Principles of mental physiology

3

Click here to load reader

description

Carpenter

Transcript of Principles of mental physiology

  • Classics in Psychology

    Robert H. Wozniak - Bryn Mawr College

    William Benjamin Carpenter: Principles of Mental Physiology (1874)

    Scientific psychology has historical roots in both mental philosophy and physiology. When it first appeared, itwas even commonly referred to as the new physiological psychology. While this undoubtedly reflected theinfluence of Wilhelm Wundts great compendium of the new science, the Grundzge der physi-ologischenPsychologie; 95 Wundt was by no means the first to talk in terms of a physiological psychology. 96 Nor washe the first to focus on the border between physiological and philosophical analysis or to eschew (or inWundts case postpone) purely metaphysical for empirical analysis and observation.

    In England, in the period between 1850 and 1875, a small group of physicians developed what was, in effect,a school of physiological psychology built around just these principles. 97 The primary assumptions of thegroup were that biology and medicine, not metaphysics, would provide the necessary foundation forpsychology, that mind must be understood in its relationship to nervous function, and that mind and body existin mutual inter-action. At the same time, however, there was also recognition that mind and body are notidentical and that mind plays an active, determining role in human affairs.

    The intellectual leader of this group was a physician/physiologist by the name of William B. Carpenter. 98 In1852, Carpenter incorporated a large section on physiological psychology into the fourth edition of what was,at the time, the leading English language text on human physiology. 99 Rewritten, expanded, and published in1874 as a separate volume entitled Principles of Mental Physiology, 100 Carpenters work provided thedefinitive statement of the mid-19th century British physiological psychology point of view. It was also thefirst English language text of its type to employ systematic discussion of abnormal mental phenomena in theservice of furthering an understanding of the nature of the mind and its relationship to physiologicalmechanism. 101

    The basic premise of Carpenters analysis was that the mind is composite in nature, consisting of both unconscious cerebration and conscious process. By unconscious cerebration, Carpenter meant theautomatic, reflex activity of the cerebrum that yields properly intellectual results (e.g., reasoning processes oreven the exercise of the imagination) without the processes themselves being accessible to consciousness.Although Carpenter was anticipated in this doctrine by Laycock among others, 102 it was through his clear andforceful articulation of this view in the Principles of Mental Physiology 103 and his use of the term unconsciouscerebration to physiologize the concept that the doctrine became widely accepted.

    Recognition of the composite nature of mind led Carpenter to two other highly characteristic views, one havingto do with the nature of the causal determination of mental process, the other with the nature of themind/body relation. With regard to mental causality, Carpenter argued that in terms of its unconscious,automatic, reflex activity, mind was clearly determined by physical circumstance. In its conscious activity,however, it was influenced by the intervention of an active mental force of Will. Although he recognized theinherent contradiction between these points of view, he was unable to abandon either. As he put it: It will, Idoubt not, be considered by many, that there is a palpable inconsistency between the two fundamentaldoctrines which are here upheld;that of the dependence of the Automatic activity of the Mind uponconditions that bring it within the nexus of Physical Causation; and that of the existence of an independentPower, controlling and directing that activity, which we call Will. I can only say that both are equally true to myown consciousness. 104

    This same adherence to common sense observation at the expense of logical coherence also characterizedCarpenters discussion of the relationship between mind and body. In common with others in his group, heheld a strict mind/body inter-actionism. Indeed, his discussion of interactionism is possibly the clearest andmost unambiguous in all of the 19th century mind/body literature.

    Nothing, Carpenter wrote, can be more certain, than that the primary form of mental activity, Sensationalconsciousness, is excited through physiological instrumentality. A certain Physical impression is made, forexample, by the formation of a luminous image upon the Retina of the EyeLight excites Nerve-force, andthe transmission of this Nerve-force excites the activity of that part of the Brain which is the instrument of our

  • Visual Consciousness. Now in what way the physical change thus excited in the Sensorium is translated (soto speak) into that psychical change which we call seeing the object whose image was formed upon ourRetina, we know nothing whatever; but we are equally ignorant of the way in which Light produces ChemicalchangeAnd all we can say is, that there is just as close a succession of sequencesas intimate a causalrelation between antecedent and consequentin the one case, as there is in the other. 105

    Conversely, the like Correlation may be shown to exist between Mental states and the form of Nerve-forcewhich calls forth Motion through the Muscular apparatuseach kind of Mental activity, Sensational,Instinctive, Emotional, Ideational, and Volitional, may express itself in Bodily movementJust as a perfectlyconstructed Galvanic battery is inactive while the circuit is interrupted, but becomes active the instant that thecircuit is closed, so does a Sensation, an Instinctive tendency, an Emotion, an Idea, or a Volition, whichattains an intensity adequate to close the circuit, liberate the Nerve-force with which a certain part of theBrainis always charged. 106

    Thoroughgoing interactionism of this sort, coupled with the notion of unconscious cerebration and a belief inunconscious psychic determinism led Carpenter to emphasize the relevance of abnormal mental states to hisanalysis of mind. Thus most of the second half of the Principles of Mental Physiology was devoted to topicssuch as reverie and abstraction, sleep, dreaming, and somnambulism, mesmerism and spiritualism,intoxication and delerium, and insanity, with each analyzed in terms of the relationship between unconsciouscerebration and conscious mental process. Through this discussion, as well as through his emphasis onunconscious process, Carpenter helped legitimize the study of exceptional mental states within generalpsychology.

    95 Wundt, W. (1874). Grundzge der physiologischen Psychologie. Leipzig: Wilhelm Engelmann; for adiscussion of the content and significance of Wundts work, see the essay on Wundts Grundzge in thisvolume.

    96 Although there may have been still earlier uses of this term, the earliest that I have been able to identify isthat of Chardel. C. (1831). Essai de psychologie physiologique. Paris: Au Bureau de lEncyclopdie Portative.

    97 Included in this group were Benjamin Collins Brodie (17831862), William Benjamin Carpenter (181385),Robert Dunn (17991877), Henry Holland (17881873), Thomas Laycock (181276), John Daniel Morell(181691), and Daniel Noble (181085).

    98 181385. For biographical information on Carpenter, see Carpenter, J.E. (1888). Memorial sketch. In W.B.Carpenter. Nature and Man. Essays Scientific and Philosophical. London: Kegan Paul, Trench.

    99 Carpenter, W.B. (1852). Principles of Human Physiology (4th edition). London: Churchill.

    100 Carpenter, W.B. (1874). Principles of Mental Physiology, with Their Applications to the Training andDiscipline of the Mind, and the Study of its Morbid Conditions. London: Henry S. King.

    101 Taine had done much the same thing in French, see essay on Taine in this volume; Maudsley had alsoargued for the relevance of psychopathological phenomena to general psychology but had yet to treat thesephenomena systematically in this regard, see essay on Maudsley in this volume.

    102 Laycock, T. (1860). Mind and Brain; Or, The Correlations of Consciousness and Organisation; with TheirApplications to Philosophy, Zoology, Physiology, Mental Pathology, and the Practice of Medicine. Edinburgh:Sutherland and Knox.

    103 Carpenter (1874), op. cit., Chapter 13, pp. 51543.

    104 Ibid., pp. ixx.

    105 Ibid., pp. 1213.

    106 Ibid., pp. 1314.

    Extracted from Classics in Psychology, 18551914: Historical Essays ISBN 1 85506 703 X Robert H. Wozniak, 1999

    Classics in Psychology, 18551914 Historical Essays - Contents