation of both proper and improper interpretations

Page 2: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Vasil Penchev* Bulgarian Academy of Sciences: Institute for the Study of Societies and Knowledge: Dept. of Logical Systems and Models; [email protected] Moscow, VII International Congress "Modes of Thinking, Ways of Speaking“ The School of Philosophy of the Faculty of Humanities (National Research University Higher School of Economics) 30 April 2016

Page 3: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Skolem’s relativity of ‘set’

• The great Norwegian scientist, mathematician and logician Thoralf Skolem (1922) introduced the “relativity of the notion of set” and the “improper interpretation” of a set-theory structure, based on the axiom of choice

• One can demonstrate that they can serve as a ground of the logic of ground

Page 4: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Thesis:

The “improper interpretation” of an infinite set-theory structure founds the “proper interpretation” and thus that structure self-founds itself as the one interpretation of it can found the other

Page 5: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Kolmogorov’ s complexity

• The mapping of the proper into the improper interpretation of a mathematical structure is also a quantity of its complexity in the sense of Kolmogorov, Chaitin, and Martin-Löf (1965-1977)

• Thus involved, the quantity of information can be interpreted as the quantity of “substance” or “being” of that structure allowing of self-grounding

Page 6: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Skolmem’s “paradox” as a property of infinity

• The innovation cited in the beginning and known also as “Skolem’s paradox” can be discussed as a special property of infinity implying the concept of choice and thus of information

• Indeed any finite set can be well-ordered without utilizing the axiom of choice. However that well-ordering is trivial and coincides with the identical mapping of the set into itself

Page 7: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

The well-ordering principle

• In other words, the “improper interpretation” of any finite set is identical to the “proper one” of it

• However, the same statement can be deduced in no way as to any infinite set and should be postulated being known as the well-ordering theorem (principle) which is equivalent to the axiom of choice

Page 8: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

The sense of Skolem’s “paradox”

• Thus, the sense of “Skolem’s paradox” is to demonstrate that the axiom of choice is equivalent to treating any infinite set not only as a countable one, but also even as a finite one just involving the “relativity of the notion of set”

• Even more, any finite set can be in turn interpreted as an infinite one once the axiom of choice is admitted

Page 9: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Skolem’s paradox and the one-to-one mapping of an infinite into a finite set

• Consequently, the extreme sense of “Skolem’s paradox” should be that the axiom of choice is equivalent to a one-to-one mapping of any finite into any infinite set therefore involving the concept of choice and thus of information as follows:

Page 10: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

The mapping by both kinds of distribution

• That mapping required by the axiom of choice and requiring it in turn should be grounded on a generalized function (Schwartz distribution) replacing it with an usual function randomly choosing only one value of the function for any value of the independent variable (argument)

• Consequently, the concept of choice can be defined by a pair of a generalized function and a usual one obeying the above condition

Page 11: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Choice and information by distributions

• Furthermore, the quantity of information is definable as some mapping of those pairs into a number set

• This is a generalized introduction of the quantity of information reducible to the standard definition of it where the set of the function values is finite for any value of the independent variable

• It includes the quantity of quantum information in the case where that set is infinite for at least one value of the argument

Page 12: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

The three definitions of information:

• The Kolmogorov – Chaitin – Martin-Löf measure of information as complexity can be obtained by the well-ordering of that mapping choice by choice

• The information of the relation of two probability distributions is equivalent to the minimal length of a series of bits necessary to be reconstructed the one probability distribution into the other

Page 13: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

The relation of infinity and finiteness: choice and information

• The special Skolem property of infinity implying both concepts of choice and information can be summarized so:

• Choice can be thought as the fundamental way for infinity and finiteness to be reconciled consistently

• The concept and quantity of information are derivative from ‘choice’ as the quality and quantity of choice(s)

Page 14: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

The finite improper interpretation of any infinite set

• If the axiom of choice is given, any infinite set possesses always an improper finite interpretation, which implies in turn that any finite set possesses an improper infinite interpretation

• Thus the introduction of infinity under the axiom of choice implies the doubling of any mathematical structure either finite or infinite with an improper twin interpretation correspondingly either infinite or finite

Page 15: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Both proper and improper interpretations

• That property can ground any consistent mathematical structure in itself by itself so:

• The improper interpretation can be always interpreted as the ground of the proper one and the improper and proper interpretations are isomorphic to each other

• Consequently, that structure self-founds by the mediation of the improper twin interpretation

Page 16: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Infinity and finiteness as twins

• Thus the introduction of infinity in the pair of infinity and finiteness implies the self-foundation of any consistent mathematical structure under the condition of the axiom of choice

• In other words, the concepts of choice and information by means of the axiom of choice implies for infinity and finiteness to be twined as two copies or two interpretations of some joint structure

Page 17: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

The axiom of choice between finiteness and infinity

• However, if the axiom of choice does not hold, a gap divides finiteness from infinity

• The same can be literally repeated as to the grounding and grounded, too:

• Thus the axiom of choice twins also them implying self-foundation. Its rejection divides them correspondingly into a meta-theory and a theory incommensurate to each other

Page 18: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Gödel’s completeness theorem

• The so-called completeness theorem of Gödel (1930) can serve as an illustration:

• The finite set of axioms and the infinite set of theorems implied by the formers under the conditions of the cited theorem can be considered as the above twin interpretations implying self-foundation (completeness)

Page 19: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Gödel’s incompleteness theorem

• The so-called first incompleteness theorem of Gödel (1931) can be interpreted in the same context as the impossibility of an infinite set of statements to ground itself constructively (including Peano’s axioms) on the finite set of axioms

• However, the sense of Gödel’s incompleteness theorem outlines better on the background of his completeness theorem (1930)

Page 20: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Completeness vs incompleteness

• The real distinction between the completeness (1930) and the incompleteness (1931) is due to the added constructiveness by means of Peano arithmetic

• In other words, the completeness of mathematics can be only nonconstructive for Peano arithmetic

Page 21: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Peano arithmetic needs a generalization

• If one needs constructive completeness, the Peano arithmetic should be generalized:

• For example, by transfinite induction instead of induction as did Gentzen (1936, 1938)

• Or by admitting the middle as to infinite sets as did intuitionism

Page 22: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Zermelo’s strategy

• Zermelo’s strategy (1908) of the foundation of set theory in a consistent way is another illustration: A set can be accepted to be a set if and only if it is a true subset of another set

• This excludes the universal set • However, its sense in the above context is

different:

Page 23: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Zermelo’s strategy and Skolem’s paradox

• One can choose a relevant subset (B) of the complement to any set (A) so that the pair of A and B to be considered correspondingly as one of the proper and improper interpretation of some joint structure

• Even more, Skolem’s innovation can serve as the base of a rigorous proof for consistency of the ZFC set theory

Page 24: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Skolem’s paradox as a “paradox”

• In fact, Skolem’s “paradox” is a breakthrough into the true understanding of infinity and its ability to constitute a self-grounding pair with finiteness

Page 25: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

The structure of the paper • Section 2 elucidates Skolem’s paradox after the axiom

of choice as the only consistent way to agree the finite Peano arithmetic with the transfinite (ZFC) set theory

• Section 3 offers an inherently random and probabilistic description of the pure mathematical existence and thus an unambiguous description of any infinite set by a certain probability distribution

• Section 4 interprets Schwartz’s distributions by probabilistic distribution and thus deduces the mutual complementarity of the choice of a set (E) as an equivalent to a certain infinite set and the choice of an element of E

Page 26: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

The structure of the paper

• Section 5 defines choice and information as pairs of Schwartz’s and probabilistic distribution

• Section 6 offers the idea of dual completeness and compares it with the completeness by Gentzen’s transfinite induction and by the intuitionist “middle”

• The conclusive Section 7 offers a viewpoint to mathematics and to its foundation from the theory of information

Page 27: Skolem’s “paradox” as logic of ground: The mutual foundation of both (im)proper interpretations

Спасибо за внимание! Ожидаю ваши вопросы и

комментарии