Pragmatics ELT J 1994 Peter Tan 100

1
7/21/2019 Pragmatics ELT J 1994 Peter Tan 100 http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/pragmatics-elt-j-1994-peter-tan-100 1/1  ey concepts in  LT Pragmatics The philosopher Charles Morris  saw  pragmatics  as part  of  the science  of  signs  or  semiotics. Semiotics could  be  divided  up  into three branches  of  enquiry: syntactics  (or syntax), which is the study of the formal relations  of  signs to one another ;  semantics,  the study of the relations  of  signs  to  the objects  to  which  the signs are applicable ; and  pragmatics,  the study of the relations of signs to interpreters . (Levinson 1983:1). It has since then been common  to  divide  the  study  of language into for levels: phonology, syntax, semantics, and pragmatics. Phonology, syntax, and semantics are often seen as the three components of grammar, which investigates language  without specific reference  to context  or  to interpreters. Pragmatics would therefore be distinguished from the other levels as the branch of linguistics that investigates  the  rules  and  principles that govern language  in use in its  various contexts (situational, sociological, ideological, etc.).  By  defi- nition, therefore, pragmatics  is  inter-disciplinary  in nature. Basic  to all  pragmatic research  is  speech-act theory, first developed  by  Austin  and  Searle,  and  Grice s theory of implicature. Speech-act theory sees language use not merely  as  saying,  but  also  as  doing.  If  using language  is  doing something, there must be  a  doer,  S, and also someone, H, to whom or for whom the action  speech act)  is  done. Which speech  act is  being per- formed  is  determined not only  by  the form  of  words used,  but  also who  S and H are and how  they  are related,  and the  physical context.  An  utterance like  Can you play the piano? is more likely to be interpre- ted as a request  if  H is  obviously  able to do so, and S  is in  a  position  to  ask H to, and  if  there  is a  piano  in  the vicinity.  If  these conditions  do not  apply (e.g.  H has just recovered from  a  stroke,  or is  the parent  of  S,  or there  is  no piano  in  the vicinity), the utterance would more likely be interpreted as  a  question. Whereas speech-art theory focuses  on  rules for the appropriate performance  of  particular speech acts, Grice s theory  of  implicature focuses  on  principles that inform  the  problem-solving task  of  determining the particular speech act being performed. An implica- ture is distinguished from what is said (what is in the sentence,  as it  were). Based  on  Grice s theory, there- fore, the earlier utterance Can you play the piano? can be discounted as a (mere) question  if  H obviously has the ability to play the piano, because such an inter- pretation would be in breach of the maxim of Quantity, one of the mixtures  of  the  Co-operative Principle,  i.e. too much has been said. The Co-operative Principle ( make your contribution such as  is  required,  at  the stage  at  which  it  occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the talk exchange in which you are engaged ) is the one generally used to reach the implicatures of utterances, and can be broken down into four broad categories  of  maxims:  Quality (speak  the  truth,  and  what  you  have evidence  for), Quantity  (say neither too much nor too little),  Manner (avoid verbosity, obscurity, etc.),  and  Relation (talk relevantly). More recent developments have concentrated on nar- rowing or expanding the Co-operative Principle. Sper- ber  and  Wilson (1986),  for  instance, propose  the principle  of  relevance, and suggest that all the earlier maxims can be subsumed under this principle. Others like Leech (1983) propose more principles, such as the Politeness Principle,  the  Irony Principle,  and the  Ban- ter Principle.  Formulations like I m  a  terrible cook may be taken not seriously  in  spite  of  the maxim  of quality) because of the dictates of the Modesty Maxim, one  of  the maxims  of  the Politeness Principle. Brown and Levinson (1987) provide an alternative treatment of politeness in terms of S s and H s face requirements. Received August 1993  urther reading Brown P.  and  S Levinson. 1987.  Politeness: Some Universals  in  Language Usage.  Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Leech G N 1983. Principles  o Pragmatics. London: Longman. Levinson S 1983. Pragmatics.  Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sperber D and  D Wilson. 1986.  Relevance: Communication Blackwell. and Cognition.  Oxford: Dr Peter Tan, Department of English Language and Literature, National University of Singapore 10 0 ELT Journal Volume 48/1 January 1994© Oxford University Press 1994   a  t  v  e  p  o  o  U n  v  e  s  t  y  b  a  y  o n  N  o  v  e m  b  e  3  ,  0  5  t  t  p  :  /  /  e  t  j  .  o x  o  d  j  o  u n  a  s  .  o  g  / D  o  w n  o  a  d  e  d  o m  

description

Pragmatics Peter Tan

Transcript of Pragmatics ELT J 1994 Peter Tan 100

Page 1: Pragmatics ELT J 1994 Peter Tan 100

7/21/2019 Pragmatics ELT J 1994 Peter Tan 100

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/pragmatics-elt-j-1994-peter-tan-100 1/1

  ey concepts in  LT

Pragmatics

The philosopher Charles Morris

  saw

 pragmatics

 as

part

  of

  the science

 of

  signs

 or

  sem iotics. S emiotics

could  be divided  up into three branch es of  enquiry:

syntactics  (or syntax), which is the study of the formal

relations

 of

 s igns to one another ;   semantics,  the study

of the relations

 of

  signs

 to

  the objects

  to

 which

 the

signs are app licable ; and pragm atics,  the study of the

relations of signs to interpreters . (Levinson 1983:1). It

has since then been common

  to

 divide

  the

 study

 of

language into for levels: phonology, syntax, semantics,

and pragmatics. Phonology, syntax, and semantics are

often seen as the three components of grammar, which

investigates language  without specific reference  to

context

 or

  to interpreters. Pragmatics would therefore

be distinguished from the other levels as the branch of

linguistics that investigates  the rules  and principles

that govern language

  in use in its

  various contexts

(situational, sociological, ideological, etc.).

 By

 defi-

nition, therefore, pragmatics

  is

  inter-disciplinary

  in

nature.

Basic

  to all

 pragm atic rese arch

  is

  speech-act theory,

first developed

  by

  Austin

  and

 Searle,

  and

  Grice s

theory of implicature. Speech-act theory sees language

use not merely

 as

 saying,

 but

 also

 as

 doing.

  If

 using

language

 is

 doing something , there must be

 a

 doer,

 S,

and also someone, H, to whom or for whom the action

  speech act)

  is

 done. W hich speech

 act is

  being per-

formed

  is

 determined not only

 by

  the form

 of

 words

used,  but also who  S and H are and how  they are

related,

  and the

 physical contex t.

  An

 utterance like

 Ca n you play the pian o? is mo re likely to be interpre-

ted as a request if H is  obviously  able to do so, and S is

in

 a

 position

 to

 ask H to, and

 if

 there

 is a

 piano

 in

 the

vicinity.

 If

  these conditions

 do not

 apply (e.g.

 H has

just recovered from

  a

 s troke,

 or is

 the parent

 of

 S ,

 or

there

 is

 no piano

 in

 the vicinity), the utteranc e would

more likely be interpreted as

 a

 question.

Whereas speech-art theory focuses

  on

  rules

  for the

appropriate performance  of  particular spe ech a cts,

Gric e s theory

  of

  implicature focuses

  on

  principles

that inform

  the

 problem -solving task

 of

  determining

the particular speech act being performed. An implica-

ture is distingu ished from w hat is sa id (what is in the

sentence,

 as it

 were). Based

 on

 Gric e s theory, there-

fore, the earlier utterance Ca n you play the piano ?

can be discounted as a (mere) question

 if

 H obviously

has the ability to play the piano, because such an inter-

pretation wou ld be in breach of the maxim of Qu antity,

one of the mixtures

 of

 the  Co-op erative Principle,  i.e.

too much has been said.

The C o-operative Principle ( ma ke your contribution

such as

 is

 required,

 at

 the stage

 at

 which

 it

 occurs, by

the accepted purpose or direction of the talk exchange

in which you are enga ge d ) is the one generally used to

reach the implicatures of utterances, and can be broken

down into four broad categories

 of

 maxims:   Quality

(speak

  the

 truth,

  and

 what

  you

 have evidence

 for),

Quantity   (say neither too much nor too little),   Manner

(avoid verbosity, obscurity, etc.),

 and

 Relation  (talk

relevantly).

More recent developments have concentrated on nar-

rowing or expanding the Co-operative Principle. Sper-

ber

  and

  Wilson (1986),

  for

  instance, propose

 the

principle

 of

 relevan ce, and suggest that all the earlier

maxims can be subsumed under this principle. Others

like Leech (1983) propose more principles, such as the

Politeness Principle,  th e   Irony Principle,  and the  Ban-

ter Principle.  Formu lations like I m  a  terrible cook

may be taken not seriously

  in

 spite

 of

 the m axim

 of

quality) because of the dictates of the Modesty M axim ,

one

 of

 the maxim s

 of

 the Politeness P rinciple. B rown

and Levinson (1987) provide an alternative treatment

of politeness in terms of S s and H s face requirem ents.

Received August 1993

  urther reading

Brown P.

 an d  S

Levinson.

  1987.  Politeness: Some

Universals  in  Language Usage.  Cambridge:

Cambridge Universi ty Press .

Leech

G N

1983.

 Principles

  o

Pragmatics.

London: Longman.

Levinson S

1983.

  Pragmatics.  Cambr idge :

Cambridge University Press.

Sperber D

and

  D Wilson.

  1986.

  Relevance:

Communication

Blackwell .

and Cognition.  Oxford:

Dr Peter Tan, Department of English Language and

Literature, National University of Singapore

10 0

ELT Journal Volume 48/1 January 1994© Oxford Un iversity Press 1994

  a  t  L i   v e r  p o ol   Uni   v e r  s i   t   yL i   b r  a r  y on N o v e m b  e r  3  ,2  0 1  5 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   e l   t   j   . oxf   or  d  j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om