More General Conditions Under Which Mean-Variance Decision Making Is Unjustified

1
Risk Analysis, Vol. 30, No. 3, 2010 DOI: 10.1111/j.1539-6924.2010.01358.x Response More General Conditions Under Which Mean-Variance Decision Making Is Unjustified Bill Huber has presented a new, simpler, and more general proof of the fact that mean-variance decision making violates the principle that a rational decisionmaker should prefer higher to lower proba- bilities of receiving a fixed gain, all else being equal. The new version holds even for preferences that can- not be represented by well-behaved (e.g., continu- ous, downward-sloping) indifference curves, showing that the result is quite fundamental. It is perhaps somewhat startling that mean-variance methods con- tinue to enjoy widespread practical application in risk management, as this practice risks failing to se- lect dominant choices unless restrictive assumptions (such as normally distributed consequences) can be justified. I thank Bill Huber for improving upon and gen- eralizing my note on the inconsistency of mean- variance preferences with the dominance principle (“first-order stochastic dominance” (FSD), in the ter- minology of the field), that rational decisionmakers should, whenever possible, choose prospects that make preferred outcomes more probable. My orig- inal note mentioned that it did not cover the case of vertical indifference curves. Bill Huber’s proof takes care of that case, and several others in which the con- venient assumptions of smooth, downward-sloping indifference curves do not hold. As Bill pointed out in private correspondence, the new proof es- tablishes the result with great generality: not only is the framework of expected utility theory dis- pensed with, but even the assumption that prefer- ences are well-defined and that prospects can be well-ordered is relaxed. Thus, the inconsistency of mean-variance decision making with FSD seems to be quite fundamental. Interestingly, this observation, which builds on several decades of theoretical research, has not prevented continuing enthusiasm for mean-variance models among theorists and practitioners, even when the special circumstances that would prevent FSD violations (such as normal distributions of conse- quences) cannot be assumed. It is an interesting empirical question to what extent practitioners who apply mean-variance risk models in different fields are led thereby to make dominated decisions. Tony Cox 329 0272-4332/10/0100-0329$22.00/1 C 2010 Society for Risk Analysis

Transcript of More General Conditions Under Which Mean-Variance Decision Making Is Unjustified

Page 1: More General Conditions Under Which Mean-Variance Decision Making Is Unjustified

Risk Analysis, Vol. 30, No. 3, 2010 DOI: 10.1111/j.1539-6924.2010.01358.x

Response

More General Conditions Under Which Mean-VarianceDecision Making Is Unjustified

Bill Huber has presented a new, simpler, andmore general proof of the fact that mean-variancedecision making violates the principle that a rationaldecisionmaker should prefer higher to lower proba-bilities of receiving a fixed gain, all else being equal.The new version holds even for preferences that can-not be represented by well-behaved (e.g., continu-ous, downward-sloping) indifference curves, showingthat the result is quite fundamental. It is perhapssomewhat startling that mean-variance methods con-tinue to enjoy widespread practical application inrisk management, as this practice risks failing to se-lect dominant choices unless restrictive assumptions(such as normally distributed consequences) can bejustified.

I thank Bill Huber for improving upon and gen-eralizing my note on the inconsistency of mean-variance preferences with the dominance principle(“first-order stochastic dominance” (FSD), in the ter-minology of the field), that rational decisionmakersshould, whenever possible, choose prospects thatmake preferred outcomes more probable. My orig-inal note mentioned that it did not cover the case ofvertical indifference curves. Bill Huber’s proof takes

care of that case, and several others in which the con-venient assumptions of smooth, downward-slopingindifference curves do not hold. As Bill pointedout in private correspondence, the new proof es-tablishes the result with great generality: not onlyis the framework of expected utility theory dis-pensed with, but even the assumption that prefer-ences are well-defined and that prospects can bewell-ordered is relaxed. Thus, the inconsistency ofmean-variance decision making with FSD seems tobe quite fundamental.

Interestingly, this observation, which builds onseveral decades of theoretical research, has notprevented continuing enthusiasm for mean-variancemodels among theorists and practitioners, even whenthe special circumstances that would prevent FSDviolations (such as normal distributions of conse-quences) cannot be assumed. It is an interestingempirical question to what extent practitioners whoapply mean-variance risk models in different fieldsare led thereby to make dominated decisions.

Tony Cox

329 0272-4332/10/0100-0329$22.00/1 C© 2010 Society for Risk Analysis