politics after aesthetics

download politics after aesthetics

of 14

Transcript of politics after aesthetics

  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    1/14

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    This article was downloaded by: [Macquarie University]On: 10 July 2009Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 907465010]Publisher RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House,37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713695220

    David Ferris

    Online Publication Date: 01 August 2009

    Ferris, David(2009)'Politics after Aesthetics: Disagreeing with Rancire',Parallax,15:3,37 49

    10.1080/13534640902982587

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13534640902982587

    Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf

    This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial orsystematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply ordistribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.

    The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contentswill be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug dosesshould be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss,actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directlyor indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.

    http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713695220http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13534640902982587http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdfhttp://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdfhttp://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13534640902982587http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713695220
  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    2/14

    Politics after Aesthetics: Disagreeing with Ranciere

    David Ferris

    More than anyone else in the late twentieth century, Jacques Rancie` re has

    undertaken a redefinition of the relation of the aesthetic to politics. This redefinition

    occurs against the long history through which politics has turned to the aesthetic as

    either a support or an ideological antagonism, a history that has condemned theaesthetic to a representative role whether in the positive sense intended by Schiller

    in his Aesthetic Education or in the negative sense so crucial to how the aesthetic has

    social and political meaning in Adornos Aesthetic Theory.1 Rather than reassert such

    a role one more time, Rancie` re undertakes a redefinition of the aesthetic that not

    only challenges the representational categories into which it has been placed but

    also redefines the aesthetic in terms of political existence. This does not mean that

    politics is conflated with the aesthetic, as if one could be simply identified as the

    other. Such identification disregards the specificity of the aesthetic and also the

    specificity of politics. The question Rancie` re confronts is then how to think their

    relation without recourse to the history that has overdetermined the relation of

    politics and aesthetics.

    In a remark from his Politics of Literature, Rancie` re insists on a specific link

    between the aesthetic and politics: politics of literature means that literature

    does politics as literature that there is a specific link between politics as a definite

    way of doing and literature as a definite practice of writing.2 There is no ambiguity

    here and certainly not the kind that allows for the easy substitution of politics and

    literature so present in contemporary critical discourse. Ranciere is clear: politics is a

    definite way of doing and literature is a definite practice of writing. Although this

    remark distinguishes politics and writing as belonging to different spheres, Rancie` re

    will still speak of a specific link through which literature becomes known in terms of

    politics. Yet, if this link is to avoid rehearsing yet again the history that not only gives

    us politics andaesthetics but gives them to us within a way of thinking that remains

    steadfastly representational, what other link can be specified? In short, how can

    politics andaesthetics still be thought without recourse to the authenticity implied byany mode of representation, whether positive or negative? Another way of posing

    this question is to ask whether the pairing of politics and aesthetics can be thought

    otherwise in an age when politics still continues to determine what is significant and

    what is not?

    parallax

    ISSN 1353-4645 print/ISSN 1460-700X online q 2009 Taylor & Francishttp://www.tandf.co.uk/journals

    DOI: 10.1080/13534640902982587

    parallax, 2009, vol. 15, no. 3, 3749

    parallax

    37

  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    3/14

    In the passage just cited from Politics of Literature, Rancie` re already gives an

    indication of how he will think a specific link between politics and literature as well

    as the difficulty of doing so. Before even defining politics as doing, Rancie` re refers

    to literature as something that does politics. The placing of does within quotation

    marks is a curious act especially in a context that would avoid the representational

    history in which literature and the aesthetic were tied to the political: to quote is to

    re-present. But, do these quotes simply mean that literature is an imitation of the

    doing that characterizes politics? A weak form of politics? But, if not an imitation or

    a weak form of politics, why must literature be placed within quotes? Why must

    literature be quoted as literature when the articulation of its political significance is

    at stake?

    As if to counter this quotational recourse, Rancie` re, in subsequent remarks from this

    same essay, offers a definition of literature as such, a literature that presumably

    should not and cannot be put within quotation marks. Here, literature as suchpromises the specificity of literature, that is, what makes literature literature rather

    than something else. As Rancie` re provides this definition, the notion of a specific

    link is again evoked although in this context it is no longer explicitly given as a link

    between writing and the visibility of things:

    Literature as such: literature conceived neither as the art of writing in

    general nor as a specific state of the language, but as a historical mode

    of visibility of writing, a specific link between a system of meaning of

    words and a system of visibility of things.3

    Rancie` re presents literature as a system separated from another system, a

    separation embodied by the respective modes of existence of these two systems: the

    meaning of words and the visibility of things. Yet, what Rancie` re refers to when herefers to the meaning of words is also a visibility. Thus, literature, by bringing words

    to visibility, enters into a link with what Rancie` re calls the visibility of things while

    being differentiated according to the object that it makes visible. On the basis of this

    link, Rancie` re goes on to define the visibility of literature (literature as such) as a

    way of linking meaning and action, of framing the relation between the sayable

    and the visible, of enabling words with the power of framing a common world.4

    Such a literature, in effect, attains what politics has always as its goal whenever its

    purpose is under question, namely, linking meaning and action. However, in this

    instance, what is at stake is not the well-worn cliche of theory and praxis that

    increasingly hovers behind political discourse since Marx, but rather a doing that

    occurs through literature as it makes visible the system of meaning. In other words,

    it is not a question of meaning being represented by an action, and vice versa.

    Instead, meaning is understood to be action, something that does, and in thatdoing, it attains visibility. With this visibility, literature as such occurs for

    Rancie` re. At the same time, this occurrence is justified to the extent that a link takes

    place in some way. Without such a link, literature as such would remain

    insignificant, it would have no intervention in what Rancie` re refers to as the

    distribution of sensible, to a distribution that organizes and structures what can be

    apprehended by the senses, in other words, the apprehension of the visible. It is thus

    on the specificity of this link that everything depends and above all else the

    Ferris

    38

  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    4/14

    recovery of a significance for an aesthetic that challenges the historical and critical

    ease with which the aesthetic is confined to the ideological on the one hand, and, on

    the other, to a political philosophy that is no more than an account of politics as a

    form of representation, in short, such political philosophy would be no more than an

    aesthetics without ideology.

    For Rancie` re, the political significance of the aesthetic is tied crucially to this non-

    representational link between two systems of visibility. As such, the link itself, if it is

    to remain non-representational, poses the question of what form of existence this

    link can take when representation is no longer available to it. Here, Adornos

    development of a negative dialectics is interpretable as a symptomatic response to

    such a question. The negation of negation demanded by Adornos dialectical

    account of the aesthetic, that is, his embrace of a politics of aesthetics through the

    denial of negation as the representation of what it is different from (to cite the

    famous example of Koje` ve after Hegel, the master already represents the slave),finally remains unproductive with respect to the tradition it would transform. To

    put this another way, the Frankfurt School could only arrest the dialectical

    foundation of its own thought. As such, it pushed the realm of representational

    politics to a negative extreme but could not break with that realm without

    sacrificing the significance of its desired social critique and the politics that such a

    desire assumes. Rancie` re, through what he calls the distribution of the sensible,

    undertakes another thinking of the relation of politics and aesthetics, one that would

    no longer submit itself to such a radical negation of representation but which seeks to

    position such a relation without characterizing it in either positive or negative terms.

    In a series of interviews first published under the title Le partage du sensible: esthe tique et

    politique, Rancie` re offers the following condensed definition of what he means by the

    distribution of the sensible:

    I call the distribution of the sensible the system of self-evident facts

    of sense perception that simultaneously discloses the existence of

    something in common and the delimitations that define the respective

    parts and positions within it. A distribution of the sensible therefore

    establishes at one and the same time something common that is

    shared and exclusive parts.5

    This double determination of commonality and exclusivity structures a community

    so that everything that possesses visibility is assigned a part. Rancie` re then defines

    this visibility in relation to politics in the following terms: politics bears upon ( porte

    sur) what is seen and what can be said about it, around who has the ability to see and

    the talent to speak, around the properties of spaces and the possibilities of time.6

    Here, the realm of language and the realm of the visibility of things (to which

    literature as such possesses a specific link) make up, not what politics is, but what

    politics bears upon. This distinction made here introduces two senses of politics,

    one that speaks of politics as social organization, and one that goes to the core

    of Rancie` res understanding of how politics exists in its actuality. The first, in

    Rancie` res terminology is not an authentic politics but rather the way in which

    roles are assigned to only those parts of a community that possess visibility.

    parallax

    39

  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    5/14

    This configuration results from the activity of what Rancie` re calls the police.7

    What the police produces is a community configured according to a consensus about

    the roles played by each of the parts they define within that community. In contrast,

    Rancie` re gives the name politics to the way in which this distribution can be

    reconfigured by a part that remains invisiblewhich he refers to as the part of those

    who have no part. This understanding of politics places a group within a

    community in such a way that only those parts given visibility can participate in the

    consensus such a community is built upon. But, because a group has no part, its

    claim to have a role, that is, to become visible, challenges the grounds on which the

    distribution of the sensible has taken place in the hands of the police, namely,

    inequality. Making this claim is the beginning of politics.

    Rancie` re describes the effect of this claim as follows:

    Political activity is always a mode of expression that undoes theperceptible divisions of the police order by putting into act a

    presupposition which is in principle heterogeneous to the police, that

    of the part of those without a part, which manifests itself, in the end,

    as the pure contingency of that order, the equality of any speaking

    being with any other speaking being.8

    Equality, so often taken as if its determining characteristic were similarity, functions

    here as the mark of a heterogeneity that arises as soon as those who have no part

    contest their invisibility by speaking. This contesting, Rancie` re continues, is the

    occasion of politics but a politics that only becomes real once two heterogeneous

    processes meet. The first process is the distribution of the sensible performed by the

    police; the second is the process of equality initiated by those who have no visibility

    in the former distribution. Here, the assertion of equality should not be confusedwith politics; politics only occurs in the antagonism between this assertion and how

    the sensible has been distributed by the police. As a result, equality cannot be

    recognized as the object or issue of politics, nor can it, as a principle, be restricted to

    politics. All equality does is to

    give politics reality in the form of specific cases [ . . . ] what makes an

    action political is not its object or the place where it is carried out, but

    solely its form, the form in which the confirmation of equality is

    inscribed in the setting up of a dispute, of a community existing solely

    through being divided.9

    The specificity of the act that defines Rancie` res understanding of politics removes

    theory as well as any other general principle from a role in determining politics asthe appearance of one meaning or another. Already here, the tendency to appeal to

    politics as a source of meaning for either the aesthetic or for the activity of criticism is

    unsustainable since such a tendency demands that there is something political in

    itself that can be referred to and used as a measure for judgment. If even the

    principle through which politics is expressed cannot belong to politics then what

    Rancie` re has given as politics is also something that has built into the impossibility of

    agreement. In this case, Rancie` res sense of politics can only be based on, as he

    Ferris

    40

  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    6/14

    admits, the recognition of presuppositions that ought to be discerned in the

    practices that put them to work.10 Presuppositions, as enabling principles, are not in

    themselves political until they have been put to work. It is this notion of work that is

    crucial to Rancie` re and, here, work is another name for configuration. From this

    work, there arises the sense of politics as a definite way of doing referred to in the

    passage from Politics and Literature cited at the beginning of this article. When the

    specificity of this way of doing takes place in an act of speaking or making visible that

    is carried out by those who have been given no part in the distribution of the

    sensible, this act is irresolvable precisely because, within the community or place

    where it occurs, there is contention over what the act of speaking means to the

    parties involved in it. This contention centers on the irreconcilable difference

    between those who think that all speaking beings are equal and those who do not. By

    speaking, those who belong to the part that has no part understand the former, and

    by speaking those who have a part understand the latter.

    The irresolvable disagreement that lies at core of Rancie` res understanding of

    politics is what his understanding of the aesthetic and also the literary must in some

    way be linked to. Remarks in Disagreement already point to this link as something

    that defines the literary in a fundamentally political way. Rancie` re writes:

    The modern political animal is first a literary animal, caught in the

    circuit of a literariness that undoes the relationships between the

    order of words and the order of bodies that determine the place of

    each.11

    Here, the literary is understood as a disordering of those relationships between words

    and bodies through which the order instituted by the police functions. Rancie` re

    defines this disordering by the literary in the following sentence: It inscribes asubject name as being different from any identified part of the community. 12 Where

    the literary possesses a politics it is in the difference between a name and what has

    been identified as the parts that can be given names. This understanding is very

    much in line with Rancie` res account of politics as disagreement. In fact, politics and

    the literary are so much in line with the one other that the question of a link between

    them seems superfluous. Are they not in fact so much in agreement with one another

    that the aesthetic can only, yet again, be a form of politics? If so, to what extent has

    Rancie` res understanding of politics done no more than find another albeit much

    more resourceful and far reaching answer to the question of what the aesthetic is

    even as he refuses the place of such a question with respect to politics? Another way

    of framing these questions is to ask why Ranciere is still compelled to decide the

    significance of the aesthetic in political terms.

    The aesthetic has always posed a problem with respect to determining its

    significance if not just its function, a problem recognized from the very beginning of

    political discourse in Platos Republic and also in the history through which literature

    is continually re-determined as one form of representation or another. The word

    aesthetic also bears the imprint of this problematic. In the transformation of the

    aesthetic from the name that identifies sense perception (that is, the sensible) in the

    eighteenth century to its emergence as the category naming the form in which art

    parallax

    41

  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    7/14

    appears, the sensible recedes as the visible gives way to an invisible yet still

    representable meaning. Rancie` res account of politics clearly distinguishes itself

    from the representational mode that the aesthetic took on with this transformation.

    In fact, if Rancie` res account of politics is placed within this history of the aesthetic,

    it would mark a recovery of the aesthetic as the realm of the sensible rather than the

    limited and imprecise appearance of the idea, as in Kant, or of the spirit, as in Hegel.

    The difference indicated by this positioning of Rancie` re is that the aesthetic possesses

    a visible specificity in the form of sensibility in the earliest stage of its history.

    Although Rancie` re will not rest his account of politics on the historical specificity of

    the aesthetic as a mode of visible apprehension, his remarks in Politics and

    Literature already insist on such specificity as the means through which the

    aesthetic retains its proper significance.

    In Disagreement, this significance appears as the autonomization of the aesthetic. This

    means two things for Rancie` re. First, the specificity achieved through autonomiza-tion is a freeing up [of the aesthetic] in relation to the norms of representation

    thereby effectively ending their reign as decisive where the aesthetic is concerned.

    Second, this autonomization provides

    the constitution of a kind of community of sense experience that works

    on the world of presumption, of the as ifthat includes those who are

    not included by revealing a mode of existence of sense experience that

    has eluded the allocation of parties and lots.13

    In its specificity, its autonomy, and in its freeing from the norms of representation,

    the aesthetic constitutes the possibility of an as if, of a category that is at once

    sensible but at the same time has no part within the distribution of meaning that

    belongs to the norms of representation that decide what is aesthetically meaningfuland what is not. The as if returns representation to the appearance it already is. It

    is this return to appearance that forms the basis of Rancie` res account of aesthetics in

    terms of politics. But, for Rancie` re, this does not mean that politics is merely

    appearance. Rancie` re is firm on this point: there has therefore not been any

    aestheticization of politics in the modern age because politics is aesthetic in

    principle.14 Still, to claim that politics is aesthetic in principle is to claim, first, that

    there is a principle to which politics submits and, second, without the aesthetic there

    can be no politics in the sense that Rancie` re develops this word.

    The first of these claims appears to counter Rancie` res earlier remark that the sole

    principle of politics is equality.15 While this earlier statement does not make politics

    the same as equality (equality is not peculiar to [politics] and is in no way in itself

    political), the subsequent insistence that politics is aesthetic in principle raises aquestion about Rancie` res account of how disagreement is fundamental to the

    political make-up of a community. In particular, it raises a question about the

    insertion of the aesthetic into an account of politics that has placed principles outside

    the specific operation of politics. Rancie` re not only states this emphatically, but does

    so by insisting that nothing is political in itself for the political only exists by a

    principle that is not proper to it, equality.16 For politics to come into existence

    through the impropriety of a principle is to assert, at the very least, that politics

    Ferris

    42

  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    8/14

    attains meaningfulness by means of what it is not. Can such an assertion, at this

    point of Rancie` res account of politics, be reconciled with the claim that politics is

    aesthetics in principle? If not, why is such a claim even made? Or, why does it need

    to be made?

    In a later work, Malaise dans lesthetique (2004), Rancie` re again rejects the

    aestheticization of politics that held such sway over Benjamins account of art and

    politics. Here, the stake is again the relation of politics and aesthetics:

    Politics consists in reconfiguring the distribution of the sensible that

    defines the commonality of a community, in introducing subjects and

    objects, in rendering visible those who were not, and in making

    understood speakers who had only been perceived as noisy animals.

    This work of creating dissensus constitutes an aesthetic of politics that

    has nothing to do with the forms of establishing power and themobilization of the masses that Benjamin called the aestheticization

    of politics.17

    Rancie` res reference to Benjamin refuses the separateness of aesthetics and politics

    by refusing the possibility that politics can be aestheticized a position that

    presupposes that politics is an object that can be submitted to such an act. Yet, when

    Rancie` re grants politics the ability to create dissensus it occurs when politics is

    understood in terms of the aesthetic. While the creation of this dissensus is

    distinguished from the aestheticization of politics that Benjamin associates with

    fascism, it is not completely unrelated to what Benjamin had called the politicization

    of the aesthetic.18 Benjamins politicized aesthetic also sought to produce a dissensus

    that would resist the aesthetic appropriation of politics but this dissensus was not

    developed to the extensive scale Rancie` re pursues when he makes disagreement thebasis of politics. However, when Rancie` re articulates this difference to Benjamin in

    Malaise dans lesthetique, his phrasing resorts to the chiasmatic structuring Benjamin

    had also relied upon:

    The relation between aesthetics and politics is, more precisely, the

    relation between this aesthetic of politics and the politics of the

    aesthetic, that is, the manner in which the practices and the forms of

    visibility of art themselves intervene in the distribution of the sensible

    and in its reconfiguration.19

    The relation of aesthetics and politics is a double relation comprised of an inversion

    of the positions occupied by politics and aesthetics. But here, again, Rancie` re places

    one side of a relation within quotation marks as he did when he spoke of howliterature does politics in Politics and Literature while politics remained a definite

    way of doing. Not only does this pose the question of why this recurs, but also raises

    the question of a difference that Rancie` res politics, and the disagreement it

    advances, cannot yet resolve, or can only resolve by setting disagreement against the

    project of a philosophy that achieves politics by eliminating politics, a project that

    validates that there is something to eliminate in the name of the unity Rancie` re

    accords to philosophy.20 However, the possibility of such an elimination remains

    parallax

    43

  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    9/14

    a distraction. The principal question is why politics and aesthetics must still fulfill a

    dual role: co-extensive and inseparable. Why the articulation of disagreement as the

    basis of what a political community holds in common must disagree with itself in

    relation to the aesthetic?

    The specific link Rancie` re speaks of between politics as a definite way of doing and

    literature as a definite practice of writing is implicated in these questions. Such a link

    demands that there should be a separation between politics and aesthetics but, at the

    same time, the terms of Rancie` res engagement with this link demands that such a

    link cannot be in any way representational. Accordingly, the significance of one

    cannot be seen through the other since, in this case, they could not be distinct systems

    of visibility. But how, then, is their relation to be understood if they must both be

    specific yet also articulate the disagreement that informs Rancie` res sense of politics?

    In a later passage from Malaise dans lesthetique, Rancie` re takes up again the questionof the autonomy of art invoked in Disagreement and takes up its relation to the

    distribution of the sensible against and through which Rancie` res politics of

    disagreement is established:

    It is really therefore in the form of autonomous experience that art

    touches the distribution of the sensible. The aesthetic regime of art

    institutes the relation between the forms of identification of art and the

    forms of political community in a way that recuses in advance every

    opposition between an autonomous art and a heteronomous art, an art

    for arts sake and an art in the service of politics, a museum art and an

    art of the street. Aesthetic autonomy is not the autonomy of doing art

    that modernism celebrated. It is the autonomy of a form of sensible

    experience. And it is this experience that appears like the seed of a newhumanity, of a new form of individual and collective life.21

    On this occasion, Rancie` res remarks emphasize how the autonomous experience of

    art touches the distribution of the sensible in a way that the claim to equality had

    also done when voiced by those whose part is to have no part in a community. Here,

    such touching does not occur through the equality of speaking beings but through

    what Rancie` re now calls the aesthetic regime of art.

    Rancie` re identifies three such regimes for art: the ethical regime of images; the

    representative regime of the arts; and the aesthetic regime of art. For Rancie` re, the

    first does not properly belong to art since the images involved in this regime, because

    they are images of the divine, have to be judged as a function of their intrinsic truth

    and their effects on the manner of being of individuals and collective existence. 22

    Whether such images or art or are not art depends, Rancie` re states, on how they are

    apprehended: the same statue of the same goddess can be art or not be art or can be

    art differently according to the regime of identification in which it is apprehended

    (saisie). There is first of all a regime in which the statue is exclusively apprehended as

    an image of the divinity.23 This regime is ethical because its significance rests on an

    identification that presupposes the divine. The second regime (the representative

    regime of the arts) no longer concerns judgments about the image as a valid

    Ferris

    44

  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    10/14

    identification of a divinity but instead understands art as a function of an imitation

    or representation that gives particularity to what is created so that imaginary

    existence (the divine) is accompanied by an expressivity that has vraisemblance to

    what is known expressivity figured as traits of femininity where the statue of a

    goddess is concerned. The third regime, the aesthetic regime of art, is the regime that

    distinguishes itself from both the ethical and the representative for Rancie` re.

    With this third regime, Rancie` re locates what he views as properly aesthetic, that is,

    a work of art that does not depend on an idea or on the norms (here redefined as

    canons) of representation. Instead, the aesthetic property is located in a specific

    sensorium.24 Rancie` re explains: the property of being something artistic refers not

    to a distinction between modes of making (faire), but to a distinction amongst

    modes of being. That is what the aesthetic means: the property of being art in the

    aesthetic regime of art is no longer given by criteria of technical perfection but by

    the assignment to a certain form of sensible apprehension.

    25

    With thisdetermination of aesthetic, art makes visible what it is rather than what it was or

    should be, that is, it becomes free from the role that traditional aesthetics has

    assigned to it, it becomes free appearance. Yet, as Rancie` res presentation of last

    regime shows, this freeing occurs within a triadic structure that marks a movement

    from an identification in which the sensible is first subjugated to the idea, then it

    appears in a limited form within art as representation, then, freed from the demand

    to imitate, it is left with the appearing of sensible experience as the index of its

    significance. While such a determination of the aesthetic clearly marks an

    intervention within the history of aesthetics and the regimes by which it distributes

    meaning to art, there remains the question of how the sensible experience of the

    aesthetic can retain its specificity as art. This question is particularly crucial if the

    aesthetic is unable to take on a political significance without either deriving its force

    from a mirroring of the intervention that equality makes when the part that has nopart speaks, or, without becoming indistinguishable from politics as in Rancie` res

    assertion that politics is aesthetics in principle26 and as in the reversal of politics

    and aesthetics that places an indifference at the centre of how Rancie` re links these

    two modes of sensible experience.27 In the case of the intervention based on the

    claim of equality, the aesthetic must in some way parallel the politics that is

    embodied in disagreement. However, it must do so without being derived from a

    claim that underpins such disagreement, a claim whose generality, the ability to

    speak and become visible in that speaking, is indifferently present as the condition of

    being human. In this case, if there is to be a specific link between aesthetics and

    politics, the aesthetic must be identified in its difference to politics. If this link were

    to be established on the basis of indifference on the principle that politics is

    aesthetics then, at the core of Rancie` res account of the politics, there is a

    necessary indifference that allows politics to determine whatever it touches or istouched by. The most important issue this indifference raises is not, however, a

    critical issue or even a critique of what Rancie` re claims. Rather, the issue is why the

    compulsion to submit the aesthetic to politics returns. This recognition of this issue

    poses yet another series of questions. What is at stake for politics in the

    determination of the aesthetic? Why, when a decision about the meaning of modern

    politics is at stake, must the aesthetic be brought to heel, even to the point of

    insisting that its most purely aesthetic moment, lart pour lart, does not remain in

    parallax

    45

  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    11/14

    conflict with politics but is itself already politicized?28 And, in the end, why can

    politics not let go of the aesthetic?

    The very idea of a pure art is an affront to political significance. Here, the aesthetic

    emerges as the category against which politics, in its role as what determines the

    significance of modern existence, must always test itself. That this test has failed

    whenever the aesthetic is claimed to derive meaning from either an idea or as a

    representational form has only exacerbated this affront. What then remains for

    politics is the task of articulating itself as a possibility that cannot be reduced to or

    restricted to indifference or to a state of mere existence, in effect, a condition. The

    indifference of equality on which Rancie` re first articulates the significance of politics

    as disagreement runs the risk of such a restriction and nowhere more so than when

    politics is embodied in an irreconcilable difference that sustains itself through the

    most essential example of what it is to be human: the equality of the claim to speak.

    The disagreement that arises in the equality of this claim is not only Rancie` rescentral insight into what a community holds in common, but, as such, it is a

    determination of politics as what exists in its self-separation from itself. That the

    aesthetic is also constituted in this way is evident from how Rancie` re configures the

    three regimes of the aesthetic. When the aesthetic becomes free appearance, it does

    so by separating out appearance from the ethical and representative regimes. When

    this aesthetic attains political significance it is because it institutes a type of time and

    a type of space29 as the result of a separation:

    What links the practice of art to the question of the common is the

    constitution of art, at once material and symbolic, of a certain time-

    space, of a suspension in relation to the ordinary forms of sensible

    experience. Art is not political in the first place because of the

    messages and feelings it transmits onto the order of the world. Nor isart political by the manner in which it represents the structures of

    society, the conflicts or identities of social groups. Art is political by

    the separation (ecart) it takes in relation to these functions, by the type

    of time and the type of space it institutes, by the manner it delimits

    (decouper) this time and populates this space [ . . . ] what is proper to art

    is this delimitation (decoupage) of material and symbolic space. By this

    means, art touches politics.30

    As the possibility of disagreement is maintained by the distribution of the sensible,

    the possibility of the political significance of the aesthetic is maintained by its

    separation from the mediating functions of transmission and representation. As free

    appearance, art is given a political function but only to the extent that this role is a

    function of what it is not. Such an aesthetic, like disagreement, is a resistance tomodes of determination and representation that appropriate art. In the case of the

    aesthetic, Rancie` re thinks this resistance in terms of the creation of a time and space

    in which art occurs in the purity of its appearance, free from the task of mediating

    another significance but also free to populate that space itself. This appearance is

    deemed political precisely because of its difference to those forms through which

    another object or issue is represented or transmitted. However, the moment when

    this aesthetic becomes linked to politics is the moment when it marks its difference to

    Ferris

    46

  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    12/14

    politics. Rancie` re writes, cest par la` que lart touche a` la politique. Toucher a`: to touch,

    border on both senses establish a border and that border is the specificity of a

    sensible experience in which politics and aesthetics meet.

    In an interview from 2000, Rancie` re remarks for me, the political always comes into

    play in questions of divisions and boundaries.31 If this remark is taken into

    consideration here, it is this touching that is also a separation that institutes politics.

    In other words, politics is not just the self-separation of a community within itself,

    and the aesthetic is not just the separation of its mode of visibility (appearance) from

    itself, it is also the separation of these two modes of separation. This separation that

    cannot be reconciled, that is, Rancie` res disagreement, is metapolitical in essence. It

    is the moment of a politics that is indifferent even to itself to the extent that what

    matters is its capacity to recur as a self-separation delimited by a specific time and

    space. It is in such a delimitation, such a cutting or decoupage, that art, the aesthetic,

    and politics are in principle the same since the principle at stake in each case is anarrest of what has always been at stake in politics and the aesthetic: an object or an

    issue that affirms their existence in time and space. Rancie` re, by affirming their

    existence as the arrest of what is at stake in each, has opened the question of the limit

    within which both politics and the aesthetic exist. By making each the sensible

    experience of that limit, Rancie` re has given the rationale of a history in which

    politics is always after aesthetics in the double sense that the word after holds

    here. Politics is the pursuit of a separation it can only have come after. To disagree

    with Rancie` re is to recognize this double sense, a double sense that his sense of

    disagreement has identified as a politics and an aesthetics.

    In the end, there is something unseen in this identification. It is not the unseen of a

    part that has no part (that is merely the limit of visibility, a part that is invisible in

    quotation marks, or to reuse a locution from Kant, partness without part), but theagreement of a separation, the agreement of a politics to separate from itself and

    delimit itself as politics in that separation. Only then can politics claim the difference

    displaced by its indifference to itself. But, to claim that difference, does it not also

    require a disagreement with Rancie` re, a disagreement with his delimitation of a

    space and a time as the common frame within which politics and aesthetics agree

    with one another? A disagreement with a politics of indifference that can only

    reproduce its disagreement? In this case, what name can be given to such a

    disagreement? Politics? Aesthetics? Does the problem of such a naming then account

    for why Rancie` re claims that the sensible experience through which the aesthetic

    regime of art institutes the relation between the forms of identification of art and the

    forms of political community is an experience that appears like the seed of a new

    humanity, of a new form of individual and collective life? 32 And this call for a new

    form of individual and collective life, is this not the most insistent claim of politics tohistorical significance? And, is this not what literature is conceived as at the moment

    of its inception as literature at the beginning of the nineteenth century? Not the

    conception of literature given by Madame de Stae l in her De la litterature consideree

    dans ses rapports avec les institutions socials which Rancie` re reads as the inauguration

    of literature as the art of writing.33 Here, writing is figured as the possibility of a

    literature no longer determined as a transitive exercise but as an intransitive one in

    which the possibility of its future is always in play. The aesthetics inaugurated in the

    parallax

    47

  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    13/14

    name of this literature derives its significance from an appearing without

    appearance, without an appearance that arrests and distributes significance

    according to the designation of an object or purpose. Is this indifference of literature

    with respect to its own future the point at which modern aesthetics necessarily

    coincides with a politics that cannot in the end surrender its claim to be indifferently

    present, to be the commonality of a history that arrests its promise of emancipation

    and progress in the name of a politics that has no part to call its own? And, in the

    necessity of such coincidence, which form of visibility is to be placed within

    quotation marks? Politics or aesthetics? Which one is condemned to quote the

    other, to separate the other from itself in the name of a promise that must always

    promise to interrupt itself? Is this a new form of individual and collective life or is

    such a new form the promise of a politics that must survive even its disagreement

    with itself and does so by appropriating the aesthetic once more? Here, the

    significance of Rancie` res engagement with the long history of politics and aesthetics

    appears in the form of delimiting a history that is touched irreconcilably with thepolitics of an apparent emancipation. As a result of thisappearance, such history must

    always disagree with itself, has already disagreed with itself. Rancie` res account

    of politics andaesthetics, is the witness of that disagreement, the witness of that history.

    Notes

    1 While Schillers intention is entirely positive

    the goal of the Aesthetic Education is the construc-

    tion of a true political freedom which Schiller

    defines as the the most complete of all artworks

    the justification of this intention depends, however,

    on laws that can only be known negatively. On this

    issue in Schiller, see my The Gift of the Political:

    Schiller and the Greeks, in Schiller Gedenken Vergessen Lesen, ed. Rudolf Helmstetter, Holt

    Meyer, and Daniel Mu ller Nielaba, (Paderborn:

    Fink Verlag, 2009).2 Jacque s Rancie` re, Politics of Literature,

    SubStance 33:1 (2004), pp. 10-24.3 Jacques Rancie` re, Politics of Literature, p.12.4 Jacques Rancie` re, Politics of Literature, p.13.5 Jacques Rancie` re, Le partage du sensible: esthetique

    et politique (Paris: La fabrique, 2000), p.12. This

    text is translated under the title The Politics of

    Aesthetics (London: Continuum, 2004).6 Jacques Rancie` re, The Politics of Aesthetics, p.13.7 Onthe policesee Disagreement: Politics andPhilosophy

    (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,

    1999), pp.21-42.8 Jacques Rancie` re, Disagreement, p.30; translation

    modified.9 Jacques Rancie` re, Disagreement, p.30.10 Jacques Rancie` re, Disagreement, p.30; translation

    modified.11 Jacques Ranciere, Disagreement, p.37.12 Jacques Rancie` re, Disagreement, p.37.13 Jacques Rancie` re, Disagreement, p.58; translation

    modified.

    14 Jacques Rancie` re, Disagreement, p.58; translation

    modified.15 Jacques Ranciere, Disagreement, p.31.16 Jacques Rancie` re, Disagreement, p.33; translation

    modified.17 Jacques Ranciere, Malaise dans lesthetique (Paris:

    Galile e, 2004), pp.38-9. This work will be

    subsequently referred to as Malaise. All translationsfrom this work are mine.18 These phrases are used by Benjamin to describe

    the fascist appropriation of politics and the

    communist response, respectively, in his essay,

    The Work of Art in the Age of its Technical

    Reproducibility.19 Jacques Rancie` re, Malaise, p.39.20 See Jacques Rancie` re, Disagreement, p.63.21 Jacques Rancie` re, Malaise, p.48.22 Jacques Rancie` re, Malaise, p.43.23 Jacques Ranciere, Malaise, p.43.24 Jacques Rancie` re, Malaise, p.44.25 Jacques Rancie` re, Malaise, p.44.26 Jacques Ranciere, Disagreement, p.58.27

    Jacques Rancie` re, Malaise, p.39.28 After speaking of aesthetic autonomy as a form

    of sensible experience and after claiming that this

    experience appears like the seed of a new

    humanity, Rancie` re writes: there is therefore no

    conflict between the purity of art and its

    politicization. Ranciere, Malaise, p.48.29 Jacques Rancie` re, Malaise, p.37.30 Jacques Rancie` re, Malaise, p.36-7.

    Ferris

    48

  • 7/29/2019 politics after aesthetics

    14/14

    31 Jacques Rancie` re, Literature, Politics, Aes-

    thetics: Approaches to Democratic Disagreement,

    SubStance 29:2 (2000), p.4.32 Jacques Rancie` re, Malaise, p.48. As Benjamin

    identified in his essay The Work of Art in the Age

    of its Technical Reproducibility, the modern

    question of the political significance of the aesthetic

    is the question of the formation of a collective.33 See Jacques Rancie` re, Politique de la literature

    (Paris, Galile e: 2007), p.13.

    David Ferris is Professor of Humanities and Comparative Literature at theUniversity of Colorado at Boulder. His recent work includes essays on Giorgio

    Agamben, Friedrich Schiller, Adorno and Modernism, Benjamin and photography,

    Vattimo and the postmodern. He is currently working on a book entitled Politics after

    Aesthetics.

    parallax

    49