Retrospectives, From Usury to Interest

11
American Economic Association Retrospectives: From Usury to Interest Author(s): Joseph Persky Reviewed work(s): Source: The Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 21, No. 1 (Winter, 2007), pp. 227-236 Published by: American Economic Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/30033709 . Accessed: 16/09/2012 15:01 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . American Economic Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Economic Perspectives. http://www.jstor.org

Transcript of Retrospectives, From Usury to Interest

Page 1: Retrospectives, From Usury to Interest

American Economic Association

Retrospectives: From Usury to InterestAuthor(s): Joseph PerskyReviewed work(s):Source: The Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 21, No. 1 (Winter, 2007), pp. 227-236Published by: American Economic AssociationStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/30033709 .Accessed: 16/09/2012 15:01

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

American Economic Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to TheJournal of Economic Perspectives.

http://www.jstor.org

Page 2: Retrospectives, From Usury to Interest

Journal of Economic Perspectives-Volume 21, Number I--Winter 2007-Pages 227-236

Retrospectives From Usury To Interest

Joseph Persky

This feature addresses the history of economic terms and ideas. The hope is to

deepen the workaday dialogue of economists, while perhaps also casting new light on ongoing questions. If you have suggestions for future topics or authors, please write to Joseph Persky, c/o Journal of Economic Perspectives, Department of Econom- ics (M/C 144), University of Illinois at Chicago, 601 South Morgan Street, Room 2103, Chicago, Illinois 60607-7121.

Introduction

In modern economics, interest is defined as the rental price of money. But the word has a complex and less than fully resolved etymology. The origins of"interest" are intimately connected to the changing meaning of "usury." Canon law in the Middle Ages forbade usury, which was generally interpreted as a loan repayment exceeding the principal amount. Our modern word "interest" derives from the Medieval Latin interesse. The Oxford English Dictionary explains that interesse originally meant a penalty for the default on or late payment of an otherwise legitimate, nonusurious loan. As more sophisticated commercial and financial practices spread through Europe, fictitious late payments became an accepted if disingenuous way of circumventing usury laws. Over time, "interest" became the generic term for all

legitimate and accepted payments on loans. Since the Middle Ages, each epoch has participated in the debate over the

conditions in which lending should be prohibited as usury. Even today, state

legislatures wrestle with a modern manifestation of this debate. Most states have

legally defined usury rates that limit interest on loans between persons and corpo-

. Joseph Persky is Professor of Economics, University of Illinois at Chicago, Chicago, Illinois.

Page 3: Retrospectives, From Usury to Interest

228 Journal of Economic Perspectives

rations (Glaeser and Scheinkman, 1998). A number of state legislatures are cur-

rently considering prohibitions on the most egregious aspects of "payday lending," in which a borrower gives a payday lender a postdated personal check and receives

cash, minus the lender's fees. For example, with a $300 payday loan, a consumer

might pay $40 in fees and receive $260 in cash. With fees this high on short-term loans that are to be repaid within a few weeks, the implied per annum interest rates can reach 1000 percent and more (Stegman and Faris, 2003).

While disagreements over the definition of usury remain, the debate came to its modern climax on the eve of the industrial revolution, in a well-known inter-

change between Jeremy Bentham and Adam Smith in the late 1780s. Smith, for all his faith in a system of natural liberty, proved unwilling to let the interest rate float. Bentham argued anything else must reduce total welfare.

Here is a sketch of the bare facts: Through the first four editions of the Wealth

of Nations, Adam Smith supported state-imposed caps on the rate of interest. Much to the chagrin of many of his followers then and since, Smith thought 5 percent was

just about enough for any borrower in Great Britain to pay on a loan.1 In 1787,

writing from the estates of the Russian Count Potempkin in the backwater of Zadobrast near Krichev in Belarus, Jeremy Bentham penned his Defence of Usury as a series of letters.2 From the remote periphery of the expanding industrial revolu-

tion, Bentham claimed a place for usury in Smith's own system of economic liberties. In doing so, he explicitly sought to convince Adam Smith to give up his

support for interest rate limits. But the last edition of the Wealth of Nations to appear in Smith's lifetime, in 1789, left the usury passages unchanged.

From a superficial perspective, the entire affair amounts to nothing more than a modest dispute between a failing master (Smith died in 1790) and an over-eager disciple. (Bentham acknowledged in the Defence that all he knew of political economy originated in Smith's works.) Certainly this view is sometimes taken by those embarrassed by Smith's support of such an aggressive intervention in finan- cial markets. Yet the argument struck a fundamental chord. Gilbert K. Chesterton

(1933), for one, identified Bentham's essay on usury as the very beginning of the "modern world." I tend to agree with him. But before entertaining such ambitious claims, consider the historical context of the debate.3

1 The passages in Smith are in Book II, Chapter IV (Smith, 1776). For an example of modern chagrin, see Friedman (1976). Hollander (1999) discusses the similar reactions of Robbins (1968) and Stigler (1988). Keynes, however, often noted his support for usury laws and his general support for Smith's views on the subject (Keynes, 1936, chapter 23). 2 With one exception, the letters were addressed "to a friend," presumably Bentham's close friend

George Wilson. Letter XIII was addressed directly to Adam Smith. Bentham had journeyed into White Russia to assist his brother, Samuel, in various projects on behalf of Potempkin's efforts at Russian modernization. For a fascinating treatment of the two brothers' experiences in Russia, see Christie's (1993) The Benthams in Russia, 1780-1791. 3 The interchange between Smith and Bentham over usury has been the subject of several recent articles, including Hollander (1999), Kelly (2000) and Paganelli (2003).

Page 4: Retrospectives, From Usury to Interest

Joseph Persky 229

Early British Thought on Usury

In their open hostility to usury, the medieval churchmen of Britain, including Occam and Duns Scotus, subscribed to the traditional scholastic interpretations of Aristotle. Their writings, like those of Aquinas, defined usury in straightforward fashion as the practice of requiring payment for a loan (Noonan, 1957).4 The late scholastics in Salamanca-Catholic academics writing on economic issues between 1350 and 1650-began chipping away at this definition, excluding an ever-broader

range of normal business loans. With the enlivening of commercial markets, the "new men" of the English Renaissance supported this trend and began to change the meanings of the business vocabulary (see the "Introduction" to Wilson, 1572 [1925] by R. W. Tawney).

This shift in practice and thinking was not an unseen evolution; it was clearly observed and controversial as it occurred. Nor were all the traditionalists scholastic

churchmen. Writing in the late sixteenth century, Thomas Wilson, a scholar, judge and diplomat wrote his impassioned A Discourse on Usury (1572 [1925]), a broad attack on the spreading acceptance of interest-bearing loans among the merchant classes in England. As suggested by R. H. Tawney in his brilliant introduction to a 1925 edition of A Discourse, Wilson was representative of a traditionalist impulse reflecting early Protestant efforts to rebuild community and reestablish a sense of structured equity. Tawney quotes a letter of Wilson's (1572 [1925], p. 15), "The state is unfortunate in which nothing is permitted to anybody, but much more unfortunate in which everything is permitted to all."

Offering any number of traditional arguments, Wilson would not countenance the proposed difference between normal loans and usury at high interest. In "The Preachers Oracion," he makes clear (p. 229) that taking a low rate of interest "excuseth no man, when god forbiddeth all maner of taking." Lending according to the Preacher "shoulde be...free, simple, and for charityes sake...without anye thinge at all more than the principall."5

But this strong moral argument was increasingly undermined by the growing availability of profitable and relatively safe financial investments. In a 1601 essay "Of Usurie," Francis Bacon endorsed a system of state regulation fixing a lower interest rate (5 percent) for most loans and a higher rate (9 percent) for loans to merchants in large centers. Some 90 years later, John Locke (1691) does not even consider

seriously the possibility of an objection to interest per se. Instead he wrests only with the pragmatic issue of where to set the legal rate. A reduction to 4 percent from

4 However, as a Franciscan, Duns Scotus occasionally took exception to the interpretations of the Dominican, Aquinas, as discussed in Noonan (1957). 5 Lest lenders think such a bargain foolish, Wilson (p. 189) assured them in his "Christian Prologue" of greater rewards to come: "I will teache others to be greater usurers...to gaine more in a daye then others are able to get in seven yeres. . .Lend to your poore neighbors in time of their great neede for gaine on gods name...and you shall yerely, daylie, and howerly reape infinit gain. For as god is better able to rewarde you then man, so will he for his promise sake make you recompense with encrease infinitely."

Page 5: Retrospectives, From Usury to Interest

230 Journal of Economic Perspectives

6 percent had been proposed by the mercantilistJosiah Childe and a number of British merchants. For Locke, the point was clear. The experienced and clever would work their way around the law, while only widows and orphans would be left lending their money at the lower legal rate. Anticipating the core machinery of supply and demand theory, Locke argues that promised benefits from such a price ceiling would not materialize as the quantity supplied of funds con- tracted (p. 124).

Smith on Usury

By the late eighteenth century, virtually all economic commentators in Britain and many on the continent asserted the usefulness and accepted the legitimacy of interest payments in commerce and finance. Adam Smith was no exception. In the Wealth of Nations, Smith (1776, p. 339) simply stated what he took to be obvious when he wrote, "[A]s something can every-where be made by the use of money, something ought every-where to be paid for the use of it." Smith goes on to make a classic argument about black markets similar in spirit to Locke's. Efforts to outlaw interest only have the effect of raising the cost of borrowing: "This regulation, instead of preventing, has been found from experience to increase the evil of usury; the debtor being obliged to pay, not only for the use of the money, but for the risk which his creditor runs by accepting a compensation for that use. He is obliged, if one may say so, to insure his creditor from the penalties of usury."

The stage seemed set for Adam Smith to endorse the removal of legal restraints on interest and to move on. But Smith balked. Rather than making the case for a free market in loans, Smith made a case for limiting interest rates at something a bit above the lowest market rate. Smith (1776 [1937], p. 339) was worried about

usury: "[I]n order to prevent the extortion of usury, [a country which allows

interest] generally fixes the highest rate which can be taken without incurring a

penalty." Smith sees nothing wrong with this practice. Indeed he goes on to discuss where the legal maximum should be set: "This rate ought always to be somewhat above the lowest market price, or the price which is commonly paid for the use of

money by those who can give the most undoubted security...The legal rate, it is to be observed, though it ought to be somewhat above, ought not to be much above the lowest market rate."

The major rationale offered for this famous and much discussed limit on market transactions was Smith's (1776 [1937], p. 339) fear that at higher legal rates such as "eight or ten percent... the greater part of the money which was to be lent would be lent to prodigals and projectors, who alone would be willing to give this

high interest." It's pretty easy to know who Smith meant to include among "prod- igals," but who exactly did Smith have in mind when he wrote of "projectors"? The term was common in the eighteenth century. It included a surprisingly broad range of innovative financial and real investors. Ponzi schemes and wild speculations could be advanced by projectors, but so could real productive inventions. Else-

Page 6: Retrospectives, From Usury to Interest

Retrospectives: From Usury to Interest 231

where in the Wealth of Nations, Smith (1776 [1937], p. 301) indicates that while some projectors might invest in attractive ventures, great harm was to be expected from "chimerical projectors, the drawers and re-drawers of circulating bills of

exchange, who would employ.., money in extravagant undertakings, which

... would never repay the expence which they had really cost." Thus, Smith was concerned about both spendthrifts and inventive speculators.6

Smith (1776 [1937]) was convinced that without caps on interest rates these

prodigals and projectors would outbid "sober people." And as a result (p. 340), "a

great part of the capital of the country would..,. be ... thrown into those [hands] which were most likely to waste and destroy it." In contrast, a judicious ceiling on interest rates guaranteed the safety of lenders' money and the productive use of the

"capital of the country."

Bentham's Defence

It's not clear why Bentham undertook his Defence of Usury. The standard story is that Bentham had picked up a rumor while traveling concerning plans to lower the legal interest rate in Britain. Bentham had heard from Sir Richard Worsley (Member of Parliament and occasional diplomat, author of a book of travel observations, and plaintiff in a rather notorious adultery case against his wife Lady Seymour) that William Pitt, the prime minister, planned to lower the legal interest rate maximum from 5 to 4 percent. Worsley's information was only a rumor.7 However, Bentham made clear in a letter dated December 19, 1786, that he already had "arguments against it ready cut and dry: the former epithet you may have some doubt about; the latter you will not dispute. You know it is an old maxim of mine, that interest, as love and religion, and so many other pretty things, should be free" (Collected Works, v. X, pp. 165-168; quoted in Everett, 1931, p. 169).

In any event, Bentham's (1787a) argument started with five potential ration- ales for regulating "money bargains" (not quite in this order): 1) prevention of usury; 2) prevention of prodigality; 3) protection of indigence against extortion; 4) protection of simplicity against imposition; and 5) repression of the temerity of projectors. Let's follow Bentham through each of these.

Prevention of usury. Bentham (1787a, p. 9) argues that there is no guide to

defining usury except custom. There is no "natural fixed price." There is only custom-and customs differ. "[B]lind custom..,. has varied, from age to age, in the same country, it varies from country to country, in the same age." Custom has led to substantial variations in the legal interest rate: for example, 30 percent in

Constantinople and 5 percent in England.

6 The classic text on projects and projectors is Daniel Defoe's An Essay upon Projects (1697). 7While Pitt did not put forward such usury legislation, had he in fact done so he would have been a prime example of the frequent observation that legislators of usury laws were more often debtors than creditors. Pitt, the youngest Prime Minister in British history, died virtually bankrupt at 47.

Page 7: Retrospectives, From Usury to Interest

232 Journal of Economic Perspectives

Here Bentham (1787a) makes a key thrust. Why regulate this exchange of

lending money at interest and no other? Asserting as a given that broad systems of

price controls are generally infeasible, Bentham (p. 13) makes one of his deepest arguments: "[B]ut why a policy, which as applied to exchanges in general, would be

generally deemed absurd and mischievous, should be deemed necessary in the instance of this particular kind of exchange, mankind are as yet to learn." This

argument is often passed over in discussions of Bentham, but it must surely be the central one. For the early scholastics, the conception of just prices was a seamless whole. An extortionate price cost the customer a few coins, but it cost the seller his soul. The early scholastics believed that this was true both for goods and for money lending. Bentham in effect turned the early scholastic argument on its head. Where the scholastics looked for a justification for every price, Bentham argues that it makes little sense to look for a justification for this price of interest and this price only. We live in a material age. There is no difference between "a man who takes as much as he can get..,. for the use of a sum of money" and the man who buys "an house with it, and made a proportionable profit by the house" (p. 14). This same

argument comes up in Bentham's extended discussion in Letter IX of a comparison between fixing interest rates and fixing the prices of horses.

Prevention of prodigality. Having accepted the existence of a customary rate of interest, Bentham makes an empirical observation. Prodigals generally have prop- erty to run down, and where security exists, prodigals are likely to get the customary rate. Hence, usury laws won't stop the greater part of prodigality-even if they effectively set an interest rate near the customary level. Moreover, even if the

prodigal is kept by a usury law from borrowing against his inheritance and estates, the prodigal simply will sell or pledge to sell his property. No true prodigal is likely to be constrained in such circumstances. Prodigals are not done in by interest rates that are a few percentage points higher, but by their pattern of excessive spending and much borrowing.

Again, Bentham's argument rests on the increasing prevalence of unfettered markets in the world around him. The point here is reinforced by Bentham's discussion of purchasing on credit from trades-people, who often charged higher interest on their accounts than the money lenders. The prodigal in the marketplace has just too much opportunity to achieve his ruin. According to Bentham (and

John Stuart Mill after him), the only effective means of preventing prodigals from

dissipating their wealth would be an "interdict" that disallows the sale or pledging of property.

Protection of indigents. In the modern period, protection of the indigent has

perhaps been the most common argument for usury laws. For example, arguments for restrictions on the business practices of pawnshops and payday loans often

emphasize how such practices can be especially attractive and injurious to those with low incomes. Bentham (1787a, p. 33) emphasizes the difference between

poverty and simplicity. The poor man with "no particular defect in ... judgment, or his temper" knows as well as the rich what his interests are. In a market, the poor would be glad to take a lower rate if they could obtain it. But their willingness to pay

Page 8: Retrospectives, From Usury to Interest

Joseph Persky 233

a higher rate is evidence enough of the value of the loan to them. How is the

legislator "who knows nothing, nor can know any thing, of any one of all these

circumstances, who knows nothing at all about the matter" to justify interfering? In Bentham's view, such interference is pure folly.

Protection of simplicity. Lest anyone be unsure, by simplicity Bentham has in mind "absolute idiocy." For nothing "short of absolute idiotism, can cause the individual to make a more groundless judgment than the legislator." But in Bentham's view, the problem of simpletons in the market will involve the simple- ton's everyday buying of goods, both the prices paid and the quantities bought, not

just the problem of borrowing and interest. Again, markets surround us all. If

anything, as Bentham notes, the simpleton may have a better chance at appreciat- ing the one dimension of interest rates than the multiple dimensions of quality of

goods, which may be easier to misrepresent. Repression of the temerity of projectors. Although Smith had identified the useful-

ness of usury caps with harnessing both prodigals and overeager projectors, Bentham connects Smith especially with this latter aim. Bentham directly addresses Letter XIII, by far the longest of the volume, to Smith. In what has long been

judged a sincere tribute to Smith (for example, Everett, 1931), Bentham acknowl-

edges Smith as his intellectual teacher, claiming any persuasive argument he can make on usury must necessarily be fashioned out of the tools that Smith had constructed. Then Bentham plunges into such an argument. Far from being the

scourges of the modern economy, he argues, projectors are the very fount of "invention" and "improvement." To Bentham, invention and improvement are the core of the growth of productivity. The simple accumulation of capital in the "routine" can do only little for the standard of living. The projects of projectors, however, have allowed the "species" to advance "from that state in which acorns were their food, and raw hides their cloathing, to the state in which it stands at

present" (p. 144). Precisely because projectors deal with the "new" they should rightly face high

interest rates. In modern terms, projectors act through risky projects with little

security, and so they must pay a risk premium. The process favors success since

seeking finance generates substantial discussion of the projects. Similarly, as knowl-

edge has grown, projectors are better at weeding out unpromising projects before

seeking financing. Whatever the gains to the immediate parties, the gains to the

public are far greater. Rather than fear that the nation's savings would be wasted in the hands of mountebanks, Bentham celebrates the role of entrepreneurship and finance in driving the creative powers of the new industrial order. It makes little sense to accept all the rest-consumer sovereignty, market prices, and free trade- and reject this fundamental process of financing innovation. From Bentham's

perspective, lending to investors may well be the best of market transactions, rather than the one that should be limited or prohibited, precisely because

lending carries with it a substantial externality, that of technological advance- ment and change.

Page 9: Retrospectives, From Usury to Interest

234 Journal of Economic Perspectives

The Smith Enigma

Bentham made it very clear that he was eager to gain Smith's endorsement of his Defence. He explicitly addressed Smith in "Letter XIII" and asked for Smith to abandon support of usury legislation. The degree to which Smith concurred has been debated ever since. In his well-known biography of Smith, John Rae (1895, XXX.10) quotes a letter from Bentham's good friend George Wilson in which Wilson relates that Smith in late 1789 told a mutual friend, William Adam, that the "Defence of Usury was the work of a very superior man, and that tho' he [Bentham] had given him [Smith] some hard knocks it was done in so handsome a way that he

[Smith] could not complain, and seemed to admit that you [Bentham] were right." Rae goes on to suggest that Smith might have changed his mind.

In 1790, Bentham was apparently still optimistic that he might win Smith over. He addressed a second letter to Smith as the preface of a second edition of the

Defence. Here he refers to a bill likely to be introduced in the Irish House of Commons that would lower interest rate maximums there (Bentham, 1788-1793

[1981]). There is no known written response of Smith to Bentham's continued

urgings. Smith was to die shortly. It is known, however, that Smith sent Bentham a

copy of the new 1789 edition of the Wealth of Nations, which contained no recan- tation of his support for usury limits and a copy of the 1790 edition of the Theory of Moral Sentiments. Pagnanelli (2003) has suggested Smith was not-so-subtly hinting that Bentham would do well to read the latter volume to appreciate the argument in the former.

Throughout, Bentham identified the difference between his position and Smith's as one centered on the role of projectors in the economy. As several observers have pointed out (Crimmins, 1998), Bentham was himself very much a

projector in the sense of advocating both private-sector innovations and public- sector reforms. Even as Bentham wrote the Defence in the Belarusian outback, he and his brother, Samuel, were putting together their ambitious scheme for prison reform and industrial organization, the Panopticon. Jeremy Bentham published the resulting short volume, presented in the form of a series of letters and entitled with impressive completeness: Panopticon; or the Inspection-House: Containing the Idea

of New Principle of Construction Applicable to Any Sort of Establishment, in which Persons

of Any Description Are to be Kept Under Inspection; And in Particular to Penitentiary-Houses, Prisons, Houses of Industry, Work-Houses, Poor-Houses, Lazarettos, Manufactories, Hospi- tals, Mad-Houses and Schools: With a Plan of Management Adapted to the Principle. The

Panopticon has taken an iconic position in various critiques of the modern orga- nization. While Jeremy Bentham did suggest in his introduction that his discussion of schools was something of a humorous fancy, he and his brother meant this exercise in the design of control and monitoring as a very real project. The Benthams invested heavily and expected substantial profits from various applica- tions of the Panopticon. Their largest project sought to sell their Panopticon system to prison authorities in Britain.

Under the circumstances, it was little wonder that Bentham identified with

Page 10: Retrospectives, From Usury to Interest

Retrospectives: From Usury to Interest 235

projectors and argued that this odd breed was responsible for the great improvements in human happiness. If those attempting to be social benefactors like the Benthams could find loans at something above the legal rate, how could Smith object?

Clearly by "projectors," Smith had someone else in mind than social reformers and benefactors of humanity. Rather, as emphasized by Hollander (1999), Smith identified as projectors the various financial promoters of highly dubious projects aimed at fleecing the public of their savings. Their projects were not accidental failures, but virtually planned failures. Only by accident might they actually succeed. By prom- ising high returns they appealed to the greedy and fleeced the gullible.

Chesterton's Claim

In 1790, Adam Smith saw nothing awkward in the state's capping interest rates.

Jeremy Bentham's defense of usury held otherwise. In 1790, Smith still advocated a role for the social regulation of finance. Bentham, already a utilitarian, but not yet a radical,8 saw nothing to be gained by such interference in private contracts. What in this policy debate convinced Gilbert K. Chesterton (1933), writing more than 100 years later, that Bentham's tract marked the beginning of the modern world? The claim is put forth in Chesterton's short biography of Thomas Aquinas. Ches- terton did not offer an extended defense of his position. But it is not difficult to reconstruct his case.

Chesterton yearned for a reestablishment of the traditional communitarian ethics of Aquinas. In that system, loans were a manifestation of charity. Usury was a sin precisely because it took advantage of the needs of others. Little wonder that Chesterton bemoaned a modern world built on the principles of British liberalism. From Chesterton's vantage point, Bentham's Defence offered the clearest and least adorned early statement of those principles. Without excuses, Bentham insisted on the individual as the locus of responsibility. The spread of market relations em- powered individuals to chart their own course. The market offered opportunity to individual creativity and a harsh respect for even the poor. And no market did so more explicitly than that for borrowing and lending money.

To establish liberal modernism, the core economic sin of traditional ethics-

usury--had been transmogrified into a manifestation of the core social engine of the new age-self-interest. The sin of usurious commercial exploitation of the needs of others had been transformed into the liberal egalitarianism of the marketplace. Where Smith sensed a new world abuilding, Bentham declared its manifesto. The seamless web of personal economic justice advocated by Aquinas and Chesterton was pro- nounced unuseful and unworkable, replaced by a web of impersonal but empowering contract. Smith, never the extremist, looked to hedge the point. The young Bentham refused to let Smith (and the rest of us) have it both ways.

8 On Bentham's radicalism, see Bonner (1995) and Helevy (1955).

Page 11: Retrospectives, From Usury to Interest

236 Journal of Economic Perspectives

* I owe a debt of gratitude to James Hines and Michael Waldman for a range of useful comments. Timothy Taylor contributed a number of points as well as a general edit of the first draft. Early elements of this piece were tested on undergraduates at the University of Illinois at Chicago and Middlebury College. I am grateful for their patience.

References

Bacon, Francis. 1601 [1985]. "Of Usurie," in The Essayes or Councels, Civill and Morall. Michael Kiernan ed. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univer-

sity Press, pp. 124-29. Bentham, Jeremy. 1787a [1818]. Defence of

Usury, Fourth Edition. London: Payne and Foss; Available at Online Library of Liberty, (http://

oll.libertyfund.org/ToC/0167.php). Bentham, Jeremy. 1787b [1995]. Panopticon Let-

ters. Reprinted, Miran Bozovic, ed. London: Verso. Bentham, Jeremy. 1788-1793 [1981]. Corre-

spondence of Jeremy Bentham, Volume 4. Alexander Milne, ed. London: Athlone Press.

Bentham,Jeremy. 1838-1843 [1962]. Collected Works ofJeremy Bentham. John Bowring, ed. New York: Russell & Russell.

Bonner, John. 1995. Economic Efficiency and So- cial Justice: The Development of Utilitarian Ideas in Economics from Bentham to Edgeworth. Aldershot, UK Edward Elgar.

Chesterton, Gilbert K. 1933. St. Thomas Aqui- nas. New York: Sheed & Ward, Inc.

Christie, Ian. 1993. The Benthams in Russia: 1780-1791. Oxford: Berg Publishers.

Crimmins, James. 1998. "Political Economy and Projectors: Bentham's Defence of Usury." Conference paper, St. Petersburg Center for the History of Ideas; Available at (http://ideashistory. org.ru/almanacs/alm09/07Crimmins.htm).

Defoe, Daniel. 1697. An Essay upon Projects. Project Guttenberg; Available at (http://www. gutenberg. org/etext/4087).

Everett, Charles. 1931. The Education ofJeremy Bentham. New York: Columbia University Press.

Friedman, Milton. 1976. "Adam Smith's Relevance for 1976" Selected Papers No. 50, Graduate School of Business, University of Chi-

cago; Available at (http://gsb.uchicago.edu/ research/selectedpapers/sp50b.pdf).

Glaeser, Edward L. and Jose Scheinkman.

1998. "Neither a Borrower nor a Lender Be: An Economic Analysis of Interest Restrictions and Usury Laws." Journal of Law & Economics. 41:1, pp. 1-36.

Halevy, Elie. 1955. The Growth of Philosophical Radicalism. Boston: Beacon Press

Hollander, Samuel. 1999. "Jeremy Bentham and Adam Smith on the Usury Laws: A 'Smith- ian' Reply to Bentham and a New Problem." European Journal of History of Economic Thought. 6:4, pp. 523-51.

Kelly, Paul. 2000. "Bentham and Smith on Projectors: The Moral Psychology of Economic Liberalism." Political Studies Association-UK 50th Annual Conference; Available at (http:// www.psa.ac.uk/cps/2000/Kelly%20Paull.pdf).

Keynes, John Maynard. 1936. The General The- ory of Employment, Interest, and Money. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc.

Locke, John. 1691. Some Considerations of the Con- sequences of the Lowering of Interest, and Raising the Value of Money. London: Awnsham and John Churchill, at the Black Swan in Pater-Noster-Row.

Noonan, John. 1957. The Scholastic Analysis of Usury. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Paganelli, Maria. 2003. "ln Medio Stat Virtus: An Alternative View of Usury in Adam Smith's Think-

ing." History of Political Economy. 35:1, pp. 21-48. Rae, John. 1895. Life of Adam Smith. London:

Macmillan and Co.

Smith, Adam. 1776 [1937]. The Wealth of Na- tions. Reprint, Edwin Cannan, ed. New York: Modern Library.

Stegman, Michael and Robert Faris. 2003. "Payday Lending: A Business Model that Encour-

ages Chronic Borrowing." Economic Development Quarterly. 17:1, pp. 8-32.

Wilson, Thomas. 1572 [1925]. A Discourse

Upon Usury. Reprint, R.H. Tawney, ed. London: G. Bell and Sons, Ltd.