Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of...

47
Reverse Causation and the Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA AAAS Pacific Division: Frontiers of Time USD, San Diego, CA, June 21, 2006 Quantum Mechanics
  • date post

    21-Dec-2015
  • Category

    Documents

  • view

    220
  • download

    0

Transcript of Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of...

Page 1: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Reverse Causation and the Reverse Causation and the Transactional Transactional

InterpretationInterpretation

Reverse Causation and the Reverse Causation and the Transactional Transactional

InterpretationInterpretation

John G. CramerJohn G. CramerDept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington

Seattle, Washington 98195, USA

John G. CramerJohn G. CramerDept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington

Seattle, Washington 98195, USA

AAAS Pacific Division: Frontiers of TimeUSD, San Diego, CA, June 21, 2006

QuantumMechanics

Page 2: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Outline of TalkOutline of Talk

About Quantum Interpretations

An introduction to the Transactional Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

A new Retro-Causality Quantum Paradox(or how to send messages back in time by 50 s)

Page 3: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

A Quantum A Quantum MetaphorMetaphor

A Quantum A Quantum MetaphorMetaphor

(With apologies to Indostanis with Disabilities)(With apologies to Indostanis with Disabilities)

Page 4: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

The Blind MenThe Blind Menand the Elephantand the Elephant

by John Godfrey Saxe (1816-by John Godfrey Saxe (1816-1887)1887)

The Blind MenThe Blind Menand the Elephantand the Elephant

by John Godfrey Saxe (1816-by John Godfrey Saxe (1816-1887)1887)

It was six men of Indostan, To learning much inclined, Who went to see the Elephant,(Though all of them were blind), That each by observation, Might satisfy his mind. .

The First approached the Elephant, And happening to fall, Against his broad and sturdy side, At once began to bawl: “God bless me! but the Elephant, Is very like a wall!”

The Second, feeling of the tusk, Cried, “Ho! what have we here, So very round and smooth and sharp? To me ’tis mighty clear, This wonder of an Elephant, Is very like a spear!”

The Third approached the animal, And happening to take, The squirming trunk within his hands, Thus boldly up and spake: “I see,” quoth he, “the Elephant, Is very like a snake!”

The Fourth reached out an eager hand, And felt about the knee. “What most this wondrous beast is like, Is mighty plain,” quoth he; “ ‘Tis clear enough the Elephant, Is very like a tree!”

The Fifth, who chanced to touch the ear, Said: “E’en the blindest man, Can tell what this resembles most; Deny the fact who can, This marvel of an Elephant, Is very like a fan!”

The Sixth no sooner had begun, About the beast to grope, Than, seizing on the swinging tail, That fell within his scope, I see,” quoth he, “the Elephant, Is very like a rope!”

And so these men of Indostan, Disputed loud and long, Each in his own opinion, Exceeding stiff and strong, Though each was partly in the right, And all were in the wrong!

Moral: So oft in theologic wars, The disputants, I ween, Rail on in utter ignorance, Of what each other mean, And prate about an Elephant, Not one of them has seen!

quantum interpretational discussions

a quantum process

Page 5: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Quantum Theory and

Interpretations

Quantum Theory and

Interpretations

Page 6: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

What is Quantum Mechanics?

What is Quantum Mechanics?

QuantumMechanics

Quantum mechanics is a theory. It is ourcurrent “standard model” for describingthe behavior of matter and energy atthe smallest scales (photons, atoms,nuclei, quarks, gluons, leptons, …).

Like all theories, it consists of amathematical formalism, plus aninterpretation of that formalism.

However, quantum mechanics differs from other physical theories because, while its formalism of has been accepted and used for 80 years, its interpretation remains a matter of controversy and debate. Like the opinions of the 6 blind men, there are many rival QM interpretations on the market (Copenhagen, Many-Worlds, …).

Today, however, we’ll consider only one QM interpretation, the Transactional Interpretation of quantum mechanics.

Page 7: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

The Role of an InterpretationThe Role of an Interpretation

An interpretation of a formalism should:

Provide links between the mathematical symbols of the formalism and elementsof the physical world;

Neutralize the paradoxes; all of them;addressing only a few of the formalism’s interpretational problems is undesirable;

Provide tools for visualization, for speculation, and for extension.

An interpretation should not have its own sub-formalism!

It should not make its own testable predictions, (but it may be falsifiable, if it is found to be inconsistent with the formalism and/or with experiment)!

Page 8: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Example: Newton’s 2nd Law

Example: Newton’s 2nd Law

Formalism:

What this interpretation does: It relates the formalism to physical observables. It avoids the paradoxes that would arise if m<0. It insures that F||a.

Interpretation: “The vector force Fon a body is proportional to the productof its scalar mass m, which is positive,and the 2nd time derivative a of its vector position.”

F = m a

Page 9: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

The TransactionalThe TransactionalInterpretationInterpretationof Quantumof QuantumMechanicsMechanics

The TransactionalThe TransactionalInterpretationInterpretationof Quantumof QuantumMechanicsMechanics

Page 10: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

“Listening” to the Quantum Mechanical Formalism

“Listening” to the Quantum Mechanical Formalism

Consider a quantum matrix element:

<S> = vSdr3 = <f | S | i>

… a *- “sandwich”. What does this suggest?

Hint: The complex conjugation in is the Wigner operator for time reversal. If is a retarded wave, then is an advanced wave.

If ei(kr t) then ei(-kr t)

(retarded) (advanced)

A retarded wave carries positive energy to the future.An advanced wave carries negative energy to the past.

Page 11: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Maxwell’s Electromagnetic Wave

Equation (Classical)

Maxwell’s Electromagnetic Wave

Equation (Classical)Fic2Fit2

This is a 2nd order differential equation, which has two time solutions, retarded and advanced.

Wheeler-Feynman Approach: Use ½ retarded and ½ advanced(time symmetry).

Conventional Approach: Choose only the retarded solution(a “causality” boundary condition).

Page 12: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

A Wheeler-Feynman Electromagnetic “Transaction”

A Wheeler-Feynman Electromagnetic “Transaction”

The emitter sends retarded and advanced waves. It “offers” to transfer energy.

Page 13: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

A Wheeler-Feynman Electromagnetic “Transaction”

A Wheeler-Feynman Electromagnetic “Transaction”

The emitter sends retarded and advanced waves. It “offers” to transfer energy.

The absorber responds with an advanced wave that“confirms” the transaction.

Absorber

Page 14: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

A Wheeler-Feynman Electromagnetic “Transaction”

A Wheeler-Feynman Electromagnetic “Transaction”

The emitter sends retarded and advanced waves. It “offers” to transfer energy.

The absorber responds with an advanced wave that“confirms” the transaction.

The loose ends cancel and disappear, and energy is transferred.

Page 15: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Offer Wave:The initial wave function is interpreted as aretarded-wave offer to form a quantum event.

Confirmation wave:The conjugate wave function * is interpreted as an advanced-wave confirmation to proceed with the quantum event.

Transaction – the Quantum Handshake: The many * combinations present in the QM formalism are interpreted as indicating the formation of a forward/back-in-time standing wave that transfers energy, momentum, and other conserved quantities.

No Observers:Transactions involving observers are no different from other transactions; Observers and their knowledge play no special roles.

No Paradoxes:Transactions are intrinsically nonlocal, and all (?) paradoxes are resolved.

Few Postulates (Economical):Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle and Born’s statistical interpretationcan be derived from the Transactional Interpretation.

Overview of theTransactional Interpretation

Overview of theTransactional Interpretation

Page 16: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

We apply the same logic to QM:Step 1: The emitter sends

out an “offer wave” .

The QuantumTransactional Model

The QuantumTransactional Model

Page 17: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

We apply the same logic to QM:Step 1: The emitter sends

out an “offer wave” .

Step 2: The absorber responds with a “confirmation wave” *.

The QuantumTransactional Model

The QuantumTransactional Model

Page 18: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

The QuantumTransactional Model

The QuantumTransactional Model

We apply the same logic to QM:Step 1: The emitter sends

out an “offer wave” .

Step 2: The absorber responds with a “confirmation wave” *.

Step 3: The process repeats until energy and momentum is transferred and the transaction is completed (wave function collapse).

Page 19: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

The TI and theUncertainty Principle

The TI and theUncertainty Principle

The completed transactionprojects out only that part of the offer wave that had been reinforced by the confirmation wave (=> measurement).

Consequently, the transactioncan project out only one of two complementary variables.

This accounts for Heisenberg’s Uncertainty Principle.

Page 20: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

The TI and theBorn Probability Law

The TI and theBorn Probability Law

Starting from E&M and theWheeler-Feynman approach, theE-field “echo” that the emitterreceives from the absorber isthe product of the retarded-waveE-field at the absorber and the advanced-wave E-field at the emitter.

Translating this to quantummechanical terms, the “echo” thatthe emitter receives from eachpotential absorber is i i*, leadingto the Born Probability Law.

Wave amplitudehere is *

Page 21: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Role of the Observerin the TI

Role of the Observerin the TI

In the Copenhagen Interpretation,observers are given the special roleas “Collapsers of Wave Functions”.This leads to problems, e.g., inquantum cosmology where noobservers are presumably present.

In the Transactional Interpretation, transactions involving an observer are the same as any other transactions.

Thus, the observer-centric aspects of the Copenhagen Interpretation are avoided.

Page 22: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Can the TI be Tested?Can the TI be Tested? The simple answer is “No!”. It is the formalism of

quantum mechanics that makes all of the testable predictions.

As long as an interpretation like the TI is consistent with the formalism, it will make the same predictions as any other valid interpretation, and no experimental tests are possible.

However, an interpretations may be inconsistent with the quantum mechanical formalism and its predictions.

If this is true, then the interpretation can be falsified.

The Transactional Interpretation follows the quantum formalism very closely and does not appear to have problems in this area.

Page 23: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

The TI and The TI and Some Some

Quantum Quantum ParadoxesParadoxes

The TI and The TI and Some Some

Quantum Quantum ParadoxesParadoxes

Page 24: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Paradox 1 (non-locality):Einstein’s Bubble

Paradox 1 (non-locality):Einstein’s Bubble

Situation: A photon is emitted from a source having no directional preference.

Page 25: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Paradox 1 (non-locality):Einstein’s Bubble

Paradox 1 (non-locality):Einstein’s Bubble

Situation: A photon is emitted from a source having no directional preference.Its spherical wave function expands like an inflating bubble.

Page 26: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Paradox 1 (non-locality):Einstein’s Bubble

Paradox 1 (non-locality):Einstein’s Bubble

Question: (originally asked by Albert Einstein)If a photon is detected at Detector A, how does the

photon’s wave function at the locations of Detectors B & C “know” that it should vanish?

Situation: A photon is emitted from a source having no directional preference.Its spherical wave function expands like an inflating bubble.It reaches Detector A, and the bubble “pops” and disappears.

Page 27: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

It is as if one throws a beer bottle into Boston Harbor. It disappears, and its quantum ripples spread all over the Atlantic.

Then in Copenhagen, the beer bottle suddenly jumps onto the dock, and the ripples disappear everywhere else.

That’s what quantum mechanics says happens to electrons and photons when they move from place to place.

Paradox 1 (non-locality):Einstein’s Bubble

Paradox 1 (non-locality):Einstein’s Bubble

Page 28: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

TI Explanation:

A transaction developsbetween the source anddetector A, transferring the energy there and blocking any similar transfer to the other potential detectors, due to the 1-photon boundary condition.

The transactional handshakes acts nonlocally to answer Einstein’s question.

We will return to nonlocality, the EPR Paradox, and possible retro-causal implications later in the talk.

Paradox 1 (non-locality):Einstein’s Bubble

Paradox 1 (non-locality):Einstein’s Bubble

Page 29: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Paradox 2 (wave/particle):Wheeler’s Delayed ChoiceParadox 2 (wave/particle):Wheeler’s Delayed Choice

The observer waits until after the photon has passed the slits to decide which measurement to do.

***

A source emits one photon.Its wave function passesthrough slits 1 and 2, makinginterference beyond the slits.

The observer can choose to either:(a) measure the interference pattern at plane requiring that the photon travels through both slits.

or(b) measure at which slit image it appears in plane indicating thatit has passed only through slit 2.

Page 30: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Paradox 2 (wave/particle):Wheeler’s Delayed ChoiceParadox 2 (wave/particle):Wheeler’s Delayed Choice

Thus, in Wheeler’s accountof the process, the photon doesnot “decide” if it is a particleor a wave until after it passesthe slits, even though a particlemust pass through only one slit while a wave must pass through both slits.

Wheeler asserts that the measurement choice determines whether the photon is a particle or a wave retroactively!

Page 31: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Paradox 2 (wave/particle):Wheeler’s Delayed ChoiceParadox 2 (wave/particle):Wheeler’s Delayed ChoiceTI Explanation: If the screen at 1 is up, a

transaction forms between1 and the source andinvolves waves passingthrough both slits 1 and 2.

Page 32: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Paradox 2 (wave/particle):Wheeler’s Delayed ChoiceParadox 2 (wave/particle):Wheeler’s Delayed ChoiceTI Explanation: If the screen at s1 is up, a

transaction forms between1 and the source andinvolves waves passingthrough both slits 1 and 2.

If the screen at 1 is down, a transaction forms between detectors 1’ or 2’ and the source S, and involves waves passing through only one slit.

Page 33: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Paradox 2 (wave/particle):Wheeler’s Delayed ChoiceParadox 2 (wave/particle):Wheeler’s Delayed ChoiceTI Explanation: If the screen at s1 is up, a

transaction forms between1 and the source andinvolves waves passingthrough both slits 1 and 2.

If the screen at 1 is down, a transaction forms between detectors 1’ or 2’ and the source S, and involves waves passing through only one slit.

In either case, when the measurement decision was made is irrelevant.

Page 34: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Paradox 3 (interference):The Afshar Experiment

Paradox 3 (interference):The Afshar Experiment

In a Delayed Choice setup, place wires with 6% opacity at the positions of the interference minima at 1;

Place detector at 2’ on plane 2 and observe the particles passing through slit 2.

Question: What fraction of the light is blocked by the grid and not transmitted to 2’? (i.e., is the interference pattern still there when one is measuring particle behavior?)

Page 35: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Paradox 3 (interference):The Afshar Experiment

Paradox 3 (interference):The Afshar Experiment

Grid & 1 Slit

6% Loss

Grid & 2 Slits

<0.1% Loss

No Grid & 2 Slits

No Loss

Page 36: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Astra Image Line Plot - Rotate - Row [531]4/6/2004 6:05:39 AM

Pixel Number1,3001,2001,1001,0009008007006005004003002001000

Pix

el V

alue

240

220

200

180

160

140

120

100

80

60

40

20

0

Astra Image Line Plot - Rotate - Row [531]4/6/2004 6:09:36 AM

Pixel Number1,3001,2001,1001,0009008007006005004003002001000

Pix

el V

alue

240

220

200

180

160

140

120

100

80

60

40

20

0

Astra Image Line Plot - Rotate - Row [531]4/6/2004 6:17:35 AM

Pixel Number1,3001,2001,1001,0009008007006005004003002001000

Pix

el V

alue

240

220

200

180

160

140

120

100

80

60

40

20

0

One openWire present

Both openNo Wire

Both openWire present

Paradox 3 (interference):The Afshar Experiment

Paradox 3 (interference):The Afshar Experiment

Page 37: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Paradox 3 (interference):The Afshar Experiment

Paradox 3 (interference):The Afshar Experiment

Conclusions:

Interference is still present, even when an unambiguous Welcher-Weg (which-way) experiment is performed.

Measuring particle-like behavior does not suppress wave-like behavior, if careful non-interactive measurements are made.

It appears that light waves must pass both slits to create the interference, even when the photon passes through only one slit.

Page 38: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

TI Explanation: The initial offer waves pass through both slits on their way to possible absorbers. At the wires, the offer waves cancel in first order, so that no transactions can form and no photons can be intercepted by the wires.

Therefore, the absorption by the wires should be very small (<<6%) and consistent with what is observed.

Paradox 3 (interference):The Afshar Experiment

Paradox 3 (interference):The Afshar Experiment

destructive

Page 39: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

A new Retro-A new Retro-Causality Paradox Causality Paradox (or how to send (or how to send

messages back in messages back in time by 50 time by 50 s)s)

A new Retro-A new Retro-Causality Paradox Causality Paradox (or how to send (or how to send

messages back in messages back in time by 50 time by 50 s)s)

Page 40: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Down-Conversion with LiIO3

Down-Conversion with LiIO3

=702.2 nm

=702.2 nm

LiIO3 Crystal

351.1 nmUV Laser Beam

BeamStop

1 2 1 21 2

1 1;Laser Laser

Laser

hcE E E hc k k k

Energy and Momentum Conservation:

1 2 1 2

1' " " '

2k k k k

Entangled Photons:

Page 41: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Dopfer’s Position-MomentumEPR Experiment

Dopfer’s Position-MomentumEPR Experiment

“Heisenberg” Lensf = 86 cm

LiIO3

Down-ConversionCrystal

Double-SlitDetector D2

Double Slit Systema = 75 m, d = 255 m

CoincidenceCircuit

AuxiliaryLens

UV LaserBeam

Laser BeamStop

f 2f

or

“Heisenberg”Detector D1

f 2f

PositionMomentum

28.2o

28.2 o

Birgit DopferPhD ThesisU. Innsbruck, 1998.

Note the useof coincidence.

Page 42: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Can EPR be used for Observer-to-Observer

Communication?

Can EPR be used for Observer-to-Observer

Communication? There are theorems in the literature (Eberhard,

Shimony, …) showing that EPR nonlocal observer-to-observer communication is impossible.

Peacock and Hepburn have shown that these “proofs” are tautological and that certain key assumptions are inconsistent with aspects of the quantum formalism (e.g., BE symmetrization).

Therefore, the question remains “open” (at least a crack).

Page 43: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

Slit ImagePlane

Fiber-Optics Light Pipes

(n = 1.5)

2nd ObjectPlane Transmitter

10km

1st ObjectPlane (Slits)

“1”“0”

Receiver (interference or no interference?)

The signal arrives 50 s before it is sent!

“1”“0”

k1k0

k2

Cramer’s Retrocausal Dopfer Experiment

Cramer’s Retrocausal Dopfer Experiment

Based on a suggestionby Raymond JensenU. Notre Dame, 2006.

Page 44: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

A Transactional Analysis ofthe Dopfer Experiment

A Transactional Analysis ofthe Dopfer Experiment

D2

D1

LiIO3

Crystal

Retro-causalInfluence?

From the point of view of the Transactional Interpretation, the nonlocal connection between detection events at D1 and D2 arises because the two transactions must share a “handshake” at the LiIO3 crystal, which can only be realized when the summed energies and momenta of the two photons equal that of the pump-laser photon that created them. Moreover, if a photon is detected when D2 is in the 2f position where the one of the slit is imaged, the advanced-wave confirmation can pass only through that slit, and no 2-slit interference is possible. On the other hand, , if a photon is detected when D2 is in the f position illuminated by both slits, the advanced-wave confirmation can pass through both slits and 2-slit interference is present.

No barrier to retro-causation is apparent in this TI analysis.

k2

k1

t

x

Retarded Wave

Advanced Wave

Advance

d Wav

e

Retard

ed W

ave

f

2f

Page 45: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

ConclusionsConclusionsThe Transactional Interpretation provides a way of

understanding the counter-intuitive aspects of quantum mechanics.

Its advance-retarded handshake provides a way of understanding the intrinsic nonlocality of quantum mechanics, while preserving the constraints of special relativity.

Among quantum interpretations, the TI is unusual in providing a graphic way of visualizing quantum processes (including quantum computing).

Analysis of the Dopfer Experiment with the Transactional Interpretation does not reveal any “show-stopper” that would prevent retrocausal signaling.

Page 46: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

ReferencesReferencesTransactional

“The Transactional Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics”, Reviews of Modern Physics 58, 647 (1986). Available at http://www.npl.washington.edu/TI or at the RMP web site.

“The Plane of the Present and the Transactional Paradigm of Time”, Chapter 9 of Time and the Instant, Robin Drurie, ed., Clinamen Press, UK (2001); ArXiv reprint: quant-ph/0507089

“Zwei Experimente zur Interferenz von Zwei-Photonen Zuständen”, Birgit Dopfer, PhD Thesis, U. Innsbruck (1998).

The PowerPoint version of this talk will soon be available at: http://faculty.washington.edu/jcramer

Page 47: Reverse Causation and the Transactional Interpretation John G. Cramer Dept. of Physics, Univ. of Washington Seattle, Washington 98195, USA John G. Cramer.

TheTheEndEndTheTheEndEnd