PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a...

26
PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good

Transcript of PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a...

Page 1: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

PH354 Aristotle

Week 8. Puzzles about the Good

Page 2: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

Plan

• Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good, and eudaimonia.

• Look at Book X, Aristotle offers further discussion of the chief good for man that appears to be very different from the Book I account.

• What is going on? Is Aristotle’s discussion coherent? If so, how?

• We will look at some different proposals about how we might start to make headway with these questions. (‘Inclusive’ versus ‘dominant’ readings).

Page 3: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

The Good

• The good for an action or activity is ‘what it is aimed at’.

• At its most general the notion of the aim of an action or an activity is ‘what the action is to bring about’ or ‘what the success of the action or activity consists in’.

• It is not to be assumed right away that the aim of an action is always the intention.

• (Aristotle offers the examples; the aim of the medical art is health, the aim of shipbuilding is a vessel, economics is wealth.)

Page 4: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

The Chief Good

• If, then, there is some end of the things we do, which we desire for its own sake (everything else being desired for the sake of this), and if we do not choose everything for the sake of something else (for at that rate the process would go on to infinity, so that our desire would be empty and vain), clearly this must be the good and the chief good.’ (1094a18-22)

Page 5: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

Eudaimonia

• The chief good, Aristotle says, is clearly eudaimonia. • Ross translates this as ‘happiness’ which I will follow

(with the appropriate warnings understood).• He seems to think that this is relatively

uncontroversial (because so far relatively formal)• But if what it is that we should ultimately aim at is to

live well, what is involved in living well?

Page 6: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

The Function Argument

• Aristotle thinks that the state of happiness or what we should aim at is fixed by our nature and the kinds of things we are.

• The chief good or the final good for man is just our form, in its active or fully actual state.

• So we can understand what happiness is by understanding what our form is.

Page 7: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

The Function Argument

• 1. The final good for things of a kind is determined by the function of things of that kind (by what they are for, or what they are supposed to do)

• 2. An assumption [The function of something must be the function of it qua ‘what is peculiar to that thing’]

Page 8: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

The Function Argument

• 3. The function of human beings is living a life that involves rational activity (activity of the rational part of the soul)

• (‘There remains, then, an active life of the element that has a rational principle (of this, one part has such a principle in the sense of being obedient to one, the other in the sense of possessing one and exercising thought)’

• 4. The function of a thing of a certain kind is the same as the function of a good thing of that kind.

• (What we mean when we ask what the function of a thing of a kind is is what its function is insofar as it is a good thing of that kind; i.e. a thing that does the things that it is supposed to do.)

Page 9: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

The Function Argument

• 5. So ‘the function of man (is) the good and noble performance of actions of the soul implying a rational principle; where such actions are well performed when ‘they are performed in accordance with the appropriate excellence’.

• 6. Therefore, ‘human good turns out to be activity of soul in conformity with excellence, and if there are more than one excellence, in conformity with the best and most complete.’

Page 10: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

Excellence

• ‘Excellence’ (Ross) translates arete (cf ‘virtue’). • ‘Excellence’ (adj.) is success. ‘Excellences’ are

capacities• Human excellence concerns the soul not body• There are distinctions in the soul. Though

appetite and desire is not a matter of thinking, the passions ‘listen to’ and ‘obey’ reason.

Page 11: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

Excellence

• There are both moral and intellectual excellences• Moral: courage, temperance, prudence• Intellectual: Philosophical wisdom, understanding• If happiness is rational activity in accordance with

excellence, then the Book I account suggests that a good life is one that consists in the active exercise of both moral and an intellectual capacities.

Page 12: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

EN Book X

• In Book X, chapter 7, Aristotle appears to offer a radically different conception of eudaimonia.

• He argues that the highest good for man is an activity he calls theoria.

• Theoria is standardly translated (as in Ross) as ‘contemplation’.

Page 13: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

EN Book X

• If happiness is activity in accordance with excellence, it is reasonable that it should be in accordance with the highest excellence; and this will be that of the best thing in us. Whether it be intellect or something else that is this element which is thought to be our natural ruler and guide and to take thought of things noble and divine, whether it be itself also divine or only the most divine element in us, the activity of this in accordance with its proper excellence will be complete happiness. That this activity is contemplative we have already said. (1177a11-18)

Page 14: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

EN Book X: Contemplation

• (i) It is an activity of intellect (nous). • (ii) The objects of contemplation are truths.

(1177a23)• (iii) It involves pleasure (“the activity of

wisdom is admittedly the pleasantest of all excellent activities.”) (1177a25-27)

Page 15: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

EN Book X: Contemplation

• (iv) Contemplation is an activity that is its own end, and does not involve an external aim. It is self-sufficient. (“And this activity alone would seem to be loved for its own sake; for nothing arises from it apart from the contemplating, while from practical activities we gain more or less apart from the action.” 1177b1-4)

• (v) It is leisurely. In this it is contrasted with the messy and painful business of politics and generalship (1077b10-25)

• (vi) It is divine.

Page 16: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

EN Book X: Contemplation as Philosophy

• “And we think happiness has pleasure mingled with it, but the activity of wisdom is admittedly the pleasantest of all excellent activities; at all events philosophy is thought to offer pleasures marvelous for their purity and their enduringness, and it is to be expected that those who know will pass their time more pleasantly than those who inquire.” (1177a25-27)

Page 17: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

Problems with Book X

1. Coherence with previous books2. Philosophical adequacy

Page 18: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

‘Dominant’ vs. ‘inclusive’

• Dominant: There is just one type of activity that is the chief good. This might be any concrete excellence, but in the context of Book X, the claim is that it is intellectual.(See Kraut (1979)(1989))

• Inclusive: There are many different types of activity that are ‘chief goods’ (i.e. not good in virtue of their relation to anything else), or: the chief good is a ‘complete package’ of activities, rather than just one activity. (See Ackrill (1974), Bostock (2000), Cooper (1975) and Hardie (1965))

Page 19: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

Inclusivism

1. What kind of thing is ‘happiness’ on this view? What is it for eudaimonia to be a ‘package’ of goods which are good in themselves?

2. What is the evidence that this is indeed Aristotle’s view?

3. If Aristotle does have an inclusive conception of the end, how do we make sense of the discussion in Book X?

Page 20: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

Inclusivism: J.M. Cooper (1975(1986))

1. Things can be ends in different ways. Eudaimonia is a second-order end. Concrete goods are first-order.

2. There is a range of textual and philosophical evidence for the view. He argues that there are specific claims in Book VI that are hard to reconcile with dominance. Dominance is objectionable philosophically. EE account.

3. Book X view forced on Aristotle by metaphysics. Doesn’t compete with a view about the inclusiveness of the ends of ordinary life.(?)

Page 21: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

Inclusivism

• “For, being a part of virtue as a whole it (viz. theoretical wisdom) causes a man to flourish (merely) by being possessed and exercised.” (1144a5-6) (See f.n. 23 in Cooper (1975)(1986), p.112)

Page 22: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

Dominance in Book I

• ‘(H)uman good turns out to be activity of soul in conformity with excellence, and if there is more than one excellence, in conformity with the best and most complete.’ (1098a15-18)

• (See Ackrill (1974), Bostock (2000) for inclusivist response and Kraut (1989) for ‘dominant’ reading)

Page 23: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

Dominance

1. Coherence: How do we explain the coherence of Book X with the earlier parts of NE?

2. Adequacy: Isn’t the view attributed to Aristotle simply unsatisfactory? Isn’t that a reason to think it cannot have been his view?

Page 24: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

Dominance: Kraut (1989)

• Coherence: In order to live the life of a philosopher, one needs the ethical virtues (one needs to have the relevant excellences, and exercise them).

• But exercising or actualizing those virtues is not what the philosophical life consists in. The discussion of Book X coheres with the previous books, because those books spell out what is needed in order to live a philosophical life, the life which is the best way that human beings can live.

• The best life is ethical, in part, because it requires ethical behaviour and excellence as its foundation.

Page 25: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

Dominance: Kraut (1989)

• Adequacy: • (a) Promoting ethical values and cultivating ethical activity

is to cultivate the foundations of philosophical life. • (b) In Book X, Aristotle doesn’t deny that those who engage

in the political life, and who exercise their moral virtues in the life of the polis are, or can be, happy, or flourishing. But their eudaimonia is secondary.

• Aristotle doesn’t think we should all be doing philosophy. In the messy (and resource-limited) place that is the world as it is, those with the relevant qualities may owe it to their communities to pursue this imperfectly flourishing life.

Page 26: PH354 Aristotle Week 8. Puzzles about the Good. Plan Look at Book I. In Book I Aristotle offers a famous characterization of the notion of the chief good,

Taking Stock: Dominant or Inclusive

• We have looked at Aristotle’s function argument and the way that he introduces the notion of eudaimonia. Eudaimonia is that at which a life aims; what constitutes the final cause or end of a human being qua human being.

• The discussion of theoria in Book X focuses problems for our reading of NE, given what seems to be suggested in Book I.

• Distinction between ‘inclusive’ and ‘dominant’ conceptions of Aristotle’s views about eudaimonia. Examples and challenges.

• Where do we go from here? A question: what exactly is ‘contemplation’ (theoria)? What is it that Aristotle has in mind in Book X as the most excellent mode of life?