Nagarjuna, Enlightment and Time

download Nagarjuna, Enlightment and Time

of 9

Transcript of Nagarjuna, Enlightment and Time

  • 7/29/2019 Nagarjuna, Enlightment and Time

    1/9

    ENLIGHTENMENT AND TIME:AN EXAMINATION OF NAGARJUNA'S CONCEPTOF TIME

    Presented by

    the Wanderling

    by Anthony Birch, PhD

    he belief in the independent existence of things in the world is a mainstay of the

    common sense view of life. Trees, flowers, houses, the earth, stars and galaxies exist and willcontinue to exist without us, according to common sense. All these things, and most importantly

    our own conscious lives, however, appear to be caught up in the inexorable flow of time.

    Common sense readily admits that as time passes, ordinary physical objects, and human beings,

    come and go. It would seem, therefore, that the flow of time is itself the sole unchanging elementin an ever-changing universe.

    Yet the independent reality not only of physical objects, but the flow of time in which they

    appear to be enmeshed, are precisely the common sense conceptions that the Buddhist philosophyof the Middle Way seeks to unravel. Indeed, their unraveling is understood to be essential to theattainment of enlightenment, a complete understanding of and spiritual unity with the universe.

    Unlike many Western philosophies (including the contemporary scientific view that places the

    origin of the universe at a point in time), the Middle Way attempts to show us how to dispensewith the concept of the flow of time. Ultimately, the belief in the flow of time, a last refuge of

    common sense, is to be overcome. How are we to understand this transformation of a belief that

    seems so well-grounded not only in common sense but in science? What religious or philosophicinterpretation can we give the concept of time in the Middle Way?

    The purpose of this paper is to investigate Nagarjuna's conception of time and its relationship to

    enlightenment. In order to provide a reasonable limit to the scope of this paper, I shall confinemyself to Nagarjuna's arguments presented in his most famous work theMulamadhyamakakarikas (herein after MMK). I shall divide this examination into three parts: (1)

    Nagarjuna's goals, central terms and strategies and how these form a backdrop against which his

    conception of time is to be understood; (2) An analysis of the specific arguments Nagarjunaoffers in the MMK relating to time and allied topics such as space and motion; (3) An interpretive

    account of how one can incorporate Nagarjuna's arguments concerning time into an

    understanding of the enlightenment experience.

    http://www.geocities.com/the_wanderling/wanderling.htmlmailto:[email protected]://www.geocities.com/the_wanderling/wanderling.htmlmailto:[email protected]
  • 7/29/2019 Nagarjuna, Enlightment and Time

    2/9

    I. Nagarjuna's Plan and Purpose

    Religion and Philosophy

    In approaching Nagarjuna's thought it must be remembered that Nagarjuna's purpose isreligious. His primary aim is to inspire an understanding that will lead toward enlightenment.

    Nagarjuna uses logic and philosophy, but his aim is to indicate truths that lie beyond these

    abstract disciplines. The arguments presented by Nagarjuna should be understood as tools or waystations to be used on the path to enlightenment. The logical, the rational, and the philosophic are

    ultimately transformed to the mystical (Betty p. 139 and Streng p. 181).

    Nagarjuna has a secondary purpose that lies behind the MMK, and this also must be

    understood in a religious context: Nagarjuna wanted to refute the materialist ideas of theAbhidharma schools and return Buddhism to what he thought was the Middle Way. Nagarjuna

    was committed to explaining the radical notion that nirvana and samsara and were identical -- anidea that would be quite difficult for many of his contemporaries to accept. We should, therefore,regard the MMK as an exercise in both practical polemics and religious persuasion.

    The Meaning of Own-Being

    Almost all of Nagarjuna's arguments are structured around the conception of things which are

    said to have "own-being" (sbavhavah). It is essential that we understand how Nagarjuna definesthis term. An examination of the text (see in particular verses 7.16, 15.2, 15.8 and 15.11) shows

    that own-being is to be understood as that which is self-identical, exists by itself or through itsown accord, and is not dependent on other beings for its existence. From this definition,

    Nargarjuna believed it followed that things with own-being were eternal.

    The basic philosophic argument of the MMK is that there are no "things," either sensible

    objects of the life world or subjective components of the consciousness, which have own-being.

    All things are, rather, "empty" and without essential nature. They have only relative, dependent

    being. This applies even to Nirvana, which, because it is not separate and inaccessible, iscoincident with the life world.

    The Argument Against Causality

    Nagarjuna's attempt to show the identity of samsara and nirvana rests on his showing theunintelligibility of causality. Nagarjuna seeks to show that the common-sense view of causality

    involves contradictions. If causality can be shown to be self-contradictory, then the "things"

  • 7/29/2019 Nagarjuna, Enlightment and Time

    3/9

    which reputedly participate in the chain of causality either have no own-being or do not

    participate in causality at all. Let us consider the arguments on causality Nagarjuna offers inChapter 20 of the MMK. He says:

    1. If a product is produced through the aggregate of causes and conditions, and exists in

    the aggregate, how will it be produced in the aggregate?2. If a product is produced in the aggregate of causes and conditions and does not exist in

    the aggregate, how will it be produced in the aggregate? (Streng translation)

    In other words, if a cause C already contains its effect or product E, then cause and effect are

    essentially identical and nothing is really produced. C and E are really two different aspects of the

    same thing. By extension, causality in general, all the "production" in the world, can not be theresult of so-called "causes" because the effects that are already contained in the causes. Following

    this logic, we might therefore conclude that all the apparent goings-on in the world, the apparent

    interrelation of causes and effects, is really a kind of mirage.

    On the other hand (verse 2), we might consider that cause and effect are entirely separate, but inthat case, argues Nagarjuna, "production" again has no meaning. If C and E are independent

    events, with separate own-being, then one can not be rightfully said to cause the other. Once

    again, the world of ordinary experience would need to be reinterpreted and the meaning of"production" would have to be other than it is, if the separateness of cause and effect accounted

    for the goings-on of the world. Nagarjuna summarizes this as follows:

    19. Certainly a oneness of cause and product is not possible at all. Nor is a difference of cause

    and product possible at all.

    Let us clarify Nagarjuna's method and aims in these passages on causality. It has been argued

    by some (see Waldo, pp. 295-296.) that Nagarjuna's appeal to ordinary meanings used in these

    and similar passages throughout the MMK shows us that Nagarjuna is an ordinary languagephilosopher with a remarkable resemblance to the later Wittgenstein. Both are arguing that

    language shows us only the interdependence of words, leaving us with essential ambiguities of

    ultimate reference of words and in a dilemma about what reality is. As intriguing as this view is, I

    believe it must be rejected. Nagarjuna's arguments are not about language, but about reality (seeAnderson, passim). Nagarjuna recognizes the conventional nature of language, and even denies

    that his "ultimate" category, "emptiness," should be understood as anything other than a

    convention. The term "emptiness" does not stand for a permanent or transcendent metaphysicalreality whose meaning we can grasp by apprehending the reality behind the name. It is precisely

    because of its ambiguous and suggestive nature, not in spite of it, that language (and in particular

    "emptiness") can help guide us on the path of release.

    The argument against the own-being in causality brings us to a consideration of how timefigures in the explanation of events in the world. If causality is not logically comprehensible in

    terms of identity and difference, how are events to be related in terms of time? Would it not be

    the case that events could be related as "before" and "after" regardless of the refutation of thecausality? Thus, it might seem that Nagarjuna's view as so far presented would allow an

  • 7/29/2019 Nagarjuna, Enlightment and Time

    4/9

    essentially Humean conception of events: causality is denied but constant conjunction in

    sequential time is asserted. This would allow that time "exists" but events are logicallyindependent. Such a conception, is, of course, one that Nagarjuna would reject. Our next task is

    to see how Nagarjuna develops additional arguments concerning time.

    II. The Concept of Time

    Motion and Space

    In our study of time, it will be instructive to first consider the allied topics of motion and space.We shall consider each in turn.

    Contrary to what is often surmised, Nagarjuna does not deny motion (see Kalupahana p. 130 and

    Wayman p. 47). Nagarjuna concludes the chapter on motion with the assertion "Therefore, the

    process of going, the goer and the destination to be gone to do not exist," (2.25) but thisostensible denial of motion must be placed in the framework of the ontology Nagarjuna seeks to

    refute. Here, the moving things denied are those which have own- being. All the previous

    argumentation in the chapter shows that the motion, the object moved, and the destinationachieved are all relative to each other. As Nagarjuna states, "certainly the act of going is not

    produced without a goer" (2.6) and "the goer can not come into being when there is no going"

    (2.7). As in the case of causality, Nagarjuna establishes the relativity of two mutually dependentconceptions, i.e. the inapplicability of identity and difference: "Neither the identity nor the

    essential difference is established regarding the two conceptions goer and act of going" (2.21).

    We may state Nagarjuna's conclusion another way: "motion" can not be conceived apart from

    objects which move; motion is not an independent category of being. It is important to note theground of Nagarjuna's conclusion: "own-being" is self-contradictory when it attempts to explain

    the ordinary perceptible reality of objects in motion. No metaphysical notions, such as "Motion

    and its Objects" need be invoked once relativity is recognized.

    Now let us briefly consider Nagarjuna's notion of space in chapter 5 of the MMK. The line of

    argumentation is both inventive and quite different than in other sections of the MMK. Nagarjuna

    asserts as a matter of principle that "in no case has anything existed without a defining

    characteristic" (5.2). Whatever we regard as existing must be able to be picked out by the sensesor isolated in thought in some way. We can do this only in virtue of some "defining

    characteristic" of the thing under consideration. The problem with "space" is that it has no

    defining characteristic, nor can we consider it, as it were, in isolation prior to or apart from suchcharacteristics -- there is "nothing there" for us to consider. It seems we must conclude that space

    does not exist.

    But surely, one might reply,space seems to exist or to have come into existence (5.6). In that

    case, Nagarjuna responds, it must have a defining characteristic. Since we have established thatthere is none, we shall be forced to conclude that space is both existing and non-existing. But

    who can hold that there is an "existing-and-non-existing thing which does not have the properties

    of an existing-and-non-existing thing?" (5.6). We must therefore conclude space is not existing,not non-existing, nor both existing and non-existing.

  • 7/29/2019 Nagarjuna, Enlightment and Time

    5/9

    Again, "space" has been found to be like "things;" it can not be considered as having own-

    being. Nothing positive whatever can be asserted of it. The grounds for this conclusion involveboth the application of an independent principle of ontology and epistemology as well as the view

    of common sense. That Nagarjuna considered this view of space crucial is indicated by the

    closing verse of the chapter: "But those unenlightened people who either affirm reality or non-

    reality do not perceive the blessed cessation-of-appearance of existing things" (5.8). Theapprehension of reality from the "blessed" (enlightened) perspective is an appeal to a higher level

    truth, a distinction not yet formally introduced in the MMK. This indicates that the logical

    arguments about space are transcended in the enlightened apprehension of reality.

    At this point we can summarize Nagarjuna's ontology in the arguments under consideration(not his entire ontology) as one in which "things," in particular sensible things, have a kind of

    primary intractability to reason. This intractability arises primarily because things are not

    analyzable in terms of own-being. While we can not say that things "are," we must acknowledgethat they nevertheless "assert" themselves or are present to us in a particular mode. Nagarjuna

    will subsequently identify this mode as "empty." Since motion is relative to things, the only

    reality we can assert of it is that it is relative. Likewise, Nagarjuna's view of space is profoundlynon-Western. It is not presented as a necessary mode of apprehension nor as something

    independent in which objects reside.

    Time

    Nagarjuna devotes chapter 19 of the MMK specifically to time. Once again, he attempts toshow that time has no self-existence. There is an important difference in his arguments here

    however, for rather than developing all four arms of the tetralemma as he so often does, he

    concentrates only on the denial of time. Without trying to make too much of this fact, I wish tocall attention to it in order to support the idea that time, like space, has a kind of special status for

    Nagarjuna, at least to the extent of requiring slightly altered forms of argumentation.

    Three arguments regarding time are presented. The first argument is a reprise of the production

    argument and relies on the common-sense view that time is split into past, present and future.Nagarjuna argues if the "parts" of time have own-being, the conception of time quickly loses its

    coherence. If "the past" is considered to produce "the present" and "the future," the latter two

    parts would be already "in" the past and could therefore not be properly said to have separate

    being. On the other hand, if the present and the future are separate from the past, then their veryunconnectedness leaves them uncaused, independent and without reference to the past. But since

    the very notions of present and future imply a relation to the past, this is self-contradictory.

    Therefore, the present and future do not exist. Neither identity with nor difference from the pastis sufficient to establish the reality of the present and future. In a similar fashion, the

    independence of any of the parts of time can be attacked on the basis of their inseparability and

    necessary reference to each other. The past, for example, can not be independent because it isnonsensical if it does not terminate in the present and future.

    Nagarjuna offers a second argument against the reality of time which does not specifically rely

    on time being "split." Rather, the objection is framed in epistemological terms:

  • 7/29/2019 Nagarjuna, Enlightment and Time

    6/9

    5. A non-stationary "time" cannot be "grasped" and a stationary "time" which can be

    grasped does not exist. How, then can one perceive time if it is not "grasped"?

    In other words, if time is acknowledged to be continuously fleeting, there are no absolute staticcomponents of it that can be experienced (or, perhaps, "grasped" by the mind). If we propose, as

    the Abhidharmic metaphysicians held, that there can be a "static moment" of time, it would no

    longer count as time. Time in and of itself can never be grasped.

    The third and final argument shows that time can not be considered to be a self-existing thing

    that is somehow not dependent on other existing objects. This is because, as Nagarjuna has

    shown, there are no independent "objects" in the world, nor could time be itself truly independent

    as long as it remained defined by its relation to such supposed entities. To place the argument inmore contemporary terms, time is not a self-existing substratum or arena in which equally

    independent things endure or independent events occur.

    It is important to note that although Nagarjuna denies the independent existence of time in thischapter, he is not, apparently, denying what we might call the unmediated experience of change.

    What he does deny is that there is any coherent way of grasping or expressing this experience in

    terms of the flow of an independent substratum to reality. It seems that Nagarjuna's view of time

    is similar to Augustine's, who remarked that he knew what time was until he was called upon tospeak of it. David Kalupahana summarizes Nagarjuna's view here nicely:

    Time denied by him is absolute time....This is a rejection not of temporal phenomena, but only

    of time and phenomena as well as their mutual dependence so long as they are perceived as

    independent entities. (Kaluphana, p. 279)

    Hence, although Nagarjuna makes no positive assertions regarding time and its relation to

    things, his view seems open to the interpretation that time and the things that change are

    essentially "one." We might phrase his view this way: phenomena are always phenomena-in-fluxand time is always flux-in-phenomena. There is not a Time and Things that persist through it, but

    only a changing of things that "is" the change over time.

    III. Eternity

    As we indicated above, all of Nagarjuna's ideas are to be understood within the framework ofthe path toward Enlightenment. Enlightenment means that one understands the equation of

    samsara and nirvana, or the emptiness of the life world. SeeSunyata

    Once we see that there are no self-existent things in the universe, we come to regard "things" as

    "empty" of self-being, relative and dependent. The very emptiness of things, in fact, is what

    http://www.angelfire.com/electronic/zennun/eternity.htmlhttp://www.angelfire.com/electronic/bodhidharma/sunyata.htmlhttp://www.angelfire.com/electronic/bodhidharma/sunyata.htmlhttp://www.angelfire.com/electronic/zennun/eternity.htmlhttp://www.angelfire.com/electronic/bodhidharma/sunyata.html
  • 7/29/2019 Nagarjuna, Enlightment and Time

    7/9

    makes things be the way they really are. Once we give up the categorization of things as being,

    not-being, both being and not-being and neither being nor not-being, we can become open to thetrue experience of the life world. Finding the emptiness of samsara becomes finding the

    emptiness of nirvana. Nirvana has no own-being. Nirvana is not a "thing" to be found

    "elsewhere." The limits of samsara and nirvana are identical; "there is nothing whatever that

    differentiates the two" (MMK 25.19 and 25.20).

    If one can see this to be true, it is perhaps not too much to ask that we can imagine that

    surpassing all categories of "thinghood," including space and time, we will be in a position to at

    least imagine that an experience without reference to them is possible. This may give us some

    clue as to the meaning of the Buddhists' reports that enlightenment allows one to experience akind of ever present eternity.

    The conceptual equation ofsamsara and nirvana, however, can not do the all of the philosophic

    work (let alone the real, practical work of the devotee) of encompassing a new apprehension oftime into Enlightenment. This must be done by an inward turn to the self -- a rooting out of all

    notions of the last and most intractable ground of own-being: the notions of the substantial selfwith an eternal soul.

    Nagarjuna closes the MMK with a final chapter reaffirming the "correctness" Buddha's silenceon the issue of the survival of the soul after death. We can start by considering that the individual

    self is either eternal or non-eternal. If the self is eternal, it implies it is identical through a time

    extending beyond the limits of birth and death. In this case there would be no past state in which I

    was different from any future state. Not only would self-development be impossible, but identitywould be continuous. The individual born in this time would have to be exactly the same as one

    born countless times before. This contradicts the common sense notion that I am a unique

    individual, living at a particular time and place. Thus, it follows that while we can not disprovereincarnation, we can not prove it on the basis of lived experience. Such concerns are hopeless

    metaphysical speculation which Nagarjuna rejects in the spirit of Buddha's original teaching.

    There is an implied psychological and metaphysical doctrine in this final concern of the MMK,

    which, along with the previous discussions of motion, space, causality, and the path of releasecan help us synthesize Nagarjuna's view of time.

    (1) Because of self-attachment, there is a strong tendency to hope that a kind of hypostatized

    Time (call it Eternity) will provide a last refuge for maintaining our self-identity. This Time will

    either provide a final home for the soul or will serve as a kind of netherland apart from the worldthat souls visit between the cycles of birth and death. Nagarjuna's denial of our knowledge of the

    self's ultimate destination not only brings us back to the present reality, but quite significantly,

    removes the two "ends" of time, the past and the future, from consideration. Hence, this featureof Nagarjuna's view anticipates the absorbing concern with the here and now that became so

    important to Zen.

    (2) Nagarjuna uses ontological principles and logic, but also attempts to return us to immediate

    experience. Truly observed, space, time and motion have no own-being. Likewise, perceptible"things" are known to be empty, participating in the empty field of phenomenal becoming. If we

    pay attention to things just as they are, we can see them no longer in space or motion or time. If

  • 7/29/2019 Nagarjuna, Enlightment and Time

    8/9

    we can separate them at all, time and the changing thing are merely two aspects of the same

    perception. Time itself is never grasped, but changing things continue. It might be stated thisway: emptiness "becomes" or empties itself in the form of thing-in-motion, thing-in-space, or

    thing-in-time.

    (3) The understanding of time is a kind of spiritual opening. It enables us to face death withequanimity. As Dogen says,

    Life is a stage of time and death is stage of time, like, for example, winter and spring. We do

    not suppose that winter becomes spring, or say that spring becomes summer. (Waddell,

    Shobogenzo Genjokoan, p.136)

    Although time stages have a before and after, they each have their own integrity. Theenlightened one accepts the integrity of all time stages, as did Hui Neng when he calmly

    explained his coming death to his disciples: "It is only natural that I should go" (Price, p. 106).

    There is a further aspect to the spiritual aspect of understanding and experiencing of time that

    Nagarjuna seems to indicate. He speaks in several spots in the MMK of the "blessed cessation ofappearances" (see discussion of space above and verse 5.8 of MMK) and the "cessation of

    conditioned elements" (25.24 and 16.4) as results of enlightenment or of entering nirvana.

    Undoubtedly, desire ceases in nirvana, but does time cease too? One is reminded of the Zenconception of "walking enlightenment" described in the Sutra of Hui Neng: "Let the essence of

    mind and all phenomenal objects be in a state of thusness. Then you will be in samadhi all the

    time" (Price, p. 80). Samadhi was traditionally conceived to be "timeless," but here it is also

    present in time. Dogen's view of the eternal present is also related. David Loy interprets theessence of Dogen's eternal present time this way: "[It] is eternal because there is indeed

    something which does not change: it is always now" (Loy, p.20).

    The relation of these conceptions time and enlightenment, which grew out of later Buddhistthought, to specific passages in Nagarjuna is admittedly speculative, but their indebtedness to the

    spirit of Nagarjuna's great masterpiece, I think, is not. In any event, I believe we can only begin

    to understand Nagarjuna through an authentic struggle to understand not only the letter but the

    spirit of his text. The displacement of the ordinary views about the life world, and perhaps moreimportantly in our times, our scientific views, is a first and most difficult step on the path of the

    Middle Way.

    IV. Conclusion

    We shall be very far from understanding Nagarjuna if attempt to understand his logical,epistemological and ontological as abstractions. Nagarjuna's aim is salvation and logic and

    arguments are merely tools. The path of enlightenment can only be cleared by the use of

    argument; it can not be traversed. If space, causality and time are barriers for the ego's release,

  • 7/29/2019 Nagarjuna, Enlightment and Time

    9/9

    Nagarjuna has attempted to provide us with means to help us remove these barriers. Perhaps the

    most difficult barrier for many will be the conviction that time moves of its own accord and thatit limits or constrains the life of the soul not only now but in the hereafter. Nagarjuna's arguments

    show us how time, like ordinary things in the life world, can be understood as "empty." Once it is

    understood as empty the burden of time is lifted from the soul; time ceases and life begins.

    *************************************************************************