Political Theory and Ir_beitz

download Political Theory and Ir_beitz

of 257

Transcript of Political Theory and Ir_beitz

  • POLITICAL THEORY AND

    INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS

  • POLITICAL THEORY AND

    INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS

    With a New Afterword by the Author

    Charles R. Beitz

    PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS

    PRINCETON, NEW JERSEY

  • Copyright 1979 by Princeton University PressPublished by Princeton University Press, 41 William Street,Princeton, New Jersey 08540In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press, 3 Market Place,Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1SYAfterword 1999 by Princeton University Press

    All Rights Reserved

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    Beitz, Charles R.Political theory and international relations / Charles R. Beitz.p. cm.Includes bibliographical references and index.ISBN 0-691-07614-61. International relations. 2. World politics. I. Title.JZ1305.B45 1999327. 1'01 dc21 99-12992

    This book has been composed in VIP Baskerville

    www.pup.princeton.edu

  • Contents

    Preface viiIntroduction 3

    Part One. International Relations as a State ofNature 11

    1. The Skepticism of the Realists 152. The Hobbesian Situation 273. International Relations as a State of Nature 354. The Basis of International Morality 505. From International Skepticism to the

    Morality of States 63

    Part Two. The Autonomy of States 671. State Autonomy and Individual Liberty 712. Nonintervention, Paternalism, and

    Neutrality 833. Self-determination 924. Eligibility, Boundaries, and Nationality 1055. Economic Dependence 1166. State Autonomy and Domestic Social Justice 121

    Part Three. International Distributive Justice 1251. Social Cooperation, Boundaries, and the

    Basis of Justice 1292. Entitlements to Natural Resources 1363. Interdependence and Global Distributive

    Justice 1434. Contrasts between International and

    Domestic Society 1545. The Rights of States 1616. Applications to the Nonideal World 169Conclusion 177Afterword 185Works Cited 221Index 237

  • Preface

    OLITICAL theorists have paid insufficient attention to avariety of philosophically interesting and practically im-

    portant normative problems of international relations be-cause they have accepted uncritically the conception of theworld developed by Hobbes and taken over by many recentwriters. By accepting the conception of international relationsas a state of nature, they have committed themselves to theview that international relations is primarily concerned with"the rivalries of nation-states, and with the traditional ultimaratio of those rivalrieswar."1 As a result, other pressingquestions of contemporary international relations have beenneglected, and the current debate about new structures ofworld order has taken place without benefit of the insight andcriticism that political philosophers should provide.

    This book is an attempt to work out a more satisfactoryinternational normative political theory through a critiqueand revision of orthodox views. To assert the possibility ofinternational political theory, one must first reexamine thetraditional image of international relations as a state of natureand purge it of its skeptical elements. The traditional alterna-tive to this view, which I call the morality of states, must bereconstructed to correct for the persistent misunderstand-ing of the notion of state autonomy. The result is a third viewof international morality, which might be described as cos-mopolitan.

    Many people helped me to develop these thoughts. It is apleasure to record my thanks to these people here.

    Thomas Scanlon and Dennis Thompson supervised thepreparation of an earlier version of this book as a doctoraldissertation in the political philosophy program at Princetonand continued to help when I undertook extensive furtherrevisions. It is impossible to imagine more supportive advisorsor rigorous critics. They cheerfully read a seemingly endless

    1 Stanley Hoffmann, The State of War, p. viii.

    P

  • viii PREFACE

    series of drafts of the manuscript and provided warmencouragement in the periods when my doubts and secondthoughts gained the upper hand. In a larger sense, I bene-fited from their efforts, with others, to create a flourishingcommunity of interest in political theory at Princeton, inwhich writing a thesis could be, and was, a pleasure. For all ofthis, and for their continuing friendship, I am most grateful.

    Huntington Terrell stimulated my interest in internationalethics when I was an undergraduate at Colgate and has en-couraged my work in this area ever since. He read the presentmanuscript with exceptional care and pointed out many phil-osophical errors and infelicities of language that I would nothave noticed otherwise. I am indebted to him for this, and forteaching me some Socratic virtues, as well: he combines askepticism of received ideas with a conviction that moral phi-losophy can meet the highest analytical standards withoutsacrificing relevance to practical affairs.

    Several other people commented on the manuscript in itsvarious incarnations. Paul E. Sigmund and Robert C. Tuckeroffered criticisms at my final public oral examination for thePh.D. and were good enough to amplify their remarks later.Written comments on a subsequent version from Brian Barryand Robert O. Keohane helped me to improve the argumentin many ways. Portions of the manuscript were reviewed andcriticized by Jeffrey Hart, William Hirsch, David Hoekema, J.Roland Pennock, and Sheldon S. Wolin. I benefited fromtheir criticisms and suggestions even when I was not per-suaded by them, since I was at least forced to make my ownviews clearer.

    I was lucky to have the help of Eleanor Bennett in thepreparation of the final manuscript. She not only broughtorder out of a chaos of revisions, but also contributed a goodmeasure of whatever literacy the manuscript now possesses. Iam also happy to thank Paula Smith for her careful and effi-cient work on the index.

    For financial support at various stages of my work, I amgrateful to Princeton University, the Morris Abrams Awardin International Relations, and Swarthmore College. The dis-cussion of international distributive justice is based on my

  • PREFACE ix

    article, "Justice and International Relations" (Philosophy andPublic Affairs 4, no. 4 [Summer 1975], pp. 360-89), portions ofwhich are reproduced by permission of Princeton UniversityPress, the holder of the copyright.

    Finally, I owe debts of a different kind to my parents, Jeanand Richard Beitz, whose sacrifices made possible much ofmy education; and to Sherry Swirsky, my best friend, whoseencouragement of my work on this book has meant more tome than I can say.

    Swarthmore CollegeOctober 1978

  • POLITICAL THEORY AND

    INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS

  • Introduction

    I N THE modern history of political theory, and in most con-temporary discussions of problems of political philosophyas well, international relations appears largely as a marginalaffair. The image of a global state of nature, in which nationsare conceived as largely self-sufficient, purposive units, hasbeen thought to capture the relative absence of moral normsgoverning relations among states. At one extreme of thetraditionrepresented by Machiavelli, Rodin, and Hobbesinternational theory has denied the existence of any control-ling universal rules in relations between states, substitutingraison d'tat as the highest norm. Even when the possibility ofinternational moral ties has been grantedfor example, inpost-Grotian writings on international lawthese ties havebeen held to be substantially weaker than intranational moralbonds precisely because of the absence of supranational polit-ical authorities. The only problem in international relations tohave gained significant theoretical attention is the justificationand prevention of warthe main form of social intercoursein the global state of nature.1

    However justifiable this neglect has been in the past, manyrecent developments compel us to take another look at the"recalcitrance of international politics to being theorizedabout."2 These developments include the increasing sensitiv-ity of domestic societies to external economic, political, andcultural events; the widening gap between rich and poorcountries; the growth of centers of economic power beyondeffective regulation by individual states; the appearance ofserious shortages of food and energy caused, at least in part,by the pursuit of uncoordinated and uncontrolled growthpolicies by national governments; and the increasingly urgent

    1 See, for example, the following remark in the introduction to a widelyread contemporary work of analytical political philosophy: "In relations be-tween states the problem of establishing a peaceful order overshadows allothers." Brian Barry, Political Argument, p. xviii.

    2 Martin Wight, "Why Is There No International Theory?," p. 33.

  • 4 INTRODUCTION

    demands of third world countries for more equitable terms ofparticipation in global politics and economics. To put thepoint in language more familiar to discussions of this subject,the rise of "welfare questions" in international forums, and of"low politics" in diplomacy, parallels the increasing impact ofinternational arrangements and transnational interactions onhuman well-being. It is not that "high politics"that is, thethreat and avoidance of warhas become unimportant, butrather that it represents only one of many problems for whichsolutions must now be sought at the international level.3

    These changes in international relations have a threefoldrelevance to political theory. Since states can no longer beregarded as largely self-sufficient political orders, the imageof a global state of nature no longer provides an obviouslycorrect picture of the moral relations among states, personsof diverse nationality, and other actors in the internationalrealm. The orthodox theoretical image of international rela-tions and many practical principles thought to follow from itrequire critical examination and modification in the face ofthe new and not-so-new facts of world politics.

    At the same time, the attempt to formulate a more satis-factory normative theory puts the facts in a new light andsuggests empirical questions that have been answered insuffi-ciently thus far. The answers to such questions might formpart of the justification of international normative principles,or they might be required to determine how internationalprinciples apply. In either case, a normative theory appro-priate to the contemporary world raises questions and sug-gests problems that deserve greater attention from studentsof international relations.

    Third, and perhaps most important, one must consider therelation of political theory and international practice. Politicaltheory arises from a perception of the possibility of choice in

    3 None of the arguments in this book actually turns on the claim that inter-national interdependence is something new. Indeed, it seems more likely thatthe growth of the world economy did not follow, but rather accompanied, therise of the modern state. Both were part of the same historical process. Thus,interdependence is at least as old as the modern state. See generally Im-manuel Wallerstein, The Modern World-System.

  • INTRODUCTION 5

    political affairs. This possibility is presupposed by criticism ofthe established order as well as by engagement in efforts tochange it. When choices are to be made regarding the endsand means of political action, or the structures and rules ofinstitutions and practices, it is natural to ask by what princi-ples such choices should be guided. An important function ofthe political theorist is to formulate and examine alternativeprinciples and to illuminate the reasons why some are morepersuasive than others. Now the developments that have un-dermined the orthodox theoretical image of international re-lations have also weakened the practical consensus that therules and settled expectations of the present world system arelegitimate. An international debate is underway concerningthe future structure of world order, but political theoristshave failed to provide the kinds of guidance one normallyexpects from theory in times of political change. Recognizingthis, it would be irresponsible not to try to work out the impli-cations for our moral ideas of a more accurate perception ofthe international realm than that which informs the moderntradition of political theory. For only in this way can we morerationally understand our moral identities and assess themodes of political practice in which we engage.

    WHILE a more satisfactory international normative theory isnecessary, the would-be international theorist may expect toencounter a variety of obstacles that do not embarrass thepolitical theorist of domestic society. Chief among these is awidespread if unreflective conviction that normative interna-tional theory is not possible, since for various reasons (dis-cussed in part one, below) it is thought to be inappropriate tomake moral judgments about international affairs. Anotherobstacle is that it is not clear what the program of interna-tional theory ought to be. The main problems of the politicaltheory of the nation-state grow out of the interplay of a richtradition of philosophical argument and the recurrence of aset of relatively well defined issues in popular political debate.International relations, in contrast, has neither so rich a the-oretical tradition nor so well defined or recurrent a set of

  • 6 INTRODUCTION

    political issues. Third, our intuitions about moral problems ininternational affairs are less firm than our moral intuitionsabout domestic problems. Whatever one's view about the rela-tion of intuitions and moral theory, it seems clear that the rel-ative paucity of familiar and reliable intuitions about interna-tional problems will make it more difficult to formulate andjustify normative principles for international practice. Finally,as I shall suggest, many international normative issues cannotbe settled definitely without more satisfactory empirical in-formation than is currently available. While empirical consid-erations are, if anything, more important in internationalthan in domestic political theory, the social science of interna-tional relations is less advanced than the science of domesticsociety.

    This book is intended to help lay the groundwork for amore satisfactory normative political theory of internationalrelations. It is important to stress that I do not claim to pro-vide a systematic theory analogous to those found in thefamiliar treatises on the political theory of the nation-state. Inview of the difficulties noted above, this seems too ambitious agoal at present. Instead, I want to show that the obstacles tointernational theory are not insuperable and that there areinternational normative problems of sufficient practical im-portance and philosophical interest to warrant further theo-retical effort. In addition, I hope to call into question somereceived views about international morality and suggest theplausibility of a more cosmopolitan and less state-centeredperspective. But I do not regard my normative conclusions asfinal in any sense, and I have tried to indicate the directions inwhich criticism of my views seems most promising and fur-ther thought seems most needed.

    Although my discussion is necessarily preliminary, I hopethat it will have several kinds of value in its own right. Themost important of these is that it can bring some conceptualclarity to an area in which confusion is endemic. If readersare not persuaded by my criticisms of prevailing views or bythe alternative positions I outline, my discussion should atleast illustrate the respects in which such views require morecareful formulation and defense than they have heretofore

  • INTRODUCTION 7

    received. Even when I make no attempt to resolve outstand-ing controversies, my analyses of the normative concepts in-volved in them should make clear what the controversies areabout and what would be needed to resolve them. Further,while not pretending to offer a history of internationaltheory, I have surveyed the tradition of international theoryand indicated the ways in which elements of it are relevant tomy main concerns.4 The tradition is not, in general, veryedifying, but nonetheless one finds suggestive formulationsand illuminating arguments scattered about within it. Finally,I have given special attention to the relation of the empiricalscience of international relations and the normative issues ofinternational theory. When possible, I have assessed relevantempirical considerations and shown how these require or in-cline us to accept some normative positions and to rejectothers. When necessary, I have tried to formulate unresolvedempirical and theoretical problems in such a way as to showhow further work on them would influence their resolution.

    THIS book has three parts. Each part addresses distinct issues,but the discussion is progressive and suggests the outlines of amore systematic theory. Thus, I argue (in part one) thatinternational political theory is possible, by showing that sev-eral arguments for skepticism about international ethics are

    4 By "the tradition of international theory" I mean the writings of the clas-sical international jurists (like Grotius, Pufendorf, and Wolff); occasional re-marks on international relations that appear in treatises primarily devoted tothe political theory of the state (like Hobbes's Leviathan); and works that con-sider the causes of war and advance plans for world peace (like Kant's Per-petual Peace). Perhaps surprisingly, there is no single work that gives a com-prehensive and scholarly analysis of the growth of international thought. Themost helpful discussions are: Wight, "Why Is There No InternationalTheory?"; Arnold Wolfers, "Political Theory and International Relations,"pp. ix-xxvii; F. H. Hinsley, Power and the Pursuit of Peace; and Walter Schiffer,The Legal Community of Mankind. A detailed historical survey of the develop-ment of the idea of the law of nations, from Thomas Aquinas to the twentiethcentury, is available in E.B.F. Midgley, The Natural Law Tradition and the Theoryof International Relations. See also F. Parkinson, The Philosophy of InternationalRelations, which contains a helpful bibliography; A.C.F. Beales, The History ofPeace; and F. Melian Stawell, The Growth of International Thought.

  • 8 INTRODUCTION

    incorrect, and furthermore, that the international realm iscoming more and more to resemble domestic society in manyof the features usually thought relevant to the justification of(domestic) political principles. To support this claim, I exam-ine the traditional image of international relations as aHobbesian state of nature and argue that it is misleading onboth empirical and moral theoretical grounds.

    If international skepticism of the sort criticized in part onerepresents the dominant view about international morality,then views stemming from the modern natural law tradition(which I call the morality of states) might be said to representthe most widely held alternative. Like international skepti-cism, the morality of states makes use of the analogy of statesand persons, but it draws the normative conclusion thatstates, like persons, have some sort of right of autonomy thatinsulates them from external moral criticism and political in-terference. This idea lies behind such principles of interna-tional practice as nonintervention and self-determination,and some now familiar moral objections to political and eco-nomic imperialism. I argue in part two that the analogy ofstates and persons is highly misleading here, and that the ap-propriate analogue of individual autonomy in the interna-tional realm is not national autonomy but conformity of a so-ciety's political and economic institutions with appropriateprinciples of justice.

    Finally, I return to the analogy of international society anddomestic society to discuss whether the two realms are suffi-ciently similar that arguments for distributive justice withinthe state carry over into international relations. Current de-bate about a new international economic order clearly pre-supposes some principle of international distributive justice; Iargue that a suitable principle can be justified by analogy withthe justification given by John Rawls in A Theory of Justice foran intrastate distributive principle. Although it is clear thatstates continue to have great significance for the world's polit-ical and moral order, I argue that the importance which forvarious reasons we must accord to states does not underminethe case for global redistribution. The argument is of the firstimportance for the current debate about reforming the

  • INTRODUCTION 9

    international economic system, for its implication is that theexisting global distribution of income and wealth is highly un-just. It is important, as well, for a more refined internationalpolitical theory, because it suggests that the differences be-tween the international and domestic realms, although sig-nificant in some respects, supply no reasons why such devicesof domestic political theory as the idea of an original contractshould not be extended to international relations.

    I have said that this book is a first attempt to provide a polit-ical theory of international relations that is more systematicand more consonant with the empirical situation than tradi-tional views. In the conclusion, I characterize such a theory ascosmopolitan (in Kant's sense) and distinguish it from inter-national skepticism and the morality of states.

    A consequence of the preliminary character of my remarksis that many questions must be left unanswered. Some ofthese questions are very important, for both empirical re-search and practical politics. If there is a defense for leavingsuch crucial matters open, it is that one cannot confront themresponsibly without a prior grasp of the more elementary butalso more basic concerns of this book.

    I HA V E restricted myself to a few cursory remarks about theapplication of my views to problems of war and peace. Sincethese are often taken to be the central problems of interna-tional relations, their lack of emphasis in this book deservessome explanation. There are three main points. First, someissues related to war and peaceparticularly those having todo with the concepts of violence and nonviolence, war crimesand the rules of war, and collective guilt and responsibilityhave received considerable philosophical discussion in thepast several years, often of very high quality.5 They have not

    5 Two recent books are especially noteworthy: Michael Walzer, Just and Un-just Wars; and W. B. Gallie, Philosophers of Peace and War. Also, see the essayscontained in three most helpful collections: Richard Wasserstrom, ed., Warand Morality; Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon, eds.,War and Moral Responsibility; and Virginia Held, Sidney Morgenbesser, andThomas Nagel, eds., Philosophy, Morality and International Affairs. On nonvio-

  • 10 INTRODUCTION

    suffered from the general neglect of international relations bymoral and political philosophers.

    A second point is that some problems about the morality ofwar, like traditional questions of jus ad bellum, cannot be re-solved without a more general theory of international right.For example, claims of justice in war often turn on claims thatparticular rights (e.g., to land) have been infringed or thatrules of international conduct (e.g., those defining a balanceof power) have been broken. Such claims furnish a justifica-tion for resort to war partly because they rest on principlesthat distribute rights to international actors and define astructure of international life that actors have duties to pro-mote or uphold. But to explain why some such principlesrather than others are morally best, one needs an interna-tional political theory. If this is true, then much of what I sayin this book will be relevant to the problem of jus ad bellum,even though I have not usually drawn the connectionsexplicitly.

    Finally, I repeat a point with which I began. Contemporaryinternational relations consists of far more than the ma-neuvers of states "in the state and posture of gladiators; hav-ing their weapons pointing, and their eyes fixed on oneanother . . . ; and continual spies upon their neighbors."6 Thisadditional activity raises distinctive moral problems to whichsolutions are increasingly essential, but which are likely to beoverlooked because they fall outside the traditional concep-tion of world politics. I certainly do not mean to suggest thatthe problems of war and peace are either unimportant orwithout philosophical interest; but, by setting these issuesaside, I hope to show that other problems are at least as im-portant, in some respects more basic, and of considerablephilosophical interest in their own right.

    lence and pacifism, see especially H.J.N. Horsburgh, Non-violence and Aggres-sion.

    6 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan [1651], ch. 13, p. 115.

  • PART O N E

    International Relations asA State of Nature

  • Morality, then, as the channel to individual self-fulfillmentyes. Morality as the foundation of civic vir-tue, and accordingly as a condition precedent to successfuldemocracyyes. Morality in governmental method, as amatter of conscience and preference on the part of ourpeopleyes. But morality as a general criterion for the de-termination of the behavior of states and above all as a cri-terion for measuring and comparing the behavior ofdifferent statesno. Here other criteria, sadder, more lim-ited, more practical, must be allowed to prevail.l

    1 George F. Kennan, Realities of American Foreign Policy, p. 49.

  • T HE state, like other institutions that can affect people'swell-being and their rights, must satisfy certain moral re-quirements if we are to consider it legitimate. It is by thesestandards that we evaluate the state's claims on us and orientour efforts at political change. The normative component ofpolitical theory is the search for such standards and for thereasoning that forms their justification.

    We do not often take the same attitude toward the complexstructure of institutions and practices that lies beyond thestate. This is in accord with the modern tradition of politicaltheory, but it is worth asking if there are reasons of principlefor following tradition in this respect. In this part, I considerwhether it makes sense to look for general principles of inter-national political theory that can supply reasons for andagainst particular choices in the same way that the principlesof domestic political theory guide choices about alternativepolicies within the state. Is normative international politicaltheory possible?

    Any attempt to lay the groundwork for normative interna-tional political theory must face the fact that there is a sub-stantial body of thought, often referred to as "politicalrealism," that denies this possibility. Skepticism about interna-tional morality derives from a variety of sources, such as cul-tural relativism, apprehension about the effects of "moralism"on foreign policy, the view that rulers have an overriding ob-ligation to follow the national interest, and the idea that therecan be no moral principles of universal application in a worldorder of sovereign states. In the first section of this part, Iargue that none of these arguments supports internationalmoral skepticism, either because such arguments involveelementary confusions or fallacious assumptions, or becausethey are incomplete.

    A more sophisticated argument for international skepti-cism is that certain structural features of an anarchical worldorder make international morality impossible. This argument(reconstructed in detail in section 2) characterizes interna-tional relations as a Hobbesian state of nature, that is, as an

  • 14 A STATE OF NATURE

    order of independent agents, each pursuing its own interests,without any common power capable of enforcing rules ofcooperation. The image of international relations as a state ofnature has been influential both in the modern tradition ofpolitical theory and in contemporary thought about interna-tional affairs. Moreover, it yields a plausible argument forinternational skepticism and so deserves close attention.

    The Hobbesian argument for international skepticismcombines two premises, which I examine separately in sec-tions 3 and 4. The first is the empirical claim that the interna-tional state of nature is a state of war, in which no state has anoverriding interest in following moral rules that restrain thepursuit of more immediate interests. The second is thetheoretical claim that moral principles must be justified byshowing that following them promotes the long-range inter-ests of each agent to whom they apply. I shall argue that eachpremise is wrong: the first because it involves an inaccurateperception of the structure and dynamics of contemporaryinternational politics, and the second because it provides anincorrect account of the basis of moral principles and of themoral character of the state. Both premises are embodied inthe image of international relations as a Hobbesian state ofnature, and in both respects this image is misleading.

    If my argument against the Hobbesian conception of inter-national relations is correct, a main reason for skepticismabout the possibility of international political theory will havebeen removed. In fact, I shall argue, one cannot maintain thatmoral judgments about international affairs are meaninglesswithout embracing a more far-reaching skepticism about allmoralitysomething, I assume, that few would be willing todo. However, a successful defense of the possibility of inter-national political theory does not say much about the contentof its principles. In section 5, I characterize the traditionalalternative to Hobbesian skepticism (represented in the writ-ings of various modern natural law theorists) as the moralityof states and distinguish some of its basic substantive features,which are criticized in greater detail later in this book.

  • SKEPTICISM OF THE REALISTS 15

    1. The Skepticism of the Realists

    F OR many years, it has been impossible to make moral ar-guments about international relations to its American stu-dents without encountering the claim that moral judgmentshave no place in discussions of international affairs or foreignpolicy. This claim is one of the foundations of the so-calledrealist approach to international studies and foreign policy.On the surface, it is a most implausible view, especially in aculture conscious of itself as an attempt to realize a certainmoral ideal in its domestic political life. All the more remark-able is the fact that the realists' skepticism about the possibilityof international moral norms has attained the status of a pro-fessional orthodoxy in both academic and policy circles, ac-cepted by people with strong moral commitments about othermatters of public policy. Although the realists have often usedarguments with deep roots in modern political theory, I be-lieve that their skepticism can be shown to rest on fallaciousreasoning and incorrect empirical assumptions.

    To support this view, I shall argue that one cannot consis-tently maintain that there are moral restrictions on individualaction but no such restrictions on the actions of states. I beginby considering the distinction (implied by this argument) be-tween (generalized) moral skepticism and what I shall callinternational skepticism and show in more detail exactly whatis involved in the assumption that moral skepticism is incor-rect. It should be emphasized that this is indeed an assump-tion; I make no attempt to provide a general argumentagainst moral skepticism.

    One might be skeptical about the possibility of internationalmorality because one is skeptical, in general, about the possi-bility of all kinds of morality. Perhaps one thinks that all ormost people are incapable of being motivated by moral con-siderations, or that moral judgments are so subjective as to beuseless in resolving conflicting claims and in fulfilling theother social functions usually assigned to morality. Whateverits rationale, moral skepticism, and its derivative, skepticismabout political ethics, represent a refusal to accept moral ar-

  • l6 A STATE OF NATURE

    guments as sources of reasons for action. Moral skepticismmight take a variety of forms, including a denial that moraljudgments can be true or false, a denial that moral judgmentshave meaning, or a denial that the truth of moral judg-ments provides a reason for acting on them.

    Generalized moral and political skepticism might be coun-tered to some extent by examining the arguments that sup-port them. Probably these arguments would turn out to con-tain important confusions or deep inconsistencies. But onecould not thereby demonstrate the possibility of social orpolitical ethics; other arguments for skepticism could be ad-vanced, and at some point in the attempt to counter them onewould need to rely on substantive ethical or metaethical viewsto demonstrate the weaknesses of the skeptical arguments.This, however, would be to assume that skepticism is wrong,rather than to argue it. Generalized moral and political skep-ticism can only be shown to be wrong by exhibiting an accept-able theory of ethics and of its foundation, because one of thefunctions of such a theory is to explain the possibility of justthose features of ethics that the skeptic claims not to under-stand. At a minimum, such a theory must distinguish moralityfrom egoism and explain how it can be rational to act on rea-sons that are (or might be) inconsistent with considerations ofprudence or self-interest. Indeed, the idea that considera-tions of advantage are distinct from those of morality, andthat it might be rational to allow the latter to override theformer, seems to be at the core of our intuitions aboutmorality.2

    In what follows I shall have to assume without discussionthat some such theory can be provided. The leading con-troversies in metaethics are likely to linger for a long while,and progress in normative areas ought not to await a resolu-tion of these other problems even though they are in somesense logically prior. Obviously, one would like to offer asufficiently complete theory to meet objections on both fronts.But this seems beyond reach at present. Instead, I shall pro-

    2 For a further discussion, see Thomas Nagel, The Possibility of Altruism, pp.125-42.

  • SKEPTICISM OF THE REALISTS 17

    ceed on the assumption that we share some basic ideas aboutthe nature and requirements of morality (which I refer to asmoral intuitions) and see whether international skepticism isconsistent with them.

    One important source of international skepticism is cul-tural relativism. International lawyers and cultural an-thropologists have documented wide disparities in the viewsof rationality and of the good prevalent in the world's cul-tures. These differences are reflected in the structures of var-ious legal systems and in the attitudes customarily taken bydifferent cultures toward social rules, collective ideals, and thevalue of individual autonomy.3 In some cultures, for exam-ple, autonomy is readily sacrificed to the requirements of col-lective goals. In general, given any consistent ranking of socialgoods or any plausible view of how such rankings might bemorally justified, it is possible (and often likely) that a cultureor society can be found in which there is dominant adivergent ranking of goods or view of moral justification. Ifthis is the case, a skeptic might say, then there are no rationalgrounds for holding one social morality superior to anotherwhen their requirements conflict. Any doctrine that purportsto be an international morality and that extends beyond theleast common denominator of the various social moralitieswill be insecure in its foundations. But, typically, the least-common-denominator approach will leave most internationalconflicts unresolved because these have at their root conflictsover which principles are to apply to given situations or whichgoods should be sacrificed when several goods conflict. Sinceprinciples adequate to resolve such conflicts are fundamen-tally insecure, the skeptic claims, no normative internationalpolitical theory is possible.4

    3 For example, see F.S.C. Northrup, The Meeting of East and West, esp. ch.10; and Adda B. Bozeman, The Future of Law in a Multicultural World, pp. ix-xvii, 14-33.

    4 This construction might account for Kennan's non sequitur: "[L]et us notassume that our moral values . . . necessarily have viability for peopleeverywhere. In particular, let us not assume that the purposes of states, as dis-tinguished from their methods, are fit subjects for measurement in moralterms: "Realities of American Foreign Policy, p. 47; emphasis in original.

  • l8 A STATE OF NATURE

    This argument can be met on two levels, depending on thekind of intercultural disagreement to which it appeals. If theskeptical appeal is to disagreements over, say, the rankings ofvarious social goods or their definitions, it may be that there isno challenge to the possibility of valid international principlesbut merely to the contents of particular ones. A considerationof views held in other cultures might persuade us that our as-sumptions ought to be altered in some ways to conform withconditions of which we had previously been insufficientlyaware. This may be true of disagreements about the relativeimportance of individual autonomy and economic welfare.We are accustomed to defending individual rights in contextsof relative affluence, but considerations of economic de-velopment or of nonindustrial social structures might moveus to recognize a dimension of relativity in these defenses. Ido not mean to take a position on this issue at this point; Ionly mean to note one way in which cultural variations mightbe accommodated within an international political theory. Inthis case we would recognize a condition on the justification ofprinciples of right that had previously gone unnoticed. Here,considerations of cultural diversity enter our thinking as datathat may require revisions of particular principles; they donot undermine the possibility of normative theory itself.

    But skeptics might say that what is at issue is somethingdeeper; since different cultures might have radically differentconceptions of what morality is, we have no right to be confi-dent that our conception is correct. This carries the argumentto a second level, but now it is difficult to say what the argu-ment means. Perhaps it means that members of some otherculture typically count as decisive certain kinds of reasons foraction that we regard as utterly irrelevant from the point ofview of our own morality. If so, we may ultimately have to saythat the other culture's conception simply is not morality, or,at least, that claims founded on that conception do not countagainst our moral principles, even those that apply globally. Itmight seem that this attitude involves some sort of intellectualimperialism because it imposes a conception on cultures towhich the conception is quite alien. But surely this is not cor-rect. At some point, having learned what we can from the

  • SKEPTICISM OF THE REALISTS 19

    views of others, we must be prepared to acknowledge thatsome conception of morality is the most reasonable one avail-able under the circumstances, and go forward to see whatprinciples result. Notice that this does not say that everyonemust be able to acknowledge the reasonableness of the sameassumptions; actual agreement of everyone concerned is toostringent a requirement to place on the justification of moralprinciples (just as it is on epistemological ones). Notice alsothat the problem of relativism is not limited to internationalethics; intrasocietal conflicts might involve similar disagree-ments over fundamental ethical assumptions. In either case, itis enough, in establishing standards for conduct, that we beable to regard them as the most rational choices available foranyone appropriately situated and that we be prepared to de-fend this view with arguments addressed to anyone who dis-agrees. In this way we reach decisions that are as likely to bemorally right as any that are in our power to reach. We can dono more than this in matters of moral choice.5

    One need not embrace cultural relativism to maintain thatmoral judgments are inappropriate in international relations.Indeed, political realism more often starts from differentpremises. Some realists begin with the assertion that it is un-realistic to expect nations to behave morally in an anarchicworld. For example, Hans Morgenthau, a leading realist, ob-jects that "writers have put forward moral precepts whichstatesmen and diplomats ought to take to heart in order tomake relations between nations more peaceful and less anar-chical . . . ; but they have rarely asked themselves whetherand to what extent such precepts, however desirable in them-selves, actually determine the actions of men."6 While con-ceding the existence of some weak ethical restraints on in-ternational behavior, Morgenthau argues that internationalmorality is largely a thing of the past and that competingnational interests are now the main motives in world politics.This, he claims, is as it should be: "[T]he state has no rightto let its moral disapprobation . . . get in the way of success-

    5 There is a helpful discussion of some general issues of ethical relativismin Richard B. Brandt, Ethical Theory, pp. 271-84.

    6 Hans J. Morgenthau, "The Twilight of International Morality," p. 79.

  • 20 A STATE OF NATURE

    ful political action, itself inspired by the moral principle of na-tional survival."7

    How shall we understand this claim? One version is that wewill fail to understand international behavior if we expectstates to conform to moral standards appropriate to individ-uals. If we seek something like scientific knowledge of worldpoliticssay, a body of lawlike generalizations with at leastlimited predictive powerwe are unlikely to make muchprogress by deriving our hypotheses from moral rules ap-propriate to individual behavior.8 This seems fairly obvious,but perhaps Morgenthau's emphasis on it can be understoodin the perspective of the "idealist" legal approaches to thestudy of international relations that he sought to discredit.9 Inany event, this version of the claim does not imply that weought not to make moral judgments about international be-havior when thinking normatively rather than descriptively.

    Another version of the claim, which is encountered moreoften, is this: we are likely to make mistaken foreign policychoices if we take an excessively "moralistic" attitude towardthem.10 This might mean either of two things. Perhaps itmeans that a steadfast commitment to a moral principle thatis inappropriate to some situation is likely to move us to make

    7 Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations, p. 10. There is an ambiguityhere regarding the moral status of the national interest as an evaluativestandard. One might call this view a form of moral skepticism, or one mightsay that it demonstrates that there is a moral warrant for following the na-tional interest. I argue below that the former is the more appropriate in-terpretation. It should be noted, however, that some realist writersprobably including Aron and Morgenthauhave clearly thought that theywere arguing the latter view instead. On this ambiguity, see Hedley Bull, "So-ciety and Anarchy in International Relations," pp. 37-38.

    8 On the other hand, we may be equally misled by the research hypothesesthat follow from a variety of realist assumptions. There is a useful criticism ofrealism as a research orientation, rather than as a skeptical doctrine aboutinternational norms, in Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye, Jr., Power andInterdependence, ch. 2.

    9 As Charles Frankel suggests in Morality and U.S. Foreign Policy, pp. 12-18.See also Kenneth W. Thompson, Political Realism and the Crisis of World Poli-tics, pp. 32-38.

    10 Hans J. Morgenthau, In Defense of the National Interest, pp. 37-38. Com-pare Dean Acheson, "Ethics in International Relations Today," p. 16.

  • SKEPTICISM OF THE REALISTS 21

    immoral or imprudent decisions about it. Or it might meanthat an idealistic or overzealous commitment even to an ap-propriate principle might cause us to overlook some salientfacts and make bad decisions as a result. Each of these rec-ommends reasonable circumspection in making moral judg-ments about international relations. But neither implies thatit is wrong to make such judgments at all. What is being said isthat the moral reasoning regarding some decision is flawed:either an inappropriate moral principle is being applied, oran appropriate principle is being incorrectly applied. It doesnot follow that it is wrong even to attempt to apply moralprinciples to international affairs, yet this conclusion must beproved to show that international skepticism is true. An ar-gument is still needed to explain why it is wrong to makemoral judgments about international behavior whereas it isnot wrong to make them about domestic political behavior orabout interpersonal behavior.

    It is often thought that such an argument can be providedby appealing to the concept of the national interest. Thus, forexample, Morgenthau seems to claim (in a passage alreadycited) that a state's pursuit of its own interests justifies disre-gard for moral standards that would otherwise constrain itsactions.11

    Machiavelli argues in this way. He writes, for instance, "[I]tmust be understood that a prince, and especially a newprince, cannot observe all those things which are consideredgood in men, being often obliged, in order to maintain thestate, to act against faith, against charity, against humanity,and against religion."12 Machiavelli does not simply representthe prince as amoral and self-aggrandizing. His claim is thatviolation by the prince of the moral rules usually thoughtappropriate for individuals is warranted when necessary "tomaintain the state." The prince should "not deviate fromwhat is good, if possible, but be able to do evil if con-strained."13

    11 Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations, p. 10; see also his In Defense of theNational Interest, pp. 33-39.

    12 Niccol Machiavelli, The Prince [1532], XVIII, p. 65.13 Ibid; see also Discourses [1531], I, ix, p. 139, and II, vi, pp. 298-99.

  • 22 A STATE OF NATURE

    Now Machiavelli is not saying that rulers have license to be-have as they please, nor is he claiming that their official ac-tions are exempt from critical assessment. The issue is one ofstandards: what principles should be invoked to justify orcriticize a prince's official actions? Machiavelli holds thatprinces are justified in breaking the moral rules that applyto ordinary citizens when they do so for reasons of state.Another statement of his view might be that rulers are subjectto moral rules, but that the rules to which they are subject arenot always, and perhaps not usually, the same as the rules towhich ordinary citizens are bound. The private virtuesliberality, kindness, charityare vices in the public realm be-cause their observance is inconsistent with the promotion ofthe well-being of the state. The rule "preserve the state" is thefirst principle of the prince's morality, and it is of sufficientimportance to override the requirements of other, possiblyconflicting, rules which one might regard as constitutive ofprivate morality.14

    Is Machiavelli's position really a form of international skep-ticism? The view that a prince is justified in acting to promotethe national interest amounts to the claim that an argumentcan be given that in so acting the prince is doing the (morally)right thing. But if this is true, one might say, then Machiavel-li's view and its contemporary variants are not forms of inter-national skepticism. They do not deny that moral judgmentsare appropriate in international relations; instead, they main-tain that moral evaluations of a state's actions must be cast interms of the relation between the state's actions and its owninterests. The distinction between international skepticismand the Machiavellian view turns out to be like the distinctionbetween general moral skepticism and ethical egoism. Onepair of views denies the possibility of morality altogether,

    14 Machiavelli, Discourses, III, xli, pp. 527-28. There is, of course, an exten-sive secondary literature devoted to the explication of Machiavelli's position.No doubt many would take issue with my reading of his view, but 1 cannotenter the debate here. On Machiavelli's notion of virt and its relation to thenational interest, see Sheldon S. Wolin, Politics and Vision, pp. 224-28 and230-31.

  • SKEPTICISM OF THE REALISTS 23

    while the other pair advances a substantive moral principle.However, in both cases, the distinction is without a difference.What is distinctively moral about a system of rules is the possi-bility that the rules might require people to act in ways that donot promote their individual self-interest. The ethical egoistdenies this by asserting that the first principle of his "moral-ity" is that one should always act to advance one's own inter-ests. To call such a view a kind of morality is at least paradoxi-cal, since, in accepting the view, one commits oneself toabandoning the defining feature of morality. Thus, it seemsbetter to say, as does Frankena, that "prudentialism or livingwholly by the principle of enlightened self-love just is not akind of morality."15 Similarly, to say that the first principle ofinternational morality is that states should promote their owninterests denies the possibility that moral considerationsmight require a state to act otherwise. And this position iscloser to international skepticism than to anything that couldplausibly be called international morality.

    If Machiavelli's view is, after all, a version of internationalskepticism, it does not follow that it is incorrect. Perhaps thereis nothing that could plausibly be called international moral-ity. At this point, we can only observe that the position as out-lined provides no reason for drawing this conclusion. Whyshould we say that right conduct for officials of a state consistsin action that promotes the state's interests? It is not obviousthat the pursuit of self-interest by persons necessarily leads tomorally right action, and it is no more obvious in the parallelcase for officials of states. The argument involves a nonsequitur. At a minimum, what is needed to vindicate the na-tional interest view is an argument to show that following thenational interest always does produce morally right action ininternational relations.

    There is a tendency to resolve this problem by bringing inconsiderations regarding the responsibilities of political lead-ers to their constituents. Leaders should follow the nationalinterest, it might be said, because that is their obligation as

    15 W. K. Frankena, Ethics, p. 19; emphasis in original.

  • 24 A STATE OF NATURE

    holders of the people's trust. To do otherwise would be irre-sponsible.16 Leaving aside the fantasy of describing someleaders as trustees, the difficulty with this approach is that itinvolves an assumption that the people have a right to havedone for them anything that can be described as in the na-tional interest. But this is just as much in need of proof asinternational skepticism itself. In domestic affairs, few woulddisagree that what people have a right to have done for themis limited by what they have a right to do for themselves. Forexample, if people have no right to enslave ten percent oftheir number, their leaders have no right to do so for them.Why should the international actions of national leaders beany different? It seems that what leaders may rightfully do fortheir people, internationally or domestically, is limited bywhat the people may rightfully do for themselves. But if thisis true, then the responsibility of leaders to their constituentsis not necessarily to follow the national interest wherever itleads, without regard to the moral considerations that wouldconstrain groups of individuals in their mutual interactions.The appeal to the responsibilities of leaders does not showthat it is always right for leaders to pursue the national in-terest.

    Faced with the charge that the national interest as an ulti-mate standard is indifferent to larger moral values (e.g., theglobal interest or the welfare of the disadvantaged else-where), realists often expand the definition of the national in-terest to include these larger values. For example, Morgen-thau claims at some points that the national interest of apower must be constrained by its own morality.17 Apparentlyhe means that the calculations that enter into the identifica-

    16 See, for example, Arthur Schlesinger, Jr., "The Necessary Amorality ofForeign Affairs," pp. 72-73.

    17 Morgenthau, In Defense of the National Interest, pp. 36-37; see also his let-ter to the editor of International Affairs, There is a similar claim in Thompson,Political Realism, p. 167. In the context of policy questions, Morgenthau ismore straightforward. For example, in a discussion of U.S. policy toward In-dochina, he writes that intervention is justified whenever it advances decisionmakers' best judgments of the national interest, notwithstanding the custom-ary prohibition of interventionary diplomacy in international law and moral-ity. "To Intervene or Not to Intervene," p. 430.

  • SKEPTICISM OF THE REALISTS 25

    tion of the national interest should include the relevant moralconsiderations. This maneuver seems to allow him to main-tain the skeptical thesis (i.e., that the rule "follow the nationalinterest" is the first principle of international conduct) whileavoiding the non sequitur noted above. But it is hard to be-lieve that any serious skeptic would be satisfied with such a re-vised national interest view. What the skeptic wants to main-tain is that the definition and pursuit of the national interest isnot subject to any moral conditions. In other words, it wouldbe inappropriate to criticize leaders on moral grounds fortheir choices of foreign policy goals and means. Now supposethat Morgenthau's revised view were accepted, but that aleader mistakenly failed to include in his calculations identify-ing the national interest the relevant moral considerations.Then, apparently, the leader's conception of the national in-terest could be criticized on moral grounds, a possibility thatthe skeptic wants to avoid. Morgenthau's claim that the na-tional interest of a power must be constrained by its own mo-rality seems to be an ad hoc concession to a position inconsis-tent with his own skepticism. A consistent skepticism aboutinternational ethics must maintain that there are no moral re-strictions on a state's definition of its own interests, that is,that a state is always morally justified in acting to promote itsperceived interests. The problem is to explain how this posi-tion can be maintained without endorsing a general skepti-cism about all morality.

    In response to this challenge, the international skepticmight claim that certain peculiar features of the internationalorder make moral judgments inappropriate. National sover-eignty is often claimed to be such a feature. On this view,states are not subject to international moral requirements be-cause they represent separate and discrete political orderswith no common authority among them. Jean Bodin is some-times interpreted as arguing in this way. He writes, for exam-ple, "[T]here are none on earth, after God, greater thansovereign princes, whom God establishes as His lieutenants tocommand the rest of mankind."18 The sovereign power is

    18 Jean Bodin, Six Books of the Commonwealth [1576], I, x, p. 40.

  • 26 A STATE OF NATURE

    exercised "simply and absolutely" and "cannot be subject tothe commands of another, for it is he who makes law for thesubject."19 Such a sovereign is bound by obligations to othersovereigns only if the obligations result from voluntaryagreements made or endorsed by the sovereigns them-selves.20

    Bodin tempers his view with the claim that even princesought to follow natural reason and justice.21 He distinguishesbetween "true kings" and "despots" according to whetherthey follow the "laws of nature."22 While the discussion inwhich this distinction is drawn concerns what we might callinternal sovereigntyroughly, a prince's legal authority overhis own subjectsone might infer that a sovereign ruler'sconduct with respect to other sovereignties might be ap-praised on the same standard. This would give moral judg-ment a foothold in international relations, but such apprais-als, in Bodin's view, would lack one feature that seemsessential to full-fledged moral judgment. This featureemerges when a comparison is made between internationaland internal sovereignty. While it is possible for sovereignrulers to break the natural law, this would not justify subjectsopposing their rulers because there is no superior authorityto which appeal can be made to decide the issue.23 Analo-gously in the international case, one might argue (althoughBodin is silent on this matter) that no prince can justify oppo-sition to the policies of another prince on the grounds that thelatter has violated natural law, because there is no commonauthority capable of resolving the moral conflict. Notice thatthis is not to say that no prince can ever justify opposition tothe policies of others; it merely makes moral (i.e., natural law)justifications inappropriate.

    My interest here is in the suggestion that the absence of acommon judge provides a reason for skepticism about inter-national morality. It is clear that on some (particularlypositivist) views of jurisprudence, the absence of a common

    19 Ibid., viii, pp. 27-28. 20 Ibid., p. 29.21 Ibid., pp. 33-34. 22 Ibid., II, iii, p. 59.23 Ibid., v, p. 67.

  • THE HOBBESIAN SITUATION 27

    judge shows that there is no positive law.24 But, even if wegrant the positivists' claim that there is no genuine interna-tional law, it is difficult to see why the fact of competing na-tional sovereignties should entail there being no sense at all inmoral evaluation of international action. We do not make suchstringent demands on domestic affairs; there are many areasof interpersonal and social relations that are not subject tolegal regulation but about which we feel that moral evaluationwould be meaningful. Furthermore, in principle, it does notseem that the idea of a common judge plays a role in moralityanalogous to its role in law. Even if we do assume that there isa correct answer to every moral question, we do not assumethat there is a special office or authority responsible for pro-viding the answer.25

    This is not enough to establish the possibility of interna-tional morality, however, for someone might say that it is notsimply sovereignty, but certain special features of an order ofsovereign states, that makes international morality impossi-ble. A similar recourse is available to proponents of the viewthat the perceived national interest is the supreme value ininternational politics. In comparing international relations tothe state of nature, Hobbes produced such an argument. Be-cause it is the strongest argument available for skepticismabout international normative principles, I shall consider it atlength in the following sections.

    2. The Hobbesian Situation

    HE most powerful argument that has been given forinternational skepticism pictures international relations as

    a state of nature. For example, Raymond Aron writes: "Sincestates have not renounced taking the law into their own handsand remaining sole judges of what their honor requires, the

    24 For this argument applied to international law, see John Austin, TheProvince of Jurisprudence Determined [1832], lecture 6, pp. 193-94, 200-1.

    25 Compare Henry Sidgwick, The Elements of Politics [1891], XV, sec. 1, pp.238-41.

    T

  • 28 A STATE OF NATURE

    survival of political units depends, in the final analysis, on thebalance of forces, and it is the duty of statesmen to be con-cerned, first of all, with the nation whose destiny is entrustedto them. The necessity of national egoism derives logicallyfrom what philosophers called the state of nature which rulesamong states."26 The necessity (or "duty") to follow the na-tional interest is dictated by a rational appreciation of the factthat other states will do the same, using force when necessary,in a manner unrestrained by a consideration of the interestsof other actors or of the international community.

    The idea that international relations is a state of nature iscommon in modern political theory, particularly in the writ-ings of modern natural law theorists.27 It makes a difference,as we shall see, which version of this idea one adopts as thebasis for understanding the role of morality in internationalaffairs. Since most contemporary writers (like Aron)28 followHobbes's account, we shall begin there.

    According to Hobbes, the state of nature is defined by theabsence of a political authority sufficiently powerful to assurepeople security and the means to live a felicitous life. Hobbesholds that there can be no effective moral principles in thestate of nature. I use "effective" to describe principles withwhich agents have an obligation to conform their actions; ef-fective principles oblige, in Hobbes's phrase, "in foro externo"and are not merely principles that should regulate a pre-ferred world but do not apply directly to the actual world.Principles of the latter sort oblige "in foro interno" and requireus only to "desire, and endeavor" that the world were suchthat conformity with them would have a rational justifica-tion.29

    In Hobbes's view, one has reason to do something (likeadhere to moral norms) if doing the thing is likely to promote

    26 Raymond Aron, Peace and War, p. 580; emphasis in original.27 See the references in Otto von Gierke, Natural Law and the Theory of Soci-

    ety, vol. 2, p. 288, note 1.28 Aron, Peace and War, p. 72.29 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan [1651], ch. 15, p. 145; compare Hobbes, Phil-

    osophical Rudiments concerning Government and Society [De Cive] [1651], III, sec.33, PP. 49-50.

  • THE HOBBESIAN SITUATION 29

    one's interests, in particular, one's overriding interests inavoiding death and securing a felicitous life. Morality is a sys-tem of rules that promote each person's overriding interests,and hence to which each person has reason to adhere, onlywhen everyone (or almost everyone) complies with them. Inother words, a condition of the rationality of acting on moralrules is that one have adequate assurance of the complianceof others.30 Hobbes thinks that adequate assurance of recip-rocal compliance with moral rules can only be provided by agovernment with power to reward compliance and punishnoncompliance. Where there is no such assuranceas in thestate of nature, where there is no governmentthere is noreason to comply. Instead, there is a very good reason not tocomply, namely, one's own survival, which would be threat-ened if, for example, one abstained from harming otherswhile they did not observe the same restraint.

    Hobbes gives two accounts of why the state of nature issufficiently dangerous to render compliance with moral re-strictions unreasonable. In the earlier works (Human Natureand De Cive) he relies heavily on the psychological assumptionthat people will be moved by the love of glory to contend withothers for preeminence.31 In Leviathan, he develops anotheraccount which relies less on substantive psychological assump-tions and more on uncertainty. Here the claim is that some(perhaps only a few) people in the state of nature will be seek-ers after glory, but that prudent persons aware of this factwould become "diffident," distrustful, and competitive, al-ways ready to protect themselves by all means available.32 Onboth accounts the outcome is the state of war, "a tract of time,wherein the will to contend by battle is sufficiently known."33In such an unstable situation it would be irrational to restrictone's behavior according to moral rules, "for that were to ex-pose himself to prey, which no man is bound to."34 Thus,

    30 Hobbes, Leviathan, ch. 11, p. 85, and ch. 14, pp. 116-17.31 Hobbes, Human Nature [1650], ch. 9, pp. 40-41; De Cive, ch. 1, pp. 6-7.32 Hobbes, Leviathan, ch. 13, p. 111. This account also appears in the earlier

    works, although with less emphasis. See De Cive, Preface, pp. xiv-xv, and ch.1, p. 6.

    33 Hobbes, Leviathan, ch. 13, p. 113. 34 Ibid., ch. 14, p. 118.

  • 30 A STATE OF NATURE

    Hobbes concludes, in the state of nature "nothing can be un-just. The notions of right and wrong, justice and injusticehave there no place."35

    Some commentators have thought this conclusion toohasty. For, they point out, Hobbes allows that covenants maybe made in the state of nature, and that some such covenantsgive rise to binding obligations to perform even when per-formance cannot be shown to be in the interest of the agent.In particular, Hobbes says that covenants are binding on aperson not only "where there is a power to make him per-form," but also "where one of the parties has performed al-ready."36 Since Hobbes's definition of justice is the perform-ance of covenants, it seems that he is committed to the viewthat justice does have a place in the state of nature, at least incases involving covenants "where one of the parties has per-formed already." This position receives additional textualsupport from Hobbes's discussion of the ransomed soldier, inwhich he claims that such a soldier, having been released onpromise of subsequent payment of a ransom, thereby incursan obligation to make good on the promise even though theremay be no common power to enforce it.37

    These passages have led some to think that Hobbes doesnot hold what might be called a prudential theory of obliga-tion, for he seems to say that there are cases in which one hasan obligation to perform as one has agreed even though sup-porting reasons of self-interest are absent.38 This is a difficultposition to maintain since it is in direct conflict with other por-tions of Hobbes's text. For example, he claims, without qual-ification, that "covenants without the sword, are but words,and of no strength to secure a man at all."39 Furthermore,Hobbes's own justification of the claim about covenants whereone of the parties has performed already rests on clearly pru-dential arguments.40 While I cannot argue this issue at length,I believe that these textual considerations, taken togetherwith Hobbes's psychological egoism, support the view that his

    35 Ibid., ch. 13, p. 115. 36 Ibid., ch. 15, p. 133.37 Ibid., ch. 14, pp. 126-27.38 See, for example, Brian Barry, "Warrender and his Critics."39 Hobbes, Leviathan, ch. 17, p. 153. 40 Ibid., ch. 15, pp. 133-34.

  • THE HOBBESIAN SITUATION 31

    theory of obligation is purely prudential; people have no ob-ligation to perform actions when performance cannot beshown to advance their (long-range) self-interests.41

    To say that persons situated in the state of nature have noobligation to follow moral principles is not to say that thereare no such principles. Indeed, Hobbes proposes nineteen"laws of nature" as the constitutive principles of "the truemoral philosophy."42 These principles are such that it is in theinterests of each person that everyone abide by them. Hobbesargues that life in a society effectively regulated by the laws ofnature would be infinitely preferable to life in the state of na-ture, since, in the state of nature, where no one has an obliga-tion to restrict his actions according to moral principles, "thelife of man" is "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short."43The problem posed by Hobbes's theory is how to create con-ditions in which the laws of nature would be effective, that is,would oblige "in foro externo." Hobbes thinks that a commonpower is needed to assure each person that everyone else willfollow the laws of nature. The dilemma is that creating acommon power seems to require cooperation in the state ofnature, but cooperation, on Hobbes's account, would be irra-tional there. (Who could rationally justify taking the firststep?) There appears to be no exit from the state of naturedespite the fact that any rational person in that state couldrecognize the desirability of establishing a common powerand bringing the state of nature to a close. Thus, while thereare moral principles or laws of nature in the state of nature,they do not bind to action in the absence of a common power.

    International skeptics have seized on this feature ofHobbes's theory to support the view that there are no effec-tive moral obligations in international relations. This conclu-sion follows from the analogy that Hobbes himself draws be-tween international relations and the state of nature: "Butthough there had never been any time, wherein particularmen were in a condition of war one against another; yet in alltimes, kings, and persons of sovereign authority, because of

    41 For helpful discussions, see David P. Gauthier, The Logic of Leviathan, pp.57-62; and J.W.N. Watkins, Hobbes's System of Ideas, pp. 55-64.

    42 Hobbes, Leviathan, ch. 15, p. 146. 43 Ibid., ch. 13, p. 113.

  • 32 A STATE OF NATURE

    their independency, are in continual jealousies, and in thestate and posture of gladiators; having their weapons point-ing, and their eyes fixed on one another; that is, their forts,garrisons, and guns upon the frontiers of their kingdoms;and continual spies upon their neighbors; which is a postureof war."44 In such a situation, each state is at liberty to seek itsown interest unrestrained by any higher moral requirements:"[I]n states, and commonwealths not dependent on oneanother, every commonwealth, not every man, has an abso-lute liberty, to do what it shall judge, that is to say, what thatman, or assembly that representeth it, shall judge most con-ducing to their benefit."45 Supposing that moral rules cannotrequire a man (or a nation) to do that which he (or it) has noreason to do, the argument holds that it is irrational to adhereto moral rules in the absence of a reliable expectation thatothers will do the same.

    This seems to be the strongest argument that the skepticcan advance, because it is based on the plausible intuition thatconformity to moral rules must be reasonable from the pointof view of the agent in order to represent a binding require-ment. When the agents are persons, the force of this intuitioncan be questioned on the ground that other things than self-interest can come into the definition of rationality. A success-ful counterargument of this kind results in the view that somesacrifices of self-interest might be rational when necessary toachieve other goods. But this kind of counterargument is notas obviously available when the agents are states, since it canbe argued that, as a matter of fact, there is far less assurancethat states would sacrifice their perceived interests to achieveother goals.46 Thus, even if Hobbesian skepticism about indi-

    44 Ibid., p. 115. See also De Cive, Preface, p. xv; and De Corpore Politico[1650], II, ch. 10, p. 228.

    45 Hobbes, Leviathan, ch. 21, p. 201. Compare ch. 30, p. 342: "[E]verysovereign hath the same right, in procuring the safety of his people, that anyparticular man can have, in procuring the safety of his own body. And thesame law, that dictateth to men that have no civil government, what theyought to do, and what to avoid in regard of one another, dictateth the same tocommonwealths."

    46 Compare Edward Hallett Carr, The Twenty Years' Crisis, 1919-1939, pp.166-69.

  • THE HOBBESIAN SITUATION 33

    vidual ethics in the absence of government is rejected, itmight still move us to deny the possibility of effective regula-tive principles for the conduct of nations.47

    It is important to be clear about the conclusion to which theskeptic is committed by this argument. The conclusion fol-lows from applying Hobbes's theory of obligation to interna-tional relations. Accordingly, we might reformulate theconclusion as the claim that the officials of states have no obli-gation to conform their official actions in international affairsto moral principles. Such principles are not effective whenthere are no reliable expectations of reciprocal compliance.However, this is not to say that it would not be desirable for allstates (or their officials) to conform their actions to certainprinciples, or that some such principles, analogous toHobbes's law of nature, cannot be formulated. It is only tosay, to repeat Hobbes's phrase, that whatever internationalprinciples exist apply "in foro interno" but not "in foro externo."

    As I have said, the moral problem posed by Hobbes'stheory is how to create conditions in which the laws of naturewould be effective. Characterizing international relations as astate of nature poses a similar moral problem. If internationalrelations is a state of nature, it follows that no state has an ob-ligation to comply with regulative principles analogous to thelaws of nature. But it also follows that widespread compliancewith such principles would be desirable from the point ofview of each state.48 Carrying through the analogy with the

    47 This seems to have been Rousseau's view. See "L'tat de guerre" [1896;written 1753-1755?], pp. 297-99. Perhaps this explains the hesitation aboutquestions of international political theory expressed in The Social Contract. SeeDu contrat social [1762], III, xvi, p. 98, note 2, and IV, ix, p. 134.

    48 Apparently Hobbes recognized that this would follow from his owncharacterization of international relations as a state of nature, but he did notargue for an international Leviathan. Perhaps the reason is his view that,since states in a posture of war "uphold thereby, the industry of their sub-jects; there does not follow from it, that misery, which accompanies the lib-erty of particular men." (Leviathan, ch. 13, p. 115.) To say the least, it is notobvious that this claim is empirically accurate. Furthermore, even if it is cor-rect, it would not follow that international agreement on regulative principlesfor nations is not desirable, but only that such agreement is less urgent thanthe analogous agreement to institute civil government.

  • 34 A STATE OF NATURE

    state of nature therefore raises two further questions: what isthe content of the principles it would be desirable for everystate to accept? How can conditions be brought about suchthat it would be in the interests of each state to comply withthese principles?

    That such questions arise as a consequence of the charac-terization of international relations as a state of nature maysuggest that the skeptics are inconsistent in invoking thischaracterization to support their view. For the first questionpresupposes that it would be desirable that conditions becreated in which states would have reason to comply with cer-tain normative principles, and the second question at leastsuggests that it is possible to create such conditions. From thisone might argue that states have an obligation to do what theycan to establish the requisite conditions, at least when they cando so without unacceptable risk. If this is true, then interna-tional skepticism is false, since it would not be the case thatstates are not subject to any moral requirements.

    Hobbes does not posit an effective obligation to escape theinterpersonal state of nature because the actions necessary toescape from it are inconsistent with the actions required forself-preservation within it. To defend international skepti-cism against the difficulty noted above, one would have toargue that international relations, like the state of nature, in-volves conditions such that the actions needed to establish aneffective international morality are inconsistent with the ac-tions required for the preservation of states. In that case itwould follow that states are not subject to any binding moralrequirements. And, while it would still be the case that con-formity with appropriate international normative principleswould be desirable, it would be academic to inquire abouttheir content since there would be no way of rendering themeffective.

  • A STATE OF NATURE 35

    3. International Relations as aState of Nature

    T HE application of Hobbes's conception of the state of na-ture to international relations serves two different func-tions in the argument for international skepticism. First, itprovides an analytical model that explains war as the result ofstructural properties of international relations.49 It producesthe conclusion that conflict among international actors willissue in a state of war ("a tract of time, wherein the will to con-tend by battle is sufficiently known") in the absence of asuperior power capable of enforcing regulative rules. Second,the state of nature provides a model of the concept of moraljustification that explains how normative principles for inter-national relations should be justified. This explanation holdsthat since the basis of a state's compliance with moral rules isits rational self-interest, the justification of such rules mustappeal to those interests states hold in common.

    These two uses of the idea of an international state of na-ture are distinct because one leads to predictions about statebehavior whereas the other leads to prescriptions. While thetwo uses are related in the sense that the predictions that re-sult from the first use are taken as premises for the second,they should be separated for purposes of evaluation and criti-cism. In the first case, we need to ask whether the Hobbesiandescription of international relations is empirically accept-able: do the facts warrant application of this predictive modelto international behavior? Our question in the second case isdifferent: does Hobbes's state of nature give a correct accountof the justification of moral principles for the internationalrealm?

    Let us look first at the predictive use of Hobbes's interna-tional state of nature. The description of international rela-

    49 In this sense, Hobbes uses the state of nature to give what Kenneth Waltzhas called a "third image" account of the causes of warthat is, an accountbased on the image of international anarchy. See Man, the State, and War, pp.159-86, in which Waltz concentrates on the third-image explanations givenby Spinoza and Rousseau.

  • 36 A STATE OF NATURE

    tions as a state of nature leads to the conclusion that a state ofwar will obtain among international actors in the absence of asuperior power capable of enforcing regulative rules againstany possible violator. As I have suggested, this conclusion isrequired as one premise in the argument for internationalskepticism, for, on a Hobbesian view, the reason that no actorhas an obligation to follow rules of cooperation is the lack ofassurance that other actors will do the same. Indeed, eachactor has a reason not to follow such rules, since, in a state ofwar, an actor might rationally expect to be taken advantage ofby other actors in the system if it were unilaterally to followcooperative rules. Even if we accept Hobbes's conception ofmorality, for international skepticism to be a convincing posi-tion it must be the case that international relations is analo-gous to the state of nature in the respects relevant to the pre-diction that a state of nature regularly issues in a state of war.

    For this analogy to be acceptable, at least four propositionsmust be true:

    1. The actors in international relations are states.2. States have relatively equal power (the weakest can

    defeat the strongest).3. States are independent of each other in the sense that

    they can order their internal (i.e., nonsecurity) affairsindependently of the internal policies of other actors.

    4. There are no reliable expectations of reciprocal com-pliance by the actors with rules of cooperation in theabsence of a superior power capable of enforcing theserules.

    If these conditions are not met by international relations,then the analogy between international relations and the stateof nature does not hold, and the prediction that internationalrelations is a state of war does not necessarily follow.

    I shall argue that contemporary international relationsdoes not meet any of these conditions. Let us begin with thefirst. It establishes the analogy between the state of natureand international relations by identifying states as the actorsin international relations just as individuals are the actors in

  • A STATE OF NATURE 37

    the interpersonal state of nature. This may seem so obvious asnot to deserve mention, but it is very important for the skep-tic's argument that this condition actually obtain. The radicalindividualism of Hobbes's state of nature helps to make plaus-ible the prediction of a resulting state of war because it deniesthe existence of any other actors (secondary associations,functional groups, economic institutions, or extended fami-lies, to name a few examples) that might mediate interper-sonal conflict, coordinate individuals' actions, insulate indi-viduals from the competition of others, share risks, or en-courage the formation of less competitive attitudes. The viewthat states are the only actors in international relations deniesthe possibility of analogous international conflict-minimizingcoalitions, alliances, and secondary associations. Since it is ob-viously true that such coalitions have existed at various timesin the history of international relations, one might say flatlythat international relations does not resemble the state of na-ture in this important respect.50

    The difficulty with this claim is that Hobbes himself allowsfor the possibility of coalitions and alliances in the interper-sonal state of nature.51 However, he argues that these wouldnot be stable. They would, if anything, increase the chances ofviolence among coalitions, and the shared interests thatwould lead to their formation would not be long lasting.52

    One might make similar claims to defend the analogy ofinternational relations and the state of nature, but it is not ob-vious that the claims would be empirically correct. Some al-liances appear to confirm Hobbes's hypothesis that formingalliances increases the chances of war, despite the fact that al-liances are often viewed as mechanisms for stabilizing a bal-ance of power and making credible the threat to retaliate onattack.53 On the other hand, several types of coalitions haveproduced opposite results. For example, regional politicaland economic organizations appear to have played significant

    50 Oran Young, "The Actors in World Politics."51 Hobbes, Leviathan, ch. 17, pp. 154-55. 52 Ibid.53 See, for example, J. David Singer and Melvin Small, "Alliance Aggrega-

    tion and the Onset of War, 1815-1914."

  • 38 A STATE OF NATURE

    roles in the nonviolent resolution of international conflicts.They have also made it easier for national leaders to perceivetheir common interests in peace and stability.54 The sameseems true, although in a more limited range of circum-stances, of global international organizations like the UnitedNations.55 To Hobbes's view that coalitions (and, by exten-sion, universal organizations short of world government) areunlikely to be long lasting, it can only be replied that the im-portant question is how long any particular conflict-mini-mizing coalition is likely to endure. Clearly, one should notexpect such coalitions to persist forever, but it is historicallydemonstrable that some coalitions have enjoyed life spanssufficiently long to defeat the claim that they have made nosignificant contribution to peace and cooperation.

    The view that states are the only actors in international re-lations also denies the possibility that transnational associa-tions of persons might have common interests that wouldmotivate them to exert pressures for cooperation on their re-spective national governments. The view does so by obscuringthe fact that states, unlike persons, are aggregations of units(persons and secondary associations) that are capable ofindependent political action. These units might be groupedaccording to other criteria than citizenship, for example,according to interests that transcend national boundaries.When such interests exist, one would expect that transna-tional interest groups or their functional equivalents mightexert pressures on their respective governments to favorpolicies that advance the groups' shared interests.

    Since the second world war, the number, variety, mem-bership, and importance of transnational groups have all in-creased, in some cases dramatically.56 Early academic atten-tion to transnational interests focused on groups of specialists

    54 Joseph S. Nye, Jr., Peace in Parts, chs. 4-5.55 Ernst B. Haas, Robert L. Butterworth, and Joseph S. Nye, Jr., Conflict

    Management by International Organizations, esp. pp. 56-61.56 The most useful survey of the growth of transnationalism is provided by

    the essays in Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye, Jr., eds., TransnationalRelations and World Politics.

  • A STATE OF NATURE 39

    (economists, labor leaders) and on functionally specific trans-national organizations (the World Meteorological Organiza-tion, European Coal and Steel Community) and hypothesizedthat successful collaboration with respect to some functionswould promote by a process of social learning collaborationwith respect to other functions. The resulting progressiveenlargement of areas of transnational collaboration was ex-pected to undermine international political conflict by mak-ing clear to domestic constituencies and decision makers theextent of transnationally shared interests.57 Subsequent ex-perience has failed to corroborate the early functionalists' hy-pothesis for all cases of functional collaboration, but there areparticular cases in which the hypothesized social-learningprocess has taken root.58

    Although the central hypothesis of the theory of functionalintegration has been discredited, the insight that transna-tional interest groups might alter the outcomes of interna-tional politics by exerting pressures on national governmentpolicy making has not. In fact, the effectiveness of suchgroups in promoting their interests at the national level hasbeen illustrated in several quite different areas. Two impor-tant examples of politically effective transnational groups aremultinational corporations and informal, transnationalgroups of middle-level government bureaucrats. In each case,although to very different extents, it is clear that transnation-ally shared interests have sometimes led to substantial pres-sures on government foreign policy decisions.59 As the dif-ficulties of integration theory suggest, it should not beinferred that the effect of rapidly increasing transnational po-

    57 The most influential early statement of this view is David Mitrany, AWorking Peace System. There is a revised formulation in Ernst B. Haas, Beyondthe Nation-State, part 1. For a review of the more recent literature, see MichaelHaas, "International Integration."

    58 See James Patrick Sewell, Functionalism and World Politics, parts 1 and 3;and Ernst B. Haas, "The Study of Regional Integration."

    59 See, on multinational corporations, Joseph S. Nye, Jr., "MultinationalCorporations in World Politics," pp. 155-59, and the references cited there;and, on interbureaucracy contacts, Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye,Jr., "Transgovernmental Relations and International Organizations."

  • 40 A STATE OF NATURE

    litical activity is necessarily to minimize the chances of inter-national conflict or to promote international cooperation,because a variety of other factors is involved.60 In particular,transnational political activity is unlikely to promote interna-tional cooperation in the absence of perceptions by nationaldecision makers of significant shared interests that would jus-tify such cooperation.61 The theoretical importance of therise of transnational politics lies elsewhere. It lies in the factthat nation-states can no longer be regarded as the only, or asthe ultimate, actors in international relations, since theiractions may be influenced significantly by pressures fromgroups that represent transnational interests. Depending onthe strength and extent of these interests, this new element ofcomplexity in international relations renders problematic theHobb