Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

download Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

of 22

Transcript of Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    1/22

    Re-framing Democracy

    and Agency in IndiaInterrogating Political Society

    Edited by

    Ajay Gudavarthy

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    2/22

    Anthem Press

    An imprint of Wimbledon Publishing Company

    www.anthempress.com

    This edition first published in UK and USA 2012by ANTHEM PRESS

    75-76 Blackfriars Road, London SE1 8HA, UK

    or PO Box 9779, London SW19 7ZG, UK

    and

    244 Madison Ave. #116, New York, NY 10016, USA

    2012 Ajay Gudavarthy editorial matter and selection;

    individual chapters individual contributors

    The moral right of the authors has been asserted.

    All rights reserved. Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above,

    no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored or introduced into

    a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means

    (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise),

    without the prior written permission of both the copyright

    owner and the above publisher of this book.

    British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data

    A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    Re-framing democracy and agency in India : interrogating political society / edited by

    Ajay Gudavarthy.

    p. cm.

    Includes bibliographical references.

    ISBN 978-0-85728-350-4 (hardback : alk. paper)

    1. DemocracyIndia. 2. Political participationIndia.

    3. Civil societyIndia. 4. PostcolonialismIndia. I. Gudavarthy, Ajay.

    JQ281.R43 2012

    320.954dc23

    2012000946

    ISBN-13: 978 0 85728 350 4 (Hbk)

    ISBN-10: 0 85728 350 2 (Hbk)

    This title is also available as an eBook.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    3/22

    CONTENTS

    Preface and Acknowledgements ix

    List of Tables xi

    Chapter 1 Introduction: Why Interrogate Political Society? 1

    Ajay Gudavarthy

    Part I: Political Society and Protest Politics

    Chapter 2 Political Society in a Capitalist World 31

    Swagato Sarkar

    Chapter 3 Antinomies of Political Society Implicationsof Uncivil Development 49

    Ajay Gudavarthy and G. Vijay

    Chapter 4 Civil Society and the Urban Poor 73

    Supriya RoyChowdhury

    Chapter 5 Contentious Politics and Civil Society in Varanasi 93

    Jolie M. F. Wood

    Chapter 6 The Politics of a Political Society 125Ranabir Samaddar

    Part II: Political Society, Middlemen and Mobility

    Chapter 7 The Pyraveekar: The Fixer in Rural India 155

    G. Ram Reddy and G. Haragopal

    Chapter 8 Politics of Middlemen and Political Society 171

    Stuart Corbridge, Glyn Williams, Manoj Srivastavaand Ren Vron

    Chapter 9 Widows Organizations in Kerala State, India: Seeking

    Citizenship amidst the Decline of Political Society 201

    J. Devika and A. K. Rajasree

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    4/22

    viii RE-FRAMING DEMOCRACY AND AGENCY IN INDIA

    Part III: Civil Society and/or Political Society

    Chapter 10 Clubbing Together: Village Clubs, Local NGOs

    and the Mediations of Political Society 235

    Tom Harrison

    Chapter 11 Civic Anxieties and Dalit Democratic Culture:

    Balmikis in Delhi 253

    Omar Kutty

    Chapter 12 The Habits of the Political Heart: Recovering Politics

    from Governmentality 269

    Aparna SundarandNandini Sundar

    Chapter 13 Civil Society in the East and Some Dark Thoughts

    about the Prospects of Political Society 289

    Sanjeeb Mukherjee

    Part IV: Rejoinder

    Chapter 14 The Debate over Political Society 305

    Partha Chatterjee

    List of Contributors 323

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    5/22

    Chapter 2POLITICAL SOCIETY INA CAPITALIST WORLD1

    Swagato Sarkar

    Partha Chatterjee is one of the very few scholars in India who have

    systematically tried to theorize the specificity of Indian democratic politics.

    His conceptualization of political society can be seen as an approach to

    explicate the latters logics. This conceptualization has been modified and

    refined over the years by mediating on the concrete historical experience of

    a post-colonial country and through a critical engagement with the received

    Western normative political theory. In this paper, I will first provide a sketch

    of Chatterjees criticism of the concept of civil society, and then present a

    critical review of his concept of political society. I will focus on the three

    tension-ridden components of his project, viz. the defence of a communal

    way of life, mapping the differentiated political space, and a suspicion towards

    constitutionalism. I will argue, against Chatterjee, that the concept of political

    society does not denote a positive political development, that is, it does not

    present a possibility for substantially redefining property and law in favour

    of subaltern people/classes or the actual expansion of the freedoms of thepeople; rather, it should be used to provide a critical insight into Indian

    politics, particularly in relation to the process of capitalist expansion and

    differentiation.

    Chatterjees Critique of Civil Society

    It is well known that the discussion on political society is embedded in the

    debate on civil society and the critique of the conceptual infrastructureof Western normative theory. In this debate, normatively, civil society has

    1 This paper is a modified and expanded form of a paper published in 2008 (Sarkar

    2008).

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    6/22

    32 RE-FRAMING DEMOCRACY AND AGENCY IN INDIA

    been identified as a domain for the expansion and realization of rights

    and freedom (Cohen and Arato 1992), and instrumentally, it is seen as

    a domain wherein the distribution, exercise and control of power are

    (democratically) contested (Nonan-Ferrell 2004). With these two domainstaken together, civil society is an integral part of democracy and a

    placeholder of institutions.

    I will argue that Partha Chatterjees critique of Western normative theory

    and civil society is primarily a critique of the subject (that is, citizen) that this

    theory supposes. His critique draws attention to the interpellative structure

    and the criteria of membership of the institutions proposed/assumed by this

    theory, namely, the erasure of difference in favour of formal equality and

    freedom (Chatterjee 2004). The effect of this formal interpellation is that the

    state in its conduct can recognize or favour citizens only as unencumbered

    individuals, severed of any primordial ties a product of Western humanism

    and secularism. Since the primordial identities of the citizens are not invoked

    or referred to, they are rendered homogeneous before the state, namely, as

    a nation. It is the will of the citizens, expressed as their generalized political

    aspiration and popular sovereignty, which gives legitimacy to the state and

    forms the basis of democracy.

    Here, Chatterjee posits the concrete post-colonial context against the

    normative concept of civil society, and argues that only a handful of the elitesin post-colonial countries can meet such a criterion of citizenship. These

    elites are a product of modernity that has been inherited from colonialism,

    and can meet the demand of being unencumbered either because they are

    cultured/socialized into such a being, or can simply afford to ignore/avoid

    their primordial identities. Hence, the scope of the concept of civil society is

    restrictive. This (normative) theoretical position is also problematic because

    the concept of community, which provides meaning to most of the people in

    these countries, is suppressed and relegated to the pre-modern historical time(Chatterjee 1993, 1998, 2004). Therefore, civil society is a limited normative

    concept and an undifferentiated space.

    Put differently, Western normative theory finds only a section of the

    post-colonial society as the true bearer of modernity. One can note that,

    by foregrounding communal being (and identity), Chatterjee differentiates

    community from civil society in an ontological way, that is, a way of life

    based on a shared kinship (see below), rather than a contractual (and formal)

    associational life in civil society. He proposes to split the political space, and

    to conceptualize a domain, separate and distinct from civil society, that is,

    political society.

    Thus, the following three issues are at stake here: (i) the difference in

    ontology (/particular ways of life), (ii) the differentiation of political space, and

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    7/22

    POLITICAL SOCIETY IN A CAPITALIST WORLD 33

    (iii) the significance of formal and normative concepts vis--vis the empirical

    context. Chatterjee tries to engage with these three issues to provide a theory

    of political society which will demonstrate the democratic urge and the

    expansion of freedom of the members of political society (that is, subalterns)in India and other post-colonial countries. In other words, he attempts to

    develop a normative theory of (populist) democracy based on the experience of post-

    colonial countries like India.

    Chatterjee on Political Society

    Chatterjees advocacy for the identification of a different political space beyond

    civil society rests on three moves. First, he focuses attention on the sphere

    of governmental interventions where, he claims, a different kind of political

    engagement between the legalbureaucratic apparatus and the people who

    are excluded from civil society can be witnessed.

    The post-colonial Indian state inherited the legal-bureaucratic apparatus,

    which is able to reach as the target of many of its activities virtually all of

    the population that inhabits its territory, [whereas] the domain of civil social

    institutionsis still restricted to a fairly small section of citizens (Chatterjee

    2001, 172). According to Chatterjee, this is a new paradigm, and there is a clear

    shift from the abstract theoretical domain of citizenship to the actual domainof (public) policy. Following Foucault, he claims that the domain of policy is

    predicated upon a conception of the society as one constituted bypopulation,

    notcitizens or elementary units of homogenous families (Chatterjee 1998,

    279; 2001, 173). The regime secures legitimacy not by the participation of

    citizens in the matters of the state, but by claiming to provide for the well-

    being of the population (Chatterjee 1998, 279). Thus, Chatterjees first move

    shifts the focus of political theory from the normative category of citizen to

    the descriptive and empirical category of population.The concept of population is predicated upon an enumerable, descriptive,

    and empirical mass of people, and does not rely on a normative theory

    or abstraction. The population is assumed to contain, large elements of

    naturalness and primordiality; the internal principles of the constitution

    of particular population groups is not expected to be rationally explicable

    since they are not the products of rational contractual association, but are,

    as it were, pre-rational (Chatterjee 2001, 173 and passim). The concept

    of population offers the governmental functions and apparatus an access to

    a set of rationally manipulable instruments for reaching [a] large section of

    the inhabitants of a country as the targets of policy.

    Chatterjee makes the second move by arguing that such interventions in

    the society-as-population, if we may call it, and the interaction between these

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    8/22

    34 RE-FRAMING DEMOCRACY AND AGENCY IN INDIA

    governmental apparatus and the population groups inaugurate a new site for

    strategic manoeuvring, resistance and appropriation. Chatterjee calls this site

    political society. The strategic manoeuvre and mobilization that take place in

    this domain neither always conform, nor are consistent with, the principlesof association in civil society they often result in the transgression of law.

    Yet, Chatterjee identifies an urge for democracy in this mobilization in

    political society, as it channels the demands on the developmentalstate the state

    that looks after its people and provides benefits. Therefore, the subject at this

    stage of his argument is a subject of development.

    The third move is made by translating the subject of development into

    a political subject, by assigning an identity to it and finding a normative

    ground for it. Chatterjee is interested in exploring how people use the space

    opened by the intervention of governmental functions. As we have seen,

    such interventions perceive the society as population and then categorize the

    latter into empirical groups that become the target for policies. However,

    such categorization also infuses a new identity into the group, and many a

    time, the constituents of the group emerge as distinctpoliticalentities. These

    new groups have a territorial boundary, clearly defined in time and space

    (Chatterjee 2004, 58 and passim). Consistent with his critique of civil society

    and the foregrounding of community, Chatterjee tries to demonstrate how

    these groups become a community and thus a collective, and also findsa normative ground for the latters demands. According to him, since

    the livelihood and existence of many of the members of such groups are

    predicated upon a (collective) violation of (property) laws, they appear as

    illegal entities before the state. They are notrecognized as proper civic bodies,

    pursuing legitimate objectives. Thus, to be recognized by the governmental

    functions, they must find ways of investing their collective identity with a

    moral content (ibid., 57 and passim) and thereby give to the empirical form of a

    population group the moral attributes of a community (emphasis in original). Yet thiscommunity is about the shared interests of the members of association...

    they describe the community interms of a shared kinship the most

    common metaphoris that of a family.

    Chatterjee never spells out what he means by the moral content of an

    identity, but it seems that these new groups appropriate the proposition of the

    governments obligation to look after the poor and underprivileged population

    groups (Chatterjee 2004, 60). The objective of their mobilization is to secure

    the benefits of governmental programs (Chatterjee 2004, 66), which they

    claim as a matter of rights and use their association as the principal collective

    instrument to pursue that claim (ibid., 59). This, according to Chatterjee, is a

    clear break with the erstwhile patronclient exchanges, and an indication of

    their political assertion.

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    9/22

    POLITICAL SOCIETY IN A CAPITALIST WORLD 35

    Chatterjee explains that the mobilization which takes place on the terrain

    of political society is necessarily temporary and contextual, and depends

    entirely on the ability of particular population groups to mobilize support to

    influence the implementation of government policy in their favour (Chatterjee2004, 60, emphasis added; note implementation, notpolicyformulation, as he

    has already mentioned, The regime secures legitimacy not by the participation

    of citizens in the matters of the state, but by claiming to provide for the well-

    being of the population [Chatterjee 1998, 279]). Such strategic politics must

    operate within the constellation of the (mainstream) political formations (that

    is, parties, but also non-governmental organizations?). The success of such

    strategic manoeuvring depends on applying the right pressure at the right

    places in the governmental machinery (Chatterjee 2004, 66). However, they

    do not always have access to such right places, and therefore, to produce a

    viable and persuasive politics of the governed, there has to be considerable act

    of mediation (ibid., 64). Hence, there is a real need for finding trustworthy

    mediators who can represent them.

    It is through such political engagements that people are substantial[ly]

    redefin[ing] property and law within the actually existing modern state

    (Chatterjee 2004, 75) and are devising new ways in which they can choose how

    they should be governed... people are learning, and forcing their governors

    to learn, how they would prefer to be governed[which itself is a] goodjustification for democracy (ibid., 7778).

    A Critical Appraisal of Political Society

    As mentioned earlier, Chatterjees critique of civil society is predicated

    on the critique of the subject that Western normative theory supposes.

    Furthermore, his conceptualization of political society is predicated on the

    difference in the modes of transacting business with the constitutional state(Chatterjee 1998, 282). Thus, it is the modality of realization of rights that

    separates political society from civil society. The difference in ontology which

    Chatterjee introduced at the beginning of his critique of civil society by

    foregrounding the lived experience of a communal being, as opposed to the

    associational life of the unencumbered modern individuals in civil society

    is replaced with a critical appraisal of the procedural dimension of Indian

    democracy (involved in transacting business, as quoted above). Even though

    community is invoked in the discursive construction of the political subject,

    the successful manoeuvring (including para-legal negotiations and transgression

    and suspension of law) in political society is not dependent on that invocation;

    rather it is dependent on the majoritarian bias, as we shall later see. In sum,

    the communalassociational difference becomes untenable or insignificant

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    10/22

    36 RE-FRAMING DEMOCRACY AND AGENCY IN INDIA

    as Chatterjee carries forward his argument. While trying to explore the

    ontology of this later position, we do not find any elaboration of the concept

    of the social. Rather, Chatterjee reads social relationships and practices in

    relation to the legal-political forms of the modern state (Chatterjee 2004, 74).He engages neither with the immanent antagonisms in the social, nor with the

    quasi-transcendental conditions of the possibility and impossibility of political

    actions/interventions. To modify my last observation, I can say that, at the

    ontological level, Chatterjee posits the difference between political society and

    civil society in terms of the difference in the legal status of the entities that

    the state encounters, and the contestation and negotiations which take place

    over law, rules and norms become the focus of his analysis. It is, therefore, no

    surprise to see that the procedural dimension unfolds in terms of judging the

    legal status of the means of the chosen economic activity by, and amenities

    for physical living of, the members of political society. Political action is seen

    in terms of establishing the legal, or transgressing the illegal, status within

    the black letter (property) law (which becomes a referent point). Political space,

    then, is strictly the space of interaction between the state and the population.

    Obviously, Chatterjee sees this in a positive light.

    Chatterjee argues that as the new political entities wrangle over property

    and benefits, they also strike at the foundation of property relations. Property,

    Chatterjee reminds us, is the conceptual name of regulations by law ofrelations between individuals in civil society (Chatterjee 2004, 74 and passim).

    But as these social relations are yet to be mo[u]lded into proper forms of

    civil society, the state must maintain a fiction that in the constitution of its

    sovereignty, all citizens belong to civil society and are, by virtue of that legally

    constructed fact, equal subjects of the law. This fictional element must be

    addressed in the actual administrative processes.

    The post-colonial (Indian) state not only finds a different legal entity/subject,

    but also negotiates with it, instead of liquidating or banishing it. Accordingto Chatterjee, this negotiation does not take place because of the states

    benevolence; rather these subjectsforcethe state to do so. Therefore, a positive

    appraisal of political society is pivoted on demonstrating theagency of the people

    in forcing the state to recognize them. The normative dimension of political

    society becomes visible in terms of delineating alternative (even if contingent)

    criteria for the recognition by the state. The governmental functions and non-

    governmental agencies are forced to recognize the demands of the members of

    political society in a different way. Since, these agencies do not recognize these

    members or groups as part of civil society, so they cannot negotiate with them

    according to the formal and strict procedures and law of the land, i.e. the so-called

    autonomy of the state is not obtained here. Hence, there is a proliferation of

    layered mediations and para-legal arrangements to resolve various contentious

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    11/22

    POLITICAL SOCIETY IN A CAPITALIST WORLD 37

    issues, and to meet the demands of these groups. The governmental bodies and

    political representatives deliberate and negotiate to identify the valid claims

    (Chatterjee 2004, 69). However, such negotiations must be hidden and not

    formally recorded, as it is entirely possible that the negotiations on the grounddid not respect the principles of bureaucratic rationality or even the provisions

    of law (ibid., 73). Chatterjee appreciates this para-legal arrangement and the

    actions in political society as an act of actual expansion of the freedoms of the

    people (ibid., 66 and passim). Chatterjee argues that certain groups participate

    in political process by manoeuvring in political society, which is otherwise not

    possible within the liberal space of the associations of civil society.2 He claims

    that the transactions in political society open up the possibility to effectively

    work againstthe [existing] distribution of power in society as a whole (emphasis

    in original). This possibility, according to him, is realized through the distribution

    of property rights. He briefly refers to Amartya Sens capability approach, which

    embod[ies] a set of substantive freedoms rather than utilities or income or

    primary goods (ibid., 68) to support his claim.

    However, there is a limit to this agency argument, which also indicates

    the limit of political society. First, there is a problem of scale. In view of the

    fact that (successful) negotiations and the modalities of realization of rights

    in political society are contingent and specific to a locale the terminal stage

    of application of power the methodology (mostly ethnographic case studies)can enlighten us about micro- and capillary politics, but not about the macro

    processes. It will be difficult to induce a general condition of freedom from

    such micro-political events even though it affirms the liberal political theory

    which posits an agent (here, the governeds) who experiences freedom, in both

    the negative and positive ways, but it does not problematize the actual scale or

    type of the structural conditions. However, since Chatterjee chooses to focus

    on property relationships and welfare benefits, the structural conditions which

    make capitalist expansion possible and to what extent the members of politicalsociety can negotiate within capitalism and expand their freedom are at stake

    here. Second, Chatterjee observes that the leverage in political society is linked

    with the inherent majoritarian bias of electoral democracy (Chatterjee

    2008b, 90 and passim). Because of this bias, certain sections of the population

    are excluded from political society, producing newly marginalized groups,

    comprising of low-caste and adivasi people. Political society and electoral

    democracy have not given these groups the means to make effective claims on

    2 This participation-through-manoeuvring is not based on a communal way of life, that

    is, it is not a question of the communal way of life helping in the formation of a group,

    analogous to the concept of class-in-itself. Successful manoeuvring depends on access

    to mediators, as we will see below.

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    12/22

    38 RE-FRAMING DEMOCRACY AND AGENCY IN INDIA

    governmentality. In this sense, these marginalized groups represent an outside

    beyond the boundaries of political society.3 This third space (after civil and

    political societies) is a new category in Chatterjees writing, which John and

    Deshpande (2008, 85) call the liminal zone. Two points need to be notedhere: first, the project (of political geography) to delineate and exhaustively

    map the differentiated political space is under threat as we continuously need

    to conceive new categories to capture this spatial differentiation exhaustively

    there is always a space which remains outside (here, liminal zone). Second,

    the possibility of negotiation and transgression of law with impunity is

    perhaps linked to this majoritarian bias and the related capacity to form a

    nexus between the elite and subaltern. As I mentioned earlier, the successful

    manoeuvring in political society is not dependent on the communal way of

    life; if it were so, then the stronger communal life of adivasi people would

    have secured them a place in political society. Therefore, we need to question

    Chatterjees communitarian and post-modernist (/post-Marxist?) suspicion

    towards law and constitutionalism, and argue that law, rules and norms can be

    both emancipatory, on one hand, and repressive and disciplinary, on the other.

    In other words, the transgression of law and contingent para-legal negotiations

    cannot solely secure the emancipatory possibility (that is, the actual expansion

    of freedom) for the members of political society, as Chatterjee argues. In the

    next section, I will elaborate and dwell upon these critical issues.

    Political Society as a Critique

    Here, it is pertinent to ask why Chatterjee theorizes political society in

    a statist/state-centric and legalistic way. It might be helpful to refer to the

    original concept of governmentality to understand that impulse. While

    developing the concept of political society, particularly in terms of the politics

    of the governed, Chatterjee selectively draws from the Foucauldian conceptof governmentality. Governmentality, as we know, denotes the generalized

    governmental rationality, beyondthat of the state. Methodologically, it studies

    the strategic field of application of power, whose problematic is: [H]ow

    best to govern[?] (OMalley et al. 1997, 502). Governmentality is about

    the organization of resources and institutions, and establishment of norms

    and practices, among other things, and about justifying this constellation.

    Thereby, as we know, power assumes a productive dimension, rather than a

    3 Samir Kumar Das argues that there are sections of the population that escape the

    calculative logic of enumeration and thereby they become the ungoverneds. But it is

    not clear why this should be the case, that is, the kind of logical inconsistency or limit

    of governmentality involved here is not readily understood.

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    13/22

    POLITICAL SOCIETY IN A CAPITALIST WORLD 39

    negative and repressive one. Thomas Lemke argues that the salient feature of

    Foucaults conceptualization of governmentality is that it links technologies

    of the self with technologies of domination, the constitution of the subject to

    the formation of the state; and finally, it helps to differentiate between powerand domination (Lemke 2002, 51).

    Governmentrefers to more or less systematized, regulated and reflected

    modes of power (a technology) that go beyond the spontaneous

    exercise of power over others, following a specific form of reasoning (a

    rationality) which defines the telos of action or the adequate means to

    achieve it. (Lemke 2002, 53)

    And thereby, structuring and shaping the field of possible action of subjects

    (ibid., 52).

    In Chatterjees conceptualization of political society and the case studies

    that he engages with, we never see the interlinkage between the technologies

    of the self and technologies of domination. As mentioned earlier, what

    comes out is the politicization of the process of surveying and categorization

    (which are not exactly the technologies of domination) of the population,

    that is, people use the very categories that are generated or used in surveys and

    censuses (which again are not exactly the technologies of the self ), to stakeclaims on the state. Read in this way, Chatterjees notion of the governed

    as a subject of political society is nominal, and the process of subjection to

    power in the domain of governmental/public policy which is the premise

    of Chatterjees argument does not end up producing/constructing any

    subjectivity as such. And this happens, because governmentality is played out

    in India exclusively within the body politic of the state, not beyondthe latter.4

    My statement might seem to be contradictory to Chatterjees (2008b, 93) later

    claim that governmental power...is no longer restricted to the branches ofthe statebut extends to a host of non-state and even non-governmental

    agencies. Chatterjee does not define governmental power explicitly; however,

    it is evident that he sees governmental power to be beyond the state from the

    standpoint of the institutional space of application of power, but not from the

    problematic of subject, subjectivity5 and rationality.

    In Chatterjees writings, governmentality is just an alternative way of

    understanding the interaction of the Indian state with the population, and

    4 One can observe the nascent attempts at expanding governmentality beyond the state

    in projects like the Unique Identity (UID) project or Aadhaar.

    5 This problematic is central in Foucaults conceptualization of governmentality. Refer to

    Two Lectures by Foucault (1980), particularly pages 978.

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    14/22

    40 RE-FRAMING DEMOCRACY AND AGENCY IN INDIA

    does not refer to the generalized governmental rationality perhaps, that

    itself points to the post-colonial predicament. A lack of mediation on this

    predicament makes political society a theory of politics6 describing the

    modes of transaction between the state and the governeds. A descriptionof the social conditions in which the governeds find themselves does not

    elucidate or clarify the ontology of the social, from which the specificity of

    the post-colonial condition (and the predicament therein) a sketch of which

    is attempted below can be explained or elaborated.7 Without such a critical

    engagement, Chatterjee remains within the liberal strand of political theory,

    wherein the expansion of the liberal institutional order is presented as an

    unlimited, albeit a hindered or interrupted, process. Since Chatterjee does

    not read the practices of governmentality as political logics, governmentality

    almost becomes a shorthand for such a liberal political order, already in a

    position to accommodate and subsume various negativities, particularly in

    the context of capitalist expansion, which is an evolutionist view of political

    order. Chatterjee does not deconstruct the metaphysics (of presence) of such

    political practices, which could point to the impossibility of constituting an

    order and thereby also demonstrate (again) the limit ofnaminga political space

    as civil or political society.

    If the theory of political society has to be statist, then it might be more

    helpful to conduct a thorough investigation of the ways in which the post-colonial state transacts business with the population and the consequences

    of that on the established laws, rules and norms from various perspectives/

    standpoints. What emerges from Chatterjees description in various cases (and

    many scholars would also attest to the factual basis of those) is that the post-

    colonial state is contradictory and indecisive in its conduct:8 on the one hand, it

    is marked by hesitancy and weakness in obtaining compliance with the existing

    codified norms and in enforcing certain legal and executive orders, while on

    6 I borrow the term politics and the political from Chantal Mouffe, where the political

    refers to the dimension of antagonism which [is] constitutive of human societies,

    and politics refers to the set of practices and institutions through which an order is

    created, organizing human coexistence in the context of conflictuality provided by the

    political (Mouffe 2005, 9).

    7 Also, without such a consideration, the emergence of political subjects cannot be

    understood. The Foucauldian understanding of subject formation through subjection

    to power has been thoroughly criticized by Jacques Derrida. Refer to Derrida (1972,

    1973) and Ernesto Laclau (1990).8 Say the hesitancy of the erstwhile Left Front Government of West Bengal in the case of

    the rotting corpse of Balak Brahmachari of the Santan Dal (a religious sect) (Chatterjee

    2004, 4151), and the same governments use of police force,time and again, in suppressing

    and killing (political) dissidents (in Marichhjhapi, Singur and Nandigram).

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    15/22

    POLITICAL SOCIETY IN A CAPITALIST WORLD 41

    the other hand, it can be extraordinarily violent (that is, in using violent means

    and in violating the constitutional rights, legal provisions, and procedures) all

    of which cannot be solely seen as a response to the manoeuvring prevalent in

    political society. The other side of this argument is that the law and rules canbe transgressed by powerful people for exploiting members of political society

    or causing them misery and inconvenience (for example, the encroachment

    of village and forest land by the mining companies in Bellary in Karnataka;

    diversion of PDS rice, etc.). We also know that in the face of resource scarcity

    and other impediments, the actors, including both powerful people and

    members of political society, practise jugad, that is, they arrange things for

    themselves. It is also possible to provide alternative explanations for the post-

    colonial states tolerance of violation of (public) property rights, particularly

    in the context of the informal economy. Barbara Harriss-White (2009, 155)

    provides such an alternative argument:

    The states relation to PCP [petty commodity production] is both

    ambivalent and contradictory simultaneously endorsing actions which

    destroy PCP, protect it, promote it and permit it through enforcement

    failures and neglect. First, the state destroys PCP by means such as

    physical eviction and by displacement as a result of promoting capital-

    biased technology. Second, it subsidizes and promotes the reproductionof small enterprises not through production but through whatever

    infrastructural and welfare/social sector interventions are aimed at

    sustaining the households involved in it. Third the state promotes

    production by small enterprises not just with self-help groups and

    by permitting a mass of more or less experimental micro finance

    arrangements but also by condoning and not policing the onward

    lending of formal credit on unregulated terms and conditions

    which prevent the borrowers from accumulating. Fourth, to preventmass unemployment, widespread malnutrition, etc., it implements

    more or less exiguously policies that prevent the destruction of

    small scale production, trade and services. In so doing it creates small

    enterprises it cannot regulate and incidentally also restricts accumulation.

    Its infrastructural responsibilities to employers may be avoided if

    production is outsourced to petty producers. It does not enforce laws

    through which the super-exploitative advantage of petty production

    would be abolished. Nor does it enforce fiscal measures that would

    threaten through taxation the nutrient-bed of petty production. So

    PCP also thrives through neglect because the small individual capitals

    involved do not accumulate sufficiently for the revenue from tax to

    outweigh the costs of its collection.

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    16/22

    42 RE-FRAMING DEMOCRACY AND AGENCY IN INDIA

    These contradictory and indecisive and perhaps pragmatic approaches

    of the state indicate a predicament which underlines the power relationships

    in a post-colonial country. This predicament has been conceptualized as the

    condition of dominance without hegemony by Ranajit Guha. Guha defineshegemony within a field of power, that is, a series of inequalities or unequal

    relationships (Guha 1998, 20), as a condition of Dominance (D) such that, in the

    organic composition of D, Persuasion (P) outweighs Coercion (C) and hegemony

    operates as a dynamic concept and keeps even the most persuasive structure

    of Dominance always and necessary open to Resistance (ibid., 23, emphasis in

    original). Dominance without hegemony is the condition wherein persuasion

    never manages to outweigh coercion, that is, coercion becomes explicit in

    the formation and operation of power relationships. It is this condition that

    propels the development of strategies of co-optation and negotiations, in an

    attempt to defer or modify the (often inevitable) application of force.

    In the Indian context, the bourgeoisie never loses interest in the accumulation

    of capital, yet adopts various strategies to dispel the antagonisms it faces in that

    process and negotiates with certain impediments. Does the Indian bourgeoisie

    manage to persuade the people to facilitate the process of accumulation or

    does it ultimately depend on the application of force, or a mix of both? This

    question returns in the context of the recent economic transformation in

    India, on which Chatterjee published two articles in 2008.In the first article, Chatterjee (2008a) engages with the political economy

    of the recent economic transformation in India to delineate the changing

    relationships among the dominant groups. Here, the central problematic is the

    soleascendancy of private industrial-corporate capital in India to the position

    of hegemonic domination which is accomplished with the connivance

    [in my words] of the urban middle classes the sphere that seeks to be

    congruent with the normative models of bourgeois civil society (Chatterjee

    2008a, 57) and the parallel decline of the agrarian bourgeoisie (ibid., 56).Such ascendancy of industrial-corporate capital is rendered possible through

    primitive accumulation, namely, the dissociation of the labourer from the

    means of labour [i.e. production] (ibid., 54) and the attendant transfer of

    those means of production to the capitalists. Chatterjee thinks that political

    society again becomes a significant field of contestation and interventions in

    this new context: the need to reverse the effects of the primitive accumulation

    necessitates that the governmental agencies engage with political society to

    distribute the benefits, following the modality described above. But this

    contestation has been part of the passive revolution of capital right from

    the beginning of the career of the post-colonial state, as can be gleaned from

    Sudipta Kavirajs critique (which is seen from the standpoint of the state).

    Kavirajs critique of passive revolution is predicated on the proposition

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    17/22

    POLITICAL SOCIETY IN A CAPITALIST WORLD 43

    that the state in India is a bourgeois state (Kaviraj 1997, 48), which helps

    in capitalist reproduction (ibid., 49 and passim), when capital on its own

    cannot expand through market transactions and, therefore, depends on the

    legitimized directive mechanisms of the state.Kaviraj observes, The Indian capitalist class exercises its control over

    society neither through a moral-cultural hegemony of the Gramscian type,

    nor a simple coercive strategy on the lines of satellite states of the Third

    World (ibid., 51 and passim). Such a control is achieved through a coalitional

    strategy carried out partly through the state-directed process of economic

    growth, partly through the allocational necessities indicated by the bourgeois

    democratic political system (emphasis added).

    The (capitalist) dominance over the society is achieved through the practices

    of governance, which according to Kaviraj, refers to the process of actual

    policy decisions within the apparatuses of the state (ibid., 54 and passim). The

    dominance is created by establishing sets of vertical clientilist benefi t coalition9

    (emphasis in the original) between the ruling bloc and subordinate classes

    through certain policies. Such an approach is concerned with the calculations

    of short-term political advantages accruing from policies. The objective10 of

    establishing benefit coalitions is to ensure that actual political configurations

    do not become symmetrical to class divisions in society.

    Although one can argue, after Kaviraj, that creating vertical clientilistbenefit coalitions is the logics of political society vis--vis capitalist expansion

    and primitive accumulation, yet it will be difficult to normatively evaluate

    it as a positive development (in terms of expansion of freedom). An agency

    argument11 is not enough to salvage such an evaluation. This is because the

    very condition of capital accumulation depends on creating such vertical

    benefit coalitions, which is a social cost to accumulation, and such a

    cost does not alter or threaten the course of capitalist transformation and

    expansion (in an ontological and not a historicist sense, and thereby not

    9 I will argue that this can be seen as the institutionalized form of the colonial idiom of

    Improvement, through which the colonial rulers [used] to relate nonantagonistically to the

    ruled (Guha 1998, 30, emphasis added).

    10 Arun Patnaik offered an alternative argument. Patnaik (1988, 30) found the poverty

    alleviation programmes and targeting the poor in the 1970s as the states paternalistic

    attitude to the rural poor, through which the state diffused among the poor peasants

    its own organizational contradictions and tried to wean them away from the social

    contradictions of the real life.

    11 I will argue that the question of agency in these discussions always arises ex post facto, atthe moment of attributing the credit (or autonomy) of the action to a particular subject.

    The question of identification and recognition of that subject is very much part of

    the above objective. Therefore, to consider the agency as a (starting) premise of an

    argument is limited in explaining the case.

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    18/22

    44 RE-FRAMING DEMOCRACY AND AGENCY IN INDIA

    being a question of teleological transition). I will argue that such vertical

    benefit coalitions and para-legal negotiations simply constitute a factual

    and descriptive state of affairs in the domain of power relationships, and are

    bereft of any immediate normative problematization.

    12

    Since interventionistand transformational politics requires a normative evaluation, and the

    significance and purchase of political society depends on showing the actual

    expansion of freedom of the members of political society, it is also difficult to

    see any transformational potential of the development of political society,

    parallel to civil society.

    Let me summarize my critique of Chatterjee. The project of mapping the

    differentiated political space or defending the communal way of life has not

    been ultimately significant enough for Chatterjee to develop a theory of Indian/

    post-colonial democracy; on the other hand, the practice of transgression

    of law, rules and norms in India has to be accepted. However, the point

    is whether we can undertake any normative evaluation of this empirical

    context and proclaim that it helps in realizing the rights and freedom of

    members of political society. In other words, we need to question whether the

    (political) sociological understanding of political society can help us develop

    a philosophical understanding of democracy in India. Alternatively, if the

    transgression of law has to be taken seriously, then we should be able to use

    the concept of political society to underline the undecidability and aporeticconditions present in constitutionalism and in the process of realization of

    rights, justice and freedom, which provides a critique of the liberal theory

    of democracy, that is, it shows the limit of democracy under the capitalist

    system. This standpoint neither harbours a Marxist/anarcho-communitarian

    suspicion towards constitutionalism, nor does it attempt to furnish a liberal/

    modernist defence of the rule of law. This is what I mean by political society

    as critique, which I elaborate below.

    The context at hand is capitalist transformation, which requires areorganization of property relationships, mobility of capital, curbing

    of labour rights, rationing of social benefits, grabbing of resources and

    maintaining and enhancing of the value (actually, price) of property

    through urban development and beautification. Political society can

    be a useful concept and an analytical tool to study the condition through

    which antagonisms that were immanent or developed within this process of

    capitalist transformation in a post-colonial country (that is, the new frontiers

    of capitalist expansion and growth) are deflected, deferred or nullified.

    12 One can develop this argument further by engaging with Jacques Rancires concept

    of politic(al)s as disagreement (1998, 2004), which necessarily involves such a

    problematization.

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    19/22

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    20/22

    46 RE-FRAMING DEMOCRACY AND AGENCY IN INDIA

    The characterof the politics which emerges in this field a field created by

    governmentality is populist, and populism13 is the only morally legitimate

    form of democratic politics today. Thus, it seems that Chatterjee stands by

    his earlier claim that the politics of the governed is shifting the historicalhorizon of political modernity in most of the world (Chatterjee 2004, 75).

    This insistence on seeing political society as an innovative and promising

    political development ignores the other possibilities of (progressive) political

    interventions. The analysis of governmentality entails the study of a very

    specific domain, namely the mode of application and transformation in

    governmental rationality and power, and resistances to it. This does not exhaust

    the possibilities of analysing other domains of power relationships and the

    dislocating events within those, or of anticipating other forms of progressive

    political interventions. These limitations are also inherited by the analysis of

    political society as such. Thus, the concept of political societyas a critique of

    Indian politics is a much stronger position to defend.

    Alternatively, we may adopt a different methodology to understand the

    political and the transformational politics. We need to ask whether political

    theory should always start with (a reflection on) the state and civil society,

    while trying to understand/question the post-colonial political modernity.

    Instead of a statist/state-centric normative discussion, can we not begin with

    the conceptualization of the social, explicate its ontology, and then proceedfrom there to apprehend the quasi-transcendental conditions of possibility

    and impossibility of political change?

    Conclusion

    I have argued in this paper that the concept of political society can be more

    useful as a critique of Indian politics, rather than as an alternative normative

    theory, which can only extend the criteria of recognition by the state. Whatthe concept of political society warns us about is that a certain section of the

    society is marginalized and that their demands do not become part of

    mainstream political articulations in civil society. Political society alerts us

    about various strategies that are being developed, how people use the spaces

    available in a democracy to raise/place various demands, and how those

    13 In defence of populism, Chatterjee quotes Ernesto Laclau. But, I think, it is a

    misapplication. For Laclau (2007, 2005), populism stands as a problematic of staging thepeople within democracy, which is preceded by a Claude Lefortinspired understanding

    of power, which is empty (that is, there is a lack) at the core, and hegemonic politics is

    practised in an attempt to fill or occupy that emptiness or lack. The people becomes

    the constituency constructed or is the locus in this hegemonic political practice.

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    21/22

    POLITICAL SOCIETY IN A CAPITALIST WORLD 47

    demands are dealt with in a piecemeal way to mitigate antagonism and

    facilitate the passive revolution of capital. Yet, such strategies cannot fully

    hegemonize the people, and force the bourgeoisie to resort to violent means.

    Political society as a critique marks out the problematic of perseverance of thecondition of dominance without hegemony and the return or the spectre of

    the people14 in a democracy.

    Chatterjee reminds us that governmentality always operates on a

    heterogeneous social field, on multiple population groups, and with multiple

    strategies (Chatterjee 2004, 60 and passim). We have also seen that the politics

    in political society is necessarily temporary and contextual. Thus, any

    political intervention that wants to overcome this fragmentary and temporary

    politics would necessitate an engagement with hegemonic politics, a process

    of constructing a broader political movement beyond the fragmentary ones.

    Programmatic issues are involved in such a transformational politics, but any

    mediation on such political programmes cannot begin without an understanding

    of the specificity of the post-colonial condition and predicament, which in

    turn, requires an ontological analysis. The outcome of such an analysis will

    not necessarily initiate a transformation, but it will at least provide a critical

    insight into various political processes.

    References

    Baviskar, Amita and Nandini Sundar. 2008. Democracy versus Economic Transformation?

    Economic and Political Weekly 43, no. 46: 879.

    Chatterjee, Partha. 1993. The Nation and Its Fragments: Colonial and Post-colonial Histories.

    Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    . 1998. Community in the East. Economic and Political Weekly 33, no. 6: 27782.

    . 2001. On Civil and Political Society in Post-colonial Democracies, in Sudipta

    Kaviraj and Sunil Khilnani (eds), Civil Society: History and Possibilities, 16578. Cambridge:

    Cambridge University Press.

    . 2004. The Politics of the Governed. New York: Columbia University Press.

    . 2008a. Democracy and Economic Transformation in India. Economic and Political

    Weekly 43, no. 16: 5362.

    . 2008b. Classes, Capital and Indian Democracy. Economic and Political Weekly 43,

    no. 46: 8993.

    Cohen, J. and A. Arato. 1992. Political Theory and Civil Society. Cambridge, MA: The MIT

    Press.

    Derrida, Jacques. 1972. Interview: Jacques Derrida (with G. Scarpetta and J. L.

    Houdebine).Diacritics2, no. 4: 3543.

    . 1973. Interview: Jacques Derrida (with J. L. Houdebine).Diacritics3, no. 1: 3346.Foucault, Michel. 1980. Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 19721977, ed.

    Colin Gordon. New York: Pantheon.

    14 The populist question, similar to Laclau and Rancire.

    This chapter has been published in the volume Re-framing Democracy and Agency in India:Interrogating Political Society, edited by Ajay Gudavarthy.

    London: Anthem Press, 2012. ISBN: 9780857283504.

  • 7/31/2019 Political Society in a Capitalist World - a Critique

    22/22