Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central...

24
1 Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 Seth Cable University of Massachusetts Amherst 1. The Central Puzzle: Negation in Negative Stative Predicates In the Tlingit language (Na-Dene; Alaska, British Columbia, Yukon), there is a small but highly frequent set of stative, gradable antonym pairs, where the negative antonym is formed from: (i) The root of the positive antonym (ii) The negation marker tlél (hél) (iii) An additional (unproductive) morphological operation. (1) Negation in Negative Predicates of Tlingit 2 Positive Predicate Negative Predicate Negation of Positive a. yakʼéi tlél ushkʼé tlél ukʼé 0CL.good NEG IRR.shCL.good NEG IRR.0CL.good It is good. It is bad. It is not good. b. yaa udzigei tlél yaa ushtlél yaa usgé. sCL.smart NEG IRR.shCL.smart NEG IRR.sCL.smart He is smart. He is dumb / foolish. He is not smart. c. lix ̱ éitl tlél ushx ̱ éitl tlél ulx ̱ éitl lCL.lucky NEG IRR.shCL.lucky NEG IRR.lCL.lucky She is lucky. She is unlucky. She is not lucky. d. litseen tlél ulcheen tlél ultseen lCL.strong NEG IRR.lCL.strong NEG IRR.lCL.strong She is strong. She is weak. She is not strong. (2) On the Morphological Changes Between Positive and Negative Antonym a. In (1a)-(1c), the so-called ‘verbal classifier’ (glossed ‘CL’) of the positive predicate is changed to the ‘sh-classifier’ (glossed ‘shCL’) in the negative. b. In (1d), the root itself undergoes a consonant mutation from /ts/ to /tʃ/ 1 For reasons of space, I have put my ample acknowledgments at the end of the handout. 2 I provide only the roughest of glosses for individual Tlingit words, which can be morphologically quite complex. This simplification is most radical for verbs, as I provide glosses only for their lexical content and that inflectional morphology that is important to my argumentation. In addition, I employ the following glossing abbreviations throughout: 0CL ‘0-classifier’, 1 ‘1 st person’, 3 ‘3 rd person’, DUB ‘dubitative’, ERG ‘ergative’, FOC ‘focus particle’, FUT ‘future’, IRR ‘irrealis’, lCL ‘l-classifier’, NEG ‘negation’, O ‘object’, PL ‘plural’, POSS ‘possessive’, S ‘subject’, sCL ‘s-classifier’, shCL ‘sh-classifier’, SUB ‘subordinator’.

Transcript of Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central...

Page 1: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  1  

Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1

Seth Cable University of Massachusetts Amherst

1. The Central Puzzle: Negation in Negative Stative Predicates In the Tlingit language (Na-Dene; Alaska, British Columbia, Yukon), there is a small but highly frequent set of stative, gradable antonym pairs, where the negative antonym is formed from: (i) The root of the positive antonym

(ii) The negation marker tlél (hél) (iii) An additional (unproductive) morphological operation.

(1) Negation in Negative Predicates of Tlingit 2 Positive Predicate Negative Predicate Negation of Positive a. yakʼéi tlél ushkʼé tlél ukʼé 0CL.good NEG IRR.shCL.good NEG IRR.0CL.good It is good. It is bad. It is not good. b. yaa ḵudzigei tlél yaa ḵushgé tlél yaa ḵusgé. sCL.smart NEG IRR.shCL.smart NEG IRR.sCL.smart He is smart. He is dumb / foolish. He is not smart. c. lix̱éitl tlél ushx̱éitl tlél ulx̱éitl lCL.lucky NEG IRR.shCL.lucky NEG IRR.lCL.lucky She is lucky. She is unlucky. She is not lucky. d. litseen tlél ulcheen tlél ultseen lCL.strong NEG IRR.lCL.strong NEG IRR.lCL.strong She is strong. She is weak. She is not strong. (2) On the Morphological Changes Between Positive and Negative Antonym

a. In (1a)-(1c), the so-called ‘verbal classifier’ (glossed ‘CL’) of the positive predicate is changed to the ‘sh-classifier’ (glossed ‘shCL’) in the negative.

b. In (1d), the root itself undergoes a consonant mutation from /ts/ to /tʃ/

                                                                                                               1  For reasons of space, I have put my ample acknowledgments at the end of the handout. 2  I provide only the roughest of glosses for individual Tlingit words, which can be morphologically quite complex. This simplification is most radical for verbs, as I provide glosses only for their lexical content and that inflectional morphology that is important to my argumentation. In addition, I employ the following glossing abbreviations throughout: 0CL ‘0-classifier’, 1 ‘1st person’, 3 ‘3rd person’, DUB ‘dubitative’, ERG ‘ergative’, FOC ‘focus particle’, FUT ‘future’, IRR ‘irrealis’, lCL ‘l-classifier’, NEG ‘negation’, O ‘object’, PL ‘plural’, POSS ‘possessive’, S ‘subject’, sCL ‘s-classifier’, shCL ‘sh-classifier’, SUB ‘subordinator’.

Page 2: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  2  

(3) A Related Puzzle A few negative stative (gradable) predicates are formed with negation, but contain roots that cannot (any longer) appear in a positive form.

a. Tlél koohélʼk b. * kayahélʼk NEG IRR.0CL.strong(?) 0CL.strong(?) He is weak. (4) Another Related Puzzle/Fact

There a few positive stative (gradable) predicates whose antonyms are (or can often be) expressed in Tlingit by simply negating the positive predicate.

a. (i) naaléi (ii) tlél unalé 0CL.far NEG IRR.0CL.far It is far. It is near. b. (i) x̱ʼalitseen (ii) tlél x̱ʼeiltseen lCL.expensive NEG IRR.1CL.expensive It is expensive (dear). It is cheap. (5) The Central, Overarching Question What is the morpho-syntax and morpho-semantics of the ‘negative predicates’ in (1)?

a. What is their morphosyntactic structure?

b. How does this structure get mapped to their observed meaning? (6) Subsequent Question Can the answer to (5a,b) shed light on the superficially related facts in (3)-(4)?

• What is the nature of the root hélʼk such that only (3a) is well-formed?

• Do the negated predicates in (4a,b) actually have (strong) antonymic meanings? Or are they semantically no more than the negation of the positive predicates?

(7) Suggested Terminology: ‘NEG Antonyms’

• The ‘Negative Predicates’ in (1) • The verbal form tlél koohélʼk in (3a) • The negated predicates in (4aii) and (4bii)

Page 3: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  3  

(8) Outline of the Rest of Talk a. Section 2: Background on methodology and the Tlingit language

b. Section 3: Evidence that the negation in the ‘negative predicates’ in (1) is clausal negation (not incorporated negation)

c. Section 4: The interactions between ‘NEG antonyms’ and degree modifiers d. Section 5: Formal analysis of the ‘negative predicates’ in (1). Possible extensions to the ‘NEG antonyms’ in (3)-(4) e. Section 6: Future directions: Cross-Polar (A)nomalies in Tlingit and English 2. Linguistic and Methodological Background (9) The Tlingit Language (Lingít): A Few Bullet Points

• Traditional language of the Tlingit people of Southeast Alaska, Northwest British Columbia, Southwest Yukon Territory (shaded area in map below) 3

• Member of the Na-Dene language family; distantly related to Athabaskan languages (e.g. Navajo, Slave, Hupa). Shares the complex templatic morphology of this family.

• Highly endangered; ≤ 200 speakers, all over 60, mostly over 70. Several fluent/near-

fluent second language learners; a few raising their children in the language.

                                                                                                               3  Map graphic by X’unei Lance Twitchell. Available at http://tlingit.info/.

Page 4: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  4  

(10) Notes on the Data and Methodology

• Unless otherwise noted, all data below were obtained through interviews with native speakers of Tlingit (Summer 2015)

• Four fluent elders have participated; all are residents of Juneau, AK; all are speakers

of the ‘Northern Dialect’ of Tlingit

o William Fawcett (Kóoshdaak’w Éesh) o Carolyn Martin (K’altseen) o John Martin (Keihéenák’w) o One additional elder who preferred to remain anonymous

• Interviews lasted two hours and were held in a classroom at the University of Alaska

Southeast; 2-4 elders were present at each interview.

• Speakers were asked to translate English sentences paired with particular ‘scenarios’, as well as to judge the ‘correctness’ (broadly speaking) of constructed Tlingit sentences relative to those ‘scenarios’ (Matthewson 2004).

• The scenarios were described to speakers in English, both orally and with

accompanying written text. 3. Negation in Negative Predicates: Incorporated or Clausal? (11) A Natural First Perspective on the Facts in (1)

• It’s not at all unusual for negative predicates to be derived from positive ones via some kind of incorporated negator (11a).

• Moreover, in some languages, this incorporated negation is lexically identical to main

clause negation (11b). a. English: unhappy, ineligiable, non-syntactic b. Malay (Kroeger 2014):

(i) tidak adil (ii) Mereka tidak menolong kami NEG fair 3PL NEG help 1PL unfair They didn’t help us.

• Perhaps the difference between the negative predicates in (1) and the negation of the positive predicates is that the former have incorporated negation?

Page 5: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  5  

(12) An Ineffective Objection a. Objection:

But, in the negative predicates under (1), the negator tlél appears outside all the inflectional morphology of the verb! o If it were incorporated, wouldn’t the inflectional morphology appear outside

the negation?

b. Immediate Reply: Tlingit is a Na-Dene language. So, inflectional and derivational morphology often show unexpected orderings (Rice 2000)…

(13) A Better First Argument

• In Tlingit, clausal negation triggers so-called ‘irrealis’ morphology on the verb, with concomitant changes in the realization of aspect and mood inflection.

a. (i) tlél ukʼé (ii) * tlél yakʼéi NEG IRR.0CL.good NEG 0CL.good It is not good.

• Crucially, the negative predicates in (1) all obligatorily appear with this irrealis

morphology (see the ‘IRR’ in their glosses)

b. (i) tlél ushkʼé (ii) * tlél shikʼéi NEG IRR.shCL.good NEG shCL.good It is bad.

• We wouldnʼt typically expect a lexically-incorporated (derivational) morpheme to have effects upon the realization of inflectional morphology…

(14) An Even Better, Second Argument

Just as with clear cases of clausal negation, the negator in a NEG antonym can be separated from the rest of the verb by other material, including: • Focus particles (15) • Dubitatives (16) • Indefinites (17)

(15) Focus Particles in NEG Antonym a. Tlél áwé ushkʼé b. Tlél áwé ulcheen NEG FOC IRR.shCL.good NEG FOC IRR.lCL.strong/weak It’s bad. He’s weak.

Page 6: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  6  

(16) Dubitatives in NEG Antonym (17) Indefinites with NEG Antonym Tlél shákdéwé ushkʼé. Tlél daa sá ushkʼé NEG DUB.FOC IRR.shCL.good NEG anything IRR.shCL.good

It’s probably bad. Everything is bad. (18) Key Semantic Observation

• The sentence in (17) is not only well-formed, but is claimed to contrast with that in (18a), which contains clausal negation of the positive predicate yakʼéi ‘it is good’.

• As reflected in their English translations, (18a) below is felicitous in scenario (18b),

while (17) is not.

a. Tlél daa sá ukʼé NEG anything IRR.0CL.good

Nothing is good. b. Scenario:

A bunch of food is laid out on the table. None of the food is really any good. Some of it is just so-so (so it’s not really bad), but nothing is really good.

(19) Third Argument: Negation of Negative Predicates

• As indicated in (19a), there is not – nor is there expected to be – any morpho-syntactic incompability between clausal negation and incorporated negation.

a. He is not unlucky.

• As shown in (20)-(22) below, however, it is not possible in Tlingit to directly negate one of the negative predicates in (1).

• The ill-formedness of (20), (21a), (22a) would follow if the negation in such negative

predicates were clausal negation… o Many languages disallow multiple instances of clausal negation…

(20) Negative Predicates in (1) Cannot be Directly Negated * Tlél tlél yaa ḵushgé

NEG NEG IRR.shCL.smart Judgment: Ill-formed; not meaningful; does not mean ‘not dumb’

Page 7: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  7  

(21) Negative Predicates in (1) Cannot be Directly Negated

a. * Tlél tlél ushx̱éitl. NEG NEG IRR.shCL.lucky Judgment: Ill-formed, not meaningful, does not mean ‘not unlucky’ b. Tlél yéi utí tlél ushx̱éitl NEG thus is NEG IRR.shCL.lucky He’s not unlucky. (Lit. It’s not so that he’s unlucky.) (22) Negative Predicates in (1) Cannot be Directly Negated a. * Tlél tlél ushkʼé NEG NEG IRR.shCL.good Judgment: Ill-formed, not meaningful, does not mean ‘not bad’ b. Tlél wáa sá utí NEG how IRR.is It’s not bad. (Lit. It’s not any way)

All these facts point to the following conclusions… (23) Key Syntactic Conclusion

The negation found with the negative predicates in (1) is clausal negation; it is not some form of verbally incorporated negation.

(24) Immediately Following Conclusion

The extra morphological changes found with the negative predicates in (1) – the change in ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset – are licensed by clausal negation.

(25) Some Obvious Subsequent Questions

a. Is it negation per se that licenses these morphological changes seen in (1)? Or, would downward-entailment be sufficient? (i.e., are they like weak NPIs?)

b. Can clausal negation license these morphological changes across a clause-

boundary? Or, does only clause-mate negation license these changes?

Page 8: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  8  

(26) Downward Entailment (D.E.) is Not Sufficient for Verbal Classifier Change

• As shown by the contrast between (26a) and (26b), simply embedding the root k’éi ‘good’ in a conditional antecedent isn’t sufficient to license the shift to sh-classifier

• As shown by the contrast between (26a) and (26c), conditional antecedents do license

the use of interrogative pronouns as (plain) indefinites (as negation does) (cf. shenme ‘what’ in Mandarin)

• These facts support the following picture:

o Like in many other languages (e.g., Mandarin) interrogative pronouns in

Tlingit can be used as NPIs, where they are licensed in D.E. environments (e.g. negation, antecedent of conditionals)

o The use of an sh-classifier with the root k’éi ‘good’ in Tlingit is not

generally licensed in D.E. environments

a. Daa sá kʼéiyi, ax̱ éeshch yax̱ ayagux̱sax̱áa. anything 0CL.good.SUB 1sg.POSS father.ERG FUT.eat.up

If anything is good, my father will eat it all up. b. * Daa sá shakʼéyi, ax̱ éeshch yax̱ ayagux̱sax̱áa.

anywhing shCL.good.SUB 1sg.POSS father.ERG FUT.eat.up Judgment: Ill-formed, not meaningful c. (i) Aadóo sáwé tá? who.FOC 0CL.sleep Who is sleeping? Judgment: Cannot mean ‘Someone is sleeping’. (ii) Tlél aadóo sá utá. NEG anyone IRR.0CL.sleep Nobody is sleeping. (27) Higher Negation is Not Sufficient for Verbal Classifier Change

The contrast between (27a,b) shows that negation in a matrix clause does not license tuse of the sh-classifier with kʼéi ‘good’ in a subordinate clause. Similar facts appear in (28).

a. Yéi x̱waajée tlél ushkʼéyi 1sgS.think NEG IRR.shCL.good.SUB I think that it’s bad. b. * Tlél yéi x̱wají ushkʼéyi NEG IRR.1sgS.think IRR.shCL.good.SUB Judgment: Ill-formed, not meaningful

Page 9: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  9  

(28) Higher Negation is Not Sufficient for Verbal Classifier Change a. Tlél ax̱ tuwáa ushgú tlél x̱at ushkʼé. NEG IRR.1sgS.want NEG IRR.1sgS.shCL.good I don’t want to be bad. b. * Tlél ax̱ tuwáa ushgú x̱at ushkʼé. NEG IRR.1sgS.want IRR.1sgS.shCL.good Judgment: Ill-formed, not meaningful (29) Interim Summary: Negation in Negative Predicates

a. The morphological changes found in the negative predicates in (1) – the change to sh-classifier and the root mutation – are licensed by clause-mate clausal negation

b. When clausal negation appears in concert with these morphological changes, the

meaning is strengthened to an antonymic concept. (i.e., ‘not good’ < ‘bad’; ‘not smart’ < ‘dumb’) 4. Interactions Between ‘NEG Antonyms’ and Degree Modifiers The formal analysis presented in Section 5 will capture the facts in (29) as well as the following pattern regarding the interactions between ‘NEG antonyms’ (7) and degree modifiers. (30) Scope/Word-Order Generalization for Negation and Degree Modification

a. In order to modify a NEG antonym with a degree modifier, the modifier must precede the negation.

b. In order to negate a positive predicate modified by a degree modifier, the negation

must precede the degree modifier. As illustrated below, these generalizations are not terribly surprising…

But it’s definitely worth documenting their existence…

…And capturing them is a nice result of the proposed syntactic-semantic analysis…

Page 10: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  10  

(31) NEG Antonyms with Degree Modifiers The following examples illustrated degree modification of NEG antonyms, as well as their positive antonyms.

• In all cases, the degree modifier is yáanáx̱ ‘more than’. In all cases, modification of

the NEG antonym places the degree modifier before the negator a. (i) A yáanáx̱ áwé yakʼei yáatʼa 3O.more.than FOC 0CL.good this.one This one is better than it. (ii) A yáanáx̱ tléil ushkʼé 3O.more.than NEG IRR.shCL.good It is worse than it. b. (i) Wéitʼaa áwé a yáanáx̱ litseen that.one FOC 3O.more.than lCL.strong That one is stronger than him. (ii) A yáanáx̱ áwé tlél ulcheen 3O.more.than FOC NEG IRR.lCL.strong(+RootChange) He is weaker than him. c. (i) Ax̱ yáanáx̱ yaa ḵoodzig̱éi 1sgO.more.than sCL.smart She is smarter than me. (ii) Héitʼaa yáanáx̱ hél yaa ḵooshgé that.one more.than NEG IRR.shCL.smart He’s dumber than that one. d. (i) Kúnáx̱ a yáanáx̱ naalée very 3O.more.than 0CL.far It’s a lot farther than that. (ii) A yáanáx̱ tléil unalí 3O.more.than NEG IRR.0CL.far It’s closer than that. e. (i) Yáatʼaa a yáanáx̱ x̱ʼalitseen this.one 3O.more.than lCL.expensive This one is more expensive than that. (ii) A yáanáx̱ áwé ḵúnáx̱ tléil x̱ʼeiltseen yáatʼaa 3O.more.than FOC very NEG IRR.lCL.expensive this.one This one is much cheaper than that.

Page 11: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  11  

(32) Negation of Degree Modification The following examples illustrate the negation of positive predicates modified by degree modifiers. • In all cases, the degree modifier appears after the negation

a. Tlél a yáanáx̱ ukʼé NEG 3O.more.than IRR.0CL.good

Itʼs not better than that. (cf. (31a))

b. Tlél tlax̱ ukʼé NEG very IRR.0CL.good Itʼs not very good. c. Tléil tlax̱ a yáanáx̱ x̱ʼeiltseen NEG very 3O.more.than IRR.lCL.expensive Itʼs not much more expensive. (cf. (31e)) d. Tlél a yáanáx̱ unalí NEG 3O.more.than IRR.0CL.far It’s not farther than that. (cf. (31d)) e. Tlél tlax̱ unalí NEG very IRR.0CL.far Itʼs not very far. f. Hél tlax̱ utʼá. g. Hél a yáanáx̱ utʼá NEG very IRR.0CL.hot NEG 3O.more.than IRR.0CL.hot Itʼs not very hot. Itʼs not hotter than that. (33) Further Evidence for Semantic Contrasts in (31)-(32)

In scenario (33a), only the negation of a comparative would be true. The comparative of a negative predicate would be false (since the food is equally good).

a. Scenario: We have two plates of food that are equally good.

b. Tlél a yáanáx̱ ukʼé NEG 3O.more.than IRR.0CL.good It’s not better than that. Judgment: Acceptable in this scenario

c. A yáanáx̱ tlél ushkʼé 3O.more.than NEG IRR.shCL.good It’s worse than that. Judgment: Not acceptable in this scenario

Page 12: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  12  

(34) Further Evidence for Semantic Contrasts in (31)-(32)

In scenario (34b), only the negation of a comparative would be true. The comparative of a negative predicate would be false (since the hats are equally expensive).

a. Scenario: We have two hats that are equally expensive. b. Tléil tlax̱ a yáanáx̱ x̱ʼeiltseen NEG very 3O.more.than IRR.lCL.expensive It’s not more expensive than that. Judgment: Acceptable in this scenario c. A yáanáx̱ tlél x̱ʼeiltseen 3O.more.than NEG IRR.lCL.expensive It’s cheaper than that. Judgment: Not acceptable in this scenario. (35) Observation Regarding Negative Predicates in (4)

• The ability for tlél x̱eiltseen ‘cheap / not expensive’ (4b) and tlél unalí ‘near / not far’ (4a) to appear with degree modification (31d,e) suggests that they really do have strong, antonymic readings…

o In most semantic treatments, the negation of a positive predicate

shouldn’t project the degree argument that a degree modifier would need

• More work could/should be done, though, to somehow rule out the possibility that (31d,e) and (34c) involve some kind of metalinguistic comparative.

o In English, it is marginally possible to say things like This restaurant is more

‘not expensive’ than that other one… 5. A Formal Syntactic and Semantic Analysis of Tlingit NEG Antonyms It has been independently proposed that negative adjectives in English actually contain syntactic negation (Buering 2007, Heim 2008).

• Under such analyses, predicates like bad in English underlyingly has the following (LF) structure: [ NOT [ GOOD ] ]

• The following analysis of the Tlingit NEG antonyms in (1)-(4) builds upon the tools

and insights of this prior work…

Page 13: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  13  

5.1 The Analysis: A Special, ‘Negative Concord’ Degree Operator in Tlingit (36) Gradable Predicates are Relations Between Degrees and Entities a. [[ k’ei / good ]] = [ λd : λx : goodness(x) ≥ d ]

b. [[ tseen / strong ]] = [ λd : λx : strength(x) ≥ d ] c. [[ lei / far ]] = [ λd : λx : distance(x) ≥ d ] In order for a gradable predicate to be used as a main predicate, it must appear with the (phonologically null) POS operator… (37) The POS Operator [[ POS ]] = [ λP<dt> : Lc ⊂ P ]

• Lc is the contextually determined ‘no mans land’ of non-extreme degrees.

• For example, in the case of ‘good’, it’s those degrees of goodness that neither count as ‘good’ nor as ‘bad’.

Another ingredient I will use is the (phonologically null) degree-relative operator, DEG-REL. (38) The DEG-REL Operator a. Semantics: [[ DEG-REL ]] = [ λP<dt> : P ] b. Syntax:

• Generated in the degree argument position of a gradable predicate. • For type-theoretic reasons, undergoes movement, creating a syntactically

derived <d,t>-predicate (just like a relative clause operator) (39) Illustration: Positive Predicate Sentence a. Sentence: Yak’éi ‘it is good’ (1a) b. LF: [ POS [ DEG-REL1 [ 1 [ pro2 [ t1 [ yak’éi ] … ] c. Truth-Conditions: Lc ⊂ { d’ : goodness(x2) ≥ d’ }

• (39c) states that the degrees of goodness falling below x2’s degree of goodness contain the ‘non-extreme’ degrees.

• This could only be the case if x2’s degree of goodness is above the ‘non-

extreme’ degrees, and so is among those degrees qualifying as ‘good’.

Page 14: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  14  

To capture the ‘negative predicates’ in (1), I propose the existence (in Tlingit) of an additional degree-relative operator, NEG-REL (40) The NEG-REL Operator a. Semantics: [[ NEG-REL ]] = [ λP<dt> : P ] b. Syntax: Same as ‘DEG-REL’, except that…

• Only licensed in the specifier of NegP; must move to SpecNegP

o In this sense, it’s a bit like a ‘negative concord’ item…

• Furthermore, it is the only degree operator that is permitted to cross negation and move to SpecNegP

• Adjacency to predicate triggers (lexically stipulated) morpho-

phonological changes.

o E.g., shift to the sh-classifier; root consonantal mutation (41) Illustration: Negative Predicate Sentence a. Sentence: tlél ushkʼé ‘it is bad’ (1a) b. LF: [ POS [ NEG-REL1 [ 1 [ NEG [ pro2 [ t1 [ yak’éi ] … ] c. Truth-Conditions: Lc ⊂ { d’ : ¬ (goodness(x2) ≥ d’) }

• (41c) states that the degrees of goodness that don’t fall below x2’s degree of goodness contain the ‘non-extreme’ degrees.

• This could only be the case if x2’s degree of goodness falls below the ‘non-

extreme’ degrees, and so is among those degrees qualifying as ‘bad’. Side-Note:

• Movement of NEG-REL to SpecNegP will create a syntactically derived <d,t> predicate

• Thus, to be used a main predicate, this structure must (again) be complement to a POS operator…

• Consequently, we must allow the POS operator in Tlingit the option of being

generated above NegP…

Page 15: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  15  

(42) Comparison: Negation of a Positive Predicate a. Sentence: tlél ukʼé ‘it is not good’ (1a) b. LF: [ NEG [ POS [ DEG-REL1 [ 1 [ pro2 [ t1 [ yak’éi ] … ] c. Truth-Conditions: ¬ [ Lc ⊂ { d’ : goodness(x2) ≥ d’ } ]

• (42c) states that the degress of goodness falling below x2’s degree of goodness don’t contain the ‘non-extreme’ degrees.

• Thus, these truth-conditions will hold if either:

o x2’s goodness falls within the non-extreme degrees (x2 is just so-so) o x2’s goodness falls below the non-extreme degrees (x2 is bad)

(43) Prediction: No Negative Predicate Reading of (42a)

This analysis predicts that sentence (42a) cannot have the LF in (41b), and so cannot get the ‘negative antonym’ reading of (41a).

• After all, if there were a degree operator in SpecNegP, it could only be NEG-REL…

• But if NEG-REL were generated as the argument for yak’éi, then the classifier would

shift to the sh-classifier…

This analysis also predicts the interesting contrast in meaning between (17)-(18)… (44) Key Prediction: NEG Antonyms and NPIs a. Sentence: Tlél daa sá ushkʼé ‘Everything is bad’ (17) b. LF: [ POS [ NEG-REL1 [ 1 [ NEG [ anything [ t1 [ yak’éi ] … ]

• daa sá ‘anything’ is in the scope of NEG • NEG-REL moves to SpecNegP • The derived degree-predicate is argument to POS

c. Truth-Conditions: Lc ⊂ { d’ : ¬ ∃x (goodness(x) ≥ d’) }

• (44c) states that the non-extreme degrees are contained within those degrees

of goodness such that nothing has a degree of goodness above them.

• This could only hold if everything’s degree of goodness falls below the non-extreme degrees, and so everything qualifies as ‘bad’

Page 16: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  16  

(45) Comparison: NPI with a Positive Predicate a. Sentence: Tlél daa sá ukʼé ‘Nothing is good’ (18a) b. LF: [ NEG [ anything [ 2 [ POS [ DEG-REL1 [ 1 [ t2 [ t1 [ yak’éi ] … ]

• daa sá ‘anything’ is in the scope of NEG • There is no NEG-REL; only DEG-REL • The degree-predicated derived by DEG-REL is sister to POS • Since DEG-REL cannot move to SpecNegP, DEG-REL –

and thus POS – must be in scope of NEG c. Truth-Conditions: ¬ ∃x. Lc ⊂ { d’ : goodness(x2) ≥ d’ }

• (45c) states that there is no x such that the degrees of goodness falling below x’s degree of goodness contain the ‘non-extreme’ degrees.

• This could only hold if nothing has a degree of goodness higher than the ‘non-extreme’ degrees.

o Thus, nothing is definitely good o Though some things could be merely so-so; not really bad.

Next, I introduce the following semantics for the degree phrase yáanáx̱ ‘more than’ (again, borrowing from work by Buering (2007) and Heim (2008))… (46) Comparative Operator [[ yáanáx̱ ]] = [ λP<dt> : [ λQ<dt> : P ⊂ Q ] ] (47) Illustration: Comparative with Positive Predicate a. Sentence: A yáanáx̱ yak’éi ‘x2 is better than x4’ (31a) b. LF: [ [ [ DEG-REL3 [ 3 [ pro4 [ t3 yak’éi ]…] yáanáx̱ ]

[DEG-REL1 [ 1 [ pro2 [ t1 yak’éi ] … ] c. Truth-Conditions: { d’ : goodness(x4) ≥ d’ } ⊂ { d’ : goodness(x2) ≥ d’ }

• (47c) states that the degrees of goodness lower than x2’s goodness contains the degrees of goodness lower than x4’s goodness.

• This could only hold if x2’s degree of goodness is higher than x4’s

As shown below, this syntax-semantics predicts that yáanáx̱ ‘more than’ could take as argument a NegP whose specifier contains NEG-REL

Page 17: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  17  

(48) Illustration: Comparative with NEG Antonym a. Sentence: A yáanáx tlél ushkʼé ‘x2 is worse than x4’ (31a) b. LF: [ [ [ NEG-REL3 [ 3 [ NEG [ pro4 [ t3 yak’éi ]…] yáanáx̱ ]

[ NEG-REL1 [ 1 [ NEG [ pro2 [ t1 yak’éi ] … ] c. Truth-Conditions: { d’ : ¬(goodness(x4) ≥ d’) } ⊂ { d’ : ¬(goodness(x2) ≥ d’) }

• (48c) states that the degrees of goodness that are above x2’s degree of goodness contains the degrees of goodness that are above x4’s goodness.

• This could only hold if x2’s degree of goodness is lower than x4’s

(49) Comparison: Negation of a Positive Comparative a. Sentence: Tlél a yáanáx̱ ukʼé ‘x2 is not better than x4’ (32a) b. LF: [ NEG [ [ [ DEG-REL3 [ 3 [ pro4 [ t3 yak’éi ]…] yáanáx̱ ]

[DEG-REL1 [ 1 [ pro2 [ t1 yak’éi ] … ] c. Truth-Conditions: ¬ [{ d’ : goodness(x4) ≥ d’ } ⊂ { d’ : goodness(x2) ≥ d’ } ]

• (49c) states that it’s not the case that x2’s goodness is higher than x4’s

• Thus, these truth-conditions could hold if x2 and x4 were of equal goodness (50) Summary: the Scope/Word-Order Generalization in (30)

• We’ve just seen how our syntax/semantic gives us an analysis of the comparative sentences in (31) and (32)

• Crucially, the LFs we’ve been considering accord with the surface word-order in

those sentences.

o In general, we’ve been assuming the natural view that ‘things to the left’ outscope ‘things to the right’…

• In this way, our analysis captures the Scope/Word-Order Generalization in (30)

o In comparatives of NEG Antonyms, yáanáx̱ precedes tlél precisely because it

outscopes it.

o For exactly these reasons, tlél precedes yáanáx̱ in the negation of a (positive) comparative.

Page 18: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  18  

5.2 Some Further Predictions and Questions (51) Structures Predicted to be Ill-Formed by the Analysis

Each of the following is predicted to be ill-formed under the analysis above. It is not currently known to me whether they are in fact ill-formed (a task for this summer).

a. Comparative Operator Appearing Before Negation of a Positive Antonym

A yáanáx̱ tlél ukʼé 3O.more.than NEG IRR.0CL.good (cf. (31a), (32a))

o If degree operator yáanáx̱ ‘more than’ is before negation, then it must be scoping over negation…

o But since yáanáx̱ ‘more than’ needs a degree argument, that must mean that

tlél ukʼé is a (syntactically derived) degree predicate…

o But the only ‘degree relative’ operator that can move over tlél is NEG-REL…

o And if NEG-REL were in the structure, then the classifier with k’éi ‘good’ would have to shift to the ‘sh-classifier’

b. Comparative Operator Between Negation and a NEG Antonym

Tlél a yáanáx ushkʼé NEG 3O.more.than IRR.shCL.good (cf. (31a), (32a))

o If negation is before yáanáx̱ ‘more than’, then it must be scoping over ‘more than’…

o Consequently, there must be a ‘degree relative’ operator moving from the

degree argument position of k’éi ‘good’ to a position below yáanáx̱

o The position this ‘degree relative’ operator is moving to is not SpecNegP (obviously), and so this degree operator is not NEG-REL

o Consequently, there should be no shift to the sh-classifier on k’éi ‘good’

c. Negation of a Comparative of a NEG Antonym

Tlél a yáanáx tlél ushkʼé NEG 3O.more.than NEG IRR.shCL.good (cf. (32a))

o A sentence like this would end up having two clausal negations, and so should be just as bad as (22a)

Page 19: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  19  

(52) Intervention Effects with DegP Movement in Tlingit 4 a. Potential Problem for the Analysis in Section 5.1

o The analysis proposes that a degree relative operator ‘NEG-REL’ moves over negation, to create a syntactically derived antonym of the root…

o Such movement of degree-OPs over logical/quantificational expressions,

however, is generally thought to be impossible

o If we allowed such movements freely, we’d wrongly predict that Tlingit sentences like (53b) can be construed as true in scenarios like (54c)

b. Key Sentence:

Ldakát hás áwé du ḵín has koodligéi Bill. everyone FOC 3O.less.than lCL.big Bill Everyone is less tall than Bill. c. Falsifying Scenario: One person (Mary) is taller than Bill. d. Over-Generating a True Reading of (52b) 5 (i) Problematic LF:

[ [ [ DEG-REL2 [ 2 [ Bill [ t2 ligéi ]…] ḵín ]

[ DEG-REL1 [ 1 [ Ldakát hás [ t1 has koodligéi ]…]

§ In the LF above, DEG-REL moves over the quantificational subject ldakát has ‘everyone’

(ii) Predicted Truth-Conditions

{ d’ : height(Bill) ≥ d’ } ⊃ { d’ : ∀x. height(x) ≥ d’ }

§ These truth-conditions state that the degrees d’ such that everyone is

taller than d’ is contained in the degrees of height below Bill’s height.

§ These truth-conditions only require Bill to be taller than the shortest person!

• And so they could hold if there’s a person taller than Bill!

                                                                                                               4  I thank Rajesh Bhatt for bringing this problem to my attention, and for his helpful discussion of it. 5  This problem was first noticed by Heim (2006) for the equivalent English sentence Everyone is less tall than Bill.

Page 20: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  20  

(53) A Not-at-All Satisfying Solution (?)

§ ‘Negative concord’ items like NEG-REL are exceptionally permitted to move over negation on their way to SpecNegP

§ And, even then, they aren’t permitted to scope over quantificational DPs

Finally, let’s consider some ways in which the analysis from Section 5.1 might address those questions under (6)… (54) NEG Antonyms Whose Roots Cannot Appear without Negation a. Question:

What is the nature of roots like hélʼk, which can only appear in ‘NEG antonyms’? (i) Tlél koohélʼk (ii) * kayahélʼk NEG IRR.0CL.strong(?) 0CL.strong(?) He is weak. b. Possible Answers:

(i) Perhaps NEG-REL optionally causes litseen ‘strong’ to undergo a suppletive alternation to ka-hélʼk…

(ii) Perhaps ka-hélʼk ‘strong’ specially c-selects for NEG-REL

§ Note that the latter analysis would raise the question of whether verb forms like sh-k’éi should be analyzed similarly (via c-selection)…

(55) NEG Antonyms with No Morphological Change a. Question:

Do the negated predicates in (4) actually have (strong) antonymic readings? If so, how are those derived?

(i) naaléi (ii) tlél unalé

0CL.far NEG IRR.0CL.far It is far. It is near. b. Possible Answers: The empirical question above has yet to be answered….

But, if it turns out that those verbs do have strong, antonymic readings… These could just be cases where where NEG-REL fails to have a morpho-phonological effect…

Page 21: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  21  

6. Future Directions: Cross-Polar (A)nomalies in Tlingit? As mentioned earlier, Buering (2007) and Heim (2008) propose that English negative gradable adjectives underlyingly contain negation….

The primary empirical motivation for this comes from the facts in (56)-(57)… (56) A Curious Contrast in English: Cross-Polar (A)nomalies (Buering 2007) a. This board is shorter than it is wide. b. * This board is taller than it is narrow. (57) The Cross-Polar ‘Nomaly’ Generalization (Buering 2007)

In a subcomparative, the ‘polarities’ of the adjectives can differ only if the positive adjective is in the comparative phrase.

(58) Buering’s (2007) Analysis of Generalization (57)

Buering (2007) puts forth a treatment of (56)-(57) that rests upon the existence of certain PF-level operations occurring in English.

a. Pre-Spell Out Structure of (56a): [ This board [ [ not -er ] tall ] [ than it is wide ] ] b. PF Form of (56a): Short PF movement of –er creates the following structure: [ This board [ [ not tall ] -er ] [ than it is wide ] ] c. Subsequent Spell-Out Rules Acting on (58b): [ not tall ] à /short/ /short/ + [er] à /shorter/ d. LF-Structure of (56a): Covert movement of [not –er] creates the following: [ [ not -er ] [ 1 [ this board t1 tall ] ] [ than it is wide ] ]

§ Note that in (58d), the adjectival predicates have the same (positive) polarity

§ Under Beuring’s (2007) semantics, (58d) ends up meaning ‘this board is less tall than it is wide’

Page 22: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  22  

(59) Heim’s (2008) Analysis of Generalization (57)

In brief, Heim’s analysis eschews the PF-operations proposed by Buering (2008). Instead, Heim (2008) proposes that the PF and LF of (56a) are as follows:

a. Surface Form of (56a): [ this board [ er [ NOT long ] ] [ than it [ DEG-REL NOT ] wide ] ]

§ [ er [ NOT long ] ] à [ er [short] ] à shorter

§ The negation in ‘[ DEG-REL NOT ]’ is deleted via ellipsis under identity with the NOT that gets spelled out in ‘short’

§ The resulting string is thus pronounced this board is shorter than it is wide

b. LF Form of (56a):

[ 1 [ this board t1 NOT long ] ] [ er [ than [ NOT [ DEG-REL2 [ 2 [ it t2 NOT wide ] … ]

§ The LF in (59b) can be obtained via particular movements of er, the DEG-

REL and NOT

§ Under Heim’s (2008) semantics, (59b) ends up meaning ‘this board is more short than it is narrow’

Does Tlingit offer any perspective as to which of these analyses is closer to correct?... (60) On Applying These Analyses to Tlingit IF Tlingit exhibits the same contrast in (56) that English does, then…

a. Buering’s (2007) analysis is a bit of a non-starter.

§ In Buering’s syntax, the comparative operator –er never forms a syntactic or phonological constituent with the than-phrase.

§ This is fine for English, but it won’t be exportable directly to Tlingit, where

the comparative operator yáanáx̱ ‘more than’ forms a constituent with the standard of comparison.

b. Heim’s (2008) analysis is more amendable…

§ Heim’s analysis doesn’t depend on any English-specific PF rules, and it

assumes that the comparative operator does form an LF constituent with the ‘than’-phrase.

Page 23: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  23  

(61) The Upshot In a manner of speaking…

§ Buering (2007) predicts that Tlingit should not show the cross-polar anomaly pattern in (56), while Heim (2008) predicts that it should…

§ It would be very enlightening, then, to know which of these predictions is true!

7. Conclusion

§ In Tlingit, certain negative (gradable) predicates are formed from the combination of clausal negation and a positive root

§ I’ve put forth an analysis where these predicates are formed by means of degree

operator that must move to SpecNegP (a kind of ‘negative concord Deg-OP’)

o This analysis captures an array facts regarding the ways in which these negative predicates interact with degree operators

o This analysis also makes several further predictions which have yet to be tested with speakers…

§ This all lends indirect support to the view that negative (gradable) predicates in English

have a similar, underlyingly negative structure. (62) One Major Outstanding Question

§ How can the empirical question in (55a) be answered?

§ How can we show whether tlél unalí ‘not far’ truly has a (strong) antonymic reading meaning ‘near’?

Acknowledgements:

Deepest thanks and gratitude are owed first and foremost to Tlingit elders William Fawcett (Kóoshdaak’w Éesh), Carolyn Martin (K’altseen), John Martin (Keihéenák’w), and one additional elder, who preferred to remain anonymous. I am deeply grateful for all that they have taught me regarding the Tlingit language. Special thanks are also owed to Lance Twitchell (X’unei), James Crippen (Dzéiwsh), and Rose Underhill for their crucial logistical support of this study. Finally, I would like to dedicate this work to the memory of Dick Dauenhauer (Xwaayeenák), who with his wife Nora Marks Dauenhauer (Keixwnéi), has done more than anyone else to advance the study and preservation of Tlingit language and culture. This material has benefitted greatly from presentations at the UMass Semantics Workshop and The UMass ‘Funny Languages Afternoon’ (UMAFLAA). Special thanks to Rajesh Bhatt, Elizabeth Bogal-Allbritten, Vincent Homer, Larry Horn, Rodica Ivan, Barbara Partee, Peggy Speas, Anthony Woodbury, and Ellen Woolford, for their helpful comments upon earlier versions of this work.

This material is based upon work supported by the National Science Foundation, under Award No. BCS-1322770.

Page 24: Negation and Negative Antonyms in Tlingit 1 1. The Central ...people.umass.edu/scable/papers/NegAntonymsTlingit-HO.pdfin ‘verbal classifier’ or the mutation in the root onset –

  24  

References Buering, Daniel. 2007. “Cross-Polar Nomalies.” In Friedmand, T. and M. Gibson (eds) Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory 17, pp. 37-52. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University. Heim, Irene. 2006. “Little.” In Gibson, M. and J. Howell (eds) Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory 16, pp. 35-58. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University. Heim, Irene. 2008. “Decomposing Antonyms?” In Groenn, A. (ed) Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 12. Oslo: ILOS. Kroeger, Paul. 2014. “External Negation in Malay/Indonesian.” Language 90(1): 137-184. Matthewson, Lisa. 2004. “On the Methodology of Semantic Fieldwork.” International Journal of American Linguistics 70(4): 369-415. Rice, Keren. 2000. Morpheme Order and Semantic Scope. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.