Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer...

18
Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer [email protected]

Transcript of Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer...

Page 1: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance

Vincent Conitzer [email protected]

Page 2: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Risk attitudes• Which would you prefer?

– A lottery ticket that pays out $10 with probability .5 and $0 otherwise, or

– A lottery ticket that pays out $3 with probability 1• How about:

– A lottery ticket that pays out $100,000,000 with probability .5 and $0 otherwise, or

– A lottery ticket that pays out $30,000,000 with probability 1• Usually, people do not simply go by expected value• An agent is risk-neutral if she only cares about the

expected value of the lottery ticket• An agent is risk-averse if she always prefers the

expected value of the lottery ticket to the lottery ticket– Most people are like this

• An agent is risk-seeking if she always prefers the lottery ticket to the expected value of the lottery ticket

Page 3: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Decreasing marginal utility• Typically, at some point, having an extra dollar does

not make people much happier (decreasing marginal utility)

utility

money$200 $1500 $5000

buy a bike (utility = 1)

buy a car (utility = 2)

buy a nicer car (utility = 3)

Page 4: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Maximizing expected utility

• Lottery 1: get $1500 with probability 1– gives expected utility 2

• Lottery 2: get $5000 with probability .4, $200 otherwise– gives expected utility .4*3 + .6*1 = 1.8– (expected amount of money = .4*$5000 + .6*$200 = $2120 > $1500)

• So: maximizing expected utility is consistent with risk aversion

utility

money$200 $1500 $5000

buy a bike (utility = 1)

buy a car (utility = 2)

buy a nicer car (utility = 3)

Page 5: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Different possible risk attitudes under expected utility maximization

utility

money• Green has decreasing marginal utility → risk-averse• Blue has constant marginal utility → risk-neutral• Red has increasing marginal utility → risk-seeking• Grey’s marginal utility is sometimes increasing,

sometimes decreasing → neither risk-averse (everywhere) nor risk-seeking (everywhere)

Page 6: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

What is utility, anyway?• Function u: O → (O is the set of “outcomes” that lotteries

randomize over)• What are its units?

– It doesn’t really matter– If you replace your utility function by u’(o) = a + bu(o), your behavior will

be unchanged• Why would you want to maximize expected utility?• For two lottery tickets L and L’, let pL + (1-p)L’ be the

“compound” lottery ticket where you get lottery ticket L with probability p, and L’ with probability 1-p

• L ≥ L’ means that L is (weakly) preferred to L’ – (≥ should be complete, transitive)

• Expected utility theorem. Suppose– (continuity axiom) for all L, L’, L’’, {p: pL + (1-p)L’ ≥ L’’} and {p: pL + (1-

p)L’ ≤ L’’} are closed sets,– (independence axiom – more controversial) for all L, L’, L’’, p, we have L

≥ L’ if and only if pL + (1-p)L’’ ≥ pL’ + (1-p)L’’

then there exists a function u: O → so that L ≥ L’ if and only if L gives a higher expected value of u than L’

Page 7: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Normal-form games

Page 8: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Rock-paper-scissors

0, 0 -1, 1 1, -1

1, -1 0, 0 -1, 1

-1, 1 1, -1 0, 0

Row player aka. player 1

chooses a row

Column player aka. player 2

(simultaneously) chooses a column

A row or column is called an action or

(pure) strategyRow player’s utility is always listed first, column player’s second

Zero-sum game: the utilities in each entry sum to 0 (or a constant)Three-player game would be a 3D table with 3 utilities per entry, etc.

Page 9: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

“Chicken”

0, 0 -1, 1

1, -1 -5, -5

D

S

D S

S

D

D

S

• Two players drive cars towards each other• If one player goes straight, that player wins• If both go straight, they both die

not zero-sum

Page 10: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Rock-paper-scissors – Seinfeld variant

0, 0 1, -1 1, -1

-1, 1 0, 0 -1, 1

-1, 1 1, -1 0, 0

MICKEY: All right, rock beats paper!(Mickey smacks Kramer's hand for losing)KRAMER: I thought paper covered rock.

MICKEY: Nah, rock flies right through paper.KRAMER: What beats rock?

MICKEY: (looks at hand) Nothing beats rock.

Page 11: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Dominance• Player i’s strategy si strictly dominates si’ if

– for any s-i, ui(si , s-i) > ui(si’, s-i)

• si weakly dominates si’ if – for any s-i, ui(si , s-i) ≥ ui(si’, s-i); and– for some s-i, ui(si , s-i) > ui(si’, s-i)

0, 0 1, -1 1, -1

-1, 1 0, 0 -1, 1

-1, 1 1, -1 0, 0

strict dominance

weak dominance

-i = “the player(s) other than i”

Page 12: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Prisoner’s Dilemma

-2, -2 0, -3

-3, 0 -1, -1

confess

• Pair of criminals has been caught• District attorney has evidence to convict them of a minor crime (1 year in

jail); knows that they committed a major crime together (3 years in jail) but cannot prove it

• Offers them a deal:– If both confess to the major crime, they each get a 1 year reduction– If only one confesses, that one gets 3 years reduction

don’t confess

don’t confess

confess

Page 13: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

“Should I buy an SUV?”

-10, -10 -7, -11

-11, -7 -8, -8

cost: 5

cost: 3

cost: 5 cost: 5

cost: 5 cost: 5

cost: 8 cost: 2

purchasing cost accident cost

Page 14: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Mixed strategies• Mixed strategy for player i = probability

distribution over player i’s (pure) strategies

• E.g. 1/3 , 1/3 , 1/3

• Example of dominance by a mixed strategy:

3, 0 0, 0

0, 0 3, 0

1, 0 1, 0

1/2

1/2

Page 15: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Checking for dominance by mixed strategies

• Linear program for checking whether strategy si* is strictly dominated by a mixed strategy:

• normalize to positive payoffs first, then solve:

• minimize Σsi psi

• such that: for any s-i, Σsi psi

ui(si, s-i) ≥ ui(si*, s-i)

• Linear program for checking whether strategy si* is weakly dominated by a mixed strategy:

• maximize Σs-i(Σsi

psi ui(si, s-i)) – ui(si*, s-i)

• such that: – for any s-i, Σsi

psi ui(si, s-i) ≥ ui(si*, s-i)

– Σsi psi

= 1

Note: linear programs can be solved in polynomial time

Page 16: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Iterated dominance

• Iterated dominance: remove (strictly/weakly) dominated strategy, repeat

• Iterated strict dominance on Seinfeld’s RPS:

0, 0 1, -1 1, -1

-1, 1 0, 0 -1, 1

-1, 1 1, -1 0, 0

0, 0 1, -1

-1, 1 0, 0

Page 17: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Iterated dominance: path (in)dependence

0, 1 0, 0

1, 0 1, 0

0, 0 0, 1

Iterated weak dominance is path-dependent: sequence of eliminations may determine which

solution we get (if any)(whether or not dominance by mixed strategies allowed)

0, 1 0, 0

1, 0 1, 0

0, 0 0, 1

0, 1 0, 0

1, 0 1, 0

0, 0 0, 1

Iterated strict dominance is path-independent: elimination process will always terminate at the same point

(whether or not dominance by mixed strategies allowed)

Page 18: Risk attitudes, normal-form games, dominance, iterated dominance Vincent Conitzer conitzer@cs.duke.edu.

Two computational questions for iterated dominance

• 1. Can a given strategy be eliminated using iterated dominance?

• 2. Is there some path of elimination by iterated dominance such that only one strategy per player remains?

• For strict dominance (with or without dominance by mixed strategies), both can be solved in polynomial time due to path-independence:– Check if any strategy is dominated, remove it, repeat

• For weak dominance, both questions are NP-hard (even when all utilities are 0 or 1), with or without dominance by mixed strategies [Conitzer, Sandholm 05]– Weaker version proved by [Gilboa, Kalai, Zemel 93]