Paavola Abduction

download Paavola Abduction

of 16

Transcript of Paavola Abduction

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    1/16

    ABDUCTION AS A LOGIC AND METHODOLOGY OF DISCOVERY:

    THE IMPORTANCE OF STRATEGIES

    Paper originally published in (2004) Foundations of Science 9(3), 267-283.

    Published on the Commens site with the kind permission of the editors of the

    journal.

    Sami Paavola

    University of Helsinki

    E-mail: sami.paavola at helsinki.fi

    Abstract: There are various "classical" arguments against abduction as a logic of

    discovery, especially that 1) abduction is too weak a mode of inference to be of

    any use, and 2) in basic formulation of abduction the hypothesis is already

    presupposed to be known, so it is not the way hypotheses are discovered in the

    first place. In this paper I argue, by bringing forth the idea of strategies, that

    these counter-arguments are weaker than may appear. The concept of strategies

    suggests, inter alia, that many inferential moves are taken into account at thesame time. This is especially important in abductive reasoning, which is

    basically a very weak mode of inference. The importance of strategic thinkingcan already be seen in Charles S. Peirces early treatments of the topic, and N.

    R. Hansons later writings on abduction although they did not use the concept of

    "strategies." On the whole, I am arguing that the focus should be more on

    methodological processes, and not only on validity considerations, which have

    dominated the discussion about abduction.

    Key words: abduction, logic of discovery, strategies, methodology

    1. Basic Criticism against Abduction (as a Logic of Discovery)

    Abductive inference arouses increasing interest and methodological discussion

    in various fields. In the philosophical context abduction has, however, very often

    been subjected to severe criticism (see e.g., Frankfurt, 1958; Nickles, 1980b;Kapitan, 1992). There are, so to speak, various "classical" counter-arguments

    against abduction, especially if abduction is presented as a logic of discovery. A

    basis for these counter-arguments is the widely held view that discovery is

    something that cannot be treated by conceptual or philosophical means.

    One basic way of formulating abduction is the one made already by Charles S.Peirce (See Peirce, CP 5.189; Hanson, 1972, 86):

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    2/16

    The surprising fact, C, is observed; {268}

    But if H [an explanatory hypothesis] were true, C would be a matter of course,

    Hence, there is reason to suspect that H is true.

    So abduction can be understood as a mode of inference where explanations aresearched for (anomalous or suprising) phenomena. But this kind of an inference

    can be criticized because it is too permissive to be of much use. It seems to

    permit inferences to all sorts of wild hypotheses (Frankfurt, 1958, 596; Nickles,

    1980a, 24; Kapitan, 1992, 6). Peter Achinstein has presented various, often

    cited, counter-examples in line with this criticism. For example, the hypothesis

    that I will be paid one million dollars if this paper is published, would explain (if

    it were true) why I am writing this paper. But still, there is no reason to think

    that I am about to come a millionaire (unfortunately so!). Or another Achinstein

    example: Let us suppose as an observed fact that I am happy about some news I

    have just received. Then a hypothesis could be proposed that I have just received

    the news that I have won the Nobel Prize in literature (because it is reasonable to

    suppose that anyone who hears the news about the Nobel Prize winning is

    happy). But here again, the fact that I am happy, should give no reason to

    believe that I have won the Nobel Prize. So, from the mere fact that some

    hypothesis H, if it was true, would explain the data, does not usually follow that

    there is reason to think that that H is true (Achinstein, 1970, 92; 1971, 118;

    1987, 413). It is to be noted that Achinstein does not take into account that thefact observed should somehow be 'surprising' (Is it surprising that I am writing

    this paper? Is it surprising that I am happy? In what sense are these factssupposed to be surprising?). But still, Achinstein's argument appears to be

    basically adequate. The problem with abduction is that its basic formula seems

    to allow these kinds of inferences to all sorts of wild and crazy hypotheses.

    Another basic criticism against abduction is that it cannot be a logic of discovery

    because the hypothesis is already included (or supposed to be known) in the

    premises (see above the second premise) (e.g., Frankfurt, 1958, 594; Nickles,1980a, 23; Hoffmann, 1999, 278-9). So it seems that the new idea is not a result

    of abductive inference, and abduction can be at most a logic for preliminary

    evaluation or appraisal of a hypothesis that {269} is already discovered by someother means (Schon, 1959, 501-2; Kapitan, 1992, 2). In this sense abduction is

    often placed in that phase of activity which is carried out after original discovery

    but before final justification (e.g., Nickles, 1980a, 18-22; Laudan, 1980, 174).

    This means -- if the idea is followed -- that the old distinction between thecontext of discovery and the context of justification (see Reichenbach, 1938;

    Nickles, 1980a) is not enough, and a third region is needed. The basic idea is

    that this third area can be analysed by logical and conceptual means, although it

    is not a matter of justification in proper sense yet. But the context of discovery

    in genuine sense is still, according to this idea, something inexplicable, orpossibly a subject for empirical sciences but not for conceptual analysis.

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    3/16

    2. The Meaning of Strategies in Abduction

    I think that abduction can still be defended as a very promising candidate for a

    logic of discovery if the meaning of strategies is taken into account. JaakkoHintikka has emphasized a distinction between two sorts of rules in reasoning

    and logic (or in games in general): the definitory rules and the strategic rules.

    Hintikka maintains that for the theory of logic and reasoning, especially at the

    level of introductory textbooks and courses, the study of excellence of reasoning

    is often forgotten, and the emphasis is on the avoidance of mistakes in reasoning

    (e.g., Hintikka, 1999). According to him, students are not taught how to reason

    well but to maintain their logical virtue (i.e., to avoid logical fallacies and to

    learn what is and what is not admissible and valid). The focus has been on

    definitory rules of logic, and strategic rules have largely been neglected. The

    definitory rules tell what are valid rules in particular system of logic. By

    analogy: the definitory rules of chess tell what one is allowed to do in chess

    (how chessmen may be moved etc.). But by knowing only the definitory rules of

    chess one cannot say that one plays chess well. Excellence in chess requires that

    one master strategic rules extremely well. According to Hintikka, this same idea

    applies to logic. No one is good in logic and reasoning by knowing only the

    definitory rules of logic, but by mastering well the strategic rules.

    Strategies have, however, been a quite neglected topic in philosophy of science.There are some exceptions. In the interrogative {270} approach to inquiry, the

    meaning of strategies has been emphasized (Hintikka, 1985, 1989; Jung, 1996).But usually the merits of inference are assessed by investigating whether the

    truth of the premises guarantees or makes probable the truth of the conclusion.

    And this has also been the basic way of evaluating abduction.

    Hintikka has emphasized strategic aspects also in relationship to abductive

    inference: "the validity of an abductive inference is to be judged by strategic

    principles rather than by definitory (move-by-move) rules" (Hintikka, 1998,513). Hintikka himself does not, however, treat abduction as a separate mode of

    inference in his interrogative model of inquiry. In Hintikka's model the problem

    of abduction is subsumed under a more general problem concerning the natureof ampliative reasoning in general. In Hintikka's model, abduction is closely

    related to a question- answer step in the process of inquiry (ibid., 519-523).

    I suggest that abduction as a separate mode of inference can also be defended by

    taking strategies into account much more seriously than before (see alsoMagnani, 1999, 235- 236). But what does strategies mean in the area of

    reasoning? Strategy is in itself a very complicated concept. Strategies are related

    to goal-directed activity, where the ability to anticipate things, and to assess or

    choose between different possibilities, are important (see e.g., Hintikka, 1989,

    1999). One central point in strategic rules is that they cannot normally be judgedonly in relationship to particular moves, but the whole strategic situation must

    be taken into account (see Hintikka, 1998, 513). This means that in strategies

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    4/16

    more than one step or move can and must be taken into account at the same

    time. I am not maintaining that this characterization does full justice to the

    meaning of strategies in (abductive) inference, but it is surely one essential

    point. And in abduction, strategies are especially important because it is

    basically such a weak mode of inference. The force of abductive inference ismuch strengthened if one takes into account that the hypotheses are to be

    searched for in relationship to various phenomena and background information

    and not just in order to explain one, surprising phenomenon.

    So if I am a researcher looking for a good explanatory hypothesis for some

    anomalous phenomenon, I can (and must) try to constrain and guide my search

    by taking into account that my explanation {271} must explain or at least be

    consistent with, most other clues and information that I have available

    concerning the subject matter. And I try to anticipate that my explanation has

    some chance of survival in subsequent tests and assessments. Usually I must

    also take into account that the proposed explanation should not be totally

    unconvincing, or if it seems to be that, I should have a good further explanation

    for why this explanation still deserves attention. So, I should have an

    explanation for my explanation (see Thagard & Shelley, 1997). These are

    strategic principles where more than one move can and should be taken into

    account simultaneously.

    In Achinstein's counterexamples, one important reason why those wild

    hypotheses are not reasonable (it is to be noted that the term "reasonable" is justthe right one here) is that they do not fit well with other relevant information.

    Normally no one would pay one million dollars for any academic paper(unfortunately again!), which rules out this hypothesis as strategically bad. And

    there is no reason to think that I have won the Nobel Prize in literature - only

    because I am happy - if this hypothesis does not fit at all with other information

    concerning who I am and what I have done. Strategically, it would be bad

    reasoning to suggest such implausible hypotheses, if there were no good further

    reasons or backing for these. A strategically good hypothesis takes also intoaccount that there is an explanation for my explanation (or at least explanation

    why there cannot be any further explanation). Why someone would pay me one

    million dollars for this paper? Why would someone even suggest a Nobel Prizefor me? If there are no good answers for these questions, there is no point in

    even suggesting these kinds of hypotheses at the first place. Achinstein himself

    apparently notices the situation: normally we take the relevant background

    information into account, and we require further evidence for some oddhypothesis in order to take it seriously (see Achinstein 1970, 92; 1971, 118;

    1987, 416). But what Achinstein is missing is the idea that strategies are

    involved here.

    The strategic viewpoint does not, however, rule out the possibility of suggesting

    implausible hypotheses altogether. It is, for example, possible to imagine such acourse of events, where the one million dollars hypothesis (or the Nobel Prize

    hypothesis) is the correct one, because of some extraordinary circumstances.

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    5/16

    Especially if {272} more conventional or plausible hypotheses have not worked

    out, it might be a good strategy to try more implausible hypotheses. (In

    Achinstein's one-million dollars example, if the situation were that, for some

    reasons, it would be very surprising that I am giving this presentation, and other

    explanations would not seem to work out, it would be a good candidatehypothesis to think that someone is paying me a lot of money for this.) What I

    am arguing is that in strategies, the reasoner tries to anticipate the counter-

    arguments, and to take into account all the relevant information, and this rules

    out very "wild" hypotheses, except, when there is no other available, or

    alternatively, when these are presented simply as "wild guesses".

    I will now give further consideration to the criticism that abduction cannot be

    the logic of discovery because the hypothesis or the idea is already presupposed

    in the premises. To begin with, I am not maintaining that abductive inference is

    an automatic means for making discoveries. I agree with N. R. Hanson, who

    emphasized that abductive inference is rather a way of analysing conceptual

    issues in discoveries rather than "a manual" or an algorithmic device for making

    these discoveries (Hanson, 1961, 21-22). If abduction is to be considered as the

    logic of discovery, the whole methodological process must be taken into

    account; one must not just concentrate on the form of the argument. In this

    sense, it is for example important to think how these "surprising facts" (see the

    formulation of abduction above) operate as clues in the search for explanations

    or hypotheses. From the point of view of the inquirer, the difficult part inabductive search might be to find fruitful premises. But this does not mean that

    abduction cannot analyse properly the logical form of discoveries.Strategies are also involved here. Although the hypothesis is in the premises,

    abduction can still be the logic of discovery because, as Peirce wrote (Peirce, CP

    5.181):

    "It is true that the different elements of the hypothesis were in our minds before;

    but it is the idea of putting together what we had never before dreamed ofputting together which flashes the new suggestion before our contemplation."

    How I interpret this idea from the strategic viewpoint is that a hypothesissuggested can in itself be something old and even well known. But the way in

    which this hypothesis is seen to fit with this particular problem in question

    {273} and with other relevant information (besides the one anomalous

    phenomenon) is crucial. And it is also essential that there is a further explanationor clarification for this particular hypothesis. For example, the idea of evolution

    was not new when Charles Darwin proposed it. It was widely admitted that it

    would have been a good explanation for various phenomena, but the problem

    was that there were no plausible explanations for how evolution operates more

    specifically (and in fact there seemed to be lots of evidence which was againstthe evolutionary hypothesis). As Darwin later recollected his discovery and its

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    6/16

    relationship to the known facts (Darwin in his autobiography: Barlow, 1958,

    118-119):

    "It was evident that such facts as these [various important observations that he

    had made on the famous voyage of the Beagle], as well as many others, could beexplained on the supposition that species gradually become modified; and the

    subject haunted me. But it was equally evident that neither the action of the

    surrounding conditions, nor the will of the organisms (especially in the case of

    plants), could account for the innumerable cases in which organisms of every

    kind are beautifully adapted to their habits of life. I had always been much

    struck by such adaptations, and until these could be explained it seemed to me

    almost useless to endeavour to prove by indirect evidence that species have been

    modified."

    And likewise many details in Darwin's theory were not new, but the real

    discovery and insight was that Darwin showed that these ideas really work in

    this particular context. This is also how Howard Gruber has described Darwin's

    famous Malthusian insight (Gruber, 1981, 42):

    " his notebooks show that he had or almost had the same idea a number of

    times before, during the fifteen months of deliberate effort leading up to the

    moment in question. So the historic moment was in a sense a re-cognition ofwhat he already knew or almost knew."

    So my point is, that the basic formula of abduction can still be an essential part

    in the logic of discovery (even though the hypothesis is in the premises) if the

    difficult part in discovery is the recognition that the hypothesis really is a viable

    way of solving this particular problem and that the hypothesis works more

    generally (and not only in relationship to one, particular anomalous

    phenomenon).I am not maintaining that the importance of strategies in discovery means that in

    (scientific) discovery the researchers always {274} have their hypotheses

    already at their disposal and that the only problem would be to strategically see,somehow, a connection between moves in games of reasoning. Discovery means

    that something new is brought (or abducted!) to the particular situation. But

    strategies must be taken into account when "aha-experiences" or insights are

    involved. An aha-experience means that the hypothesis (or the solution) inquestion fits with those constraints and clues that are involved in the problem

    situation in question, i.e., the insight seems to take into account many counter-

    arguments and moves in advance. It is not enough that the hypothesis explains

    only some detached, anomalous phenomena (e.g., for Darwin the idea of

    evolution and the Malthusian principle were important discoveries only whenthese ideas could be integrated to the larger argument concerning species, and

    not as separate and unconnected explanations). It almost seems that the basis for

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    7/16

    the aha-experience is a situation where, first, various constraints and hints

    characterize the situation and then some solution seems to fit with these

    constraints. And this outlining of constraints and hints is, I submit, closely

    related to strategic thinking, at least in the sense I use 'strategies' here. A good

    insight is also a good one strategically.I think that strategies are also involved when it is said that abductive inference

    starts from anomalous or somewhat surprising phenomena. It might be asked,

    why it is so often emphasized that abductive inference starts from surprising

    phenomena (but cf. Hoffmann, 1999, 281)? It does not seem to affect to the

    validity of inference if it starts from surprising or from non-surprising

    phenomenon. I think that this is also a strategic rule, for the following reasons:

    In difficult problems or in cases where something new is required, it is a good

    strategy (or a worthwhile one) to start from anomalous facts or from little

    details, and try with them to find a solution or a hypothesis. This is at least a

    strategy that detectives (or detective novels) recommend (the connection

    between abduction and the reasoning that detectives use is often noticed, see

    e.g., Eco & Sebeok, 1988; Niiniluoto, 1999b). This is also how Francis Darwin

    described how (his father) Charles Darwin worked (Darwin, 1892, 94-95):

    "There was one quality of mind which seemed to be of special and extreme

    advantage in leading him to make discoveries. It was the power of never letting

    {275} exceptions pass unnoticed. Everybody notices a fact as an exception whenit is striking or frequent, but he had a special instinct for arresting an exception.

    A point apparently slight and unconnected with his present work is passed overby many a man almost unconsciously with some half-considered explanation,

    which is in fact no explanation. It was just these things that he seized on to make

    a start from."

    3. Strategies in Peirce's and Hanson's Treatment of Abduction: Methodeutic forAbduction

    Charles Peirce's seminal writings concerning abduction already contained manystrategic insights, although he did not label them as such (Hintikka, 1998, 512-

    6). Peirce made a distinction between three areas of logic: (Speculative)

    Grammar, Critic, and Methodeutic. Peirce characterized this "trivium" in various

    ways during his long career, so it is not possible to interpret this distinction inexact terms or unequivocally (see e. g., Peirce, CP 1.559; CP 1.444; CP 2.93).

    Especially the third area, Methodeutic, leaves room for various interpretations

    (in many writings he called it e.g., "Speculative Rhetoric") (Liszka, 1996). In

    Grammar the nature and meanings of signs are studied; in Critic arguments are

    classified and the validity and the force of arguments are studied (see Peirce, CP1.191). Methodeutic, however, "studies the methods that ought to be pursued in

    the investigation, in the exposition, and in the application of truth." (ibid.), and

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    8/16

    "the principles of the production of valuable courses of research and exposition."

    (Peirce, EP2, 272).

    In order to develop further the model of abductive inference, all these three

    Peircean areas of logic (Grammar, Critic, Methodeutic) are salient. According to

    Peirce, Critic is important in abduction although it is a very "weak" mode ofinference (Peirce, CP 5.188):

    " abduction, although it is very little hampered by logical rules, nevertheless

    is logical inference, asserting its conclusion only problematically or

    conjecturally, it is true, but nevertheless having a perfectly definite logical

    form."

    The area of Grammar should also be developed further in order to better

    understand the nature of abductive inference. For example, the special role of

    iconic and perceptual elements in abductive inference is, I think, part of

    Grammar (see Peirce, CP, 2.96; Shelley, 1996; Thagard and Shelley, 1997). But

    what is important from the {276} point of view of this paper is that, in abductive

    inference, the role of Methodeutic can be seen as especially significant because,

    in Peirce's words, "Of the different classes of arguments, abductions are the only

    ones in which after they have been admitted to be just, it still remains to inquire

    whether they are advantageous." (Peirce, HP, 1035)

    I maintain that according to the Peircean distinction of these three areas of logic,strategies would belong to Methodeutic. Methodeutic studies the process of

    inquiry and the way in which inquiry is carried on, and strategies are part of it.As Peirce in his time emphasized Methodeutic in reasoning, Hintikka, in recent

    decades has emphasized the need for strategic rules and study of fruitful

    methods of logical reasoning.

    There are also other concepts and ideas in Peirces writings (besides

    Methodeutic) where the issue of strategies comes to the fore. Hintikka has

    suggested that in Peirce's concept of habit "there lurks a strategic rule tryingto get out" (Hintikka, 1998, 515). Peirce also emphasized the notion of "the

    economy of research," which is very closely related to strategic principles

    (Peirce, CP 7.220). According to Peirce various sorts of "economical" (broadlyinterpreted) factors should guide the choice of the hypotheses, for example,

    caution, which takes into account what will happen if the hypothesis suggested

    does not work out. One example of this economical caution is the game of

    twenty questions where the idea is to guess what object someone is thinking bymaking good questions (ibid.). Only such questions are allowed as can be

    answered by Yes or No (this limitation makes the game intriguing; there would

    be no game if you were allowed to ask the object thought of right away). The

    success in this game is based on skilful questions that break up the search area

    most efficiently. I think it is quite clear that this is the same as saying that thesuccess is based on good strategies.

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    9/16

    Peirce himself often maintained that we humans must have some sort of an

    instinct that guides our guesses (see e.g., Peirce, CP 2.753; CP 5.172-4). Peirce's

    argument was that a human could not arrive at his or her theories by pure

    chance. There are an infinite number of theories that could be suggested if there

    is nothing that helps us. According to Peirce our abductive guesses are nottotally {277} haphazard or blind because we have an instinct for making these

    guesses. But this explanation raises several questions. Is there any evidence that

    we humans have this kind of a guessing instinct? How would it operate? There

    is some plausibility to the Peircean idea that evolution has moulded us to guess

    such hypotheses about physical and psychical life, which have been important

    for our survival. But how could this guessing instinct help humans to discover

    modern scientific theories which are often counter-intuitive and against a

    common sense way of understanding things? Peirce himself admitted that this

    instinct explanation is not very plausible when one considers the genesis of very

    complicated theories by which we "penetrate further and further from the

    surface of nature" (Peirce, CP 7.508; see also Peirce, CP 7.606). It is also

    problematic to combine this instinct explanation with the idea that abduction is a

    third mode of inference. It seems that if the crucial element in abduction is the

    guessing instinct there is not much room for abductive reasoning. There are

    various suggestions how instinct and inference can be combined in a Peircean

    scheme (e.g., Fann, 1970; Anderson, 1987) but still it is a quite problematic how

    this combining could satisfactorily be done.Nicholas Rescher has suggested that Peirce's "somewhat mysterious" capacity of

    instinct should be replaced by a methodology of inquiry (Rescher, 1995, 321-3;Hoffmann, 1999, 297). The idea is that scientific inquiry and discovery is not

    blind because methods and methodology give rational principles that guide the

    processes of inquiry. Methods themselves, according to Rescher, have emerged

    through evolutionary trial-and-error process. I am not trying to evaluate

    Rescher's solution comprehensively, but I think that Rescher is making a very

    important point here. Scientists need not start from scratch because methods andmethodologies that have proven to be successful are guiding inquiry. But it

    seems that Rescher's solution cannot be the whole story. If methods and

    methodology are supposedly reached by trial-and-error, are we not facing againthe same problem that was supposed to be solved (this is one version of the

    classical Meno paradox)? Are these methods found by pure chance in

    evolutionary way? Is this possible? And if so, is there some kind of an

    agreement what these successful methods nowadays are? If they guide scientificinquiry in contrast {278} to instincts, should we not know them explicitly? And

    even if we could characterize these methodologies in general terms, is there any

    guarantee that they work in particular cases?

    What I have tried to argue has some similarities to Rescher's solution. There is

    no need to abandon the idea that we humans might have some abilities that canbe called "instincts" and which help us when we are trying to discover

    something new. But these abductive instincts cannot be the fundamental basis

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    10/16

    for abductive inference. In order to understand abductive reasoning better, the

    focus should be more on methodological processes. But unlike Rescher, I don't

    think that the most important feature of methodology is that it is moulded by

    evolutionary process.

    The focus on strategies means that inquiry is seen as a kind of a problem solvingprocess where the inquirer uses the best inquiry strategies possible. The use of

    strategies explains why inquiry is not purely blind, even when something new is

    discovered. The inquirer must try to take into account all the information that is

    relevant to his or her subject area. Strategically, and from the point of view of

    the inquirer, it would be bad reasoning to suggest very "wild" hypotheses, or

    hypotheses based on pure chance; it is wise to take into account existing

    knowledge. It is true that new (especially revolutionary) discoveries often mean

    that some parts of this existing knowledge must be abandoned. But even then the

    inquirer must be able to combine the new ideas with existing knowledge or

    constraints, (or to be able to show that the existing knowledge is in some ways

    inadequate). These constraints can be negative, in a sense that they inhibit new

    ideas, but they can also be positive in suggesting methods, theories, information

    and so on which must be taken into account and which might give clues how to

    solve the problems in question. This idea is similar to the role of "normal

    science" or "paradigms" in Thomas Kuhns famous model of scientific growth

    (Kuhn, 1970). Paradigms are not automatic ways of solving problems, but they

    give good suggestions for how to conduct inquiry. This is the reason whyinquiry does not always have to start from scratch. Kuhn does not extend the

    idea to revolutionary situations where paradigms themselves change. But evenin revolutionary situations, existing knowledge constrains and guides the search

    for new information and discoveries. {279}

    I think that Norwood Russell Hansons old ideas concerning abduction should

    also be seen from a strategic angle. Hanson was already a proponent of the idea

    of the logic of discovery in the 1950s and 1960s when these subjects were not

    popular in philosophy of science (Hanson, 1961, 1972). Hanson's formulationshave been criticized as inadequate for the logic of discovery (see e.g., Nickles,

    1980b). My suggestion is that this criticism has been concerned more with the

    validity of abduction (with "Critic" in Peircean terms), and Hanson himself wasmore interested in abduction as a part of methodological processes of inquiry

    (i.e., Methodeutic). Hanson explicitly criticized the "logic of the finished

    research reports;" he put the emphasis on processes of discovery and maintained

    that these processes can be analysed by conceptual means (Hanson, 1961, 20-22).

    In his writings concerning abduction, Hanson distinguished three ingredients in

    "the logic of discovery" (Hanson, 1965, 47-65). It is reasoning which

    "1) proceeds retroductively, from an anomaly to2) the delineation of a kind of explanatory H which

    3) fits into an organized pattern of concepts." (ibid., 50)

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    11/16

    I think that these points can be seen as strategic principles although Hanson

    himself did not develop these ideas explicitly in this way. The starting point in

    anomalies (point 1) can be seen as a strategic principle (see the end of chapter 2.

    above). Hanson also pointed out that abduction does not mean that someparticular hypothesis is found straight away. An important phase in the process

    of discovery might be that the type of the solution is delineated before the

    solution is acquired (point 2) (Hanson, 1961; Niiniluoto, 1999a, S440-1). This is

    strategic thinking: the constraints and hints that help in hypothesis finding are

    taken into account. And the goal in abductive inference (at least in most cases) is

    to find an overall pattern into which all evidence and clues fit (point 3), and this

    phase especially requires that various inferential moves be put together skilfully

    and by taking various clues and constraints into account (a paradigmatic case is

    detective stories, but this is in itself a very general model). {280}

    4. Conclusion: A Logic and Methodology of Discovery

    Various approaches in the philosophy of science nowadays emphasize the need

    to find a model for inquiry that is not strictly logical, at least in the "old" sense

    (i.e., in the sense that formal logic has been usually understood in the last

    century) but one that is not purely relativistic or historicistic either (see e.g.,Pera, 1994; Jung, 1996; Thagard, 2000; Aliseda, 2001). This need arises

    especially from an aim to understand processes of discovery and knowledgeformation and not just finished products (Sintonen, 1996; Aliseda 1997).

    Philosophy of science and logic have for long concentrated on analysing the

    structure of finished products, e.g., what is an explanation, and not processes of

    inquiry, e.g., how good explanations are searched for and found (Aliseda, 2001).

    There have been some notable exceptions, e.g., N. R. Hanson, but usually these

    processes were literally defined to be something that cannot be analysed byconceptual means, or by philosophical models.

    Thomas Nickles has made a distinction between "heuristic appraisal" and

    "epistemic appraisal" in methodology (Nickles, 1989). Epistemic appraisal is thestandard way of doing things in the philosophy of science. It is a retrospective,

    justificatory assessment of scientific results. Heuristic appraisal means that the

    promisingness, or fertility of scientific proposals or problems is being assessed.

    It can be maintained that this is at least as important, if not more important thanepistemic appraisal. Nowadays heuristical aspects are often emphasized when

    rationality of discovery is searched for (Jung, 1996; Magnani, 1999, 235-236;

    Aliseda, 2001).

    The "friends of discovery" have for long emphasized that the concept of

    rationality must be broadened if the context of discovery is to be taken intoaccount (Nickles, 1980b). There is a new opportunity for this broadening when

    new conceptual means are developed, i.e., conceptual means that try to capture

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    12/16

    processes of inquiry and discovery (see e.g., Hintikka, 1985, 1998; Sintonen,

    1996; Jung, 1996; Aliseda, 1997, 2001). The basic point is that even though old

    models of formal and symbolic logic are not adequate, it is possible to develop

    new formal models and tools that are more appropriate for this (see also

    Thagard, 2000). In this sense there is no need to leave "the context of discovery"only to psychologists {281} or to empirical scientists, for there are also

    conceptual and logical issues involved here.

    The point in this paper has been that the logical apparatus should be broadened

    at least in two dimensions from the "standard" way. Deductive logic is not

    enough, and the model of abductive inference is especially needed in order to

    understand the processes of discovery. But abduction in itself is not enough.

    Besides validity considerations (which are in themselves important in abduction)

    there is the art of using (abductive) reasoning. This concerns the area of

    "Methodeutic" (in Peircean terms); an area especially important in abductive

    reasoning. It seems that this is in some sense a return to a pre-Fregean sense of

    logic, where the boundaries between logic and methodology are quite vague

    (Aliseda, 2001); boundaries between logic and psychology must also be drawn

    anew (see Thagard, 2000). In any case, this shift to focus more on processes of

    inquiry necessitates a re-consideration of abductive strategies.

    References

    Achinstein, P., 1970, Inference to scientific laws, in: Stuwer, R. H., ed.,Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 5: 87-111.

    Achinstein, P., 1971, Law and Explanation. An Essay in The Philosophy of

    Science, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Achinstein, P., 1987, Scientific discovery and Maxwell's kinetic theory,Philosophy of Science 54: 409-434.

    Aliseda, A., 1997, Seeking Explanations: Abduction in Logic, Philosophy ofScience and Artificial Intelligence. Institute for Logic, Language, and

    Computation, Dissertation Series, University of Amsterdam, Holland.

    Aliseda, A., 2001, A place for logic in scientific methodology: a secondopportunity?, a paper presented at the Model-Based Reasoning: Scientific

    Discovery, Technological Innovation, Values Conference, Pavia, Italy, May 17-

    19, 2001.

    Anderson, D. R., 1987, Creativity and the Philosophy of C.S. Peirce. MartinusNijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht.

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    13/16

    Barlow, N., ed., 1958, The Autobiography of Charles Darwin, 1809-1882, with

    original omissions restored, Collins, St James's Place, London.

    Darwin, F., 1892, Reminiscences of my father's everyday life, in: F. Darwin, ed.,

    Charles Darwin: His Life Told in an Autobiographical Chapter, and in aSelected Series of His Published Letters, John Murray, Albemarle Street,

    London, pp. 66-103.

    Eco, U. and Sebeok, T. A., eds., 1988, The Sign of Three. Dupin, Holmes,

    Peirce, Indiana University Press, USA.

    {282}

    Fann, K. T., 1970, Peirces Theory of Abduction. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.

    Frankfurt, H. G., 1958, Peirce's account of inquiry, The Journal of Philosophy

    55(14): 588-592.

    Gruber, H. E., 1981, On the relation between 'aha experiences' and the

    construction of ideas, History of Science 19: 41-59.

    Hanson, N. R., 1961, Is there a logic of scientific discovery, in: Feigl, H. and

    Maxwell, G., eds., 1961, Current Issues in the Philosophy of Science, Holt,Rinehart and Winston, Inc., New York.

    Hanson, N. R., 1965, Notes toward a logic of discovery, in: Bernstein, R. J. ed.

    Perspectives on Peirce, Yale Univ. Press, New Haven and London, pp. 42-65.

    Hanson, N. R., 1972, Patterns of Discovery, University Press, Cambridge, first

    printed 1958.

    Hintikka, J., 1985, True and false logic of scientific discovery, Communication

    & Cognition 18(1/2): 3-14.

    Hintikka, J., 1989, The role of logic in argumentation, Monist 72: 3 - 24.

    Hintikka, J., 1998, What is abduction? The fundamental problem of

    contemporary epistemology, Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 34/3:503-533.

    Hintikka, J., 1999, Is logic the key to all good reasoning?, in Hintikka, J., 1999,

    Inquiry as Inquiry: A Logic of Scientific Discovery, Jaakko Hintikka Selected

    Papers, Volume 5, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht.

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    14/16

    Hoffmann, M., 1999, Problems with Peirce's concept of abduction, Foundations

    of Science 4: 271-305.

    Jung, S., 1996, The Logic of Discovery. An Interrogative Approach to Scientific

    Inquiry, American University Studies, Series V, Philosophy, Vol. 168, PeterLang, New York.

    Kapitan, T., 1992, Peirce and the autonomy of abductive reasoning, Erkenntnis

    37: 1 26.

    Kuhn, T. S., 1970, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Second edition,

    enlarged, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Laudan, L., 1980, Why was the logic of discovery abandoned, in: Nickles, T.,

    ed., 1980, Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality, D.Reidel Publishing

    Company, Dordrecht, pp. 173-183.

    Liszka, J. J., 1996, A General Introduction to the Semeiotic of Charles Sanders

    Peirce, Indiana University Press, Bloomington and Indianapolis.

    Magnani, L., 1999. Model-based creative abduction, in: Magnani, L.,

    Nersessian, N. J. & Thagard, P., eds., 1999, Model-Based Reasoning inScientific Discovery, Kluwer Academic / Plenum Publishers, New York.

    Nickles, T., 1980a, Introductory essay: scientific discovery and the future of

    philosophy of science, in: Nickles, T., ed., 1980, Scientific Discovery, Logic,

    and Rationality, D.Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht.

    Nickles, T., ed., 1980b, Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality, D.Reidel

    Publishing Company, Dordrecht.

    Nickles, T., 1989, Heuristical appraisal: a proposal, Social Epistemology 3(3):

    175 188.

    {283}

    Niiniluoto, I., 1999a, Defending abduction, Philosophy of Science 66: S436-

    S451.

    Niiniluoto, I., 1999b, Abduction and geometrical analysis. Notes on Charles S.

    Peirce and Edgar Allan Poe, in: Magnani, L., Nersessian, N. J. & Thagard, P.,

    eds., 1999, Model-Based Reasoning in Scientific Discovery, Kluwer Academic /

    Plenum Publishers, New York.

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    15/16

    Peirce, C., S., (CP), 1931-1958, Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce,

    vols. 1 6, Hartshorne, C. and Weiss, P., eds.; vols. 7-8, Burks, A. W., ed.,

    Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass.

    Peirce, C., S., (HP), 1985, Historical Perspectives on Peirces Logic of Science.A History of Science, 2 vols., edited by Carolyn Eisele, Mouton Publishers,

    Berlin.

    Peirce, C., S., (EP2), 1992-1998, The Essential Peirce. Selected Philosophical

    Writings, vol. 2 1893-1913, the Peirce Edition Project, ed., Indiana University

    Press, Bloomington and Indianapolis.

    Pera, M., 1994, The Discourses of Science, The University of Chicago Press,

    Chicago.

    Reichenbach, H., 1938, Experience and Prediction. An Analysis of the

    Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge, The University of Chicago Press,

    Chicago, Illinois, U.S.A.

    Rescher, N., 1995, Peirce on abduction, plausibility, and the efficiency of

    scientific inquiry, in N. Rescher, 1995, Essays in the History of Philosophy,

    Aldershot, Avebury.

    Schon, D., 1959, Comment on mr. Hanson's "The logic of discovery", TheJournal of Philosophy, 56(11): 500-503.

    Shelley, C., 1996, Visual abductive reasoning in archeology, Philosophy of

    Science, 63: 278-301.

    Sintonen, M., 1996, Structuralism and the interrogative model of inquiry, in:Balzer, W., and Moulines, C. U., eds., 1996, Structuralist Theory of Science.

    Focal Issues, New Results, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, New York.

    Thagard, P., 2000, Coherence in Thought and Action, A Bradford Book, MIT

    Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.

    Thagard, P. and Shelley, C., 1997, Abductive reasoning: logic, visual thinking,and coherence, in: M.L. Dalla Chiara, K. Doets, D. Mundici, and J. van

    Bentham, eds., Logic and Scientific Methods, Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp. 413- 427,

    on-line: http://cogsci.uwaterloo.ca/Articles/Pages/%7FAbductive.html.

    | Top |

  • 8/14/2019 Paavola Abduction

    16/16

    About Commens The Metaphysical Club Papers Home Page About

    Peirce Research Resources Links