Sensitive Semantics2

download Sensitive Semantics2

of 4

Transcript of Sensitive Semantics2

  • 7/31/2019 Sensitive Semantics2

    1/4

    Sensitive Semantics

    Nothing has had a greater impact on 20th-

    century analytic philosophy than Freges

    Sense/Reference (Sinn/Bedeuting) distinction. What has received less attention1, no doubt at

    least in part due to Freges own disdain for natural language (Sprache), is his distinctionbetween that ofsinn (the context-neutral element of a sentence which orbits its referential

    axis) and kraft(that which determines the contextual significance of that sentences being

    uttered; the assertoric, imperative, interrogative and optativeforce which captures the

    sentences mood). Whilst not wishing to sanction such a divide in principleI dont believe

    it worksI do wish to sanction it in practice. First, as it serves as a useful tool for dividing

    two approaches to the subject (there are those that endorse it; those that dont); second,

    because it raises interesting questions about the subjects nature and future, for if Michael

    Dummett is right, without it, philosophy2

    has no future, at least not in any systematic sense3.

    In essence, this dissertation can be seen as an attempt to rebut Dummetts claim. That a)

    analytic philosophy has a future without the sense/force distinction and b) the distinction on

    its own is no guarantee of future progress, entails that the division, so conceived, provides

    neither necessary, nor sufficient grounds for the execution of the kind of project Dummett has

    in mind and so should be jettisoned. The case will be argued on contextualist grounds. I

    believe it to be both novel and important.

    Contextualism, it will be argued, at least in its contemporary semantic form, has been most

    clearly and radically articulated by Charles Travis. Nothing, however, as far as the following

    polemic goes turns on this; it is enough that he is held to be the villain of the piece by the

    relevant parties4

    . That the current constellation of positions that endorse a context-neutralsemantics of one form or another

    5renders his view unpopular, however, affords no grounds

    for its being discarded for we are not, as Austin would put it, playing old Harry with the

    underdog; the devil is in the detail alone. It will be argued, therefore, that whilst numerous

    objections both can and should be raised for the case against, an abandonment of

    contextualist principles would constitute, at best, a pyrrhic victory (or loss, as the case may

    well be). As criticisms of this position are developed, we will put more flesh on the bones of

    the view, or better, views of Travis. For the time being, let us start with Austin:

    It seems to be fairly generally realized (sic.) nowadays that if you just take a bunch of

    sentences...impeccably formulated in some language or other, there can be no

    question of sorting them out into those that are true and those that are false; for

    (leaving out of account so called analytic sentences) the question of truth and

    falsehood does not turn only on what a sentence is, nor yet on what it means, but on,

    1Dummett asides!

    2Need to point out that this might refer to analytic philosophy, or philosophy tout court

    3

    Reference Dummett4Include protagonists here Charles and Lepore, Jerry Fodor and Tim Williamson

    5Reference C&L, Davidson, minimalist & deflationist accounts Horwich etc.

  • 7/31/2019 Sensitive Semantics2

    2/4

    speaking very broadly, the circumstances in which it is uttered. Sentences are not as

    such either true or false. (Austin 1962b, pp.110-111quoted in Travis 2008 p.26)

    Travis grants Austin proved badly mistaken about the first point. Contemporary analytic

    philosophy, he thinks, has taken a recent turn for the worse. We are told, nevertheless, thathe was right about the rest, and that rest constitutesthe core idea of occasion-sensitivity

    (Ibid): viz that the illocutionary force of an utterance is determined by context alone, and that

    this holds the key to determining that which is said by whom it is said of at the time of their

    saying it (simpliciter, truth conditions).

    Before continuing, let us first make clear both what is and is notat issue here: to wit, those

    indexical sophistries the correct treatment of which both flexible and inflexible semanticists

    would not contest, at least not in any significantway. That I am here is meaningful if and

    only if the corresponding demands of modal saturation (most notably time, place and

    identity) are satisfied is trivial, handled both sensitively and insensitively in a convergent

    manner789

    . Once token reflexivity is thrown into the medley, however, thought is tied less

    loosely to the linguistic forms within which it is expressed: that the same thought manifests

    itself within different sentential contexts10

    combined with the fact that isomorphic sentential

    expressions can express a multiplicity of thoughts11

    is substantial and allows for an

    unshadowing ofmentalese1213

    which its antagonists cannot account for. If adaptability is

    held to be a virtue, evolutionists notwithstanding, then clearly contextualism is not without its

    charm. What is it, outside of context, for an object to be blue14

    ? What is it, for that matter,

    for an object to be an object15

    ?

    Earlier on, reference was made to contextualist semantics. In fact the position we find

    ourselves in, should we take seriously the truths of which Travis so speaks, extends beyond

    this. Occasion sensitivity, taking the former point as given, places extensive demands upon,

    not just analytic philosophy, but also metaphysics, epistemology and cognitive science16

    , the

    likes of which cannot be met by much of the current work being undertaken in those fields.

    That the world is not ontologically self-sufficient (it requires contextto do some work on its

    behalf); that expanding and contracting contextual modalities force a reconsideration of our

    basic conception of knowledge (post-Gettier); that the characteristic lack of systematicity

    6Need to reference

    7Reference Charles and Lepore leads to problems with their account (ultimately a moderate contextualism

    rather than a semantic minimalism8

    Insert Travis quote (pp2-3 OS)9

    Davidson quote (there was an event (performed by Jones (at midnight) that was the buttering of the toast))

    [symbolise] is this what we really mean?!10

    Insert example11

    Insert quote from Travis pigs grunting12

    Of course in ruling out both rigid and flaccid identity designation and so too systematicity13

    Need to add that antagonists might accept one side of the dichotomy, but only occasion sensitivity endorses

    both hence unsystematic14

    Rerference Travis?15Reference Austin S&S

    16One could of course go on here

  • 7/31/2019 Sensitive Semantics2

    3/4

    vital to semantic flexibility both violates and invalidates the principle of compositionality

    required to run both computational and connectionist models of mind (on at least two counts)

    and more generally, that the inaccessibility of a context-neutral semantics vitiates against the

    possibility of devising a coherent, deflationist or minimalist account of truth17

    (parochialism, at the risk of equivocation, is anything but parochial) all pose a threat tomuch, if not most, of what is currently at stake in contemporary philosophy. But all of this,

    of course, requires a level of demonstration that would be beyond the modest scope of this

    proposal. Such points, nevertheless, will be touched upon as the work progresses.

    There is a second, yet adjacent issue at play here concerning thepossibilia of progression in

    philosophy; more precisely, how one moves forward in the subject given the absence of a

    system which proceeds according to generally agreed methods of enquiry [of a special

    sort]18 (TOE p. 455). I have hinted at and will develop one way in which such an obligation

    may be met; one that both acknowledges Dummets general attitude that the philosophy of

    language is the foundation of the rest of philosophy19 since it is only by the analysis of

    language that we can analyse thought (TOE p. 442) but resists his inference that it is difficult

    to see how a systematic theory of meaning for a language is possible without acknowledging

    the distinction between sense and force20

    . (TOE p. 450). Such a conception might comprise

    a third way of handling progress21

    which evades the constraints a commitment to

    Dummetts general principle obliges whilst still preserving a progression of sorts. Whilst not

    explicitin Travis there is, nevertheless, an implicit global commitment to the view that

    occasion sensitivity pervades all areas of the discourse22

    . That a) penumbral indeterminacy

    and a rejection of sharp cut-offs present in AristotlesCondition (etal), insofar as it

    precipitates a reconsideration of what we might call true; b) the extent to which theexpansion and contraction of modalpossibilia

    23impinges upon the epistemic conditions

    which legislate over factive meaning (bleats meaning sheep and the possibility of

    ringer situations -A Sense of Occasion et al); c) the unshadowing of thought militates

    against the compositional account of cognition required to construct a representational

    model of mind (and the subsequent productivity and systematicity of thought which regiment

    our conceptual repertoire and so manufacture the modal infinities of mentalese); but perhaps

    most importantly, and simply, that d) meaning, in the traditional sense of the word, is far

    more sensitive to occasion than we might otherwise imagine, indicates that the causal

    influence exerted by radical contextualism is pervasive. As to the question of where next?,

    as we shall see, far from being thwarted, the contextualist practitioner is actually spoilt for

    choice.

    17Insert Crispin Wright quote to show that the two are not synonymous

    18Which will be de

    19See note 2 of Grahamsit article WSUP

    20For without systemacity, there can be, as we shall see, for Dummett, no progress

    21

    In relation to Dummets two conceptions of progress and systematicity (CAP) 22Reference Travis article on Philosophy in the 21

    stCentury

    23See for example Millar p. 342

  • 7/31/2019 Sensitive Semantics2

    4/4

    The second sense concerns Wittgensteins conception of philosophy; most notably the view

    that philosophy is therapeutic through and through24

    . For if the role of philosopher consists

    in nothing more than shewing the fly the way out of the fly-bottle25

    what form of progress,

    if any, can be envisioned beyond the clarification of characteristic kinds ofintellectual

    confusion the only remedy for which is extended and patient treatment (TOE p. 439)?Paradoxically, as I hope to show, Dummett argues that Wittgenstein offers a more robust

    account than Austin, whosephilosophy is not a therapy, but an empirical study [of particular

    words and their particular uses] incapable of systematisation (TOE p. 440). It will be

    argued that this is perhaps not so, but that Wittgensteins contextualism does offer us a future

    of sorts and that progress in philosophy more of a kind of work on oneself (PO p. 161),

    whilst slow, can nevertheless be significant. I see no reason to view the above two positions

    as divergent; proceeding in different directions, perhaps, but ultimately applying the same

    method of criteria. Much of the above exposition, however, turns on earlier arguments

    presented by Michael Dummett, and it is to these we now turn.

    24reference

    25reference