Philosophy and the Real World - An Introduction to Karl Popper - Bryan Magee

67

description

Human knowledge is a special case of animal knowledge. From the amoeba to Einstein, learning takes the same course: it starts from a problem caused by the clash between expectations and experience, proceeds to a proposed solution, and then to the testing of that solution. With the emergence of science, failure need no longer be fatal: we can kill off our theories, instead of being killed off ourselves.Popper's evolutionary and objectivist view of the growth of knowledge is expounded clearly and persuasively by his close friend, Bryan Magee. Popper himself has endorsed this account of his views as accurate.Magee is well-known in Britain as a writer, formeber Member of Parliament, and TV popularizer of philosophy. He is Senior Research Fellow in the History of Ideas at London University. His books include The Philosophy of Schopenhauer, Aspects of Wagner, The Democratic Revolution, and Men of Ideas."...an absolutely faithful account of Popper's ideas, presented in delightfully crystalline prose." -Anthony Quinton

Transcript of Philosophy and the Real World - An Introduction to Karl Popper - Bryan Magee

Philosophy and the Real World

An Introduction to Karl Popper

Bryan Magee

Open Court La Salle, Illinois 61301

To order books from Open Court, call toll free 1-800-815-2280.

This book has been reproduced in a print-on-demand format from the 1994 Open Court printing.

A Open Court Publishing Company is a division of Carus Publishing Company.

© 1985 by Open Court Publishing Company

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior written permission of the publisher, Open Court Publishing Company, POB 599, Peru, Dlinois 61354.

Second printing 1990 Third printing 1994

First published as Papper by Fontana Paperbacks, London, 1973. Fourth impression, with corrections, April1975. Tenth impression, with revised Postscript and Bibliography, November 1982.

©Bryan Magee 1973, 1975, 1982

Printed and bound in the United States of America.

Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data

Magee, Bryan Philosophy and the real world.

Rev. ed. of: Popper, 1973. Bibliography: p. 1. Popper, Karl Rairnund, Sir, 1902- I. Magee, Bryan. Popper. ll. Title.

B1649.P64M33 1985 192 84-29597 ISBN 0-87548-436-0

Short though it is, this book has benefitted im­measurably from criticisms of an earlier draft giv­en to me by Lord Boyle, Mr. Tyrrell Burgess, Professor Ernest Gellner, Sir Ernst Gombrich, Mr. David Miller, Professor John Watkins, Professor Bernard Williams and Sir Karl Popper.

to Ninian and Libushka with love

Contents

1 Introduction 3

2 Scientific Method-the Traditional View and Popper's View 13

3 The Criterion of Demarcation between what is and what is not Science 32

4 Popper's Evolutionism and his theory of World 3 55

5 Objective Knowledge 65

6 The Open Society 75

7 The Enemies of the Open Society 90

Postscript 114

Bibliography 117

Man has created new worlds-of language, of music, of poetry, of science; and the most impor­tant of these is the world of the moral demands, for equality, for freedom, and for helping the weak.

The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol I, p.65

Philosophy and the Real World

An Introduction to Karl Popper

1

Introduction

Karl Popper is not, as yet anyway, a household name among the educated, and this fact requires explana­tion. For as Isaiah Berlin writes in his biography of Karl Marx (third edition 1963), Popper's The Open Society and Its Enemies contains 'the most scrupulous and formida­ble criticism of the philosophical and historical doc­trines of Marxism by any living writer'; and if this judg­ment is anywhere near sound, Popper is-in a world one third of whose inhabitants live under governments which call themselves Marxist-a figure of world im­portance. But quite apart from this he is regarded by many as the greatest living philosopher of science­indeed, Sir Peter Medawar, a winner of the Nobel Prize for Medicine, said on BBC Radio 3 on 28 July 1972: 'I

3

Introduction

think Popper is incomparably the greatest philosopher of science that has ever been.' Other Nobel Prize win­ners who have publicly ackowledged his influence on their work include Jacques Monod and Sir John Eccles, who wrote in his book Facing Reality (1970): ' ... my scientific life owes so much to my conversion in 1945, if I may call it so, to Popper's teachings on the conduct of scientific investigations .... I have endeavoured to fol­low Popper in the formulation and in the investigation of fundamental problems in neurobiology.' Eccles's ad­vice to other scientists is 'to read and meditate upon Popper's writings on the philosophy of science and to adopt them as the basis of operation of one's scientific life'. Nor is it only experimental scientists who take this view. The distinguished mathematician and theoretical astronomer, Sir Herman Bondi, has stated simply: 'There is no more to science than its method, and there is no more to its method than Popper has said.' The range of Popper's intellectual influence, unapproached by that of any English-speaking philosopher now liv­ing, extends from members of governments to art his­torians. In the Preface to Art and Illusion (described by Kenneth Clark as 'one of the most brilliant books on art criticism I have ever read') Sir Ernst Gombrich writes: 'I should be proud if Professor Popper's influence were to be felt everywhere in this book.' And progressive Cabinet Ministers in both of the main British political parties, for instance Anthony Crosland and Sir Edward Boyle, have been influenced by Popper in the view they take of political activity.

These examples illustrate, straight away, some im­portant things besides the extraordinary range of appli­cation of Popper's work. They show that-unlike that of so many contemporary philosophers-it has a nota­bly practical effect on people who are influenced by it: it changes the way they do their own work, and in this

4

Introduction

and other respects changes their lives. It is, in short, a philosophy of action. Also, it has had such influence on many people who are themselves of first-rate dis­tinction in their own fields. One could scarcely say, then, that Popper is neglected. This underlines all the more, though, the surprisingness of the fact that he is not better known-many lesser thinkers are more fa­mous. This is due partly to chance, partly to unintend­ed misrepresentation of his work, and partly to an as­pect of his method which facilitates misapprehension of it by those who have not studied it.

Karl Popper was born in Vienna in 1902. In his early and middle teens he was a Marxist, and then became an enthusiastic Social Democrat. Apart from his studies in science and philosophy he was involved not only in left-wing politics and in social work with children un­der the aegis of Adler, but also in the Society for Pri­vate Concerts founded by Schoenberg. For him, as for so many others, it was a thrilling time and place to be young. After his student days he earned his living as a secondary school teacher in mathematics and physics; but his chief absorptions continued to be social work, left-wing politics, music-and of course philosophy, where he found himself, as he has tended to ever since, at variance with the fashion prevailing in his place and time, which for his generation there and then was the logical positivism of the Vienna Circle. Otto Neurath, a member of the Circle, nicknamed him 'the Official Opposition'. This made him something of an odd man out. He found it impossible to get his early books published in the form in which he wrote them. His first book was not published until1979, and has yet to appear in English. His first and seminal published work, Logik der Forschung (published in the autumn of 1934, dated 1935) was a savagely cut version of a book twice as long. It contains the chief of what have since

5

Introduction

become the generally accepted arguments against logi­cal positivism.

Beneath the surface violence of the political scene in Vienna in the 1930s the left's opposition to fascism was crumbling. Later, in The Open Society and Its Enemies (vol ii, pp. 164-165), Popper characterized the radical Marxist view as having been: 'Since the revolution was bound to come, fascism could only be one of the means of bringing it about; and this was more particularly so since the revolution was clearly long overdue. Russia had already had it in spite of its backward economic conditions. Only the vain hopes created by democracy were holding it back in the more advanced countries. Thus the destruction of democracy through the fascists could only promote the revolution by achieving the ul­timate disillusionment of the workers in regard to dem­ocratic methods. With this, the radical wing of Marxism felt that it had discovered the "essence" and the "true historical role" of fascism. Fascism was, essentially, the last stand of the bourgeoisie. Accordingly, the Commu­nists did not fight when the fascists seized power. (No­body expected the Social Democrats to fight.) For the Communists were sure that the proletarian revolution was overdue and that the fascist interlude, necessary for its speeding up, could not last longer than a few months. Thus no action was required from the Com­munists . They were harmless. There was never a "communist danger" to the fascist conquest of power.'

Included in the historical reality behind this passage were agonized debates about political strategy and mo­rality in which Popper was involved, and which were the seedbed of much of his later political writing. He carne to foresee, with depressing accuracy, the annexa­tion of Austria by Nazi Germany, to be followed by a European war in which his native land would be on the wrong side; and he determined to leave before this

6

Introduction

happened. (This decision saved his life: for although his childhood had been a Protestant one, and both his parents had been baptized, Hitler would have catego­rized him as a Jew.) From 1937 to 1945 he taught phil­osophy at the University of New Zealand. In the earlier part of this period he virtually taught himself Greek in order to study the Greek philosophers, especially Plato. In the middle part he wrote, in English, The Open Society and Its Enemies-'a work,' as Isaiah Berlin says in the source quoted earlier, 'of exceptional originality and power'. Popper regarded this as his war work. The final decision to write it was made on the day he re­ceived the news he had so long dreaded, of Hitler's invasion of Austria. This and the fact that the outcome of the Second World War was still uncertain in 1943, when the book was finished, added to the depth of passion which informs this defence of liberty and at­tack on totalitarianism, whose develornent and appeal it also attempts to explain. It was published in two volumes in 1945, and brought Popper his first real fame in the English-speaking world.

In 1946 he carne to England, where he has lived ever since. In philosophy the prevailing orthodoxy he found on his arrival, in so far as there was one at all, was the logical positivism he had left behind him in Vienna be­fore the war. This had been imported into England in A. J. Ayer's Language, Truth and Logic, which had been pubished in January 1936. Popper's own Logik der For­schung was still untranslated and virtually unknown; indeed, in so far as it was known about, its contents were usually misapprehended. It did not appear in En­glish until the autumn of 1959, a quarter of a century after its original publication, under the title The Logic of Scientific Discovery . This translation contained a special preface in which Popper dissociated himself from the (by this time) newly fashionable linguistic philosophy,

7

Introduction

but Mind, the chief journal of linguistic philosophy, reviewed the book uncomprehendingly and without referring to the preface. In his middle age Popper found himself odd man out again in England, just as he had been in Austria in his youth. Nevertheless the solitary international reputation he had long since begun to acquire continued to expand, and he received social recognition in England (he was knighted in 1965). But neither Oxford nor Cambridge wanted him as a Professor. However, he spent the last 23 years of his university career at the London School of Econom­ics, where he became Professor of Logic and Scientific Method.

It was during these years that he released his next two books, both of them collections of articles most of which had already been published. When The Poverty of Historicism came out in 1957 Arthur Koestler wrote in The Sunday Times that it was 'probably the only book published this year which will outlive this century'. (The set of articles of which it consists had been re­jected by Mind.) It can be regarded as a pendant to The Open Society and Its Enemies. Similarly Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, published in 1963, can be seen as a pendant to The Logic of Scientif­ic Discovery. He has published one more book since his retirement in 1969, another collection of essays called Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach, which came out in 1972. There will probably be several more, for some unpublished books are complete in manu­script; and in addition to the articles, over 100 of them, which have appeared in academic journals, he has an even greater number of articles and written lectures which he has not published. Throughout his life he has been excessively reluctant to let his work go to the printer: there has always been room-and time-for a few more improvements, a few more corrections.

8

Introduction

At the beginning of his career the logical positivists saw him as being concerned with essentially the same problems as themselves, and interpreted his work in the light of this assumption. Linguistic philosophers have since done much the same. Both have therefore sincerely believed, and asserted, that his work is noth­ing like as different from theirs as he himself insists, and they find his insistence tiresome. I shall come to the substance of these misunderstandings in due course. The point I want to make here is that Popper's work itself contains a feature, unavoidable when right­ly understood, which has got between him and poten­tial readers-who, being only potential, are not yet in a position to understand it. He believes, in a sense which will be made fully clear later, that only through criti­cism can knowledge advance. This leads him to put forward most of his important ideas in the course of criticizing other peoples': for instance, most of his argu­ments in The Open Society and Its Enemies are advanced in criticism of Plato and Marx. One consequence of this is that generations of students have plundered the work for these critiques without reading the book as a whole. It has even come to be widely thought of as being a critique of Plato and Marx-with the result that many people who have heard of it but not read have a mistaken conception of it. Some even assume it, be­cause of its attack on Marx, to be a work of right wing tendencies. The academic controversy it has stirred up has centred not on Popper's positive arguments but on whether his view of other philosophers is valid. Whole books have been written on this, like In Defense of Plato by Ronald B. Levinson, and The Open Philosophy and The Open Society by Maurice Cornforth. Argument has ramified through the pages of academic journals about whether Popper's translation of this or that Greek pas­sage faithfully preserves Plato's meaning. The defence

9

Introduction

of democracy which the book also contains has not re­ceived a fraction of this academic attention. Yet even if it could be shown that the treatment of both Plato and Marx is misconceived, the argument in favour of de­mocracy would still be the most powerful in the lan­guage. Any intellectually serious criticism of The Open Society and Its Enemies should be chiefly concerned with appraising its arguments, not its scholarship-though as I shall illustrate later the scholarship is in any case respectable.

Related to this is another, much slighter obstacle be­tween Popper and possible readers. He believes that philosophy is a necessary activity because we, all of us, take a great number of things for granted, and many of these assumptions are of a philosophical character; we act on them in private life, in politics, in our work, and in every other sphere of our lives-but while some of these assumptions are no doubt true, it is likely that more are false and some are harmful. So the critical examination of our presuppositions-which is a philo­sophical activity-is morally as well as intellectually im­portant. This view is of philosophy as something lived and important for all of us, not an academic activity or a specialism, and certainly not as consisting primarily in the study of the writings of professional philoso­phers. Nevertheless it does mean that most of Popper's work consists of the critical examination of theories, and in consequence there is a great deal of discussion of 'isms', and a great many allusions to thinkers of the past, especially in the first works he wrote in English when he was still under the influence of the German academic tradition.

On the other hand few philosophers have taken so much trouble to be clear. The writing is so clear as to disguise its own depth, and a few readers have mistak­enly supposed that what was being said was rather

10

Introduction

simple, perhaps even a bit obvious. They have missed the thrill of illumination and the excitement to be got from it. The prose itself is massively distinguished: it is magnanimous and humane, with a combination of in­tellectual and emotional pressure reminiscent of Marx's -there is the same driving force behind the argument, the same sweep and bite, the same bigness and self­confidence, yet a tighter logical rigour. Once the reader has accustomed himself to the terminology it is ex­hilarating, and has great holding power. Above all­and this is a striking feature of all Popper's work-it is super-abundantly rich in arguments.

Popper's is a systematic philosophy in the great cen­tral tradition of the subject. But only the most painstak­ing and unparochial of students could be expected to have read all the various lectures and publications in which it has been been presented, in different lan­guages, journals, countries and decades, let alone to see that these are interconnecting parts of a single ex­planatory framework which extends to the whole of human experience. To take a single example: Popper is an indeterminist in both physics and politics. His argu­ment that it is logically impossible to give a scientific prediction of the future course of history was first put forward in The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science in a paper called Indeterminism in Quantum Physics and in Classical Physics. Its development in one direction became part of his defence of political freedom and his critique of Marxism; in another it led him to work on a · propensity theory of probability which, applied to quantum physics, offers a solution to certain problems in the theory of matter which connect with the historic schism between Einstein, de Broglie and Schrodinger on the one hand and Heisenberg, Niels Bohr and Max Born on the other. Only very few fulltime students with the necessary technical equipment are likely to have

11

Introduction

followed these connections through, and related them to each other.

What I have tried to do in this book is give a bold, clear outline of Popper's thought which exhibits its sys­tematic unity. This involves, for reasons which will become obvious, starting with the theory of knowledge and the philosophy of science. I beg readers who per­haps regard themselves as uninterested in these fields but have opened this book out of an interest in the social and political theories not to skip, for Popper has extended ideas originally worked out in the natural sciences to the social sciences, and a knowledge of the former is indispensable to a deeper understanding of the latter. What is more, I shall be trying to show how the two are parts of a single philosophy which em­braces both the natural and the human worlds . I hope also to make it clear why this philosophy has the special influence it does, and in broad terms why it is at odds with other contemporary philosophies-though in a book as short as this it is not possible to go into specific controversies. Nor is it feasible to go into the more technical aspects of physics, probability theory or logic, so I shall not attempt to examine the detailed support from these fields which Popper brings to his general arguments. My concern will be solely with the latter.

12

2

Scientific Method-the Traditional View and Popper's View

The word 'law' is ambiguous, and anyone who talks of a natural or scientific law being 'broken' is confusing the two main uses of the word. A law of society pre­scribes what we may or may not do. It can be broken­indeed, if we could not break it there would be no need to have it: society does not legislate against a citizen's being in two places at once. A law of nature, on the other hand, is not prescriptive but descriptive. It tells us what happens-for instance that water boils at 100° Centigrade. As such it purports to be nothing more than a statement of what-given certain initial conditions, such as that there is a body of water and that it is heated -occurs. It may be true or false, but it cannot be 'bro­ken', for it is not a command: water is not being ordered

13

Scientific Method

to boil at 100° Centrigrade . The pre-scientific belief that it was (by some god) is the reason for the unfortunate ambiguity: the laws of nature were thought to be com­mands of the gods. But nowadays no one would dispute that they are not prescriptions of any kind, to be 'kept' or 'obeyed' or 'broken', but explanatory statements of a general character which purport to be factual and must therfore be modified or abandoned if found to be inaccu­rate .

The search for natural laws has long been seen as the central task of science, at least since Newton. But the way scientists were supposed to proceed was first sys­tematically described by Francis Bacon. Although his formulation has been much qualified, added to, refined and sophisticated since his day, something in the tradi­tion he pioneered has been accepted by nearly all scien­tifically minded people since the seventeenth century. The scientist begins by carrying out experiments whose aim is to make carefully controlled and meticulously measured observations at some point on the frontier between our knowledge and our ignorance. He sys­tematically records his findings, perhaps publishes them, and in the course of time he and other workers in the field accumulate a lot of shared and reliable data. As this grows, general features begin to emerge, and individuals start to formulate general hypotheses­statements of a lawlike character which fit all the known facts and explain how they are causally related to each other. The individual scientist tries to confirm his hypothesis by finding evidence which will support it. If he succeeds in verifying it he has discovered an­other scientific law which will unlock more of the se­crets of nature. The new seam is then worked-the new discovery is applied wherever it is thought it might yield fresh information. Thus the existing stock of scientific knowledge is added to, and the frontier of

14

Traditional View and Popper's View

our ignorance pushed back. And the process begins again on the new frontier .

The method of basing general statements on ac­cumulated observations of specific instances is known as induction, and is seen as the hallmark of science. In other words the use of the inductive method is seen as the criterion of demarcation between science and non­science. Scientific statements, being based on observa­tional and experimental evidence-based, in short, on the facts-are contrasted with statements of all other kinds, whether based on authority, or emotion, or tra­dition, or speculation, or prejudice, or habit, or any other foundation, as alone providing sure and certain knowledge. Science is the corpus of such knowledge, and the growth of science consists in the endless pro­cess of adding new certainties to the body of existing ones.

Some awkward questions about this were raised by Hume. He pointed out that no number of singular ob­servation statements, however large, could logically entail an unrestrictedly general statement. If I observe that event A is attended by event B on one occasion, it does not logically follow that it will be attended by it on any other occasion. Nor would it follow from two such observations-nor from twenty, nor from two thou­sand. If it happens often enough, said Hume, I may come to expect that the next A will be attended by a B, but this is a fact of psychology, not of logic. The sun may have risen again after every past day of which we have knowledge, but this does not entail that it will rise tomorrow. If someone says: Ah yes, but we can in fact predict the precise time at which the sun will rise to­morrow from the established laws of physics, as ap­plied to conditions as we have them at this moment', we can answer him twice over. First, the fact that the laws of physics have been found to hold good in the

15

Scientific Method

past does not logically entail that they will continue to hold good in the future. Second, the laws of physics are themselves general statements which are not logi­cally entailed by the observed instances, however nu­merous, which are adduced in their support. So this attempt to justify induction begs the question by taking the validity of induction for granted. The whole of c;mr science assumes the regularity of nature-assumes that the future will be like the past in all those respects in which natural laws are taken to operate-yet there is no way in which this assumption can be secured. It cannot be established by observation, 'since we cannot observe future events. And it cannot be established by logical argument, since from the fact that all past fu­tures have resembled past pasts it does not follow that all future futures will resemble future pasts. The con­clusion Hume himself came to was that although there is no way of demonstrating the validity of inductive procedures we are so constituted psychologically that we cannot help thinking in terms of them. And since they seem to work in practice we go along with them. This does mean, however, that scientific laws have no rationally secure foundation-neither in logic, nor in experience, since every scientific law, being unrestrict­edly general, goes beyond both.

The problem of induction, which has been called 'Hume' s problem', has baffled philosophers from his time to our own. C. D. Broad described it as the skele­ton in the cupboard of philosophy. Bertrand Russell wrote in his History of Western Philosophy (pp. 699-700): 'Hume has proved that pure empiricism is not a suffi­cient basis for science. But if this one principle [induc­tion] is admitted, everything else can proceed in accordance with the theory that all our knowledge is based on experience. It must be granted that this is a serious departure from pure empiricism, and that those

16

Traditional View and Popper's View

who are not empiricists may ask why, if one departure is allowed, others are to be forbidden. These, however, are questions not directly raised by Hume's arguments. What these arguments prove-and I do not think the proof can be controverted-is, that induction is an in­dependent logical principle, incapable of being inferred either from experience or from other logical principles, and that without this principle science is impossible.'

That the whole of science, of all things, should rest on foundations whose validity it is impossible to dem­onstrate has been found uniquely embarrassing. It has turned many empirical philosophers into sceptics, or irrationalists, or mystics. Some it has led to religion. Virtually all have felt bound to say, in effect: 'We have to admit that, strictly speaking, scientific laws cannot be proved and are therefore not certain. Even so, their degree of probability is raised by each confirming in­stance; and in addition to the whole of the known past every moment of the world's continuance brings count­less billions of confirming instances-and never a sin­gle counter-example. So, if not certain, they are proba­ble to the highest degree which it is possible to conceive; and in practice, if not in theory, this is indis­tinguishable from certainty.' Nearly all scientists, in so far as they reflect on the logical foundations of what they are doing, go along with this attitude. To them the overwhelmingly important thing is that science de­livers the goods-it works, it produces a never-ending stream of useful results: and rather than go on banging their heads against the brick wall of an apparently in­soluble logical problem they prefer to get on with doing more science and getting more results. The more philo­sophically reflective among them, however, have been deeply troubled. For them, and for philosophers gener­ally, induction has presented an unsolved problem at the very foundations of human knowledge, and until

17

Scientific Method

such time as it might be solved the whole of science, however intrinsically consistent and extrinsically use­ful, must be conceded to be somehow floating in mid air, unfixed to terra firma.

Popper's seminal achievement has been to offer an ac­ceptable solution to the problem of induction. In doing this he has rejected the whole orthodox view of scie-n­tific method outlined so far in this chapter and replaced it with another. It is, of course, this that lies behind the quotations from Medawar, Eccles and Bondi on the first page of this book. And as might be expected of so fundamental an achievement it has proved fruitful beyond the confines of the problem that gave rise to it, and has led to the solution of other important prob­lems.

Popper's solution begins by pointing to a logical asymmetry between verification and falsification. To express it in terms of the logic of statements: although no number of observation statements reporting obser­vations of white swans allows us logically to derive the universal statement 'All swans are white', one single observation statement, reporting one single observa­tion of a black swan, allows us logically to derive the statement 'Not all swans are white .' In this important logical sense empirical generalizations, though not verifiable, are falsifiable. This means that scientific laws are testable in spite of being unprovable: they can be tested by systematic attempts to refute them.

From the beginning Popper drew the distinction be­tween the logic of this situation and the implied meth­odology. The logic is utterly simple: if a single black swan has been observed then it cannot be the case that all swans are white . In logic, therefore-that is, if we look at the relation between statements-a scientific law is conclusively falsifiable although it is not conclu-

18

Traditional View and Popper's View

sively verifiable. Methodologically however, we are presented with a different case, for in practice it is al­ways possible to doubt a statement: there may have been some error in the reported observation; the bird in question may have been wrongly identified; or we may decide, because it is black, not to categorize it as a swan but to call it something else. So it is always possible for us to refuse, without self-contradiction, to accept the validity of an observation statement. We could thus re­ject all falsifying experiences whatsoever. But since conclusive falsification is not attainable at the method­ological level it is a mistake to ask for it. If we did, and meanwhile kept reinterpeting the evidence to maintain its agreement with our statements, our approach would have become absurdly unscientific. Popper therefore proposes, as an article of method, that we do not systematically evade refutation, whether by intro­ducing ad hoc hypotheses, or ad hoc definitions, or by always refusing to accept the reliability of inconvenient experimental results, or by any other such device; and that we formulate our theories as unambiguously as we can, so as to expose them as clearly as possible to refu­tation. On the other hand he also says we should not abandon our theories lightly, for this would involve too uncritical an attitude towards tests, and would mean that the theories themselves were not tested as rigor­ously as they should be. So although Popper is what might be called a na'ive falsificationist at the level of logic he is a highly critical falsificationist at the level of methodology. Much misunderstanding of his work has sprung from a failure to appreciate this distinction.

Let us now consider a practical example. Suppose we start by believing, as most of us are taught at school, that it is a scientific law that water boils at 100° Centigrade. No number of confirming instances will prove this, but we can nevertheless test it by searching

19

Scientific Method

for circumstances in which it does not hold. This alone challenges us to think of things which, so far as we know, no one else has hit on. If we are at all imaginative we shall soon discover that water does not boil at 100° Centigrade in closed vessels. So what we thought was a scientific law turns out not to be one. Now at this point we could take a wrong turning. We could salvage our original. statement by narrowing its empirical content to 'Water boils at 100° Centigrade in open vessels.' And we could then look systematically for a refutation of our second statement. And if we were rather more imagina­tive than before we should find it at high altitudes: so that to salvage our second statement we would have to narrow its empirical content to 'Water boils at 100° Cen­tigrade in open vessels at sea-level atmospheric pres­sure.' And we could then begin a systematic attempt to refute our third statement. And so on. In this way we might regard ourselves as pinning down ever more and more precisely our knowledge about the boiling point of water. But to proceed in this way, through a series of statements with vanishing empirical content, would be to miss the most important features of the situation. For when we discovered that water did not boil at 100° Centi­grade in closed vessels we had our foot on the threshold of the most important kind of discovery of all, namely the discovery of a new problem: 'Why not?' We are challenged now to produce a hypothesis altogether rich­er than our original, simple statement, a hypothesis which explains both why water boils at 100° Centigrade in open vessels and also why it does not in closed ones; and the richer the hypothesis is the more it will tell us about the relationship between the two situations, and the more precisely it will enable us to calculate different boiling points. In other words we will now have a sec­ond formulation which has not less empirical content than our first but very considerably more. And we

20

Traditional View and Popper's View

should proceed to look systematically for a refutation of that. And if, say, we were to find that although it gave us results in both open and closed vessels at sea-level atmospheric pressure it broke down at high altitudes we should have to search for a third hypothesis, richer still, which would exlain why each of our first two hy­potheses worked, up to the point it did, but then broke down at that point; and also enable us to account for the new situation as well. And then we should test that. From each of our successive formulations conse­quences would be derived which went beyond the ex­isting evidence: our theory, whether true or false, would tell us more about the world than we yet knew. And one of the ways in which we tested it would be by devising confrontations between its consequences and new observable experience; and if we discovered that some of the things it told us were not the case this would be a new discovery: it would add to our knowl­edge and it would start all over again the search for a better theory.

This, in a nutshell, is Popper's view of the way knowledge advances. There are several things to em­phasize. If we had set out to 'verify' our original state­ment that water boils at 100° Centigrade by accumulat­ing confirming instances of it we should have found no difficulty whatever in accumulating any number of con­firming instances we liked, billions and billions of them. But this would not have proved the truth of the state­ment, nor would it (and this realization may come as something of a shock) have increased the probability of its being true. Worst of all, our accumulation of confirm­ing instances would of itself never have given us reason to doubt, let alone replace, our original statement, and we should never have progressed beyond it. Our knowl­edge would not have grown as it has-unless in our search for confirming instances we accidentally hit upon

21

Scientific Method

a counter-instance. Such an accident would have been the best thing that could have happened to us. (It is in this sense that so many famous discoveries in science have been 'accidental'.) For the growth of our knowl­edge proceeds from problems and our attempts to solve them. These attempts involve the propounding of theo­ries which, if they are to provide possible solutions at all, must go beyond our existing knowledge, and which therefore require a leap of the imagination. The bolder the theory the more it tells us, and also the more daring the act of imagination. (At the same time, though, the greater is the probability that what the theory tells us is wrong; and we should use rigorous tests to discover whether it is.) Most of the great revolutions in science have turned on theories of breathtaking audacity not only in respect of creative imagination but in the depth of insight involved, and the independence of mind, the unsecured adventurousness of thought, required.

We are now in a position to see why it is inherent in Popper's view that what we call our knowledge is of its nature provisonal, and permanently so. At no stage are we able to prove that what we now 'know' is true, and it is always possible that it will turn out to be false . Indeed, it is an elementary fact about the intellectual history of mankind that most of what has been 'known' at one time or another has eventually turned out to be not the case. So it is a profound mistake to try to do what scientists and philosophers have almost always tried to do, namely prove the truth of a theory, or justi­fy our belief in a theory, since this is to attempt the logically impossible. What we can do, however, and this is of the highest possible importance, is to justify our preference for one theory over another. In our successive examples about the boiling of water we were never able to show that our current theory was true, but we were at each stage able to show that it was

22

Traditional View and Popper's View

preferable to our preceding theory. This is the char­acteristic situation in any of the sciences at any given time. The popular notion that the sciences are bodies of established fact is entirely mistaken. Nothing in science is permanently established, nothing unalterable, and indeed science is quite clearly changing all the time, and not through the accretion of new certainties. If we are rational we shall always base our decisions and ex­pectations on 'the best of our knowledge', as the popu­lar phrase so rightly has it, and provisionally assume the 'truth' of that knowledge for practical purposes, be­cause it is the least insecure foundation available; but we shall never lose sight of the fact that at any time experience may show it to be wrong and require us to revise it.

On this view the truth of a statement, by which Pop­per means (following Tarski) its correspondence to the facts, is a regulative idea. An analogy with the notion of 'accuracy' will make clear what this means. All mea­surement, whether of time or space, can only be within a certain degree of accuracy. If you order a piece of steel six millimetres long you can have it made accu­rately to within the finest margin of which the very best instruments are capable, which is now fractions of a millionth of a millimetre. But where, within that mar­gin, the exact point of six millimetres is something which, in the nature of things, we do not know. It may be that your piece of steel actually is exactly six mil­limetres long, but you can not know it. All you know is that the length is accurate to within such and such a fraction of a millimetre, and that it is nearer the desired length than anything measurably longer or measurably shorter. With the next improvement in machine tools you may be able to get a piece of steel whose accuracy you can be sure of to within an even closer margin. And another with the next improvement after that. But

23

Scientific Method

the notion 'exactly six millimetres', or exactly any other measurement, is not something that can ever be met with in experience. It is a metaphysical notion. But from this it does not follow that mankind cannot make invaluable and prodigious use of measurement; nor that accuracy does not matter; nor that we cannot make progress through ever greater and greater degrees of accuracy.

Popper's notion of 'the truth' is very like this: our concern in the pursuit of knowledge is to get closer and closer to the truth, and we may even know that we have made an advance, but we can never know if we have reached our goal. 'We cannot identify science with truth, for we think that both Newton's and Ein­stein's theories belong to science, but they cannot both be true, and they may well both be false.' 1 One of his favourite quotations is from the pre-Socratic philosopher Xenophanes, which he translates as follows:

The gods did not reveal, from the beginning, All things to us, but in the course of time Through seeking we may learn and know things better. But as for certain truth, no man has known it, Nor shall he know it, neither of the gods Nor yet of all the things of which I speak. For even if by chance he were to utter The final truth, he would himself not know it: For all is but a woven web of guesses.

Popper's view of science slides on to its history like a glove. But the particular event which brought home to him the permanently conjectural nature of scientific knowledge was Einstein's challenge to Newton. New-

1Popper on p. 78 of Modern British Philosophy (ed. Bryan Magee) .

24

Traditional View and Popper's View

tonian physics was the most successful and important scientific theory ever to be advanced and accepted. Everything in the observable world seemed to confirm it: for more than two centuries its laws were corroborat­ed not just by observation but by creative use, for they became the foundation of Western science and technol­ogy, yielding marvellously accurate predictions of everything from the existence of new planets down to the movements of the tides and the workings of ma­chinery. If anything was knowledge, this was; the most secure and certain knowledge man had ever acquired about his physical environment. If any scientific laws had been verified inductively as Laws of Nature, these had, by countless billions of observations and experi­ments. To generation after generation of Western man they were taught as definitive, incorrigible fact. Yet af­ter all this, at the beginning of our own century, a theory different from Newton's was put foward by Ein­stein. Opinions about the truth of Einstein's theory var­ied, but its claims to serious attention could not be de­nied, nor its claim to go beyond Newton's theory in the range of its applications. And this itself is the point. All the observational evidence which fitted Newton's theory (and some about which Newton's theory said nothing) also fitted Einstein's. (In fact it can be logically demonstrated-and had been long ago, by Leibniz­that any finite number of observations can be accom­modated within an indefinitely large number of differ­ent explanations.) The world had simply been wrong in believing that all that untold evidence proved Newton's theory. Yet a whole era of civilization had been based on it, with unprecedented material success. If this amount of verification and inductive support did not prove the truth of a theory, what ever could? And Pop­per realized that nothing could. He saw that no theory could ever be relied on to be the final truth . The most

25

Scientific Method

we can ever say is that it is supported by every obser­vation so far, and yields more, and more precise, pre­dictions than any known alternative. It is still replacea­ble by a better theory.

If Newton's theory is not a body of truth inherent in the world, and derived by man from the observation of reality, where did it come from? The answer is: it came from Newton. 2 It was a man-made hypothesis which fitted all the facts known at the time and from which physicists might have gone on deducing consequences to use and rely on until this got them into intolerable difficulties-though in fact the new theory began to emerge before this point was reached; and there had always been some anomalies in the old theory. A theory might, like Euclid's geometry or Aristotle's logic, be accepted as objective knowledge for over 2000 years, and be almost infinitely fruitful and useful during that time, and yet still in the end be found wanting in some unforeseeable respect, and eventually replaced by a better theory. We now have what most physicists think is an alternative preferable to Newton's theory. But this is still not the final truth. Einstein himself regarded his theory as defective, and spent the second half of his life trying to find a better one. We can expect that one day a theory will be advanced which contains and accounts for Einstein's just as Einstein's contains and accounts for Newton's .

The fact that such theories are not bodies of imper­sonal facts about the world but are products of the hu­man mind makes them personal achievements of an astonishing order. Scientific creation is not free in the same sense as artistic creation for it has to survive a

2Qr rather, according to Popper's theories as explained later, in Chapter 4, from interaction between Newton and World 3. The meaning of this can be left till we come to it.

26

Traditional View and Popper's View

detailed confrontation with experience: nevertheless the attempt to understand the world is an open task, and as creative geniuses Galileo, Newton and Einstein are on a par with Michelangelo, Shakespeare and Bee­thoven. An awareness of this, and wonder at it, per­vades Popper's work. It is therefore all the more impor­tant to be clear about the fact that his theory is an account of the logic and history of science and not of the psychology of its practitioners. He is not under the impression-no one could be-that scientists in general have regarded themselves as doing what he describes. The point is that, whether they realize it or not, this is the rationale of what they do, and accounts for the way human knowledge develops. What goes on in the mind of a scientist may be of interest to him, and to people who know him, or to the man who writes his biogra­phy, or to people interested in certain aspects of psy­chology, but it has no bearing on how his work is to be judged. If I were a scientist and published a scientific theory the world would ask questions not about subjec­tive me but about the objective theory. What does it tell us? Is it internally consistent? If so, is it genuinely em­pirical, or is it tautological? How does it compare with other, already well-tested theories? Does it tell us more than they do? How is it to be tested? And so on. People (it could be myself as well as others) will apply it to particular conditions and by deductive processes will derive logical consequences in the form of singular statements which can be tested by observation and ex­periment. The better it comes out of such tests, and such comparisons with other theories, the better cor­roborated we shall regard it as being.

About this process as a whole there are three points to stress. First, how I arrived at the theory has no bear­ing on its scientific or logical status. Second, the obser­vations and experiments in question, far from giving

27

Scientific Method

rise to the theory, are partially derived from it, and are designed to test it. Third, at no point does induction come into the matter. The traditional view of the way we think, and of scientific method, gave rise to the problem of induction, but the traditional view was radi­cally mistaken and can be replaced, as here, by a more accurate one within which the problem of induction does not arise. So induction, Popper is saying, is a dis­pensable concept, a myth. It does not exist. There is no such thing.

A critic might object that Popper has excluded from consideration the very process in which induction does occur, namely the process of theory-formation. Granted, our critic might say, that singular observa­tions cannot entail a general theory, they may neverthe­less suggest one, especially to a scientist of insight and imagination; so in fact theories can be, and are, arrived at by generalization from observed instances. Admit­tedly, he may say, there is always a 'jump' involved from the singular to the general; but the process is not a purely random or irrational one: there is a kind of logic involved, and it is this that we call induction.

Popper's reply is as follows. From the fact that it is of no scientific or logical significance how a theory is ar­rived at it follows that no way is illegitimate, and there­fore perfectly good theories may well be arrived at in the way the critic describes. However, the description is of a psychological process, not a logical one. And in fact this whole problem of induction has its roots in a failure to distinguish logical from psychological pro­cesses. We have accounts from scientists of their hav­ing arrived at theories in any number of different ways: in dreams or dreamlike states; in flashes of inspiration; even as a result of misunderstandings and mistakes. If one pursues the point, a study of the history of science leaves no doubt that most theories are arrived at not in

28

Traditional View and Popper's View

any of these ways, and not by generalizing from ex­perimental observations either, but by modifying al­ready-existing theories. There can/ no more be a logic of creation in the sciences than there 'can be such a thing in the arts. 'It so happens that my arguments in this book [The Logic of Scientific Discovery, p. 32] are quite inde­pendent of this problem. However, my view of the matter, for what it is worth, is that there is no such thing as a logical method of having new ideas, or a logical reconstruction of this process. My view may be expressed by saying that every discovery contains "an irrational element", or "a creative intuition", in Berg­son's sense. In a similar way Einstein speaks of the "search for those highly universal laws ... from which a picture of the world can be obtained by pure deduc­tion . There is no logical path", he says, "leading to these ... laws. They can only be reached by intuition, based upon something like an intellectual love ('Einfuh­lung') of the objects of experience."' In a letter to Pop­per which is printed as an appendix to the English translation of Logik der Forschung Einstein states quite explicitly his agreement with Popper 'that theory can­not be fabricated out of the results of observation, but that it can only be invented'.

What is more, observation as such cannot be prior to theory as such, since some theory is presupposed by any observation. Failure to recognize this is, in Pop­per's view, the flaw in the foundations of the empirical tradition. The belief that science proceeds from obser­vaton to theory is still so widely and so firmly held that my denial of it is often met with incredulity . . .. But in fact the belief that we can start with pure observations alone, without anything in the nature of a theory, is absurd; as may be illustrated by the story of the man who dedicated his life to natural science, wrote down everything he could observe, and bequeathed his price-

29

Scientific Method

less collection of observations to the Royal Society to be used as inductive evidence .... Twenty-five years ago I tried to bring home the same point to a group of phys­ics students in Vienna by beginning a lecture with the following instructions: "Take pencil and paper; care­fully observe, and write down what you have ob­served!" They asked, of course, what I wanted them to observe. Clearly the instruction, "Observe!" is ab­surd .. . . Observation is always selective. It needs a chosen object, a definite task, an interest, a point of view, a problem. And its description presupposes a de­scriptive language, with property words; it presup­poses similarity and classification, which in its turn presupposes interests, points of view, and problems.' 3

This means 'that observations, and even more so observation statements and statements of experimental results, are always interpretations of the facts observed; that they are interpretations in the light of theories' . •

At every level, then, our knowledge can consist only of our theories. And our theories are the products of our minds. Even the concepts with which we think are not, as empiricists from Locke and · Hume to the present day have believed, 'given' to us from outside by objective regularities in our environment, but are developed by us in response to our own problems, in­terests and points of view: like our knowledge they too are made, not found. But of a concept it cannot be asked, as it can of a theory, whether it is true or false; and the asking of 'what is?' questions about concepts ('what is life?' . . . 'What is mind?') leads to sterile analysis and verbalism (more of this in the next chap­ter) . So we should eschew the elucidation of concepts for the testing of theories. And when it comes to this

3Conjectures and Refutations, p. 46. <The Logic of Scientific Discovery, p. 107n.

30

Traditional View and Popper's View

' the problem "Which comes first, the hypothesis (H) or the observation (0)", is soluble; as is the problem, "Which comes first, the hen (H) or the egg (0)". The reply to the latter is, "An earlier kind of egg"; to the former, "An earlier kind of hypothesis" . It is quite true that any particular hypothesis we choose will have been preceded by observations-the observations, for !xample, which it is designed to explain. But these ob­servations, in their turn, presupposed the adoption of a frame of reference: a frame of expectations: a frame of theories . If they were significant, if they created a need for explanation and thus gave rise to the invention of a hypothesis, it was because they could not be explained within the old theoretical framework, the old horizon of expectations . There is no danger here of an infinite regress. Going back to more and more primitive theo­ries and myths we shall in the end find unconscious, inborn expectations.'>

It will be seen that at this point Popper's theory of knowledge merges into a theory of evolution. We shall take up the connection, after the next chapter, in Chap­ter 4.

5Conjectures and Refutations, p . 47.

31

3

The Criterion of Demarcation between what is and what is not Science

According to what I have called the traditional view, what distinguishes science from non-science is the use of inductive method. But if there is no such thing as induction this cannot be the criterion of demarcation. What is, then? One way of reaching Popper's answer to this question is by pursuing the contrast with the view he replaced.

According to the traditional, inductivist view, what scientists are looking for are statements about the world which have the maximum degree of probability, given the evidence. Popper denies this. Any fool, he points out, can produce an indefinite number of predic­tions with a probability almost equal to !-propositions like 'It will rain', which are practically bound to be true and can never be proved false-never, because how-

32

What is and is not Science

I'VCr many millions of years go by without a drop of r.1in it may still remain true that it will, one day, rain. l'he probability of such statements is maximal because the informative content is minimal. Indeed, there are true statements whose probability is equal to I and whose informative content is nil, namely tautologies, which tell us nothing at all about the world because they are necessarily true regardless of the way things ,1re.

If we make the statement in our above example fal­sifiable by restricting it to a finite time span-'It will rain some time in the next year' -it is still virtually bound to be true, even though it can now be proved false; so it remains unhelpful. If we add to its content further, say by making it refer to a particular area-'It will rain in England some time in the next year' -we are at last beginning to say something, because there are quite a number of places on the earth's surface where it will not rain in the next year. Now, for the first time, some worthwhile information is being con­veyed. And the more specific we make our statement­we can narrow it down to 'It will rain in England in the next week', then to 'It will rain in London in the next week', and so on-the more probable that it will prove wrong, but at the same time the more informative and, if true, useful it becomes-until we get to statements like 'It will rain in central London this afternoon', which may be very far from obvious (at noon on a cloudless summer day) and are of real practical useful­ness.

What we are interested in, then, are statements with a high informative content, this consisting of all the nontautological propositions which can be deduced from them. But the higher the informative content the lower the probability, according to the probability cal­culus; for the more information a statement contains,

33

Criterion of Demarcation

the greater the number of ways in which it may turn out to be false. Just as any fool can produce statements of a very high probability which tell us practically noth­ing, so any fool can produce statements with a very high informative content if he is not bothered about whether they are false. What we want are statements of a high informative content, and therefore low proba­bility, which nevertheless come close to the truth . And it is precisely such statements that scientists are inter­ested in. The fact that they are falsifiable makes them also highly testable: informative content, which is in inverse proportion to probability, is in direct propor­tion to testability . The true statement with the highest possible informative content would be a full, specific and accurate description of the world; and every possi­ble observaton or experience would constitute a test, a potential falsification, of it; and the probability of its being true would be unimaginably close to zero, since the number of ways in which it was possible that things were otherwise would be also the highest possi­ble. 'It is not truisms which science unveils. Rather, it is part of the greatness and the beauty of science that we can learn, through our own critical investigations, that the world is utterly different from what we ever imagined-until our imagination was fired by the refu­tation of our earlier theories.' 1

A sense of awe at science and the world it reveals is to be found even in Popper's writings on politics. In The Poverty of Historicism (p. 56) he says: 'Science is most significant as one of the greatest spiritual adven­tures that man has yet known.' This is like a form of the religious sense, though Popper is perhaps not what people usually mean by a religious man; for it is, after all, central to most religious beliefs that behind the

1The Logic of Scientific Discovery, p. 431.

34

What is and is not Science

world of appearances, the everyday world of common sense and ordinary human observation and experience, there is a reality of a different order which sustains that world and presents it to our senses. Now it is precisely such a reality that science reveals-a world of unob­servable entities and invisible forces, waves, cells, par­ticles, all interlockingly organized and structured down to a deeper level than anything we have yet been able to penetrate. Men presumably always have looked at flowers and been moved by their beauty and their smell: but only since the last century has it been possi­ble to take a flower in your hand and know that you have between your fingers a complex association of or­ganic compounds containing carbon, hydrogen, oxy­gen, nitrogen, phosphorus, and a great many other ele­ments, in a complex structure of cells, all of which have evolved from a single cell; and to know something of the internal structure of these cells, and the processes by which they evolved, and the genetic processes by which this flower was begun, and will produce other flowers; to know in detail how the light from it is re­flected to your eye; and to know details of those work­ings of your eye, and your nose, and your neurophysi­ological system, which enable you to see and smell and touch the flower. These inexhaustible and almost in­credible realities which are all around us and within us are recent discoveries which are still being explored, while similar new discoveries continue to be made; and we have before us an endless vista of such new pos­sibilities stretching into the future, all of it beyond man's wildest dreams until almost the age we our­selves are living in. Popper's ever-present and vivid sense of this, and of the fact that every discovery opens up new problems for us, informs his theoretical meth­odology. He knows that our ignorance grows with our knowledge, and that we shall therefore always have

35

Criterion of Demarcation

more questions than answers. He knows that interest­ing truth consists of quite staggeringly unlikely propo­sitions, not to be even conjectured without a rare bold­ness of imagination. And he knows that such adventurous hypotheses are far more likely to be wrong than right, and can not be even provisionally accepted until we have made a serious attempt to find out what might be wrong with them. He knows that if, on the other hand, we reach for the most probable ex­planation every time we come up against a problem it will always be that ad hoc explanation which goes least beyond existing evidence, and therefore gets us least far. Bolder theorizing, though it will get us further if proved right, is more likely to be proved wrong. But that is not to be feared. 'The wrong view of science betrays itself in the craving to be right.' 2

The realization that this is so can have a liberating effect on the working scientist which Sir John Eccles has headily described. 'The erroneous belief that science eventually leads to the certainty of a definitive explanation carries with it the implication that it is a grave scientific misdemeanour to have published some hypothesis that eventually is falsified. As a conse­quence scientists have often been loath to admit the falsification of such an hypothesis, and their lives may be wasted in defending the no longer defensible . Whereas according to Popper, falsification in whole or in part is the anticipated fate of all hypotheses, and we should even rejoice in the falsification of an hypothesis that we have cherished as our brain-child. One is there­by relieved from fears and remorse, and science becomes an exhilarating adventure where imagination and vision lead to conceptual developments transcend­ing in generality and range the experimental evidence.

2The Logic of Scientific Discovery, p. 281.

36

What is and is not Science

'IIH• precise formulation of these imaginative insights tnlo hypotheses opens the way to the most rigorous tc..,ling by experiment, it being always anticipated that tlw hypothesis may be falsified and that it will be re­pl.lced in whole or in part by another hypothesis of r,n•ater explanatory power.' 3

Not only working scientists may be liberated in this w.1y. For all of us, in all our activities, the notions that Wl' can do better only by finding out what can be im­proved and then improving it; and therefore that short­romings are to be actively sought out, not concealed or JltiSsed over; and that critical comment from others, far t rom being resented, is an invaluable aid to be insisted on and welcomed, are liberating to a remarkable de­gree. It may be difficult to get people-conditioned to resent criticism and expect it to be resented, and there­tore to keep silent about both their own mistakes and others' -to provide the criticisms on which improve­ment depends; but no one can possibly give us more service than by showing us what is wrong with what we think or do; and the bigger the fault, the bigger the tmprovement made possible by its revelation. The man who welcomes and acts on criticism will prize it almost ,lbove friendship: the man who fights it out of concern to maintain his position is clinging to non-growth. Anything like a widespread changeover in our society towards Popperian attitudes to criticism would consti­tute a revolution in social and interpersonal relation­ships-not to mention organizational practice, which we shall come to later.

But to return to the scientist: his critical search for better and better theories imposes high demands on any he is prepared to entertain. A theory must first of all provide a solution to a problem that interests us. But

3J. C. Eccles: Facing Reality, p. 107.

37

Criterion of Demarcation

it must also be compatible with all known observations, and contain its predecessor theories as first approxima­tions-though it must also contradict them at the points where they failed, and account for their failure. (Herein, incidentally, lies the explanation of the con­tinuity of science.) If in a given problem situation more than one theory is put forward which does all these things we have to try to decide between them. The fact that they are different may mean that from one of them it is possible to deduce testable propositions which are not deducible from the other; and this may make our preference empirically decidable . If other things remain equal our preference will always be, after tests, for the theory with the higher informative content, both be­cause it has been better tested and because it tells us more: such a theory is better corroborated as well as more useful. 'By the degree of corroboration of a theory I mean a concise report evaluating the state (at a certain time t) of the critical discussion of a theory, with re­spect to the way it solves its problems; its degree of testability; the severity of tests it has undergone; and the way it has stood up to these tests. Corroboration (or degree of corroboration) is thus an evaluating report of past performance. Like preference, it is essentially com­parative: in general, one can only say that the theory A has a higher (or lower) degree of corroboration than a competing theory B, in the light of the critical discus­sion, which includes testing, up to some time t. '4 So at any given time, among competing theories, it is the best corroborated theory with the highest informative content that gives the best results and is therefore, or should be, the prevailing one.

The point has been made that at any given time the overwhelming majority of scientists are not trying to

40bjective Knowledge, p. 18.

38

What is and is not Science

'lVt'rthrow the prevailing orthodoxy at all but are work­Ing happily within it. They are not innovating, and tlll'y seldom have to choose between competing theo­III.'S: what they are doing is putting accepted theories to work. This is what has come to be known as 'normal ·.dcnce', from Thomas S. Kuhn's use of the phrase in !'lie Structure of Scientific Revolutions (second edition 1970). The point is a valid one, I think, but it is not a point against Popper. It is true that Popper's writings .1rc somewhat loftily exclusive in their references to the jltlthbreaking geniuses of science, whose activities his theories most obviously fit. And it is also true that most scientists take for granted, in order to solve problems at .1 lower level, theories which only a few of their col­leagues are questioning. But at that lower level their .tctivities will be found to be open to the Popperian .malysis, which is essentially a logic of problem solv­ing. Popper has. always been primarily concerned with discovery and innovation, and therefore with the test­ing of theories and the growth of knowledge: Kuhn is concerned with how the people who apply these theo­ries and this knowledge go about their work. Popper has always been careful to make the distinction, drawn already in this book, between the logic of scientific ac­tivities and their psychology, sociology, and so forth : Kuhn's theory is in fact a sociological theory about the working activity of scientists in our society. It is not irreconcilable with Popperism, and what is more, Kuhn has modified it considerably in Popper's direction since he first put it forward. Readers who want to pursue this question are referred to the symposium Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge .5

Talking as we now are of the uses to which theories are put brings us to the matter of their truth content,

sEd. Lakatos and Musgrave, Cambridge University Press, 1970.

39

Criterion of Demarcation

this being Popper's term for the class of true statements which follow from a theory. It is important to realize that all empirical statements, including false ones, have a truth content. For instance, let us suppose that today is Monday. Then the statement 'Today is Tuesday' is false. Yet from this false statement it follows that 'To­day is not Wednesday', 'Today is not Thursday', and many other statements which are true. True, in fact, are an indefinite number of other statements which fol­low from our false one: for instance, 'The French name for this day of the week contains five letters', or 'Today is not early closing day in Oxford'. Every false state­ment has an indefinite number of true consequences­which is why, in argument, disproving an opponent's premises does nothing to refute his conclusions. More to the point, it is why a scientific theory which is not true may lead us to a great many conclusions which are-more, it may be, than any of its predecessors­and therefore be highly important and useful. Of course, most of the truth content of any theory will be either trivial or irrelevant to our particular purposes: what we want, obviously, is relevant or useful truth content. But we may even get more of this from a false statement than from a true one. Suppose it is now one minute to noon: then the statement: 'It is twelve o'clock precisely' is false. Yet for almost every purpose I can think of this false statement has more relevant and use­ful truth content than the true statement 'The time is now between ten in the morning and four in the after­noon'. Likewise in science: for most purposes a clearcut statement which is slightly out is more serviceable than one which is true but vague. I am not, obviously, sug­gesting that we should rest content with false state­ments. But scientists are commonly in the position of having to use a theory which they know to be faulty, because there is as yet no better one available.

40

What is and is not Science

As I said earlier, Popper recommends that we formu­l.llt' our theories in as clearcut a way as possible, so as to expose them most unambiguously to refutation. And at the methodological level we should not, he ... ,ys, (see page 19) systematically evade refutation by n>ntinually reformulating either our theory or our evi­dence in order to keep the two in accord. This is what 111<1ny Marxists do, and many psychoanalysts. Thus I hey are substituting dogmatism for science while daiming to be scientific. A scientific theory is not one which explains everything that can possibly happen: on the contrary, it rules out most of what could pos­sibly happen, and is therefore itself ruled out if what it rules out happens. So a genuinely scientific theory places itself permanently at risk. And here we come to Popper's answer to the question raised at the begin­ning of this chapter. Falsifiability is the criterion of demar­mtion between science and non-science. The central point is that if all possible states of affairs fit in with a theory then no actual state of affairs, no observations, no ex­perimental results, can be claimed as supporting evi­dence for it. There is no observable difference between its being true and its being false. So it conveys no scien­tific information. Only if some imaginable observation would refute it is it testable. And only if it is testable is it scientific.

I have mentioned Marxism and psychoanalysis at this point because it was consideration of these, among other theories, that led the young Popper to his crite­rion of demarcation. He was thrilled and impressed by the way Einstein's theory of relativity seemed to expose itself nakedly to refutation by predicting observable ef­fects which no one would have dreamt of expecting. The General Theory (and incidentally Einstein's progress from the Special to the General Theory is the subject of an uncompleted book of Popper's) led to the

41

Criterion of Demarcation

conclusion that light must be attracted by heavy bod­ies. Einstein saw that if this were correct then light which travels close to the sun on its way from a star to the earth must be deflected by the gravitational pull of the sun. Normally in daytime we cannot see such stars, because of the sun's brilliance, but if we could, the de­flection of their light-rays would make them appear to be in different positions from those we know them to occupy. And the predicted difference could be checked by photographing a fixed star in such circumstances by day, and then again at night when the sun was not there. Eddington tested this by one of the most famous scientific observations of the century. In 1919 he led an expedition to a point in Africa from which, he calculat­ed, a forthcoming eclipse of the sun was about to ren­der such stars visible, and hence photographable, by day. On 29th May the observations were made. And they corroborated Einstein's theory. Other theories which claimed to be scientific and were at the height of intellectual fashion in the Vienna of Popper's youth, such as those of Freud and Adler, did not, and could not be made to, put their lives at stake in this way. No conceivable observations could contradict them. They would explain whatever occurred (though differently). And Popper saw that their ability to explain every­thing, which so convinced and excited their adherents, was precisely what was most wrong with them.

The only other fashionable theory of scientific pre­tensions and comparable appeal, Marxism, was in a different case. Falsifiable predictions were indeed deducible from it. The trouble was that a number of such predictions had already been falsified. But Marx­ists refused to accept the falsification, and never-end­ingly reformulated the theory (and the evidence) to keep falsification at bay. With them, in practice, as with the psychoanalysts in theory, their ideas had the unfal-

42

What is and is not Science

tft.tble certainty of a religious faith, and the insistence lltlll they were scientific was, however sincere, mistak-•' fl ,

I 'opper often pointed out that the secret of the enor­ntous psychological appeal of these various theories lay 111 their ability to explain everything. To know in ad­' oil ICe that whatever happens you will be able to under­,(,tnd it gives you not only a sense of intellectual mas­,,., y but, even more important, an emotional sense of ·•·cure orientation in the world. Acceptance of one of tiH·se theories had, he observed, 'the effect of an intel­lc•t 'lual conversion or revelation, opening your eyes to a 111'w truth hidden from those not yet initiated. Once your eyes were thus opened you saw confirming in-l.tnces everywhere: the world was full of verifications of

till' theory. Whatever happened always confirmed it. lhus its truth appeared manifest; and unbelievers were

1 ll·arly people who did not want to see the manifest truth; who refused to see it, either because it was .tgainst their class interest, or because of their repres­'ltons which were still "un-analysed" and crying aloud lor treatment. ... A Marxist could not open a newspa­per without finding on every page confirming evidence for his interpretation of history; not only in the news, hut also in its presentation-which revealed the class bias of the paper-and especially of course in what the paper did not say. The Freudian analysts emphasized that their theories were constantly verified by their " -linical observations". As for Adler, I was much im­pressed by a personal experience. Once, in 1919, I re­ported to him a case which to me did not seem particu­l.lrly Adlerian, but which he found no difficulty in oll1alysing in terms of his theory of inferiority feelings, .1lthough he had not even seen the child. Slightly o.;hocked, I asked him how he could be so sure. "Be­cause of my thousandfold experience," he replied;

43

Criterion of Demarcation

whereupon I could not help saying: "And with this new case, I suppose, your experience has become thousand-and-one-fold." '6

Popper has never-and this cannot be too strongly emphasized-dismissed such theories as valueless, still less as nonsense. From the beginning, large numbers of people, associating him with the logical positivists, supposed that he did, and in consequence misunder­stood what he was saying. 'This does not mean that Freud and Adler were not seeing certain things correct­ly: I personally do not doubt that much of what they say is of considerable importance, and may well play its part one day in a psychological science which is test­able . But it does mean that those "clinical observa­tions" which analysts naively believe confirm their theory cannot do this any more than the daily confirma­tions which astrologers find in their practice. And as for Freud's epic of the Ego, the Super-ego, and the Id, no substantially stronger claim to scientific status can be made for it than for Horner's collected stories from Olympus. These theories describe some facts, but in the manner of myths . They contain most interestingly psy­chological suggestions, but not in a testable form.

'At the same time I realized that such myths may be developed, and become testable; that historically speaking all-or very nearly all-scientific theories originate from myths, and that a myth may contain im­portant anticipations of scientific theories. Examples are Ernpedocles' theory of evolution by trial and error, or Parrnenides' myth of the unchanging block universe in which nothing ever happens and which, if we add another dimension, becomes Einstein's block universe (in which, too, nothing ever happens, since everything is, four-dimensionally speaking, determined and laid

6Conjectures and Refutations, pp. 34-35.

44

What is and is not Science

(!own from the beginning). I thus felt that if a theory is found to be non-scientific, or "metaphysical" (as we 1111)-;ht say), it is not thereby found to be unimportant, 111 insignificant, or "meaningless", or "nonsensical" . lll1l it cannot claim to be backed by empirical evidence in the scientific sense-although it may easily be, in "ome genetic sense, the " result of observation" .' 7

The first widespread misunderstanding of Popper's work, extensively and still propagated in print, consist­l'd in seeing him as advancing falsifiability as the crite­IIOn of demarcation not, as in fact he was, between '>dence and non-science, but between sense and non­"l'nse-and then (because the rnisunderstanders them­selves believed that what was not science was non­.,ense) to insist in answer to protest that it carne to much the same thing in the end anyway. For the logi­cal positivists, determined to clear away the metaphysi­cal verbiage with which philosophy had become dogged, were centrally concerned to find a principle of demarcation between statements which really did say something and statements which did not. And they ar­rived at the view that significant propositions were of two kinds. There were statements in logic and math­ematics, which did not purport to give information about the empirical world and could therefore be estab­lished as true or false without reference to experience: the true ones were tautologies and the false ones self­contradictions. And there were statements which did purport to give information about the empirical world whose truth or falsehood must therefore make some observable difference to something, and so could be established by observation. Every statement which was not a formal proposition in mathematics or logic (which Bertrand Russell had tried to show were the same

7Conjectures and Refu tations, pp. 37-38.

45

Criterion of Demarcation

thing) and was also not empirically verifiable must be meaningless. Verifiability, thus, was held to be the cri­terion of demarcation between meaningful and mean­ingless statements about the world.

Popper from the beginning attacked this on several grounds. First, whether or not singular statements were empirically verifiable, universal statements such as scientific laws were certainly not, so the verification principle eliminated not only metaphysics but the whole of natural science. Second, the verification prin­ciple pronounced all metaphysics to be meaningless, yet historically it is out of metaphysics-out of supersti­tious, mythical and religious conceptions of the world -that science has emerged. An idea which is at one time untestable, and therefore metaphysical, may with changed circumstances become testable and therefore scientific. 'Examples of such ideas are atomism; the idea of a single physical "principle" or ultimate ele­ment (from which the others derive); the theory of ter­restrial motion (opposed by Bacon as fictitious); the age-old corpuscular theory of light; the fluid-theory of electricity (revived as the electron-gas hypothesis of metallic conduction).'R Not only can a metaphysical theory be meaningful, it may actually be true; but if we have no way of testing it there can be no empirical evidence for it, and therefore it cannot be held to be scientific. Even so, theories which cannot be empirically tested may still be critically discussed, and have the arguments for and against them compared, as a result of which one of them may appear preferable to another. So far from regarding metaphysics as nonsense, Popper always declared himself to hold metaphysical beliefs, for instance about the existence of regularities in nature. A third and devastating point he made against the logical

RThe Logic of Scientific Discovery, p. 278.

46

What is and is not Science

positivists was that if verifiable and tautologous assertions alone are held to be meaningful then any debate about the concept of 'meaning' must contain meaningless statements.

It was the prolonged inability of logical positivists to meet arguments such as these that led eventually to the withering away of logical positivism. But for a long time, they mistook Popper by understanding him in their own terms. Because he was arguing with them about topics of central importance to them they took him to be a philosopher of the same kind as them­selves; and because their chief aim was to find a crite­rion of demarcation between sense and nonsense, and they were becoming uncomfortably aware of the force of some of the arguments against verifiability, they took him to be ingeniously proposing falsifiability in­stead; and many of their arguments against him rest on this false assumption. As I have already remarked, be­cause of this obsession with meaning, and their inflexi­ble view that unscientific theories were meaningless, they met his assertion that he was in fact proposing something entirely different with the protest that it really carne to much the same in the end. The truth is that Popper was never a positivist of any kind; quite the reverse, he was the decisive anti-positivist, the man who put forward from the beginning the arguments that led (after an excessively long time) to logical posi­tivism's dissolution. The totally different nature of his approach from theirs may be illustrated by the simplest of examples: the logical positivists would have said that 'God exists' is just meaningless noise, exhaust; Popper would have said that it is a statement which has mean­ing and could be true, but because there is no conceiv­able way in which it might be falsified it is not a scien­tific statement.

Not only was Popper not putting forward a criterion

47

Criterion of Demarcation

of meaning: he has always held that to do so is a major philosophical error. He also believes that habitual dis­cussion of the meanings of words is not only boring but harmful. The notion that we must define our terms before we can have a useful discussion is, he holds, demonstrably incoherent, for every time one defines a term one has to introduce new terms in the definition (otherwise the definition is circular) and one is then required to define the new terms. So we can never get to the discussion at all, because we can never complete the necessary preliminaries. Discussion, then, has to make use of undefined terms. Similarly the notion that precise knowledge requires precise definition is de­monstrably wrong. Physicists are not in the habit of debating the meaning of terms like 'energy', 'light', and all the other concepts they habitually employ. Pre­cise analysis and definition of such terms would present inexhaustible difficulties, and physicists leave them for the most part undefined. Yet the most accu­rate and extensive knowledge we have is in the physi­cal sciences. Another point to be made about good defi­nitions in science is that they are, as Popper puts it, properly to be read from right to left and not from left to right. The sentence 'A di-neutron is an unstable sys­tem comprising two neutrons' is the scientists' answer to the question 'What shall we call an unstable system comprising two neutrons?', not an answer to the ques­tion 'What is a di-neutron?' The word 'di-neutron' is a handy substitute for a long description, that is all: no information about physics is to be gained from analy­sing it. Physics would go on exactly the same without it: only communication would have been made a little more cumbersome. 'The view that the precision of science and of scientific language depends upon the precision of its terms is certainly very plausible, but it is none the less, I believe, a mere prejudice. The precision

48

What is and is not Science

of a language depends, rather, just upon the fact that it takes care not to burden its terms with the task of being precise. A term like "sand-dune" or "wind" is certainly very vague. (How many inches high must a little sand­hill be in order to be called "sand-dune"? How quickly must the air move in order to be called "wind"?) How­ever, for many of the geologist's purposes, these terms are quite sufficiently precise; and for other purposes, when a higher degree of differentiation is needed, he can always say "dunes between 4 and 30 feet high" or "wind of a velocity of between 20 and 40 miles an hour". And the position in the more exact sciences is analogous. In physical measurements, for instance, we always take care to consider the range within which there may be an error; and precision does not consist in trying to reduce this range to nothing, or in pretending that there is no such range, but rather in its explicit recognition.'~

If one wanted to be provocative one might assert that the amount of worthwhile knowledge that comes out of any field of enquiry (except of course language stud­ies) tends to be in inverse proportion to the amount of discussion about the meanings of words that goes on in it. Such discussion, far from being necessary to clear thinking and precise knowledge, obscures both, and is bound to lead to endless argument about words in­stead of about matters of substance. Language is an instrument, and what matters is what is done with it­in this case its use to formulate and discuss theories about the world. A philosopher who devotes his life to a concern with the instrument is like a carpenter who devotes all his working time to sharpening up his tools but never uses them except on each other. Philoso­phers, like everyone else, have a duty to speak clearly

9The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. ii, pp. 19-20.

49

Criterion of Demarcation

and directly; but like the physicists they should do their work in such a way that nothing of importance depends on the way they use words.

From this standpoint Popper consistently attacked both of the philosophies fathered by Wittgenstein-the logical positivism that developed out of logical atomism and dominated one generation; and the linguistic analysis that dominated the next. 'Language analysts believe that there are no genuine philosophical prob­lems, or that the problems of philosophy, if any, are problems of linguistic usage, or of the meaning of words. I, however, believe that there is at least one philosophical problem in which all thinking men are interested. It is the problem of cosmology: the problem of understanding the world-including ourselves, and our knowledge, as part of the world . All science is cosmology, I believe, and for me the interest of philosophy, no less than of science, lies solely in the contributions which it has made to it.'Jtl

Many different twofold distinctions have been applied in the history of philosophy (e .g. nominalist/realist; empiricist/transcendentalist; materialist/idealist) and none of them should be driven too hard: what can make them particularly misleading is that, whichever of them is applied, large-scale figures usually straddle the divide. But one of the dualisms which runs through most of the subject's history is that between a view of philosophy which sees it as an attempt to understand our use of concepts, and a view of philosophy which sees it as an attempt to understand the world. Obvi­ously it is impossible to understand the world without the use of concepts, and therefore people on both sides of the distinction will usually believe with some justifi-

10Preface to the 1959 edition of The Logic of Scientific Discovery.

50

What is and is not Scie11ce

cation that they are doing both jobs. Nevertheless the difference of emphasis is often extreme. It was the fa­mous distinction in the Middle Ages between the (to us, now, misleadingly named) realists, who were of the first kind ('concepts are real entities in themselves, and come before particulars: the latter derive from and de­pend on the former') and the nominalists, who were of the second kind ('concepts function as names for things, which are therefore prior: the labels can be changed without changing reality'). For most of this century philosophy in the English-speaking world has been weighted heavily towards the elucidation of con­cepts. Popper is very much a philosopher of the other kind (although he is a realist in today' s sense of the word, the sense of believing that a material world ex­ists independently of experience).

At the very beginning of My Philosophical Development Bertrand Russell tells how, until about 1917-by which time he was 45 and had done nearly all the philosoph­ical work for which he is now famous-he 'had thought of language as transparent-that is to say, as a medium which could be employed without paying at­tention to it'. Wittgenstein, on the other hand, was ob­sessed with language, and in particular with meaning, all his life. His first book, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, which was published in 1921, was the text most influ­ential on the Vienna Circle. He came subsequently to regard it as mistaken, and mistaken precisely because it incorporated a false theory of meaning. He thereupon set out to investigate the different sorts of ways in which we can be misled by our own use of language, having been so misled himself, and this nourished a new school of philosophy, usually called 'linguistic analysis'. Wittgenstein' s chief book in this vein, Philo­sophical Investigations, published posthumously in 1953, has probably had more influence on British philosophy

51

Criterion of Demarcation

since the Second World War than any other book. (The runner up, Gilbert Ryle's The Concept of Mind, was itself profoundly influenced by the later Wittgenstein.)

On page 216 of My Philosophical Development Russell wrote: 'During the period since 1914 three philosophies have successfully dominated the British philosophical world: first that of Wittgenstein's Tractatus , second that of the Logical Positivists, and third that of Wittgen­stein's Philosophical Investigations. Of these, the first had very considerable influence upon my own thinking, though I do not now think that this influence was wholly good. The second school, that of the Logical Positivists, had my general sympathy though I dis­agreed with some of its most distinctive doctrines. The third school, which for convenience I shall designate as WII to distinguish it from the doctrines of the Tractatus which I shall call WI, remains to me completely unin­telligible. Its positive doctrines seem to me trivial and its negative doctrines unfounded. I have not found in Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations anything that seemed to me interesting and I do not understand why a whole school finds important wisdom in its pages.' Russell became increasingly alienated from his profes­sional colleagues as he gr~w older. On page 214 of My Philosophical Development he wrote of 'Wittgenstein, by whom I was superseded in the opinion of many British philosophers. . . . It is not an altogether pleasant experience to find oneself regarded as antiquated after having been, for a time, in the fashion . It is difficult to accept this experience gracefully.' But at least he had done his great work, and acquired his great reputation, before Wittgenstein became known. Popper, who ex­plicitly shares Russell's view of the later Wittgenstein, 11

11see Modern British Philosophy (ed. Bryan Magee), pp. 131 ff.

52

What is and is not Science

had no chance of doing so. And it has been his quite peculiar misfortune, in Austria as well as England, to live the bulk of his professional life in Wittgenstein-dominated places and times. This is the key to the otherwise baffling underestimation of him by his professional colleagues when this is contrasted with his influence outside his own profession, and on so many such gifted people. As Geoffrey Warnock has said: 12 'Philosophers tend very much to take up the subject in the state in which they find it, and to swim contentedly along in the way the stream is going.' But in one respect Popper's experience looks like being the opposite of Russell's: late in his life, now that the failure of the Wittgensteinian philosophies to fulfil the hopes of their adherents has become impossible to ignore, he is coming into his own.

Before we leave this subject of past and present mis­understandings one further point is important to make. A striking feature of the analytic hegemony of recent decades has been a genuine belief on the part of philosophers holding that the task of philosophy is the elucidation of concepts, and of conceptual schemes, that this is really what all good philosophers have been doing all along, whether they realized it or not. Gener­ations of students have acquired modern techniques of analysis by being taught to use them on the writings of the great dead; and many books have been written about the individual giants of the past which re-present them as having been analytic philosophers of a kind. As Alasdair Macintyre has said:13 'When British philosophers do write about the history of philosophy their method customarily is to treat the historic figure concerned as much like one of their contemporaries as

12ln Modern British Philosophy (ed . Bryan Magee), p . 88. 13ln Modern British Philosophy (ed . Bryan Magee), p. 193.

53

Criterion of Demarcation

possible and to debate with him as they would with a colleague at the Aristotelian Society'. This has been going on long enough now for the radical yet sincere misunderstanding embodied in much of it to have spread widely both in the contemporary literature and in university teaching. So there is no question of any special injustice being done to Popper when it is said of him that his work is not so very different from that of his distinguished contemporaries, or that the young Popper was not as much at variance with the logical positivists as all that. The attitude has many distinguished victims besides Popper.

54

4 +I • +1+1+1+ 1 +1+ • ___/'.

I I I I I I I I I I I I I •1•1•1•1•1•1• 1 • 1 •1•

• 1•1•1•1•1•1•1•1•1•1• 1 •1•

Popper's Evolutionism and his theory of World 3

The traditional view of scientific method had the fol­lowing stages in the following order, each giving rise to the next: 1, observation and experiment; 2, inductive generalization; 3, hypothesis; 4, attempted verification of hypothesis; 5, proof or disproof; 6, knowledge. Pop­per replaced this with: 1, problem (usually rebuff to existing theory or expectation); 2, proposed solution, in other words a new theory; 3, deduction of testable propositions from the new theory; 4, tests, i.e. at­tempted refutations by, among other things (but only among other things), observation and experiment; 5, preference established between competing theories.

If we ask of Popper's schema: where did the theory or expectation in 1 come from whose breakdown con­stituted our problem, the short answer usually is: from

55

Popper's Evolutionism

stage 5 of a prior process. And if we follow successive processes back, we come to expectations that are in­born, not only in human beings but in animals. 'The theory of inborn ideas is absurd, I think: but every or­ganism has inborn reactions or responses; and among them, responses adapted to impending events. These responses we may describe as "expectations" without implying that these "expectations" are conscious. The new-born baby "expects", in this sense, to be fed (and, one could even argue, to be protected and loved). In view of the close relation between expectation and knowledge we may even speak in quite a reasonable sense of "inborn knowledge". This "knowledge" is not, however, valid a priori; an inborn expectation, no matter how strong and specific, may be mistaken. (The newborn child may be abandoned, and starve.) Thus we are born with expectations; with "knowledge" which, although not valid a priori, is psychologically or genetically a priori, i.e. prior to all observational experience.' 1

So Popper's theory of knowledge is coterminous with a theory of evolution. Problem-solving is the pri­mal activity: and the primal problem is survival. 'All organisms are constantly, day and night, engaged in prob­lem-solving; and so are all those evolutionary sequences of organisms-the phyla which begin with the most primi­tive forms and of which the now living organisms are the latest members.' 2 In organisms and animals below the human level trial solutions to problems exhibit themselves in the form of new reactions, new expectations, new modes of behaviour, which, if they persistently triumph over the trials to which they are subjected, may eventually modify the creature itself in

56

1Conjectures and Refutations, p. 47. 20bjective Knowledge, p. 242.

Theory of the World

one of its organs or one of its forms and thus become (by selection) incorporated in its anatomy. (One reason why Popper rejects empiricist epistemology, and insists that all observation must be theory-soaked, is that our sensory organs themselves, representing as they do sophisticated attempts to adapt to our environment, incorporate theories.) Error elimination may consist either in so-called natural selection-which is the failure to survive of an organism that has failed to make a necessary change, or has made an inappropriate one-or in the development within the organism of controls which modify or suppress inappropriate changes.

Like Darwin's, Popper's theory offers no explanation of the genesis of life but relates only to its develop­ment. In fact Popper believes that origination, whether of life or theories or works of art, is not susceptible of rational explanation. As he says in different parts of The Poverty of Historicism: 'In the world described by physics nothing can happen that is truly and intrinsi­cally new. A new engine may be invented, but we can always analyse it as a re-arrangement of elements which are anything but new. Newness in physics is merely the newness of arrangements or combinations. In direct opposition to this, biological newness is an intrinsic sort of newness .... Novelty cannot be causal­ly or rationally explained, but only intuitively grasped. . . . So far as newness can be rationally analysed and predicted, it can never be " intrinsic".' The problem of emergence, the emergence of the genu­inely new, preoccupies him and is one of the subjects on which there may be important contributions from him still to come.

In the biological process of evolution, seen as the history of problem-solving, one development is of an importance above all others, and that is the develop-

57

Popper's Evolutionism

rnent of language. Animals make noises with expres­sive and signalling functions, but to these two pur­poses, virtually always present in human speech, man has added at least two more, the descriptive and the argumentative functions (though the most sophisticat­ed forms of animal communication, like the dance of the bees, already include some very rudimentary de­scriptive messages) . Language made possible, among so many other things, the formulation of descriptions of the world, and thus made understanding possible. It gave rise to the concepts of truth and falsity. In short it made the development of reason possible-or rather was itself a part of the development of reason-and thus marked the emergence of man from the animal kingdom. (Incidentally the fact that man emerged from the animal kingdom by slow degrees in the way he did means that he was living in groups for a huge span of time through the process, so the widely held view that all social phenomena can ultimately be explained in terms of human nature must be wrong: man was social for a long time before he was human.) Popper believes that it is language, in the sense of a structured form of contact, communication, description and argument through signs and symbols, that makes us human not only as a species but as individuals: that for each one of us the acquisition of a language in this sense makes full human consciousness, the consciousness of self, possi­ble. (In a striking number of ways Popper's work in this field anticipated that of Chomsky.)

The first descriptions of the world seem to have been animistic, superstitious, magical; and to question them or anything else that gave cohesion and identity to a tribe was tabu and usually met with death. So the indi­vidual primitive man carne into a world dominated by abstractions-kinship relations, forms of social organi­sation and government, law, custom, convention, tra-

58

Theory of the World

dition, alliances and enmities, ritual, religion, myth, superstition, language-all of which were manmade but none of them made by him, and most of them not amenable to alteration by him either, or even open to questioning by him. As against each man, then, they stood as a kind of objective reality, shaping him from birth, making him human, determining almost every­thing about his life, yet quasi-autonomous. It is Pop­per's contention that most such things were never planned or intended. 'How does an animal path in the jungle arise? Some animal may break through the un­dergrowth in order to get to a drinking-place. Other animals find it easiest to use the same track. Thus it may be widened and improved by use. It is not planned-it is an unintended consequence of the need for easy or swift movement. This is how a path is orig­inally made-perhaps even by men-and how lan­guage and any other institutions which are useful may arise, and how they may owe their existence and devel­opment to their usefulness. They are not planned or intended, and there was perhaps no need for them be­fore they carne into existence. But they may create a new need, or a new set of aims: the aim-structure of animals or men is not "given", but it develops, with the help of some kind of feedback mechanism, out of earlier aims, and out of results which were or were not aimed at. In this way, a whole new universe of pos­sibilities or potentialities may arise: a world which is to a large extent autonomous.'3

Throughout his account of the evolution of life and the emergence of man and the development of civiliza­tion, Popper makes use of the notion not only of an objective world of material things (which he calls 'World 1') and a subjective world of minds (World 2)

30bjective Knowledge, pp. 117-118.

59

Popper's Evolutionism

but of a third world, a world of objective structures which are the products, not necessarily intentional, of minds or living creatures; but which, once produced, exist independently of them. Forerunners of this in the animal world are nests built by birds or ants or wasps, honeycombs, spiders' webs, beavers' dams, all of which are highly complicated structures built by the animal outside its own body in order to solve its prob­lems. The structures themselves become the most cen­trally important part of the animal's environment, towards which much of its most important behaviour is oriented-indeed, it is commonly born in one of them, which in that case constitutes its very first experience of the physical environment outside its mother's body. Furthermore, some of the animal kingdom's structures are abstract: forms of social organization, for instance, and patterns of communication. In man, some of the biological characteristics which developed to cope with the environment changed that environment in the most spectacular ways: the human hand is only one example. And man's abstract structures have at all times equalled in scale and degree of elaboration his transformation of the physical environment: language, ethics, law, religion, philosophy, the sciences, the arts, institutions. Like those of animals, only more so, his creations acquired a central importance in the environ­ment to which he had then to adapt himself, and which therefore shaped him. Their objective existence in relation to him meant that he could examine them, evaluate and criticize them, explore, extend, revise or revolutionize them, and indeed make wholly unexpect­ed discoveries within them. And this is true of his most abstract creations of all, for example mathematics. 'I agree with Brouwer that the sequence of natural num­bers is a human construction. But although we create this sequence, it creates its own autonomous problems

60

Theory of the World

in its turn. The distinction between odd and even num­bers is not created by us: it is an unintended and un­avoidable consequence of our creation. Prime numbers, of course, are simply unintended autonomous and ob­jective facts; and in their case it is obvious that there are many facts here for us to discover: there are conjectures like Goldbach's. • And these conjectures, though they refer indirectly to objects of our creation, refer directly to problems and facts which have somehow emerged from our creation and which we cannot control or influence: they are hard facts, and the truth about them is often hard to discover. This exemplifies what I mean when I say that the third world is largely autonomous, though created by us.' 5

World 3, then, is the world of ideas, art, science, language, ethics, institutions-the whole cultural heri­tage, in short-in so far as this is encoded and pre­served in such World 1 objects as brains, books, ma­chines, films, computers, pictures, and records of every kind. Although all World 3 entities are products of human minds, they may exist independently of any knowing subject-the Linear B scripts of the Minoan civilization have only recently been deciphered-pro­vided they are encoded and preserved in some poten­tially accessible World 1 form. (Hence the crucial differ­ence between the knowledge in people's heads and the knowledge in libraries, the latter being far and away the most important.) In Facing Reality (p. 170) Sir John Eccles subscribes to the conclusions 'that man alone has a propositional language and that this language can be employed only by subjects who have conceptual

•Goldbach conjectured that every even number is the sum of two primes. No one has yet found a proof for this, yet it fits every known case it has been applied to.-B. M.

sQbjective Knowledge, p. 118.

61

Popper's Evolutionism

thought, which is essentially thought related to the components of World 3. This thought transcends the perceptual present. . . . By contrast the behaviour of animals is derived from their perceptual present and their background conditioning .... There is no evi­dence that animals share this World even in the small­est degree. In this fundamental respect men are radical­ly different in kind from animals.'

The concept of a manmade yet autonomous third world is one of the most promising growth points of Popper's philosophy. Its application to the body-mind problem is the subject of one of his unpublished books. (The view that it is through interaction with World 3 that we become selves is alone endless in its ramifica­tions.) Quite apart from this, the World 3 theory helps us to see why both sides in the age-old dispute about whether moral, aesthetic and other standards are ob­jective or subjective have put forward unanswerable ar­guments. It offers an analysis of another problem cen­tral to Western philosophy, the problem of social change: for it is because of the objective character of man's third-world creations, and the transactions to which this gives rise between him and them, that they -ideas, institutions, languages, ethics, arts, sciences and all the other things I listed before-have histories. They do not necessarily progress, but they are of their nature open to change, and for most of the time they change continuously. Above all, Popper's theory ex­plains how an evolutionary process can have a ra­tionale without there being (as, say, Marx believed) any overall plan or plot, and also without there being (as, say, Hegel believed) some spirit or vital force moving the process along, as it were, from inside. This is an extraordinarily illuminating idea, likely to prove most rich in its applications. Ernst Gombrich's highly origi­nal use of it in the history and criticism of art has re-

62

Theory of the World

suited in work which is regarded by many as having a touch of genius. As for Popper's own use of it: espe­cially important are the solutions he offers along these lines to problems about political change which have en­grossed the greatest political philosophers from Plato to Marx; and to problems about intellectual and artistic change which have engrossed many philosophers since Hegel, and some long before.

In the history of World 3 as a whole the most impor­tant development since the emergence of language has been the emergence of criticism, and later of the accept­ability of criticism. As I said earlier, all or almost all human societies of which we have knowledge seem to have had an interpretation of the world which was ar­ticulated in some myth or religion, and in primitive so­cieties any questioning of its truth is usually punishable by death. The truth is to be kept inviolate, and handed on unsullied from generation to generation. For this purpose institutions develop-mysteries, priesthoods, and, at an advanced stage, schools. 'A school of this kind never admits a new idea. New ideas are heresies, and lead to schisms; should a member of the school try to change the doctrine, then he is expelled as a heretic. But the heretic claims, as a rule, that his is the true doctrine of the founder. Thus not even the inventor admits that he has introduced an invention: he be­lieves, rather, that he is returning to the true orthodoxy which has somehow been perverted.'6

Popper believes that as a matter of history the first schools to not only permit criticism but encourage and welcome it were those of the pre-Socratic philosophers of ancient Greece, starting with Thales and his pupil Anaximander and his pupil Anaximenes.7 This spelt the

6Conjectures and Refutations, p. 149. 7See also the quotation from Xenophanes on p. 24.

63

Popper's Evolutionism

end of the dogmatic tradition of passing on an unsullied truth, and the beginning of a new rational tradition of subjecting speculations to critical discussion. It was the inauguration of scientific method. Error was turned from disaster to advantage. For dogmatic man, like animals and the lower organisms, had stood or fallen with his theories. 'On the prescientific level, we are often ourselves destroyed, eliminated, with our false theories; we perish with our false theories. On the scientific level, we systematically try to eliminate our false theories-we try to let our false theories die in our stead.'s When man no longer shared the death of his theories he was emboldened to venture. Whereas, before, the entire weight of intellectual tradition had been defensive and had served to preserve existing doctrines, now, for the first time, it was put behind a questioning attitude and became a force for change. The pre-Socratics concerned themselves with questions about the natural world. Socrates applied the same critical rationality to human behaviour and social institutions. There began that runaway growth of enquiry and resultant knowledge which almost sensationally differentiates the civilization of ancient Greece, and its legatees, from all others.

8Popper in Modern British Philosophy (ed. Bryan Magee), p . 73.

64

• \ • 'N (. ~ r;-~

5 ~ ·/· ... -~

• ~ • J. • ••

~ ........ • • •••••••

• • • • • ••••• • • • • • • • • ••• .1..- J_.__

Objective Knowledge

A seamless unfolding of the story from the amoeba to Einstein exhibits the same pattern throughout its length. 'The tentative solutions which animals and plants incorporate into their anatomy and their behav­iour are biological analogues of theories; and vice versa: theories correspond (as do many exosomatic products such as honeycombs, and especially exosomatic tools, such as spiders' webs) to endosomatic organs and their ways of functioning. Just like theories, organs and their functions are tentative adaptations to the world we live in. And just like theories, or like tools, new organs and their functions, and also new kinds of behaviour, exert their influence on the first world which they may help

65

Objective Knowledge

to change.' 1 Popper has characterized the underlying pattern of this continuous development in the formula

P~~rs~EE~P2

where P1 is the inital problem, TS the trial solution proposed, EE the process of error elimination applied to the trial solution and P2 the resulting situation, with new problems. It is essentially a feedback process. It is not cyclic, for P2 is always different from P1: even com­plete failure to solve a problem teaches us something new about where its difficulties lie, and what the mini­mum conditions are which any solution for it must meet -and therefore alters the problem situation. Nor is it dialectical (in any Hegelian or Marxist sense) since it regards contradiction (as distinct from criticism) as something that cannot be accommodated on any level, and still less welcomed.

This formula incorporates some of the most impor­tant of Popper's ideas. He himself has put a good strong saddle on it and ridden it into many different fields of human enquiry; and where he has not been, some follower of his often has. For most of his life he maintained that it was not applicable to mathematics or logic. He was belatedly convinced that it was by the work of Imre Lakatos-who was thus in this respect more Popperian than Popper. About the arts Popper has published little, though music in particular means a great deal to him, and it was in connection with his early studies in the history of music that his seminal idea about problem-solving came to him. However, in Ernst Gombrich' s Art and Illusion the history of the visual arts is accounted for in specifically Popperian terms of an endless and 'gradual modification of the

10bjective Knowledge, p. 145.

66

Objective Knowledge

traditional schematic conventions of image making un­der the pressure of novel demands'. Virtually all pro­cesses of organic development (whether literal or figurative) and all learning process can be looked at in this way, even the process by which human beings get to know each other. The psychiatrist Anthony Storr, without having read Popper, arrived at the following conclusion: 'When we enter a new situation in life and are confronted by a new person, we bring with us the prejudices of the past and our previous experiences of people. These prejudices we project upon the new per­son. Indeed, getting to know a person is largely a mat­ter of withdrawing projections; of dispelling the smoke-screen of what we imagine he is like and replac­ing it with the reality of what he is actually like.' 2

The adoption of this approach has certain natural consequences. First of all it focuses interest on problems, not only for oneself but in one's appreciation of the efforts of others. A task does not begin with the at­tempt to solve a problem (the trial solution is the sec­ond term in the formula, not the first). It begins with the problem itself, and with the reasons for its being a problem. One learns to work hard and long at the for­mulation of problems before one switches one's main attention to the search for possible solutions; and one's degree of success in the latter is often determined by one's degree of success in the former. If one studies the work of, say, a philosopher, the first question one asks oneself is: 'What problem is he trying to solve?' In my experience most students of philosophy are not taught to ask, and do not think to ask themselves, this ques­tion. Rather they ask: 'What is he trying to say?' As a result they commonly have the experience of thinking they understand what he is saying without seeing the

2The Observer Magazine, 12 July, 1970.

67

Objective Knowledge

point of his saying it. For only by understanding his problem-situation could they do that.

Another consequence, which is fundamental to Pop­per's whole philosophy and is likely to affect the way someone influenced by it sees everything, is the reali­zation that complex structures-whether intellectual, artistic, social, administrative or whatever-are only to be created and changed by stages, through a critical feedback process of successive adjustments. The notion that they can be created, or made over, at a stroke, as if from a blueprint, is an illusion which can never be ac­tualized. This evolutionary view leads one inevitably to a concern with developments over time. For instance the history of science, or philosophy, is seen not as a record of past errors but as a running argument, a chain of linked problems and their tentative solutions, with us in the present walking forward, if we are lucky, holding one end. Whereas positivist and linguis­tic philosophers have been notoriously little concerned with the history of their own subject, a Popperian ap­proach leads to a sense of personal involvement in the history of ideas. (Hence the fact that Popper himself, a philosopher of science familiar with modern physics, is also a passionate scholar.)

A consequence of always proceeding from problems which really are problems-problems which one actu­ally has, and has grappled with-is, for oneself, that one will be existentially committed to one's work; and for the work itself, that it will have what Existentialists call 'authenticity'. It will be not only an intellectual in­terest but an emotional involvement, the meeting of a felt human need. Another consequence will be an un­concern for conventional distinctions between subjects: all that matters is that one should have an interesting problem and be genuinely trying to solve it.

Popper's philosophy-objectively regarded and not

68

Objective Knowledge

confused with the conduct of any individual, even of Popper himself-could scarcely be more undogmatic, for it puts the greatest premium of all on boldness of imagination; and it holds that we never actually know­that our approach to any and every situation or prob­lem needs to be always such as to accommodate not merely unforeseeable contributions but the permanent possibility of a radical transformation of the whole con­ceptual scheme with which, and even within which, we are operating. It is fundamentally at variance with all views of science or rationality which see these as excluding passion or imagination or creative intuition; and it condemns as 'scientism' the notion that science gives us certain knowledge and might even be able one day to give us settled answers to all our legitimate questions. A great deal of the disillusionment with science and reason which is so widespread in our age is based on precisely such mistaken notions of what science and reason are-and to that extent does not apply to Popperism. If Popper is right, there are not two cultures-one scientific and the other aesthetic, or one rational and the other irrational-but one. The scientist and the artist, far from being engaged in op­posed or incompatible activities, are both trying to ex­tend our understanding of experience by the use of cre­ative imagination subjected to critical control, and so both are using irrational as well as rational faculties. Both are exploring the unknown and trying to articu­late the search and its findings. Both are seekers after truth who make indispensable use of intuition.

But it follows that if learning and growth and devel­opment proceed through the submission of expecta­tions to the test of experience, and the acknowledge­ment of areas of conflict, and the turning of these to progressive use (or, even, on the purely intellectual level, through the control and correction of specula-

69

Objective Knowledge

tions, which may be more or less bold, by criticism, which may be more or less severe) then we can never make an absolutely fresh start. Even if it were possible for a man to begin from the beginning he would get, by the time he died, no further than Neanderthal man. These are facts which many people of a radical or inde­pendent turn of mind are intensely reluctant to face. Before we as individuals are even conscious of our existence we have been profoundly influenced for a considerable time (since before birth) by our relation­ship to other individuals who have complicated histo­ries, and are members of a society which has an infi­nitely more complicated and longer history than they do (and are members of it at a particular time and place in that history); and by the time we are able to make conscious choices we are already making use of catego­ries in a language which has reached a particular de­gree of development through the lives of countless generations of human beings before us. Popper does not say, though he might have done, that our very ex­istence itself is the direct result of a social act per­formed by two other people whom we are powerless to choose or prevent, and whose genetic legacy is built into our body and personality. We are social creatures to the inmost centre of our being. The notion that one can begin anything at all from scratch, free from the past, or unindebted to others, could not conceivably be more wrong.

This truth extends to intellectual and artistic activi­ties of every kind. The very possibility of making marks on a surface, or producing noises, in order to express or communicate or give pleasure, was reached only af­ter countless evolutionary ages; and artists who imag­ine they are going back to the beginning are, whatever they do, taking things up at a highly advanced stage and standing on the shoulders of innumerable genera-

70

Objective Knowledge

tions. In everything we are, and everything we do, we inherit the whole past, and however much we might want to make ourselves independent of it there is no way in which we possibly can. This gives tradition an inescapable importance. It is where we have to start from, if only by reacting against it. Usually the way we make advances is by criticizing it and effecting changes: we use the tradition, we ride forward on its back. The situation is fundamentally the same in the sciences as in the arts. 'All this means that a young scientist who hopes to make discoveries is badly advised if his teacher tells him, "Go round and observe," and that he is well advised if his teacher tells him: "Try to learn what people are discussing nowadays in science. Find out where difficulties arise, and take an interest in dis­agreements. These are the questions which you should take up." In other words, you should study the problem situation of the day. This means that you pick up, and try to continue, a line of enquiry which has the whole background of the earlier development of science be­hind it; you fall in with the tradition of science .. .. From the point of view of what we want as scientists­understanding, prediction, analysis, and so on-the world in which we live is extremely complex. I should be tempted to say that it is infinitely complex, if the phrase had any meaning. We do not know where or how to start our analysis of this world. There is no wisdom to tell us. Even the scientific tradition does not tell us. It only tells us where and how other people started and where they got to.'3

Since the fact that things have reached this or that point in this or that branch of this or that science, or academic field, or art (or society, or language) is an objective fact as far as each individual is concerned

3Conjectures and Refutations, p. 129.

71

Objective Knowledge

when he comes on the scene; and since any criticism he may put forward, or proposed change, or solution to a problem, has to be formulated in language before it can be tested or even discussed; any such proposal becomes an objective proposal. It can be argued about, attacked, defended, used, without reference to the man who put it forward. Indeed, this is what happens most of the time with interesting ideas. This underlines the enormous importance of objectifying our ideas in language or behaviour or works of art. While they are only in our heads they are barely criticizable. Their public formulation itself usually leads to progress. And the validity of any argument about them is again an objective matter: it is not determined by how many in­dividuals are prepared to accept it. Even if a theory is a scientific one and has been most rigorously tested by its proposer, the scientific world does not adopt it until his experiments and observations have been repeated by others. 'I know', considered as a statement about me, asserts my disposition to do and say and believe certain things, and also claims justification for this; but none of that is knowledge in the objective sense: no one is going to accord my untested assertions the status of knowledge (unless the knowledge is of some­thing in my own states of consciousness, as when I answer the questions of the optician, or tell the doctor where the pain is-and even these direct reports of our own current states of awareness are not always accu­rate, as every doctor discovers from experience). Thus in scientific work we do not take even our own obser­vations as certain, indeed we do not even accept them as scientific observations, until we have repeated and tested them. In all these respects, then, knowledge is objective. It inhabits the public domain (World 3). It is not in the private states of mind of individuals (World 2).

72

Objective Knowledge

In this private, individual sense most human knowl­edge is not 'known' by anybody at all. It exists only on paper. The desk on which I write is surrounded by shelves of reference books: let us take one which Pop­per has himself used for this example-a book of loga­rithm tables. These constitute knowledge of a prodi­giously useful kind which is in active use every day all over the world in the construction of buildings, bridges, roads, aeroplanes, machines and a thousand other things. Yet I doubt whether there is a soul in the world who 'knows' these tables, not even the man who compiled my book of them (indeed, it may even have been compiled by computer). This goes for records of every kind. Even an individual scholar devoting his life to creating his own works of scholarship normally makes notes, usually copious, from all sorts of docu­ments, books, works of reference and so on, and writes his books from his notes: he does not even 'know' (in the World 2 sense) everything in his own books. He cannot reel off all the statistical and other tables, dates, page references and so on; he cannot recite all the quo­tations word for word-indeed, the whole point is: he cannot recite his own books . They are on paper: they are not in his head. The libraries and record systems and filing cabinets of the world consist of World 3 material most of which is likewise not in anybody's head but is nevertheless knowledge of a more or less valuable and useful kind. Indeed, it is most of the knowledge we have. Its status as knowledge and its value and useful­ness are independent of whether there is anyone who 'knows' it in the subjective sense. Knowledge in the objective sense is knowledge without a knower: it is knowledge without a knowing subject.

From this standpoint Popper launches an onslaught on orthodox epistemology. 'Traditional epistemology has studied knowledge or thought in a subjective sense

73

Objective Knowledge

-in the sense of the ordinary usage of the words "I know" or "I am thinking". This, I assert, has led stu­dents of epistemology into irrelevancies: while intend­ing to study scientific knowledge, they studied in fact something which is of no relevance to scientific knowl­edge. For scientific knowledge simply is not knowledge in the sense of the ordinary usage of the words "I know" .... The traditional epistemology, of Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and even of Russell, is irrelevant, in a pretty strict sense of the word. It is a corollary of this thesis that a large part of contemporary epistemology is irrelevant also. This includes modern epistemic logic, if we assume that it aims at a theory of scientific knowl­edge. However, any epistemic logician can easily make himself completely immune from my criticism, simply by making clear that he does not aim at contributing to the theory of scientific knowledge.'4

As Popper says in the Preface to Objective Knowledge: 'The essays in this book break with a tradition that can be traced back to Aristotle-the tradition of this com­monsense theory of knowledge. I am a great admirer of common sense which, I assert, is essentially self-criti­cal. But while I am prepared to uphold to the last the essential truth of commonsense realism, I regard the com­monsense theory of knowledge as a subjectivist blunder. This blunder has dominated Western philosophy. I have made an attempt to eradicate it, and to replace it by an objective theory of essentially conjectural knowl­edge. This may be a bold claim but I do not apologize for it.'

40bjective Knowledge, p. 108.

74

• • ~· ~~ -v. -~. •

~ •• 1 •• • • • •

6 • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • •

r-. • • • • • • • • • • • . / ~ • • • • • • • • • • • ~_.._ • • • • • • • • • • • •

------- ----------- --- L__L_ - L_ '-

The Open Society

From Plato to Marx most great political philosophies have had their roots in related views not only of social and historical development but of logic and science, and ultimately of epistemology. Readers who have fol­lowed me thus far can see now that Popper's is no ex­ception. Because he regards living as first and foremost a process of problem-solving he wants societies which are conducive to problem-solving. And because prob­lem-solving calls for the bold propounding of trial solu­tions which are then subjected to criticism and error­elimination, he wants forms of society which permit the untrammelled assertion of differing proposals, fol­lowed by criticism, followed by the genuine possibility of change in the light of criticism. Regardless of any

75

The Open Society

moral consideration, he believes that a society organ­ized on such lines will be more effective at solving its problems, and therefore more successful in achieving the aims of its members, than if it were organized on other lines. The common notion that the most efficient form of society, in theory at least, would be some form of dictatorship, is on this view utterly mistaken. That the dozen or more countries in the world that have the highest living standards (not that this would be his main criterion) are all liberal democracies is not because democracy is a luxury which their wealth enables them to afford: on the contrary, the mass of their people were living in poverty when they achieved universal suffrage. The causal connection is the other way round. Democracy has played a vital role in bringing about and sustaining high living standards. Materially, as in other ways, a society is practically bound to be more successful if it has free institutions than if it does not.

All government policies, indeed all executive and ad­ministrative decisions, involve empirical predictions: 'If we do X, Y will follow: on the other hand if we want to achieve B we must do A.' As everyone knows, such predictions not infrequently turn out to be wrong­everyone makes mistakes-and it is normal for them to have to be modified as their application proceeds. A policy is a hypothesis which has to be tested against reality and corrected in the light of experience. Detect­ing mistakes and inherent dangers by critical examina­tion and discussion beforehand is an altogether more rational procedure, and one as a rule less wasteful of resources, people and time, than waiting till they re­veal themselves in practice. Furthermore it is often only by critical examination of the practical results, as dis­tinct from the policies themselves, that some of the mistakes are to be identified. For, in this connexion, it

76

Open Society

is essential to face the fact that any action we take is likely to have unintended consequences. This simple point is one whose implications are highly charged for politics, administration and any form of planning. It can be illustrated easily. If I want to buy a house my very appearance in the market as a buyer will tend to raise the price; but although this is a direct conse­quence of my action no one can possibly maintain that it is an intended one. And when I go on to take out an insurance policy to raise a mortgage, this will tend to raise the value of the insurance company's shares; and again this direct consequence of my action has no con­nection with my intentions. (See pp. 108 and 110.) Things are all the time happening which nobody planned or wants. And this inescapable fact should be allowed for both in decision making and in the creation of organizational structures: if it is not it will be a per­manent source of distortion. This again reinforces the need for critical vigilance in the administration of poli­cies, and the allowance for their correction by error elimination. So not only do authorities which forbid critical examination of their policies condemn them­selves to making many of their mistakes in a more ex­pensive form, and discovering them later, than they need; they also-if, as is usually the case, they likewise forbid critical examination of the practical application of their policies-condemn themselves to pressing on with mistakes for some time after these have begun to produce injurious unintended consequences. The whole approach, characteristic of highly authoritarian structures, is anti-rational. As a result the more rigid perish with their false theories, or at best (if they are lucky and ruthless) ossify, and the less rigid make a progress which is bruised, costly and unnecessarily slow.

It is not enough for anyone with power (whether in

77

The Open Society

government or some lesser organization) to have poli­cies, in the sense of aims and goals, however clearly formulated. There must also be the means for achiev­ing them. If the means do not exist, they must be created: otherwise the goals, however good, will not be reached. In one respect, therefore, organizations and institutions of every kind have to be looked on as ma­chines for implementing policies. And it is as difficult to design an organization so that its output is what you want as it is a physical machine. If an engineer designs a new machine but his design is not right for the pur­pose; or if he is adapting an already existing machine, but has not changed it in all necessary ways; then what will come out of it can not possibly be what he wants: it can be only what the machine can produce-which will not only be something other than what he wants but may be seriously defective by any standards, and even dangerous . And precisely this is true of a great deal of organizational machinery: it is incapable of do­ing what the people operating it require of it, regard­less of their cleverness, good intentions or well-for­mulated goals. There is need, therefore, for a political (or administrative) technology as well as a political (or administrative) science, one that embodies a perma­nently but constructively critical attitude to organiza­tional means in the light of changing goals . The im­plementation of every policy needs to be tested; and this is to be done not by looking for evidence that one's efforts are having the desired effects but by looking for evidence that they are not. Testing in this sense is usu­ally cheap and easy in practice, if only because minute accuracy is seldom necessary. The British higher educa­tion system already contains at least one department devoted to the Popperian study of institutions (set up by Tyrrell Burgess at the North East London Polytech­nic) and its results are both simple and of great poten-

78

Open Societl{

tial usefulness, for huge sums and efforts are com­monly expended on mistaken policies without any provision for the tiny sums and efforts required at the same time to see if undesired results are emerging. People in organizations tend, on the contrary, to turn a blind eye to evidence that what they want is not hap­pening, in spite of the fact that such evidence is pre­cisely what they ought to be looking for. And of course the perpetual search for, and admission of, error at even the organizational level is hardest of all in au­thoritarian structures. Thereby does their irrationality extend into the very instruments they use.

Popper's moral sentiments about political matters have been expressed, if with less depth of passion, by others. His writing is deeply moving at this level; but what is distinctive about him is the wealth and power of argumentation with which he has shown that the heart has reason on its side. For it has been widely believed, and in our century more than any other, that rationality, logic, the scientific approach, call for a soci­ety which is centrally organized, and planned and or­dered as a whole. Popper has shown that this, besides being authoritarian, rests on a mistaken and supersed­ed conception of science. Rationality, logic and a scien­tific approach all point to a society which is 'open' and pluralistic, within which incompatible views are expressed and conflicting aims pursued; a society in which everyone is free to investigate problem-situa­tions and to propose solutions; a society in which everyone is free to criticize the proposed solutions of others, most importantly those of the government, whether in prospect or application; and above all a so­ciety in which the government's policies are changed in the light of criticism.

Since policies are normally advocated, and their im­plementation supervised, by people who are in some

79

The Open Society

way or other committed to them, changes of more than a certain magnitude involve changes in personnel. So if the open society is to be a reality the most fundamental requirement is that those in power should be remova­ble, at reasonable intervals and without violence, and replaceable by others with different policies. And for this to be a genuine option people with policies differ­ent from those of the government must be free to con­stitute themselves as an alternative government, ready to take over: that is to say they must be able to or­ganize, speak, write, publish, broadcast and teach in criticism of the people in power, and must have consti­tutionally guaranteed access to a means of replacing them, for example by regularly held free elections.

Such a society is what Popper means by 'democ­racy', though as always he would set no special store by the word. The point to be emphasized is that he sees democracy in terms of the preservation of certain kinds of institutions-what used to be called, before American cold war propaganda brought the term into disrepute, free institutions-especially those which en­able the ruled effectively to criticize their rulers and to change them without bloodshed. He does not see it as just the election of governments by a majority of the governed, for that view leads to what he calls 'the para­dox of democracy'. What if the majority votes for a party, such as a Fascist or Communist party, which does not believe in free institutions and nearly always destroys them when it gets into power? The man com­mitted to choice of government by majority vote is here in an insoluble dilemma: any attempt to stop the Fas­cist or Communist party taking over means acting con­trary to his principles, yet if they do take over they will put an end to democracy. Furthermore he has no moral basis for active resistance to, say, a Nazi regime if a majority has voted for it, as in Germany it very nearly

80

Open Society

did. Popper's approach is free of this paradox. A man committed to the preservation of free institutions can without self-contradiction defend them against attack from any direction, whether from minorities or majori­ties. And if there is an attempt to overthrow free insti­tutions by armed violence he can without self-contra­diction defend them by armed violence; for if, in a society whose government can be changed without force, a group nevertheless resorts to it because it can not get its way otherwise, then whatever it may think or intend it is setting up by violence a government which will be removable only by violence-in other words a tyranny. Indeed, force may be morally justi­fied against an existing regime which sustains itself by force, if one's aim is to establish free institutions-and one has a serious chance of succeeding-for then one's object is to replace the rule of violence by a rule of reason and tolerance.

Popper points to other paradoxes which his ap­proach avoids. One already suggested is the paradox of tolerance: if a society extends unlimited tolerance it is likely to be destroyed, and tolerance with it. So a toler­ant society must be prepared in some circumstances to suppress the enemies of tolerance. It should not do so unless they constitute a genuine danger-quite apart from anything else this leads to witch-hunting. And it should try all in its power to meet such people first on the level of rational argument. But they may 'begin by denouncing all argument; they may forbid their follow­ers to listen to rational argument, because it is decep­tive, and teach them to answer arguments by the use of their fists or pistqls'; and a tolerant society can survive only if it is prepared, in the last analysis, to restrain such people by force. 'We should . . . consider incite­ment to intolerance and persecution as criminal, in the same way as we should consider incitement to murder,

81

The Open Society

or to kidnapping, or to the revival of the slave trade, as criminal. ' 1

Another, more familiar paradox, first implicitly for­mulated by Plato, is the paradox of freedom. Unquali­fied freedom, like unqualified tolerance, is not only self-destructive but bound to produce its opposite-for if all restraints were removed there would be nothing whatever to stop the strong enslaving the weak (or meek). So complete freedom would bring about the end of freedom, and therefore proponents of complete freedom are in actuality, whatever their intentions, enemies of freedom. Popper points more particularly to the paradox of economic freedom, which makes possi­ble the unrestrained exploitation of the poor by the rich, and results in the almost complete loss of eco­nomic freedom by the poor. Here again there 'must be a political remedy-a remedy similar to the one which we use against physical violence. We must construct social institutions, enforced by the power of the state, for the protection of the economically weak from the economically strong .... This, of course, means that the principle of nonintervention, of an unrestrained economic system, has to be given up; if we wish free­dom to be safeguarded, then we must demand that the policy of unlimited economic freedom be replaced by the planned economic intervention of the state. We must demand that unrestrained capitalism give way to an economic interventionism. '2 And he goes on to point out that opponents of state interventionism as such are guilty of self-contradiction. 'Which freedom should the state protect? The freedom of the labour market, or the freedom of the poor to unite? Whichever decision is taken, it leads to state intervention, to the use of

82

1The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. i, p. 265. 2The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. ii, p. 125.

Open Society

organized political power, of the state as well as of unions, in the field of economic conditions. It leads, under all circumstances, to an extension of the economic responsibility of the state, whether or not this responsibility is consciously accepted.'3 And more generally: 'If the state does not interfere, then other semi-political organizations such as monopolies, trusts, unions, etc., may interfere, reducing the freedom of the market to a fiction. On the other hand, it is most important to realize that without a carefully protected free market, the whole economic system must cease to serve its only rational purpose, that is, to satisfy the demands of the consumer . ... Economic "planning" that does not plan for economic freedom in this sense will lead dangerously close to totalitarianism.'•

In all these cases the maximum possible tolerance or freedom is an optimum, not an absolute, for it has to be restricted if it is to exist at all. The government inter­vention which alone can guarantee it is a dangerous weapon: without it, or with too little, freedom dies; but with too much of it freedom dies also. We are brought back to the inescapability of control-which must mean, if it is to be effective, removability-of govern­ment by the governed as the sine qua non of democracy. This however, though necessary, is not sufficient. It does not guarantee the preservation of freedom, for nothing can: the price of freedom is eternal vigilance. As Popper has remarked, institutions are like fortresses in that although to be effective they have to be properly constructed this alone will not make them work: they have also to be properly manned.

By and large political philosophers have regarded the most important question as being 'Who should

3The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. ii, p. 179. .Yhe Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. ii, p. 348.

83

The Open Society

rule?' and their differing philosophies seek to justify different answers: a single man, the well-born, the rich, the wise, the strong, the good, the majority, the prole­tariat, and so on. But the question itself is mistaken, for several reasons. First, it leads straight to another of Popper's paradoxes, which he calls 'the paradox of sov­ereignty'. If, say, power is put in the hands of the wis­est man, he may from the depths of his wisdom ad­judge: 'Not I but the morally good should be the ruler'. If the morally good has power he may say, being saint­ly: 'It is wrong for me to impose my will on others. Not I but the majority should rule'. The majority, having power, may say: 'We want a strong man to impose or­der and tell us what to do'. A second objection is that the question: 'Where should sovereignty lie?' rests on the assumption that ultimate power must be some­where, which is not the case. In most societies there are different and to some extent conflicting power cen­tres, not one of which can get everything its own way. In some societies power is quite widely diffused. The question 'Yes, but where does it ultimately lie?' elimi­nates before it is raised the possibility of control over rulers, when this is the most important of all things to establish. The vital question is not 'Who should rule?' but 'How can we minimize misrule-both the likeli­hood of its occurring and, when it does occur, its consequences?'

The argument up to this point, then, is that the best society we can have, from a practical as well as moral point of view, is one which extends the maximum pos­sible freedom to its members; that the maximum free­dom is a qualified one; that it can be created and sus­tained at optimum level only by institutions designed for that purpose and backed by the power of the state; that this involves large-scale state intervention in politi­cal, economic and social life; that too little or too much

84

Open Society

intervention will alike result in unnecessary encroach­ments on freedom; that the best way to minimize the dangers both ways is to preserve, as the most impor­tant institutions of all, constitutional means whereby the governed can remove the wielders of state power and put in their places other men with different poli­cies; that any attempt to render such institutions in­effective is an attempt to introduce authoritarian gov­ernment and should be prevented, if necessary by force; that the use of force against tyranny may be justi­fied even when the tyranny has majority support; but that the only untyrannical aims the use of force can have are the defence of free institutions where they exist and their establishment where they do not.

It has always seemed to me obvious that this is a philosophy of social democracy-as plainly anti-conser­vative on the one side as it is anti-totalitarian (and as such anti-Communist) on the other. For it is above all else a philosophy of how to change things, and to do so in a way which, unlike violent revolution, is rational and humane. As I believe I have now shown, it is seamlessly interwoven with Popper's philosophy of science. But we must also remember that the man who wrote The Open Society had, just behind him, 20 years of involvement with active members of the Social Dem­ocratic Party of Austria . As a Social Democrat he had become convinced that the nationalization of the means of production, distribution and exchange, which constituted the foundations of his party's platform, would not of itself solve the problems it was intended to solve yet might well destroy the values the party held most dear. Being a young man, without political influence except on his friends, what he would have liked to see but assumed he had no chance of seeing was the renunciation by the Social Democrats of the Marxist analysis of social change, and the replacement

85

The Open Society

of this by the sort of ideas he was arguing for. In the end he became disillusioned with his party, not primar­ily because of its muddle-headedness intellectually but because of the way it exposed the workers to violence which it had no programme for resisting; because of its leaders' fear of responsibility; and above all because of its complicity with the Communists in not offering all­out resistance to the Nazis' seizure of power-even though its motives were not, like the Communists', machiavellian, but characteristically flabby. He has re­tained ever since a distrust of Social Democratic parties. He would now describe himself, if pressed, as a liberal in the old fashioned sense of the word.

And here I must declare an interest. I am a demo­cratic socialist and I believe that the young Popper worked out, as no one else has ever done, what the philosophical foundations of democratic socialism should be. And like him I would like to see these ideas replace the garbled mixture of Marxism and liberal­minded opportunism which passes for political theory on the democratic left: in 1962 I published a book ad­vocating this in the context of British Labour Party poli­tics called The New Radicalism. In short, while making it clear that Popper is no longer a socialist, I want to claim his ideas for the democratic socialism in which he was so deeply enmeshed when he began to produce them, and in response to whose needs they were produced. This is where I believe their real significance is, and where their future lies. My longest-running argument with the older Popper is about what in my contention is his failure to accept, in matters of practical politics, the radical consequences of his own ideas. (If I am right about this, there is at least one famous precedent: Marx used to protest, in later life, that he was not a Marxist.)

The general guiding principle for public policy put forward in The Open Society is: 'Minimize avoidable suf-

86

Open Society

fering'. Characteristically, this has the immediate effect of drawing attention to problems. If, say, an Education Authority set itself the aim of maximizing opportunity for the children under its care it might, understand­ably, not be sure how to go about doing this; or it might start thinking in terms of spending its money on the building of model schools. But if, rather, it sets it­self the aim of minimizing disadvantage, this directs its attention immediately to the most underprovided schools-those with the worst staffing problems, the most overcrowded classes, the slummiest buildings, the least or worst educational equipment-and makes doing something about them the first priority. The Pop­perian approach has this consequence right across the board: instead of encouraging one to think about build­ing Utopia it makes one seek out, and try to remove, the specific social evils under which human beings are suffering. In this way it is above all a practical ap­proach, and yet one devoted to change. It starts from concern with human beings, and involves a perma­nent, active willingness to remould institutions.

'Minimize unhappiness' is not just a negative formu­lation of the Utilitarian maxim 'Maximize happiness'. There is a logical asymmetry here: we do not know how to make people happy, but we do know ways of lessening their unhappiness. Readers will at once see an analogy between this and the verifiability or falsifia­bility of scientific statements. 'I believe that there is, from the ethical point of view, no symmetry between suffering and happiness, or between pain and plea­sure .... human suffering makes a direct moral appeal, namely, the appeal for help, while there is no similar call to increase the happiness of a man who is doing well anyway. (A further criticism of the Utilitarian for­mula "Maximize pleasure" is that it assumes, in prin­ciple, a continuous pleasure-pain scale which allows us

87

The Open Society

to treat degrees of pain as negative degrees of pleasure. But, from the moral point of view, pain cannot be out­weighed by pleasure, and especially not one man's pain by another man's pleasure. Instead of the greatest happiness for the greatest number, one should de­mand, more modestly, the least amount of avoidable suffering for all; and further, that unavoidable suffer­ing-such as hunger in times of unavoidable shortage of food-should be distributed as equally as possible.)'s

Such an approach, Popper rightly claims, leads to a perpetual stream of demands for immediate action to remedy identifiable wrongs. And such action is of a kind most likely to secure widespread agreement, and result in manifest improvement. He is also, and again rightly, anxious to avoid Utopianism, which in practice is intolerant and authoritarian (this point will be re­turned to at greater length in the next chapter). There is, however, some doubt as to whether 'Minimize un­happiness' goes far enough to be our chief political maxim, for all its great heuristic value. It confines itself to rectifying abuses and anomalies within an existing pattern of distribution of power, possessions and op­portunity. Taken literally, it would seem to rule out even such moderate liberal measures as state subsidy of the arts, and the municipal provision of such things as sports grounds and swimming baths. So extremely conservative a position would be an unnatural conse­quence of Popper's radical philosophy, at least in an affluent society-it has, indeed, proved too conserva­tive for even a professional Conservative politician6,_ and Popper himself would not want to rest on it. We should make it a methodological rule always to apply it

88

5The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. i, pp. 284-285. 6Sir Edward Boyle: New Society, 12.9.1963

Open Society

first, and act on the consequences, but then wherever possible to look at the situation afresh, in terms of a second, richer formulation which subsumes our first one. The second formulation is: 'Maximize the freedom of individuals to live as they wish'. This requires massive public provision in education, the arts, housing, health, and every other aspect of social life-but always with the effect of extending the range of choice, and hence the freedom, open to individuals.

89

• • • • • • • • • • • • • • •

7 • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • •

• • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • •

• I • • • • • • • • • • •

The Enemies of the Open Society

• • • • • • • • • • • • • •

Although in my view the most importantly relevant aspect for today of The Open Society and Its Enemies is its philosophy of social democracy, and although this was close to Popper's heart when he wrote the book, it was not his chief reason for writing it. One has to remem­ber that for most of the period while he was working on it Hitler was meeting with success after success, conquering almost the whole of Europe, country by country, and driving deep into Russia. Western civili­zation was confronted with the immediate threat of a new Dark Age. In these circumstances what Popper was concerned to do was to understand and explain the appeal of totalitarian ideas, and do everything he could to undermine it, and also to promulgate the value and importance of liberty in the widest sense.

90

Enemies

This capacious programme places the philosophy of so­cial democracy in the most unparochial of contexts, un­parochial in time as well as in place .

Near the centre of Popper's explanation of the ap­peal of totalitarianism is a socio-psychological concept which he calls 'the strain of civilization' -a concept re­lated to that formulated by Freud in Civilization and Its Discontents. We often hear it asserted that most people do not really want freedom, because freedom involves responsibility, and most people are frightened of responsibility. Whether or not this applies to 'most people' there is a vital element of truth in it. Accepting responsibility for our lives involves continually facing difficult choices and decisions, and bearing the conse­quences of them when they are wrong, and this is bur­densome, not to say alarming. And there is something in all of us, something infantile perhaps, which would like to escape it by having the load taken from our shoulders. However, our strongest instinct being the instinct for survival, our strongest need is probably the need for security; so we are prepared to shift responsi­bility only to someone or something in whom we have greater confidence than in ourselves. (This is why people want their rulers to be 'better' than themselves, and why they embrace so many implausible beliefs that reinforce confidence that this is so, and why they are so seriously disturbed by revelations that it is not so.) We want the unavoidable and difficult decisions that govern our lives to be taken by someone stronger than ourselves who nevertheless has our interests at heart, as might a stern but benevolent father; or else to be given to us by a practical system of thought that is wis­er than we and makes fewer or no mistakes. Above all we want release from fear. And in the end most fears­including the most basic such as fear of the dark, fear of strangers, fear of death, fear of the consequences of

91

Enemies of the Open Society

our actions and fear of the future--are forms of fear of the unknown. So we are all the time pressing for assur­ances that the unknown is known really, and that what it contains is something we are going to want anyway. We embrace religions which assure us that we shall not die, and political philosophies which assure us that so­ciety will become perfect in the future, perhaps quite soon.

These needs were met by the unchanging certainties of pre-critical societies, with their authority, hierarchy, ritual, tabu and so on. But with the emergence of man from tribalism and the beginnings of the critical tradi­tion, new and frightening demands began to be made: that the individual should question authority, question what he had always taken for granted, and assume responsibility for himself and for others. By contrast with the old certainties, this threatened society with disruption and the individual with disorientation. As a result there was from the beginning a reaction against it, both in society at large and (this was partly Freud's point) within each individual. We purchase freedom at the cost of security, equality at the cost of our self-es­teem, and critical self-awareness at the cost of our peace of mind. The price is steep: none of us pays it happily, and many do not want to pay it at all. The best of the Greeks were in no doubt about the merits of the exchange: and better-it has since been said of the greatest of their social critics and questioners-to be Socrates discontented than a pig contented. Yet there was a reaction in which Socrates was put to death for his questioning. And from his pupil Plato onwards there has never been any lack of outstandingly gifted individuals opposed to society's becoming more 'open' . They have wanted it to go back, or forward, to one which was more 'closed'.

So from the beginning of critical thought, with the

92

Enemies

pre-Socratics, the developing tradition of civilization has had running parallel to it (or perhaps it would be more accurate to say running within it) a tradition of reaction against the strain of civilization, which pro­duced accompanying philosophies of return to the womblike security of a precritical or tribal society, or of advance to a Utopia. Because such reactionary and Utopian ideals meet similar needs they have deep and essential affinities. Both reject existing society and pro­claim that a more perfect one is to be found at some other point in time. Hence both tend to be violent and yet romantic. If you think society is going from bad to worse you will want to arrest the processes of change; if you regard yourself as establishing the perfect society of the future you will want to perpetuate that society when you get it, and this likewise will mean arresting the processes of change; so both the reactionary and the Utopian are aiming for an arrested society. And since change could only conceivably be prevented by the most rigid social control-by stopping people from doing anything on their own initiative which might have serious social consequences-both are led into totalitarianism. This development is inherent from the beginning, though when it comes about people will say that the theory has been perverted. It is already com­monplace to hear it said of this or that reactionary theory (e.g. that the most efficient form of government would be a dictatorship) or theory of a perfect future (e.g. Communism) that it is all very fine as a theory but unfortunately does not work out in practice. This is a fallacy. If a theory fails to work in practice this alone shows that something is wrong with the theory. (Such, quite apart from anything else, is the point of scientific experiment.)

But although the practical consequences of reaction­ary and Utopian theories are societies like those of Hit-

93

Enemies of the Open Society

ler and Stalin, the desire for a perfect society is clearly not itself rooted in human wickedness, but the reverse. The most horrific excesses have been perpetrated with sincere moral conviction by idealists whose intentions were wholly good; like those, for example, of the Span­ish Inquisition. The ideological and religious autocra­cies and wars that constitute so much of Western his­tory are the most biting exemplification of the proverb 'the road to hell is paved with good intentions'. Nor is it only fools who are led along this path: indeed the sense of dissatisfaction with existing society which starts people off is more likely to go with intelligence and imagination than with their absence-the unintelli­gent and unimaginative tend rather to accept things as they find them, and to be conservative. So the revolt against civilization-that is to say against the realities of freedom and tolerance, and their consequences in diversity, conflict, the acceptance of unpredictable and uncontrollable change, and manifold insecurity-has, as I suggested earlier, been spearheaded by some of the greatest among the intellectual leaders of mankind. And their genius has made elitism-a contempt for the inert conservatism of ordinary people, and hence a prac­tical non-acceptance of egalitarianism and democracy­all the more 'natural' for them, and them all the more comfortable in it. Popper, in his attacks on the enemies of the open society, attributes to most of them the high­est of motives, and to some of them the highest of intelli­gence, and acknowledges that their appeal is to some of our finest instincts, and to insecurities deep in us all.

He takes Plato as the supreme example of a philoso­pher of genius whose political theory embodies a wish to return to the past, and incorporates an extensive and detailed critique of it in the first of the two volumes of

94

Enemies

The Open Society and Its Enemies. The second volume contains a corresponding critique of Marx as the su­preme philosopher whose theory projects a perfect fu­ture. (He distinguishes Marxism from Utopian theories for reasons which will become clear later, but he argues out his opposition to both.) His way of tackling these heavyweight opponents, especially Marx, constitutes in itself one of the most important lessons in method to be gained from his writings. Throughout the history of advocacy and controversy the approach even of polemicists of genius, like Voltaire, has been to seek out and attack the weak points in an opponent's case. This has a severe disadvantage. Every case has weaker as well as stronger parts, and its appeal lies, obviously, in the latter; so to attack the former may embarass its adherents but not undermine the considerations on which their adherence largely rests. This is one of the reasons why people so rarely change their views after losing an argument. More often such a reverse leads eventually to a strengthening of their position, in that it leads them to abandon or improve the weakest parts of their case. It often happens that the longer two intelli­gent people go on arguing the better each side's case becomes, for each is being all the time improved by the other's criticism. The Popperian analysis of this is self­evident. What Popper aims to do, and at his best does do, is to seek out and attack an opponent's case at its strongest. Indeed, before attacking it he tries to strengthen it still further. He sees if any of its weak­nesses can be removed and any of its formulations im­proved on, gives it the benefit of every doubt, passes over any obvious loopholes; and then, having got it into the best-argued form he can, attacks it at its most powerful and appealing. This method, the most intel­lectually serious possible, is thrilling; and its results,

95

Enemies of the Open Society

when successful, are devastating. For no perceptible version of the defeated case is reconstructable in the light of the criticism, every known resource and reserve of substance being already present in the demolished version. This is what Popper is thought to have done with Marxism-hence the comment from Isaiah Berlin quoted in the second sentence of this book. And I must confess I do not see how any rational man can have read Popper's critique of Marx and still be a Marxist. But that is something we shall come to in a moment.

In the academic world the most controversial aspect of The Open Society and Its Enemies has always been the attack on Plato. All too much of the comment on this has been ignorant. I have heard many talk who as­sumed that the first volume of The Open Society primar­ily is a critique of Plato, that Popper takes a disparaging view of Plato's stature as a philosopher, and that he has been 'totally rebutted', or some such phrase, in Ro­nald B. Levinson's excellent, massive and scholarly book In Defense of Plato (to which Popper made reply in an Addendum to the fourth edition, 1961, of The Open Society). None of these things is true. Popper describes Plato unequivocally as 'the greatest philosopher of all time' (p. 98), and uses, naturally and without irony, phrases like 'with all the might of his unequalled intel­ligence' (p. 109). He does in fact subscribe to White­head's dictum that the whole of Western philosophy is footnotes to Plato. Nor is criticism of Plato his primary purpose: Levinson states the position correctly when he writes, on p. 17 of In Defense of Plato, 'Popper's at­tack upon Plato is the negative aspect of his own posi­tive conviction, which motivates his entire book, that the greatest of all revolutions is the transition from the "closed society" to the "open society", an association of free individuals respecting each other's rights within the framework of mutual protection supplied by the

96

Enemies

state, and achieving, through the making of responsi­ble, rational decisions, a growing measure of humane and enlightened life.' And far from totally rebutting Popper's judgment of Plato, Levinson concludes by conceding the most important part of it. 'First and fore­most we have agreed that Plato was proposing, in Pop­per's terms, to "close" his society, in so far as this denotes regimentation of the ordinary citizens (p. 571) .... Plato's political ideal can be classified without distortion as a very highly differentiated one among the many varieties of authoritarian governments denot­ed by our generalized version of Webster's definition of totalitarianism; it can also, as we earlier agreed, be called "totalitarian" in Sabine's carefully guarded sense of a government which "obliterates the distinction be­tween areas of private judgment and of public con­trol".' (p. 573.) Levinson disagrees pungently with a great many things Popper says, yet always with respect for his 'wide and detailed acquaintance with many fields of thought' and 'his unqualified commitment to liberal and democratic ideals, to the defence of which the entire work [The Open Society and Its Enemies] is dedicated' (p. 19). The persisting notion that Popper's Platonic scholarship has somehow been shown to be rubbishy is itself rubbishy in the sense that it is reiter­ated without knowledge. The more important philoso­phers are not guilty, however. Bertrand Russell wrote: 'His attack on Plato, while unorthodox, is in my opin­ion thoroughly justified'. And Gilbert Ryle, himself a notable Plato scholar, wrote in his review of Popper's book in Mind: 'His studies in Greek history and Greek thought have obviously been profound and original. Platonic exegesis will never be the same again'. A quar­ter of a century later, on BBC Radio 3 (28 July 1972) Ryle specifically re-endorsed this judgment.

Platonism as such is not a live issue in the political

97

Enemies of the Open Society

and social life of the modern world. Nor is the philos­ophy of the pre-Socratics. But Marxism is. In fact in one overwhelmingly practical respect the personal achieve­ment of Marx as represented by the situation of our time is without parallel in the history of mankind. Less than a hundred years ago, there he was, an intellectual in his fifties, living in Hampstead with his wife and family, devoting his days to reading and writing, little known to even the educated public. And in under sev­enty years of his death a third of the entire human race, including the whole of Russia and its empire, and the whole of China, had adopted forms of society which called themselves by his name. It is a phenomenon whose utter extraordinariness is still, I think, insuffi­ciently pondered. But few would deny that Marx is the most influential philosopher of the last hundred years, and that an understanding of the world we live in to­day is impossible without some knowledge of his polit­ical and social thought. And, unlike twenty years ago, today interest in Marxism is increasing, not diminish­ing, in our universities and among the intelligent young throughout the West.

Central to Marxism is its claim to be scientific. Marx saw himself as, so to speak, the Newton or Darwin of the historical, political, economic-in fact what one might generally call the social-sciences. He offered to dedicate the second volume of Das Kapital to Darwin, 'for whom he had a greater intellectual admiration than for any other of his contemporaries, regarding him as having, by his theory of evolution and natural selec­tion, done for the morphology of the natural sciences, what he himself was striving to do for human history. Darwin hastily declined the honour in a polite, cau­tiously phrased letter, saying that he was unhappily ignorant of economic science, but offered the author his good wishes in what he assumed to be their com-

98

Enemies

mon end-the advancement of human knowledge.' ' The heart of the matter is this: Marx believed that the development of human societies was governed by scientific laws of which he was the discoverer. His con­ception of science was unavoidably pre-Einsteinian. Like every other well-informed man of his time he thought that Newton had discovered Natural Laws which govern the motions of matter in space, so that given the relevant data about any physical system one could predict all its future states. Thus we can predict the times of sunrise and sunset, eclipses, the move­ments of tides, and so on. However, although Natural Laws enable us to foretell the future of our solar system they do not enable us to control it: they work, it might be said, with iron necessity towards inevitable results which we can scientifically predict and describe but not alter. Marx saw his own discoveries as paralleling this precisely, and he drew the parallel by a deliberate use of Newtonian terms . In Das Kapital he describes himself as having discovered 'the Natural Laws of capitalist production', and warns that 'even when a society has got upon the right track for the discovery of the Natu­ral Laws of its movement-and it is the ultimate aim of this work to lay bare the Economic Law of Motion of modern society-it can neither clear by bold leaps, nor remove by legal enactments, the obstacles offered by the successive phases of its normal development. .. . It is a question of these laws themselves, of these tenden­cies working with iron necessity towards inevitable re­sults . The country that is more developed industrially only shows, to the less developed, the image of its own future.'

The fact that Marx personally welcomed the future which he saw as inevitable is scientifically irrelevant.

1lsaiah Berlin, Karl Marx, p. 232.

99

Enemies of the Open Society

Strictly speaking he could no more be said to be ad­vocating it than an astronomer is advocating the eclipses he predicts, though he may enjoy watching them when they happen, and so look forward to them and be pleased at their coming. At all times Marx was insistent that his theory was 'scientific' in this sense­he was describing, not prescribing: and he dismissed other forms of Socialism by contrast as 'Utopian' -at best mere advocacy, at worst mere visions. Popper ac­cepts this distinction between, on the one hand, the Marxist belief that we are powerless to shape the course of history, and on the other hand Utopian be­liefs that it is in our power to make a perfect society­though Marxism has been widely misunderstood as be­ing a belief of the latter kind, and seems actually to be thought so by most Communists, who are thus what Popper would term 'vulgar Marxists' and what Marx would have termed 'Utopian Socialists'. The truth is, I think, that Communism is Utopian and Marxism not, which makes it important to keep the distinction in mind.

A crucial consequence of Marxism's claim to be science is that it must defend itself sucessfully at a scientific level of argument or else lapse into incoher­ence. And if it suffers defeat at any point on this level, it has no recourse to other forms of argument: it must, in short, submit itself to tests and accept the conse­quences. And what Popper is thought to have done is demolish its claims to scientific truth beyond any seri­ous possibility of their reconstitution. He has not done this by showing Marx's theory to be unfalsifiable. Vul­gar Marxism is unfalsifiable, but Popper does not make the mistake of attributing vulgar Marxism to Marx. Karl Marx's own theory, treated with the intellectual seri­ousness it deserves, yielded a considerable number of

100

Enemies

falsifiable predictions, the most important of which have now been falsified. For instance, according to the theory only fully developed Capitalist countries could go Communist, and therefore all societies would have to complete the Capitalist stage of development first: but in fact, except for Czechoslovakia, all the countries to have gone Communist have been pre-industrial­none has been a fully developed Capitalist society. Ac­cording to the theory the revolution would have to be based on the industrial proletariat: but Mao Tse-Tung, Ho Chi-Minh and Fidel Castro explicitly rejected this and based successful revolutions on the peasantries of their different countries. According to the theory there are elaborate reasons why the industrial proletariat must inevitably get poorer, more numerous, more class-conscious and more revolutionary: in fact, in all industrial countries since Marx's day, it has become richer, less numerous, less class-conscious and less rev­olutionary. According to the theory Communism could be brought about only by the workers themselves, the masses: in fact in no country to this day, not even Chile, has the Communist party managed to get the support of the majority in a free election; where they have achieved full power it has been imposed on the majority by an army, usually a foreign one. According to the theory, ownership of the Capitalist means of production was bound to become concentrated in few­er and fewer hands: in fact, with the development of the joint-stock company, ownership has become so widely dispersed that control has passed into the hands of a new class of professional managers. And the emergence of this class is itself a refutation of the Marxist prediction that all other classes would inevita­bly disappear and be polarized into two, an ever shrinking Capitalist class which owned and controlled

101

Enemies of the Open Society

but did not work, and an ever expanding proletariat which worked but did not own or control.

And then, to take up a different tack, what Marx and Engels had to say about most sciences has been ren­dered obsolete by the subsequent development of those sciences: for instance their theory of matter by post-Einsteinian physics, and their understanding of individual behaviour by post-Freudian psychology. The Ricardian economic foundations of Marxism itself have been swept into limbo by post-Keynesian eco­nomics, and its Hegelian logical foundations by post­Frege logic. Their view of the future development of political institutions was quite unlike what has actually occurred-chiefly, I suspect, because of their failure to take the growth of parliamentary democracy seriously (a failure again imposed on them by their theory, which precluded any such serious development).

All this constitutes the refutation of a theory claim­ing to be scientific by the basic method of submitting its predictions to the test of experience and finding them falsified. But it will be remembered from earlier chap­ters that this, though the main, is not the only kind of test a theory has to pass: it has also to meet the logical criteria of internal consistency and coherence. And Marxism's fundamental tenet that the development of the means of production is the sole determinant of his­torical change is shown to be logically incoherent by the fact that no such theory can explain how it is that the means of production do develop instead of remain­ing the same.

Marx's view that history develops according to scien­tific laws is one example of what Popper calls 'histori­cism'. 'I mean by "historicism" an approach to the so­cial sciences which assumes that this aim is attainable by discovering the "rhythms" or the "patterns", the "laws" or the "trends" that underlie the evolution of

102

Enemies

history.' 2 Examples of historicist beliefs are: that of the Old Testament Jews in the mission of the Chosen People; that of the early Christians in the inevitability of mass conversions to be followed by the Second Coming; that of some Romans in the destiny of Rome to rule the world; that of Enlightenment liberals in the inevitability of progress and the perfectibility of man; that of so many Socialists in the inevitability of Socialism; that of Hitler in the establishment of a Thousand Year Reich. One has only to start listing some of the more famous examples to note their low fruition-rate. But apart from specific theories, the general notion that history must have a destination, or if not that a plot, or at any rate a meaning, or at least some sort of coherent pattern, seems to be widespread.

If historical inevitability is to be seriously argued a limited number of explanations is possible. Either his­tory is being directed by some outside intelligence (usually God) in accordance with its own purposes. Or history is being driven forward by some inside intelli­gence (immanent spirit, life force or some such entity as 'the destiny of man'). Or there is no spirit at all, in which case entirely deterministic material processes must be at work. The first two alternatives are in an obvious sense metaphysical: they are not falsifiable, and certainly not scientific. And the third rests on a conception of science which is no longer tenable.

The reasons for Popper's rejection of these views should be clear from everything that has gone before in this book. He is an indeterminist who believes that change is the result of our attempts to solve our prob­lems-and that our attempts to solve our problems in­volve, among other unpredictables, imagination, choice and luck. Of these we are responsible for our

2The Poverty of Historicism , p. 3.

103

Enemies of the Open Society

choices. Insofar as any process of direction is at work it is we, in our interaction with each other, and with our physical environment (which we as a species have not created) and with World 3 (which we as a species have created, but which each individual inherits and can do only a little to change) who move history forward. Any purposes it embodies are our purposes. Any meaning it has is meaning we give it.

From the standpoint of these ideas he attacks all his­toricist theories. And the one on which he mounts his most powerful attack is Marxism, both because it is the most influential of them in the modern world and be­cause it is the one above all which claims that the de­velopment of history takes place according to scientific laws, and that knowledge of these laws (which it pro­vides) enables us to predict the future. Popper's argu­ment at its most technical consists in showing that no scientific predictor, whether a human scientist or a cal­culating machine, can possibly predict, by scientific methods, its own future results. In more homely terms the argument takes the following tack. It is easy to show that the course of human history has been strongly influenced by the growth of human knowl­edge, a fact which even people who regard all knowl­edge as the by-product of material development can admit without self-contradiction. But it is logically im­possible to predict future knowledge: if we could pre­dict future knowledge we would have it now, and it would not be future; if we could predict future discov­eries they would be present discoveries. From this it follows that if the future contains any significant dis­coveries at all it is impossible to predict it scientifically, even if it is determined independently of human wishes. And there is another argument: if the future were scientifically predictable it could not, once discov­ered, remain secret, since it would in principle be redis-

104

Enemies

coverable by anybody. This would furthermore present us with a paradox about the possibility/impossibility of taking evasive action. On these logical grounds alone historicism collapses; and we must reject the notion, central to the Marxist programme, of a theoretical his­tory corresponding to theoretical physics.

With the collapse of the notion that the future is scientifically predictable the notion of the totally planned society goes down as well. This is also shown to be logically incoherent in other ways: first, because it cannot give a consistent answer to the question 'Who plans the planners?'; and second because, as has been shown, our actions in any case are likely to have unin­tended consequences. This latter point, incidentally, exposes the fallacy in the assumption made by Utopi­ans generally (though not by Marx-indeed Marxism is clearer about this than many Social Democrats) that 'when something "bad" happens in society, something we dislike, such as war, poverty, unemployment, then it must be the result of some bad intention, some sinis­ter design: somebody has done it "on purpose"; and, of course, somebody profits from it. I have called this philosophical assumption the conspiracy theory of society.'3 Other fronts in Popper's onslaught on Marxism are supported by arguments which have been expounded earlier in this book and need not be repeated, the most important being that Marx, in putting forward what he called 'scientific Socialism', was wrong not only about society but also about science, his view of it being the one Popper believes himself to have overthrown. If Popper is right about science then his is also the only genuinely scientific political philosophy; and also, most importantly, the hostility to science and the revolt against reason, both of which are so

Wopper in Modern British Philosophy (ed. Bryan Magee), p. 67.

105

Enemies of the Open Society

prominently expressed in today's world, are directed at false conceptions of science and reason.

Popper's arguments that we can know of no mean­ing in history other than that invested in it by human beings have a psychologically disturbing, because disorienting, effect on some people who feel them­selves placed in some sort of existentialist void by them. Others fear that if Popper is right all values and norms must be arbitrary. The latter misapprehension is well dealt with in The Open Society (vol. i, pp. 64-65). 'Nearly all misunderstandings can be traced back to one fundamental misapprehension, namely, to the be­lief that "convention" implies "arbitrariness"; that if we are free to choose any system of norms we like, then one system is just as good as any other. It must, of course, be admitted that the view that norms are conventional or artificial indicates that there will be a certain element of arbitrariness involved, i.e. that there may be different systems of norms between which there is not much to choose (a fact that has been duly emphasized by Protagoras). But artificiality by no means implies full arbitrariness. Mathematical calculi, for instance, or symphonies, or plays, are highly artifi­cial, yet it does not follow that one calculus or sympho­ny or play is just as good as any other.' His full expla­nation of why not, and of what he believes to be man's true orientation, is provided by his evolutionary theory of knowledge, in particular his theory of World 3, which is to be found in writings discussed by us ear­lier, though published by him later.

Some of Popper's arguments against Marxism apply to Utopianism-for instance his argument against the possibility of societies being 'swept away' and replaced by something 'wholly new'. 'The Utopian approach may be described as follows. Any rational action must have a certain aim. It is rational in the same degree as

106

Enemies

it pursues its aim consciously and consistently, and as it determines its means according to this end. To choose the end is therefore the first thing we have to do if we wish to act rationally; and we must be careful to determine our real or ultimate ends, from which we must distinguish clearly those intermediate or partial ends which actually are only means, or steps on the way, to the utlimate end. If we neglect this distinction, then we must also neglect to ask whether these partial ends are likely to promote the ultimate end, and ac­cordingly, we must fail to act rationally. These prin­ciples, if applied to the realm of political activity, de­mand that we must determine our ultimate political aim, or the Ideal State, before taking any practical ac­tion. Only when this ultimate aim is determined, in rough outline at least, only when we are in possession of something like a blueprint of the society at which we aim, only then can we begin to consider the best ways and means for its realization, and to draw up a plan for practical action.' 4

Popper's arguments against any approach to politics which starts from a blueprint and then sets out to actu­alize it have to be faced by any idealist if he seriously wants to be an idealist without illusions. There is first the argument that wherever you want to go you have no choice but to start from where you are. It is no more possible to start from scratch in politics than it is in epistemology or science or the arts. All real, as distinct from envisaged, change can only be change in actually existing circumstances. Utopians commonly assert that before this or that thing can be changed, society as a whole will have to be changed; but what this comes down to is the assertion that before you can change anything you must change everything, which is self-

4The Open Society and Its Enemies, val. i, p. 157.

107

Enemies of the Open Society

contradictory. Second, whatever actions we take will have some unintended consequences which may easily be at odds with our blueprint. And the more wholesale the action the more plentiful the unintended conse­quences. To claim rationality for sweeping plans to change society as a whole is to claim a degree of de­tailed sociological knowledge which we simply do not possess. And to talk in the Utopian way about means and ends is to use a metaphor misleadingly: what is actually in question is one set of events close in time, which are referred to as 'the means', followed by an­other more distant set of events, which are called 'the end'. But these will be followed in turn-unless history just stops-by yet further successive sets of events. So the end is not an end in fact, and there can be no seri­ous defence for privileges claimed for what is merely the second set of events in an endless series. What is more the first set of events, being closer in time, are more likely to materialize in the form envisaged than the second, more distant and more uncertain. Rewards promised by the latter are less sure than the sacrifices made for them in the former. And if all individuals have equal moral claims it is wrong to sacrifice one generation to the next.

As to the blueprint itself, it is an ascertainable fact that people differ about the kind of society they want­even conventional Conservatives, Liberals and Social­ists do so, to allow for no others. So whatever the na­ture of the group that gets into power with the aim of putting its blueprint into production it will have to ren­der the opposition of others ineffective, if not coerce them into serving an end they disagree with. Whereas a free society cannot impose common social purposes, a government with utopian aims has to, and is bound to become authoritarian. The radical reconstruction of society is a huge undertaking which is bound to take a

108

Enemies

long time: is it even remotely likely that social objec­tives and ideas and ideals will not substantially change during that time, especialy as it will be, by definition, a time of revolutionary upheaval? Yet if they do change it means that what appeared the most desirable form of society, even to the people who made the blueprint, will diverge further and further from it as they ap­proach it-and further still from anything wanted by their successors, who had nothing to do with making the blueprint in the first place. This is related to an­other argument, to the effect that not only are the plan­ners themselves part of the society they wish to sweep away but their social experience, and therefore social assumptions and aims, however critical, are bound to have been deeply conditioned by it. So really sweeping it away includes sweeping them and their plans away too. In any case a social reconstruction which is radical and, because radical, prolonged, is bound to uproot and disorient very large numbers of people, thereby creating widespread . psychological as well as material adversity; and one must expect at least some people to oppose measures that threaten them with these effects. Such people will be seen by the power-holders trying to actualize the ideal society as opposing the wholly good out of self-interest-and there will be half a truth in this. So they will be seen as enemies of society. Inevitably this will make them victims in what follows. For ideal goals, being unattainable, are a long time coming, and the period over which criticism and oppo­sition have to be stifled is prolonged more and more; so intolerance and authoritarianism will intensify, albeit with the best of intentions. And precisely because in­tentions and goals are thought to be ideal the persistent failure of the latter to materialize is bound to give rise to accusations that someone is rocking the boat-there must be sabotage, or foreign interference, or corrupt

109

Enemies of the Open Society

leadership, for all posible explanations that rule out criticism of the revolution involve malignity on some­body's part. So it becomes necessary to identify cul­prits, and to root them out; and if culprits there must be, culprits will be found. By now the revolutionary regime will be up to its neck in the unforeseen conse­quences of its actions. For even after enemies of the revolution have received their deserts the revolutionary goals will obstinately go on not materializing; and the ruling group will be driven more and more to grasping at immediate solutions to urgent problems (what Pop­per calls 'unplanned planning') which is usually one of the things for which they most despised their predeces­sor regimes. This will open yet wider the disparity be­tween their declared aims and what they are actually doing-the latter more and more coming to resemble the activities of the most cynically unutopian govern­ments.

The fact is that nearly all of us require the most im­portant aspects of the social order to continue function­ing through any reconstruction: people must continue to be fed and clothed and housed and kept warm; chil­dren, if they are not to be intolerably victimized, must continue to be cared for and educated; transport, medi­cal, police and fire services must continue to operate. And in a modern society these things depend on large­scale organization. To sweep it all away at once would be to create, literally, a chaos; and to believe that some­how out of that an ideal society would emerge borders on the mad, as does even the belief that a society merely better t!Jan the one we have now is more likely to emerge from chaos than from the society we have now. However, even if we were determined to, we could never, despite our dreams of perfection, sweep everything away and begin again. Mankind is like the crew of a ship at sea who can choose to remodel any

110

Enemies

part of the ship they live in, and can remodel it entirely section by section, but cannot remodel it all at once.

The fact that change is never going to stop renders the very notion of a blueprint for the good society non­sensical, for even if society became like the blueprint it would instantly begin to depart from it. So not only are ideal societies unattainable because they are ideal, they are unattainable also because, to correspond to any sort of blueprint at all, they would have to be static, fixed, unchanging; and no foreseeable society is going to be those things. Indeed, the pace of social change seems to get faster, not slower, with every year that passes. And the process is going to have, so far as we can see, no end. So to have any hope at all of corresponding to the realities a political approach must be concerned not with states of affairs but with change. Our task is not the impossible one of establishing and preserving a particular form of society: it is to maximize our control over the actual changes that occur in a process of change which is never-ending-and to use that control wisely.

And because society will never be perfect, to raise questions like 'What is the ideal form of society?' is academic. Indeed, Popper condemns 'what is?' ques­tions generally: 'What is gravity?' and 'What is life?' are as irrelevant to making progress in science (see pp. 30 and 48) as 'what is freedom?' and 'What is justice?' are to making progress in politics. Equally to be con­demned are 'What is?' questions disguised by being at one remove-for instance 'Is Britain really a democ­racy?' which leads straight to 'What do you mean by democracy?' or 'What is democracy?'. Their quasi­magical attempt to capture the essence of reality in a definition has led Popper to brand the use of such questions as 'essentialism'. In politics the essentialist approach leads almost naturally to Utopianism and

111

Enemies of the Open Society

doctrinal conflict. Genuinely important questions are more like 'What should we do in these circumstances? What are your proposals?' To them the answers can be fruitfully discussed and criticized; and then, if they stand up to that, tried out. Nothing that is not a proposal can ever be put into practice. So what matters in politics, as in science, is not the analysis of concepts but the critical discussion of theories, and their subjec­tion to the tests of experience.

Because authoritarian structures incorporate the same mistaken notions of certainty, and the same mis­taken assumptions about method, as does the tradi­tional view of science, the arguments underlying Pop­per's criticism of the view that in politics we even can, let alone should aim to, establish and preserve a certain state of society are in point after point the same as those underlying his criticism of the view that science even can, let alone should aim to, establish and pre­serve certain knowledge. And his view, by contrast, that science is scientific method, and his view of how that method is to be seen, are at all levels interrelated with his view that politics is political method, and his view of how that method is to be seen. In both cases what he asks us to use with imagination and feeling is an unending feedback process in which the bold pro­pounding of new ideas is invariably attended by their subjection to rigorous error elimination in the light of experience. He calls this approach 'critical rationalism' in philosophy; in politics he calls it, 'piecemeal social engineering'. This phrase is trebly unfortunate: 'piece­meal' is usually pejorative anyway, and here it has the additional disadvantage of masking the radicalism of the method proposed; and 'engineering' has unpleas­ant connotations when applied to human beings. It sounds heartless, but nothing could be more passion­ate than Popper's advocacy of it, or more humane than

112

Enemies

some of his arguments. In trying to show how his phi­losophy is all of a piece I have concentrated in this book on the logical arguments and their interrelationships, but even more important are the moral arguments; and for these, as for so much else that we have not dealt with, the reader is advised to turn to Popper's books.

113

~

Postscript

The first edition of this book appeared in 1973. When I wrote it I had access to many unpublished writings by Popper which have since seen the light of day. Al­though I was not then able to refer to them in my text I took account of them in my presentation of his ideas. But since they are available now, something needs to be said about them explicitly.

Throughout Popper's working life it has been quite common for publication of his books to be held up for decades. His first, Die Beiden Grundprobleme der Erkennt­nistheorie (The Two Fundamental Problems of Epistemology), was written during the years 1930-3 but not published until 1979. His second, Logik der Forschung, 1934 (The Logic of Scientific Discovery, 1959), was published promptly enough in German but did not appear in its more influential English translation for another twenty­five years. In the meantime his ideas on some of the subjects dealt with in it had changed, or at least devel­oped, and at first he intended to add a postscript to the English edition in which he would discuss this. But the postscript grew under his pen to such an extent that it became a book in its own right. The decision was then taken to bring it out separately as a companion volume,

114

L

Postscript

and The Logic of Scientific Discovery appeared without it. Meanwhile Postscript had been set up in print, in 1956-7; but Popper persistently went on delaying publication of it while incorporating lavish amounts of new materi­al in the galley proofs. This process continued until 1962, the book expanding all the time, until finally he turned away from it to work on other things. The consequence was that one of his largest and most im­portant works remained in proof for a quarter of a cen­tury. It was not published until 1982-3. Even then we owe its publication not directly to Popper but to an initiative taken by W. W. Bartley III, who undertook to do the necessary editorial work involved. It was Dr. Bartley who decided to bring it out in three volumes, each with the subtitle From the Postscript to The Logic of Scientific Discovery. The main titles are, in sequence, Realism and the Aim of Science; The Open Universe: an Ar­gument for Indeterminism; and Quantum Theory and the Schism in Physics. Although published when Popper was eighty, they were written when he was at the height of his powers, and they contain some of his most valuable work.

In 1974 a two-volume appraisal of Popper's philos­ophy was published in The Library of Living Philosophers, edited by P. A. Schilpp. It was in four parts, the first being an intellectual autobiography by Popper, the sec­ond thirty-three critical articles by distinguished fig­ures, the third his 'Reply to My Critics', and the fourth an exhaustive bibliography up to that time. In 1976 he brought out the intellectual autobiography separately under the title Unended Quest.

In 1977, in collaboration with John Eccles, the Nobel prize-winning neurobiologist, he published The Self and Its Brain, an investigation of the body-mind problem. This volume is in three sections: Part I, by Popper, reviews the history of the conflict between materialism

115

Postscript

and dualism and argues for the latter; Part II, by Eccles, examines mind from a neurological standpoint; and Part III consists of a series of dialogues between the two men about the problems raised, some of them per­haps insoluble.

There remains a wealth of unpublished material. More decades will probably pass before all of it has come out. It includes two volumes which have stood complete in typescript for several years already. Both of these are collections of shorter pieces, one with the provisional title Philosophy and Physics (which con­sciously rings the changes on the title of Heisenberg's Physics and Philosophy), the other The Myth of the Frame­work. Of special interest in the latter is an extended critique of the Frankfurt School of social and political thought. For the rest, Popper's unpublished writings contain a number of original contributions to subjects on which he has published little or nothing. As far as the reading public is concerned, then, his philosophy will be a developing one for many years to come.

116

Bibliography

Books by Karl Popper

The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Hutchinson, first pub­lished 1959, latest revised (tenth) edition 1980. This is an English translation, with new footnotes and ap­pendices, of Logik der Forschung, first published in Vienna in 1934 (dated 1935); seventh edition, re­vised, with six new appendices, Tiibingen 1982. (U.S. edition: Harper & Row)

The Open Society and Its Enemies, Routledge & Kegan Paul, two volumes, first published 1945, latest re­vised (fifth) edition 1966. (U.S. edition: Princeton University Press)

The Poverty of Historicism, Routledge & Kegan Paul, first published in book form 1957, corrected edition 1961. (U.S. edition: Harper & Row)

Conjectures and Refutations: the Growth of Scientific Knowl­edge, Routledge & Kegan Paul, first published 1963, latest revised (fourth) edition 1972. (U.S. edition: Harper & Row)

117

Bibliography

Objective Knowledge: an Evolutionary Approach, Oxford University Press, first published 1972, reprinted with corrections 1973, latest (sixth) revised and expanded edition 1981.

Unended Quest: an Intellectual Autobiography, published as a separate volume by Fontana Paperbacks 1976, latest revised (sixth) edition 1982. (U.S. edition: Open Court) This is an amended version of 'Autobi­ography of Karl Popper', first published in 1974 in The Philosophy of Karl Popper in The Library of Living Philosophers, ed. P. A. Schilpp, Open Court, La Salle, Illinois.

The Self and Its Brain (with J. C. Eccles), Springer Inter­national, first published 1977, corrected edition 1981.

Die Beiden Grundprobleme der Erkenntnistheorie, J. C. B. Mohr, Tubingen, first published 1979. An English translation will be published by Open Court in 1988.

Realism and the Aim of Science. From the Postscript to The Logic of Scientific Discovery, ed. W. W. Bartley III, Hutchinson, first published 1983. (U.S. edition: Row­man & Littlefield)

The Open Universe: An Argument for Indeterminism . From the Postscript to The Logic of Scientific Discovery, ed. W. W. Bartley III, Hutchinson, first published 1982. (U.S. edition: Rowman & Littlefield)

Quantum Theory and the Schism in Physics. From the Post­script to The Logic of Scientific Discovery, ed. W. W. Bartley III, Hutchinson, first published 1982. (U.S. edition: Rowman & Littlefield)

118

Bibliography

See also Popper's contributions to Modern British Philos­ophy by Bryan Magee, Seeker & Warburg, first pub­lished 1971; and to The Philosophy of Karl Popper, ed. P. A. Schilpp, Open Court, La Salle, Illinois, first published 1974.

119

Bryan Magee, who was born in London in 1930, was educated at Christ's Hospital and (after military service abroad) Keble College, Oxford, where he took two hon­ours degrees-in modern history and in philosophy, politics and economics-and was President of the Union. After teaching for a year in Sweden, then hold­ing a fellowship in philosophy at Yale, he left academic life in 1956 to become a writer, critic and broadcaster. He is a frequent performer on radio and television, and a member of both the music and drama sections of the Critics Circle. He continued this range of activities after taking up academic work once more in 1970, when he became a lecturer in philosophy at Balliol College, Ox­ford. In 1973 he was elected a visiting fellow of All Souls. From 1974 to 1983 he was a Member of Parliament. His fifteen books have been translated into as many lan­guages, and include Aspects of Wagner (1968), Modern British Philosophy (1971), Men of Ideas (1978), The Philoso­phy of Schopenhauer (1983), and The Great Philosophers (1987), all of which are available in the United States.

120

Bryan Magee, who was born in London in 1930, was educated at Christ's Hospital and (after military service abroad) Keble College, Oxford, where he took two hon­ours degrees-in modern history and in philosophy, politics and economics-and was President of the Union. After teaching for a year in Sweden, then hold­ing a fellowship in philosophy at Yale, he left academic life in 1956 to become a writer, critic and broadcaster. He is a frequent performer on radio and television, and a member of both the music and drama sections of the Critics Circle. He continued this range of activities after taking up academic work once more in 1970, when he became a lecturer in philosophy at Balliol College, Ox­ford. In 1973 he was elected a visiting fellow of All Souls. From 1974 to 1983 he was a Member of Parliament. His fifteen books have been translated into as many lan­guages, and include Aspects of Wagner (1968), Modern British Philosophy (1971), Men of Ideas (1978), The Philoso­phy of Schopenhauer (1983), and The Great Philosophers (1987), all of which are available in the United States.

120