Moi_Language and Attention - English 2015

33
April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi 1 Toril Moi LANGUAGE AND ATTENTION An edited and rewritten translation of Språk og oppmerksomhet (2013) Introduction On 22 July 2011, Anders Behring Breivik detonated a bomb in Oslo which killed eight people and injured over two hundred others. Then he drove to Utøya, a small island in the lake of Tyrifjorden where the Norwegian Labor Party was having its annual youth camp. At Utøya, he killed 69 persons one by one, at extremely close range: inches, not yards. Almost all the victims at Utøya were under twenty. Some were as young as fourteen. If ordinary language philosophy teaches us anything, it is that when our sense of the meaning of words disappears, so does our sense of reality. The terrorist of Utøya turned out to have written a manifesto, mostly made up of excerpts from conservative and racist websites. For years he had been cutting and pasting, citing and recirculating other people's words. His relationship to language was profoundly alienated. So was his relationship to reality. To him, the callous killing of children was simply the "marketing operation" for his manifesto. 1 He had lost -- or maybe he never really had -- any sense of the weight of words. 1 Moi, Toril. "Markedslogikk Og Kulturkritikk: Om Breivik Og Ubehaget I Den Postmoderne Kulturen." Samtiden.3 (2012): 20-30. Print.

description

Language and Attention

Transcript of Moi_Language and Attention - English 2015

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    1

    Toril Moi

    LANGUAGE AND ATTENTION

    An edited and rewritten translation of

    Sprk og oppmerksomhet (2013)

    Introduction

    On 22 July 2011, Anders Behring Breivik detonated a bomb in Oslo which killed

    eight people and injured over two hundred others. Then he drove to Utya, a small island in

    the lake of Tyrifjorden where the Norwegian Labor Party was having its annual youth camp.

    At Utya, he killed 69 persons one by one, at extremely close range: inches, not yards.

    Almost all the victims at Utya were under twenty. Some were as young as fourteen.

    If ordinary language philosophy teaches us anything, it is that when our sense of the

    meaning of words disappears, so does our sense of reality. The terrorist of Utya turned out

    to have written a manifesto, mostly made up of excerpts from conservative and racist

    websites. For years he had been cutting and pasting, citing and recirculating other people's

    words. His relationship to language was profoundly alienated. So was his relationship to

    reality. To him, the callous killing of children was simply the "marketing operation" for his

    manifesto.1 He had lost -- or maybe he never really had -- any sense of the weight of words.

    1 Moi, Toril. "Markedslogikk Og Kulturkritikk: Om Breivik Og Ubehaget I Den

    Postmoderne Kulturen." Samtiden.3 (2012): 20-30. Print.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    2

    In Norway, Anders Johansen, a professor of non-fiction at the University of Bergen,

    wrote that the terror at Utya changed our relationship to language: Serious attempts to

    make words conform to reality are no longer immediately dismissed as nave. To many of us

    it has been crucial to find ways to say something true about what happened, in a language

    that is accurate both to facts and emotions.2

    After reading this, I realized that it was not by coincidence that I began to write about

    language and attention in May and June 2012, at the same time as I attended parts of the 22

    July trial at Oslo District Court.3 The trial made me realize that questions of language and

    attention are not esoteric topics. On the contrary: if we want a good society, one devoted to

    justice for all, we should encourage every citizen to develop the capacity to look at reality,

    other people, themselves, with the kind of attention the British philosopher Iris Murdoch calls

    a just and loving gaze.4

    Wittgenstein tells us to despise the craving for generality and instead cultivate the

    keenest attention for particulars. He also reminds us that we often fail to see the most obvious

    and ordinary things, precisely because they are obvious and ordinary. We need to learn to see

    the ordinary and the everyday afresh, learn to pay attention to the obvious. We also need to

    develop our capacity to face the difficulty of reality, focus on the things we prefer to avoid,

    2 Alvorlige forsk p bringe ord i samsvar med virkelighet blir ikke uten videre

    avfeid som naive lenger. For mange har det vrt maktpliggende kunne si noe sant om det som skjedde, i et sprk som kan vre dekkende bde saklig og emosjonelt. Anders Johansen, Virkelighetssjokk, Prosa nr. 5, 2012: 18.

    3 I would like to thank Trygve slund, who invited me to give a talk at Aschehougs Summer Seminar in June 2012. Without his invitation the original essay this chapter is based on would never have been written. But without Nora Campbells enthusiasm for the project, I would never have considered turning the talk into a proper manuscript. Nora is an excellent editor: her comments were always both challenging and inspiring. Nazneen Khan strem helped to convince me that this ought to become a text in the Voices-series. Ane Farseths deserves special gratitude, for she heroically agreed to read and comment on the original lecture draft on one hours notice.

    4 Ref. to David L. Paletz and Toril Moi op-ed in the New York Times. 2012.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    3

    the things we really dont feel we have the energy truly to take in. (The "difficulty of reality"

    is Cora Diamond's expression. I shall return to it.)

    This is not a "theory." One doesn't need to study Wittgenstein to do these things. For

    me, however, Wittgenstein, Cavell and Austin remain necessary. Because I am an intellectual

    and an academic, and because I care about the life of the mind in the university, the

    wonderful, liberating, freeing thing about Wittgenstein and Austin and Cavell too, is that

    they offer an intellctually convincing way back to the ordinary. I have no wish to break with

    academic inquiry, or turn into an anti-intellectual. On the contrary, I want intellectual life to

    engage with ordinary life, with human experience, in a language that can tell the difference

    between confused abstraction and genuine insight. Ordinary language philosophy sets us free

    to look at whatever we are interested in: Ordinary language philosophy is about whatever

    ordinary language is about, Cavell writes.5 That freedom is fantastic, but with freedom, as

    Sartre and Beauvoir always said, comes responsibility. To write about what we are interested

    in is to reveal what we take ourselves to be responsible for.

    This chapter is about the importance of attention, and of language. In this chapter I

    examine a moral attitude that we can call attention, or, more precisely, a just and loving

    gaze. This attitude is personal, existential, ethical, and potentially (but by no means always)

    political. It can be an intellectual or artistic practice, too. I draw on Iris Murdoch (who draws

    on Simone Weil), and Cora Diamond, but unlike them, I emphasize the need to find a

    language to express what the just and loving gaze sees.

    For attention alone is not enough. It is also crucial to learn to express what we see,

    learn to find the words (or the artistic forms) with which to show what the world looks like

    from the position we find ourselves in. This is why literature matters. Writers spend their

    lives trying to find the right words. They can teach us differences. If we learn to pay

    5 Cavell, Aesthetic Problems, p. 95.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    4

    attention, and to express ourselves as well and fully as we can, then we will also increase our

    faith in language, and help overcome the widespread skepticism against languages capacity

    to express something real. By training our attention, and our capacity to use language

    attentively, well gain a deeper understanding of our real need (108).

    If we imagine a utopian world in which we all looked at reality with a just and loving

    gaze, we wouldnt all see the same things in the same way. Social and political debates would

    be at least as pointed as they are now. But per definition, the just and loving gaze cant just be

    interested in its own vision. We must assume a willingness to direct that gaze, that attention

    to what other people say they see. If we spent more time trying to understand why they can't

    see exactly what we see, maybe we would become less quick to dismiss those who disagree

    with us, and thus a little better at acknowledging the point of view of others. If nothing else,

    such habits would surely improve the quality of political and ethical discussions.

    By language I certainly dont mean what is usually called literary language. (I

    seriously doubt that such a thing exists.) When Henry James had to explain what it takes to

    become a good writer, he didnt say that writers should work hard to develop a specifically

    literary language, but that they should try to notice everything: Try to be one of the people

    on whom nothing is lost.6 Literature teaches us how to unite attention and language. The

    best literary writing forces us to open our eyes, to see both language and reality as crucially

    important, as something we need to engage with, take in and think through. The best literary

    writing expresses an unusual capacity for attention, and as a result it inspires others to

    become more attentive. And while it is true that writers specialize in linguistic labor, one

    doesnt have to be a writer to use language with maximal attention. Some people manage to

    do it in everyday life, or in court.

    6 Henry James, The Art of Fiction, Longmans Magazine 4 (oktober 1884): 510.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    5

    The opposite of attentive language is language used to conceal reality. Unfortunately

    bureaucrats and academics are among the worst culprits. They often express themselves in

    ways that land us in a quagmire of words that dont mean anything, words that only serve one

    purpose: to make us acquiesce in ideas, actions and projects we dont actually understand.

    This is dangerous for intellectual life, and even more dangerous for democracy.7

    An Attentive Gaze is a Just and Loving Gaze

    By attention I don't mean the vigilance of evil. I just said that I thought an attentive

    gaze has to be a just and loving gaze. I hesitated for a long time before I decided to adopt

    Iris Murdochs formulation. It is, after all, only too easy to take just and loving to mean

    sentimental and moralizing. And the last thing I want is to imply that I am in favor of a

    judgmental and saccharine gaze.

    Attention comes from the Latin ad + tendere: to reach or stretch towards

    something. Both in English and French the word gathers a whole cluster of meanings around

    itself: to direct the mind or observant faculties, to listen, apply oneself; to watch over,

    minister to, wait upon, follow, frequent; to wait for, await, expect. The idea of caring for, or

    serving others here converges on the idea of listening, waiting, and watching.

    Two women, one French and one British, have turned attention into a fascinating

    philosophical concept. The first was the philosopher and mystic Simone Weil (190943),

    who studied philosophy at the Sorbonne at the same time as Simone de Beauvoir. The second

    was Iris Murdoch (1919-99). For Weil, to be attentif is to be waiting, watchful, open to what

    may arise: Above all our thought should be empty, waiting, not seeking anything, but ready

    7 I think of The unknown known, Errol Morriss film on Donald Rumsfeld, 2014, as a

    great example of this.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    6

    to receive in its naked truth the object that is to penetrate it, Weil writes.8 To be attentive is

    to be disponible pour la vrit: to be open, ready, available for the truth.9

    For Weil the ultimate truth is God: prayer consists of attention.10 But one doesnt

    have to be a mystic to follow Weil; an interest in earthly truth will suffice. Weil herself, in

    fact, analyzes the value of attention through a discussion of schoolwork. Any training of

    attention is an unqualified good, she claims, because it trains the mind to open itself to the

    truth. Even the most banal school studies, such as math problems or translation to or from a

    foreign language provide valuable training in attention. The right sort of attention, however,

    only arises if we manage to find joy and pleasure in the work: The joy of learning is as

    indispensable in study as breathing is in running, she writes.11

    Attention, then, is not the same thing as willed concentration. The student isnt

    supposed to focus on her schoolwork because she wants to achieve the best possible grades,

    but simply because it is valuable to learn to carry out any task with clear attention. We must

    also train ourselves into looking at our own mistakes the bad essay, the math exam we

    failed with unbiased attention. The result of the training will show itself when we least

    expect it, Weil assures us: Never in any case whatever is a genuine effort of the attention

    wasted.12

    8 Reflections on the Right Use of School Studies with a View to the Love of God,

    in Waiting for God, trans. Emma Crawfurd (New York: Harper Colophon, 1973), p. 112. Et surtout la pense doit tre vide, en attente, ne rien chercher, mais tre prte recevoir dans sa vrit nue lobjet qui va y pntrer. Simone Weil, Rflexion sur le bon usage des tudes scolaires en vue de lamour de Dieu, i crits de Marseille (194042): Philosophie, science, religion, questions politiques et sociales, redigert av Florence de Lussy, uvres compltes (Paris: Gallimard, 2008), 260.

    9 School Studies, 112; tudes scolaires, 260. 10 School Studies, 105; La prire est faite dattention, tudes scolaires, 255. 11 School Studies, 110; La joie dapprendre est aussi indispensable aux tudes que

    la respiration aux coureurs. tudes scolaires, 259. 12 School Studies, 106; Jamais, en aucun cas, aucun effort dattention vritable

    nest perdu. tudes scolaires, 256.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    7

    When Weil discusses attention and school studies, she probably imagines a studious

    youth bent over translations to and from Latin and Greek in France around 1940. For us, who

    live in an era of distraction, it is harder than ever to develop the capacity for attention. We are

    pulled in every direction by multitasking and incessant electronic interruptions. Simone Weil

    would probably have been quite horrified at students or professors for that matter who

    listen to music, surfs the web and replies to text messages while they are trying to finish a

    philosophical essay, a translation or a math problem.

    For Weil attention is neutral, waiting and open. It rests on joy, a pleasurable wish to

    see the truth. Attention is neither striving nor self-promoting. It tries to understand, not

    destroy. Iris Murdoch stresses these aspects of Weils concept by saying that attention

    express[es] the idea of a just and loving gaze directed upon an individual reality.13

    Murdoch takes the idea that focused attention has to be both loving and just from Weil, who

    writes: Not only does the love of God have attention for its substance; the love of our

    neighbor, which we know to be the same love, is made of this same substance.14 Warmth

    and compassion are not at all synonymous with attention: too much sympathy can blind us to

    reality. To manage to see another human being with the openness of genuine attention, is

    truly difficult: it is almost a miracle; it is a miracle, Weil writes.15

    Weil writes about attention because she wants to pray. Murdoch, on the other hand,

    wants to turn us into active moral agent[s], persons capable of having a genuinely moral

    relationship to reality and to act accordingly.16 Murdochs understanding of attention is far

    more action-oriented than Weils.

    13 Iris Murdoch, The Sovereignty of Good (London: Routledge, 2001), 33. 14 Weil, School Studies, 114. Ce nest pas seulement lamour de Dieu qui a pour

    substance lattention. Lamour du prochain, dont nous savons que cest le mme amour, est fait de la mme substance. Weil, tudes scolaires, 261262.

    15 School studies, 114; cest presque un miracle; cest un miracle. tudes scolaires, 262.

    16 Murdoch, Sovereignty, 33.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    8

    But is just and loving the right expression? Murdoch stresses repeatedly that she

    wants nothing to do with sentimentality and misplaced compassion. So does Weil. A just and

    loving gaze enables us to see the world as it is. It is the best strategy we have when we want

    to discover the truth about a person or a situation. We will never understand whatever it is we

    are looking at if we dont do our utmost to see the situation from the other persons point of

    view, yet without relinquishing our own perspective. A just and loving gaze tries to explain

    everything in the kindest way, but in the end, it does not shy away from criticism. A just gaze

    doesnt accept just any excuse. It is willing to judge, yet never becomes judgmental. If we

    really want to become active moral agents, there is no better alternative than Murdochs

    (and Weils) recommendation that we look at the world with a combination of justice and

    love.

    Murdoch does not write about politics. But a just and loving gaze is needed in politics

    too, perhaps more than anywhere else. The boundary between morality and politics is not

    absolute. It is both politically and morally urgent, for example, to find the right relationship

    to the Other, to groups or individuals who have been defined as different or deviant. In

    the 1920s and 30s, Simone Weil directed her attention towards the French working class. In

    spite of her bad health, she worked in a factory before leaving for Barcelona to fight in the

    Spanish Civil War: Her attention was as political as it was religious.

    In the 1970s, the womens movement set out to train womens attention, to develop

    womens capacity to see the ordinary and the everyday afresh. This is not to say that the

    feminist gaze of the 1970s was always just and loving. Sometimes it was angry, defiant, and

    deeply unjust. But the right response to a defiant or rebellious gaze is not to dismiss it, or to

    react with hatred and anger, but to pay attention to the reality it tries to convey. The task is to

    try to understand both why the anger arises, what it responds to, and what it is trying to

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    9

    achieve. At the same time we must acknowledge where the defiant or angry gaze grates

    against the reality it is trying to grasp.

    A just and loving gaze is open and waiting in relation to reality, but it is not passive.

    To be attentive is to let reality reverberate in us. Attention answers, responds and takes

    responsibility.17

    The Value of Attention: Cora Diamond

    Cora Diamond has long been interested in attention: attention to particulars, attention

    to and in literature; and attention in the sense of Murdoch's just and loving gaze. For her, as

    for Weil and Murdoch, moral reflection is a specific kind of attention, a particular response to

    the world, a way of seeing things (the world, other people, oneself).

    For Diamond, moral philosophy -- moral thought -- has to focus on the particular

    case, on the individual, the specific and the unique. She disagrees with the widespread idea

    that moral reflection is always expressed through deliberation on clear-cut choices, or in

    explicit evaluations: right, wrong, evil, good. Like Iris Murdoch, she thinks there are "moral

    attitudes which emphasise the inexhaustible detail of the world, the endlessness of the task of

    understanding."18 Deep insights can arise unexpected places, not least in literature. To show

    what she means by attention, Diamond quotes the last stanza of "Ducks," a children's poem

    by Walter de la Mare. Having described many different kinds of ducks, the poet concludes:

    All these are kinds. But every Duck

    Himself is, and himself alone:

    Fleet wing, arched neck, webbed foot, round eye,

    17 I couldnt have written this without reading Cavell on acknowledgment as response.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    10

    And marvellous cage of bone.

    Clad in this beauty a creature dwells,

    Of sovran instinct, sense and skill;

    Yet secret as the hidden wells

    Whence Life itself doth rill.19

    In this text, a perfectly ordinary duck is transformed into a creature of beauty and

    dignity, deserving of respect and admiration. Diamond wants us to see that there is something

    morally important about the quality of his attention. Lets call this an example of a just and

    loving gaze.

    Traditional moral philosophy, Diamond writes, takes a far too narrow view of what

    counts as relevant insights and thoughts about morality. It takes for granted that moral

    philosophy is only a matter of deciding what the right action is in situations where we have to

    make a difficult choice. The famous trolley problem is the quintessential example of this

    attitude. Here is one example from among the multitudes of different versions: A runaway

    railway trolley comes down the railway line. If nothing is done, it will kill five workers

    further down the track. I am standing on a bridge over the track, next to a very fat man.

    Should I push this stranger down on the line in order to save the five workers? Versions of

    the trolley problem has been used to get clear on everything from the influence of insomnia

    on our capacity for moral deliberation, through gender differences in the moral domain, to

    where to draw the limits between different moral doctrines.20

    18 Iris Murdoch, Symposium: Vision and Choice in Morality, Proceedings of the

    Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 30 (1956): 46. 19 Walter de la Mare, Ducks, i The Complete Poems of Walter de la Mare (London:

    Faber, 1969), 817. 20 Iversen, Jokaim ien, Betydningen av n natts svn for moralske valg. .

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    11

    Diamond thinks the trolley problem is truly useless (my interpretation, not her words)

    when it comes to explaining the kind of moral reasoning we actually engage in in everyday

    life. First, it is overly focused on dramatic choices. Second, it divorces the question of moral

    action from the question of how we see the world. Thus it turns morality into something that

    is placed on top of already existing knowledge.

    More generally, Diamond objects to the idea that epistemology and metaphysics

    provide the framework for what we can say about reality, and then, once that framework is in

    place, moral philosophy can tell us what is to count as good or evil, right or wrong. In this

    way morality is reduced to the question of how to label people and their actions, and divorced

    from questions concerning truth and insight (for those questions are taken to be settled before

    the moral reflection can begin.)

    Such a view is perfectly compatible with naturalistic and scientistic world views, but

    not with ordinary language philosophy. In a naturalistic world view, moral reflection may be

    an interesting pastime, unconnected to actual knowledge. Such attitudes also think of

    language as an overlay, as something external to truth, something additional, without intrinsic

    moral relevance. Ordinary language philosophy is sharply opposed to this view. Words and

    world are intertwined, and it is impossible to use language without simultaneously expressing

    a human subjectivity: as soon as we speak, we also make judgments, show others what we

    see.

    Diamond reminds us that in reality moral action only rarely take the form of a clear

    choice, in which we can make lists of arguments for and against. In real life, we often feel

    that we have no choice. Or we discover that we already have done something with huge

    moral implications, without really thinking about it. Sometimes we make long lists of

    arguments, consider them carefully, and decide what to do. Then we go out and do the

    opposite. Or we dont actually do anything. In such situations, the trolley problem is no help.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    12

    At the beginning of Iris Murdochs novel The Bell (1958), Dora Greenfield takes the

    train on a hot summers day. The train, of the kind with a long corridor running along the side

    of the compartments, is hot and overcrowded. As Dora squeezes into her middle seat in her

    compartment, she feels sweaty and fat, for her skirt is tight and she is only too aware that she

    has put on weight. An old lady struggles through the crowded corridor and reaches Doras

    compartment, delighted finally to have found Doras neighbor, a rather large old lady. Dora

    stopped listening because a dreadful thought has struck her. She ought to give up her seat.

    She rejected the thought, but it came back.21

    Dora spends over a page thinking about her new moral dilemma. Should she give up

    her seat? Couldnt the elderly lady just as well stand in the corridor herself? But she looks

    rather frail, and the corridor is really crowded. Nobody else in the compartment look as if

    they are even thinking of getting up. But Dora took the trouble to get to the train early. She

    deserves her seat. Doesnt the elderly lady deserve to stand in the corridor? In any case, Dora

    was tired. She certainly deserved to rest:

    She regarded her state of distress as completely neurotic. She decided not to

    give up her seat.

    She got up and said to the standing lady Do sit down here, please. Im

    not going very far, and Id much rather stand anyway.22

    It turns out that the elderly lady already has a corner seat by the window in a different

    carriage, and that she is only too pleased to change seats with Dora. Everyone in this

    carriage was thinner, Dora thinks as she settles into her comfortable corner.23

    21 Iris Murdoch, The Bell (New York: Penguin, 1987), 910. 22 Mudoch, The Bell, p. 10. 23 Mudoch, The Bell, p. 11.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    13

    The scene is comic: we smile at the contrast between Doras smug deliberations and

    her spontaneous leap out of her seat. But there is an edge to the comedy. The scene tells us

    that the relationship between moral reflection and action is more complicated than we think.

    Dora is by no means a saint. Her reflections arent particularly subtle. She has a tendency to

    be selfish, and she loves feeling physically comfortable. She is also a little too pleased to be

    rewarded with a better seat. (Murdoch herself considered thoughts of rewards to be alien to

    moral deliberations.24) Dora clearly has a fairly shaky understanding of why she does

    whatever she does. This turns out to be the case for her train journey too. Without really

    understanding why, she is on her way to be reunited with her husband, a man she fears.

    However, Dora still has the right attitude. While the other passengers bury themselves in their

    newspapers or determinedly stare out of the window, Dora is attentive. She takes in the

    situation. She gets up. Murdochs attitude towards Dora is humorous, but loving and just, too.

    The Difficulty of Reality

    To devote ones full attention to a phenomenon or a person, and to find a language in

    which to express what we see, is difficult. Even when we do our best, others may never

    understand us. Sometimes we are overcome by our own inadequacy: we simply cant find the

    words.

    Cora Diamond writes about the difficulty of reality. She defines it as something we

    arent capable of thinking about, maybe because it is too painful, maybe because it is

    inexplicably good:

    24 In the case of morality, although there are sometimes rewards, the idea of a reward

    is out of place. Murdoch, Sovereignty, 65.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    14

    The difficulty of reality []. That is a phrase [for] experiences in which we

    take something in reality to be resistant to our thinking it, or possibly to be

    painful in its inexplicability, difficult in that way, or perhaps awesome and

    astonishing in its inexplicability. We take things so. And the things we take so

    may simply not, to others, present the kind of difficulty, of being hard or

    impossible or agonizing to get ones mind round. 25

    Diamond is clearly not just talking about traumas. And even when she does discuss

    traumatic experiences, she does not share the post-Saussurean conviction that traumas

    necessarily fall outside language. To her, the difficulty of reality is something that has to do

    with the way we take it, or in other words: our response. When wecant find words, the

    problem is not language, it is us.

    Finding the words to express goodness is not necessarily easier than finding the words

    to express evil. Diamonds example of the way in which goodness can be experienced as the

    difficulty of reality is thought-provoking. Ruth Klger was sent to Auschwitz when she

    was thirteen.26 During the initial triage, the SS-officers female assistant, herself a prisoner in

    the extermination camp, walked up to Ruth and asked how old she was. Thirteen, she replied.

    Tell him you are fifteen, the woman said. When the SS-officer asked about her age, Ruth said

    fifteen. The officer thought she was small. The assistant pointed out that she seemed strong.

    Thats how she became registered as a prisoner in the camp, and thus got a small chance to

    survive. Klger writes:

    I have always told this story in wonder, and people wonder at my wonder.

    They say, okay, some persons are altruistic. We understand that; it doesnt

    surprise us. The girl who helped you was one of those who likes to help. []

    25 Cora Diamond, The Difficulty of Reality and the Difficulty of Philosophy, i

    Stanley Cavell, Cora Diamond, John McDowell, Ian Hacking og Cary Wolfe, Philosophy and Animal Life (New York: Columbia University Press, 2008), 4445.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    15

    But dont just look at the scene. Focus on it, zero in on it, and consider what

    happened. [] Her decision broke the chain of knowable causes. [] She saw

    me stand in line, a kid sentenced to death, she approached me, she defended

    me, and she got me through. What more do you need for an example of perfect

    goodness? [] Listen to me, dont take it apart, absorb it as I am telling it and

    remember it.27

    Klger experiences this moment as an incomprehensible miracle, something she

    simply cant understand with ordinary logical criteria. After the war, she encounters people

    who dont think there is anything special at all in her experience. Their attitude eradicates

    Klgers own deep and lasting sense of wonder. Diamond makes us see that there is

    something morally defective about such an attitude. If we are to meet Ruth Klger with a

    just and loving gaze, we have to be able to see what she sees, to take in the permanent state

    of amazement and wonder in which Ruth Klger lives.

    The Realism of Attention: Little Eyolf

    Ruth Klgers case shows that the right kind of attention isnt simply a cool, clinical

    noting down of features of reality. It takes imagination and empathy to be able truly to get

    inside the experiences of the other. I think this is what Simone de Beauvoir has in mind

    when she speaks of being absorbed by a novel, to the point of feeling the taste of another

    life.28 At the same time, however, we need to avoid what Murdoch calls fantasy.

    According to Murdoch we engage in fantasy when we project our own proliferation of

    26 I am expanding on Diamonds example, which she discusses in The Difficulty of

    Reality, 6162. 27 Ruth Klger, Still Alive: A Holocaust Girlhood Remembered (New York: The

    Feminist Press at CUNY, 2001), 108109. 28 See The adventure of Reading, ch. 5 here for the quote.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    16

    blinding self-centred aims and images on to reality.29 The just and loving gaze requires

    detachment, a kind of impersonality: The freedom which is a proper human goal is the

    freedom from fantasy, that is the realism of compassion.30 Misplaced sentimentality has

    neither moral nor artistic value.

    Both Murdoch and Diamond use the word realism about the capacity for attentive

    moral response: in the elaboration and application of moral concepts, we come to an

    understanding of what the world is, what life is, Diamond writes.31 For Murdoch, realism is

    a moral achievement, a liberation of the self, the result of an unusual capacity for unselfish

    attention. Moral philosophy therefore has to be a kind of realism. But this realism is almost

    impossible to achieve: How is one to connect the realism which must involve a clear-eyed

    contemplation of the misery and evil of the world with a sense of the uncorrupted good

    without the latter idea becoming the merest consolatory dream? 32

    I am not quite sure what Murdoch means by uncorrupted good. If she means

    something like a Platonic ideal, I cant follow her. Let me translate her idea into a more

    ordinary register: We must develop and preserve a sense of goodness as an ordinary,

    everyday phenomenon, something that doesnt have to be either extraordinary or saintly. To

    be a morally responsive human being is to look at reality with a just and loving gaze. This

    gaze, if we can develop it, makes it possible to try to do the right thing in relation to others.

    (That any action can fail, or have unanticipated consequence is part of the grammar of the

    word: thats just what an action is.)

    29 Murdoch, Sovereignty, 65. 30 Murdoch, Sovereignty, 65. 31 Diamond, Murdoch the Explorer, Philosophical Topics 38, no. 1 (2010): 57We

    have already discussed Diamonds realistic spirit.see chapter 2. 32 Murdoch, Sovereignty, 59.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    17

    To learn to love is to learn to see. Ibsens late play Little Eyolf (1894) provides an

    excellent example.33 Ibsens critics have often complained that this play is difficult to

    understand. They have been particularly concerned with what they take to be the plays

    inferior structure. According to them, it is a problem that the plays dramatic event the

    death by drowning of Rita and Alfred Allmers ten year old son, Eyolf happens already at

    the end of the first act. Eyolf drowns because he follows a strange ratwife into the fjord.

    Critics who think this is the high point of dramatic action of the play, can't figure out what

    Ibsen wanted to do in the remaining two acts.

    The play ends with a scene in which Rita and Allmers hoist the flag, after they have

    decided to do something for the poor boys who live down by the fjordside, the same boys

    who often poked fun at Eyolf, who was lame in one leg.34 Many critics have found this end

    unbearably sentimental and melodramatic.

    If we take Weil, Murdoch, and Diamond seriously, its not that difficult to understand

    what Ibsen is interested in in Little Eyolf. The play is about two ordinary, well-intentioned

    human beings who refuse to look attentively at themselves, other people or the world. When

    their son dies, suffering enters Allmerss and Ritas lives. The last two acts show how that

    suffering, the awareness of human finitude -- changes the protagonists, how it slowly makes

    them realize that they cant continue to live in their egocentric cocoon. At the end of the play,

    Rita wants to develop Something that could ressemble a kind of love in relation to other

    people.35 But that requires her to shed her illusions and learn to look at themselves, and

    others, with a realistic a just and loving gaze.

    33 This section draws on my essay on Little Eyolf, published in Chris Gray and Susan

    Wolfs collection ADD REF. 34 I follow Ibsens habit of referring to male principal characters with their last names. 35 Noget, som kunde ligne en slags krlighed .Henrik Ibsen, Hundrersutgave:

    Henrik Ibsens samlede verker, ed. Francis Bull, Halvdan Koht, and Didrik Arup Seip, 21 vols. (Oslo: Gyldendal, 1928-57), bind 12: 266.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    18

    If we read the play in this way, the structure isn't mysterious at all. In the first act

    Ibsens genius shows us Ritas and Allmerss egoism and blindness. Then the worst happens.

    In the second act we witness the emergence of the protagonists increasing self-insight, which

    culminates in the wish to care for others, in the third act.

    In the end, Rita and Allmers decide to do something for the poor children down by the

    fjordside, the children whose screams we hear, but whom we never get to see on stage. It is

    quite possible that they wont be able actually to carry out their project. But as they stand

    there hoisting the flag in the last scene, they want to try. To them, the thought of working for

    the children of others is an attempt to free themselves from illusions and try to see reality as it

    is. Ibsens own gaze at these characters is neither sentimental nor judgmental. At the end of

    the play, they are neither heroes nor villains, but two ordinary people who have to live in a

    world they now know to be as fallen and imperfect as they are.

    Even the structure of Ibsens play brings out the connection between realism and love.

    For Little Eyolf is structured as a double movement away from selfishness and towards love,

    away from fantasy and towards reality. The controversial end emphasizes Ritas and

    Allmerss attempt to go on living without closing their eyes to suffering. Metatheatrically,

    the play struggles to develop a just and loving gaze on its own imperfect characters. But

    the play is not just a narrative of their attempts. The very form of the play, the form that

    annoyed so many critics, represents an enormous effort to escape from traditional forms of

    theater (tragedy, comedy, melodram) and reach a new form of realism, a realism capable of

    showing the right kind of compassion.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    19

    I Am Learning to See: Rilke and the Attention of Modernism

    The Notebooks of Malte Laurids Brigge (1910) are as different from Little Eyolf as it

    is possible to be. Yet Rilke too is interested in the way egoism blocks the possibility of an

    attentive gaze. The Notebooks of Malte Laurids Brigge is a fiery defense of the modernist

    understanding of writing. In order to grasp what is real, important, and necessary in an

    alienated and alienating world, one must write. Through his writing, Malte questions

    absolutely everything he has been told by others, everything he has learned and heard.

    Writing is a counter-strategy to deception and inauthenticity. To write is to convey something

    genuine, something true. A true writer needs to be able to see, to experience the world for

    himself:

    I am learning to see. Why, I cannot say, but all things enter more deeply into

    me; nor do impressions remain at the level where they used to cease. There is

    a place within me of which I knew nothing. Now all things tend that way. I do

    not know what happens there.36

    This is fascinating passage sets up the Notebooks investigations of the relationship

    between the inner and the outer. By inner I mean the inner life, what Wittgenstein

    sometimes calls the soul. By outer, I mean whatever surrounds the writer. Rilke brings

    out the paradoxical nature of writing. Writing is expression, in the most literal sense of the

    word, for it turns the inner into something outer. At the same time, however, the writer

    doesnt have a soul, an inner life, until he learns to see.

    36 Rilke, Notebooks, Penguin Classics, p. 4. Ich lerne sehen. Ich wei nicht, woran es

    liegt, es geht alles tiefer in mich ein und bleibt nicht an der Stelle stehen, wo es sonst immer zu Ende war. Ich habe ein Inneres, von dem ich nicht wute. Alles geht jetzt dorthin. Ich wei nicht, was dort geschieht. Rainer Maria Rilke, Die Aufzechnungen des Malte Laurids Brigge, vol. 5, Gesammelte Werke (Leipzig: Insel Verlag, 1927), 9.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    20

    The implication is that if we dont see anything, if we dont pay attention to the

    outside, we have no inner life. Or rather: paying attention to the outer produces an inner

    space we ourselves dont understand. If we dont turn our attention to the world around us,

    we will either remain empty, or become utterly predictable, because utterly without an

    unknown inner space. When Malte learns to see, he becomes a mystery to himself, but this is

    an enrichment, the very condition of writing.

    For Malte, the more he learns to see, the more he ends up feeling unknown,

    unknowable by others. After all, he himself doesnt understand what goes on in his new,

    secret interior space. There is an incipient skepticism at work here, a skepticism which

    necessarily leads to thoughts of loneliness, madness and death. But the alternative, which is

    not to open ones eyes, is worse, for that leads to inner emptiness, to the death of the soul.

    In a brief passage, Malte describes his parents strained relationship to the local

    parson, Dr. Jespersen:

    When he visited us, Dr. Jespersen had to content himself with being some sort

    of private person; but that was precisely what he had never been. As long as

    he could remember, he had been in the souls department. The soul was a

    public institution, which he represented, and he contrived never to be off duty,

    not in even in his relations with his wife, his modest, faithful Rebekka,

    beatified by the bearing of children, as Lavater put it when writing of another

    case.37

    The passage reveals that Jespersens problem is that something that should be inner

    the soul somehow has become something outer. This externalized innerness is clearly

    37 Penguin edition p. 71.Dr. Jespersen mute sich bei uns darauf beschrnken, eine

    Art von Privatmann zu sein; das gerade aber war er nie gewesen. Er war, soweit er denken konnte, im Seelenfach angestellt. Die Seele war eine ffentliche Institution fr ihn, die er vertrat, und er brachte es zuwege, niemals auer Dienst zu sein, selbst nicht im Umgang mit

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    21

    neither a mask nor a costume, nor is it a deliberate performance. Rilke describes it as a

    department, an institution, a clunky and impractical administrative unit which Jespersen

    either doesnt want to or doesnt know how to break loose from. As a result, Jespersen has

    become impossible to relate to for anyone who doesnt piously submit to his ecclesiastical

    authority. He simply no longer knows how to behave like an ordinary human being (a

    private person). No wonder, then, that young Maltes parents find Jespersen the most boring

    guest imaginable: To be candid, there was nothing whatsoever to talk about; remnants were

    dragged out and disposed of at unbeliveable prices everything had to go.38 Without an

    inner life, language and expression becomes impossible. But to get an inner life, we need to

    learn to see.

    For Rilke, Jespersens state is a serious matter. If authenticity requires the outer to

    correspond to the inner, then Jespersen can neither be authentic or inauthentic. Since

    Jespersen is the outer shell he shows the world, the distinction becomes meaningless. For this

    reason, we cant call him a hypocrite, either. In a way, Jespersen is a postmodern subject a

    hundred years ahead of time: he is his priestly performance. No concept of falsity or

    inauthenticity can apply to him, yet paradoxically, this is precisely what makes him seem so

    hopelessly inauthentic.

    The difference between the young Malte and Jespersen is that Malte tries to see, to

    take in the world, whereas Jespersen has become a bureaucrat of the soul: his role as the

    representative for an organization has made it impossible for him to be an individual, a

    private person, a self. The irony is that this bureaucrat works precisely in the soul-business.

    I dont think Rilke thought of himself as a writer particularly concerned with moral

    issues. To convey what a shallow and self-obsessed person is like, Rilke simply shows us

    seiner Frau, seiner bescheidenen, treuen, durch Kindergebren seligwerdenden Rebekka, wie Lavater sich in einem anderen Fall ausdrckte. Rilke, Aufzeichnungen, 5, 132.

    38 Rilke, pp. 70-71.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    22

    how he talks, without sticking moral labels on any specific point, but also without shrinking

    from judgment. Yet his insistence that we must learn to see has obvious moral (or political)

    implications. Rilkes style, his way of presenting his material, his utterly original engagement

    with the relationship or non-relationship between the inner and the outer challenges his

    readers: can we see what he sees?

    Virginia Woolf and Reality

    Rereading A Room of Ones Own, I realize that Virginia Woolfs project actually is to

    unite language and attention. (If that is true, then this chapter is also a homage to Woolfs

    wonderful essay on women and literature.) The message is that women must write, not just

    for their own sake, but for the sake of the world: When I ask you to write more books I am

    urging you to do what will be for your good and for the good of the world at large. How to

    justify this instinct or belief I do not know, for philosophic words, if one has not been

    educated at a university are apt to play one false.39 But of course she goes on to justify her

    instinct anyway.

    In ordinary life, we only catch fleeting glimpses of reality. Usually we are far too

    filled with superficial and selfish thoughts to realize what actually is there, around us. A

    writer is privileged to live more than other people in the presence of this reality. It is his

    business to find it and collect it and communicate it to the rest of us (Room, 108). (I find

    Woolf a touch too Romantic here, just a shade too convinced that writers always have god-

    given powers of insight, but I cant let that deter me. At least I agree that writers are

    specialists in language and attention.) In modernity, a human being risks living her whole life

    in a kind of unreality, unless she learns to see. To read texts like King Lear, Emma, or In

    39 Virginia Woolf, A Room of Ones Own (New York: Harcourt, 2005), 108.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    23

    Search of Lost Time opens our senses: one sees more intensely afterwards; the world seems

    bared of its covering and given an intenser life (Room, 109).

    Reading matters as much as writing. (Few writers have read as much as Virginia

    Woolf, I think.) Reading texts that genuinely grasp reality, we learn to pay attention. Even if

    we cant find the words to express our experiences, we can focus our attention on them.

    According to Woolf, the reward for our attention, and for our struggle to express its insight, is

    a stronger and more vital experience of life itself.

    For Woolf, attention is disinterested and impersonal. Self-consciousness is destructive

    for any writer, but particularly for women: It is fatal for any one who writes to think of their

    sex, she declares (Room, 102103). Dont dream of influencing other people. [] Think of

    things in themselves (Room, 109). If it is crucial for women to enter literature, to become

    part of our literary tradition, it isnt because they womens only literary task is supposed to be

    that of shedding light on an otherwise neglected subspecies of the human (so that the woman

    writers only raison dtre would be to write about her gender), but because each individual

    woman writer shows us the world as she experiences it, without hidden agendas of any

    kind.40

    A writer is always searching for truth, Woolf writes. But truth has a deplorable

    tendency to slip out of our hands, just like Woolfs thought fish swims out of her head

    when she is told that because she is a woman, she is not allowed to walk on the grass. A

    writer, she insists, must communicat[e] his experience with perfect fullness. There must be

    freedom and there must be peace ( Room, 103). When women enter literature, well get

    greater insight both in women and in the world. Each woman has to find her own voice, focus

    her attention on the world, and find a language in which to express her vision. Although

    Woolf doesnt say that this is a political task, it can easily become one. In the 1970s, we

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    24

    learned from the womens movement that under the right circumstances, such a seemingly

    simple project can be political dynamite.

    Like Beauvoir, Woolf appears to think that only creative writing truly gives us

    another world. Moreover, she does seem to believe that only some few, hugely talented

    individuals have the capacity to create a genuine language with which to communicate their

    vision. If she means the capacity to create a language, and a vision, that will remain in history

    for centuries, she is surely right. But writing is not only valuable for a Dante or a

    Shakespeare. Non-fiction, and philosophy too, can change lives.

    Luckily it is easy to read A Room of Ones Own from a more democratic perspective.

    Woolf's fundamental insight is true for everyone: it is valuable to try to see reality as it is, and

    to find a language for what one sees. The result doesnt have to be War and Peace. An

    attempt to pay attention at the breakfast table, or in the next office meeting will also help

    change the world, however imperceptibly.

    Must We Read Literature?

    I have deliberately placed great emphasis on the importance of reading literary texts.

    For me, the best literature gives us the most brilliant examples of attentive language. So I

    have been quoting poetry, plays, novels, autobiographical testimony and non-fiction (if we

    can call A Room of Ones Own non-fiction). But of course it is not necessary to have read a

    single book in order to be able to look at others with a just and loving gaze. The value of

    attention is certainly not something that must be learned from philosophy and literature.

    40 I discuss some of the implications of this view on I am not a woman writer

    (2008).

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    25

    This is why I disagree with Martha Nussbaums claim that we necessarily will

    develop the capacity for compassion through reading literature.41 As if people who dont

    have the education, the leisure, or the money to sit down to read a book somehow are doomed

    to remain less sensitive and compassionate than those who do. History, of course, offers

    plenty of examples to the contrary. We have all heard stories about the concentration camp

    commanders who enjoyed Goethe and Schiller in their spare time.

    I suspect that the relationship between attention and the love of literature is the other

    way around: people who are interested in attention, will often find joy and insight in

    literature, if they have the opportunity to become readers. The reason why literature is

    valuble isnt that it makes us good. It is that it helps us to see the world more clearly. It

    does this, not because writers are the only attentive people in the world, but because they

    work so hard on their language.

    If it is expressed, the vision of the attentive gaze sees can have significant social and

    political implications.42 To work with language is to train oneself to see more clearly. Writing

    is thinking. There is no such thing as "literary language." There is only language that makes

    us see, and language which doesn't. And all the shades of transitional uses of language that

    end up somewhere on the sliding scale between them: language that makes us glimpse

    something; language that has caught hold of a "thought fish," but fails to reel it in, and so on.

    The call to look at reality with a just and loving gaze is the opposite of formalism:

    whatever form that enables the writer to express her own vision is the right one. Non-fiction,

    or even academic writing, can have as much impact as poetry. As literary scholars we dont

    need to don the formalist straight-jacket. Instead we can simply train ourselves to look at

    41 Se Martha C. Nussbaum, Not for Profit: Why Democracy Needs the Humanities

    (Princeton og Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2010). 42 Cf. Sartre and Beauvoirs unveiling through writing.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    26

    literature with the right attention, and strive to find the right language, style and form in

    which to share our vision with others.

    Language and Attention after 22 July

    Ane Farsethss recent book about contemporary Norwegian literature shows that in

    the decade leading up to the 22 July 2011, much of the best Norwegian literature was haunted

    by a sense of unreality. In this decade, Norwegian society, with its combination of oil-fueled

    affluence and social-democratic traditions, appeared to breed a desire for reality in many of

    its most talented artists.43 The postmodern fascination with performance and performativity

    had lost much of its hold, and writers as well as characters often worried about authenticity,

    veering between a fear of being seen and the wish to remain hidden.

    In an essay in the Norwegian journal Samtiden, I wrote about the mass murderer of 22

    July that He is the worst possible incarnation of a culture in search of reality.44 For at least

    a generation, it has been chic to claim that language fails to grasp reality. This made us lose

    any faith we may have had in the power of language to change reality.45 But if we lose faith

    in language, the alternative is action. In Ibsen's Rosmersholm, Rebecca West throws herself

    into the waterfall because she realizes that nothing she can say to Rosmer will overcome his

    doubt in her, and in himself.46 To find reality is to find our faith in the power of language to

    do something in the world. But there is no need to get melodramatic about it, to think

    exclusively in large-scale terms. Even de la Mares insignificant little duck pushes our

    43 Ane Farseths, Herfra til virkeligheten: Lesninger i 00-tallets litteratur (Oslo:

    Cappelen Damm, 2012). 44 Toril Moi, Markedslogikk og kulturkritikk: Om Breivik og ubehaget i den

    postmoderne kulturen, Samtiden, nr. 3, 2012: 24. 45 Cf. Sartre and Beauvoir, committed literature, etc. 46 See my chapter on Rosmersholm in Henrik Ibsen and the Birth of Modernism.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    27

    understanding of the life of animals just a little further, just because the writer looks at it with

    such tremendous attention.

    This is why I read Vigdis Hjorths 2012 novel Leve posthornet! with such pleasure.

    (The title, which refers to Kierkegaards Repetition, means Long live the Posthorn!").

    Written in the aftermath of 22 July, this novel truly tries to break down the belief that

    language cant say or do anything real. The story about Ellinor, a communications advisor

    who has completely lost the sense of the meaning of her words; who literally cant see clearly

    when she looks out of the window; who no longer is able to feel anything for the people that

    surround her, whether it is her lover, her family, or her colleagues, is simultaneously a

    profound and witty allegory of postmodern societys alienated relationship to language.

    Leve posthornet! asks about the meaning of life without becoming tragic. Hjorth finds

    the right comic tone -- her novel is a Norwegian counterpoint to the British tradition of comic

    novels from Jane Austen to Zadie Smith. Hjorth joins this tradition without giving up her

    modern and postmodern taste for game-playing. Her novel is full of genuinely funny

    references to other Norwegian novels (not least Dag Solstads parable of the faithful postman

    in Maos China, in Arild Asnes 1970), and offers us a piece of magic realism in the story

    about a teacher who is chased off an island off the coast of northern Norway because she

    makes her young students realize that they are unhappy. It is also a fine satire of political and

    commercial bureaucratic complacency.

    The title may well be derived from Kierkegaards ode to the posthorn in Repetition

    (he praises it because it is said never to sound the same tone twice), but it may also be a sly

    reference to that pioneering postmodern novel, Thomas Pynchons The Crying of Lot 49, in

    which a posthorn is the symbol of a conspiracy which may or may not exist. Furthermore,

    Derridas well-known claim that the letter never arrives, is also under attack here, for in

    Hjorths novel, the mail actually does arrive.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    28

    As the novel develops, Ellinor manages to find both language and action. She learns

    to mean what she says, and to work with something she has faith in, namely the heroic

    struggle to stop Norway from adopting the European Unions Third Postal Directive. (One of

    the best parts of the novel is the way it uses pits ordinary language to satirize bureaucratic

    language.) When Elinor develops a more genuine relationship to language, she even manages

    to shed her disdain for clichs, realizing instead that sometimes a clich expresses exactly

    what she feels. Over time, her emotional numbness leaves her, and she begins to admire and

    learn from the experiences of others.

    It is no coincidence that the action of Leve posthornet, a novel written after the

    massacre at Utya, ends in April 2011. It would be difficult to set a story about Ellinors

    new-found attention and optimism to a period that included 22 July. Yet the novel expresses

    the longing for reality, for a more genuine faith in language that intensified in the aftermath

    of those atrocious events.

    For Norwegians the terror of 22 July was, and remains, a deeply traumatic example of

    the difficulty of reality. We could not find the words. If a genuine understanding of 22 July

    demands that we be capable of looking at everything that happened that day with a just and

    loving gaze, only saints will succeed.

    Yet Oslo District Court nevertheless made huge efforts to look at the events of that

    day precisely with such a gaze. After the presentation of the post-mortem report for each

    victim, the court looked at a photograph of the victim while a one-minute long biography,

    usually written by his or her family, was read out. Many survivors from Utya spoke in court

    about their suffering. The accused was also given hours to express himself, both at the

    beginning and at the very end of the trial.

    Towards the end of the 22 July trial, Morgenbladet's commentator, Kristopher Schau,

    wrote that after the experience of sitting in court every day for ten weeks, he only had one

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    29

    conclusion: let us be good to one another. (The word he used was snill, which hovers

    somewhere between good and kind, and is often used about children.) I understand what

    he means. There is something so awful about contemplating the pain and horror of terrorism,

    day after day, that we naturally want to remember that goodness too belongs to the range of

    human capacities. The same impulse makes us join rose marches to seek comfort in

    community. (On 25 July 2011, 200,000 people marched in the center of Oslo, carrying roses

    as a symbol of their revulsion for the horrors in Oslo and at Utya. Similar marches took

    place all over Norway.)

    But here I need to stress that being "good" is not at all the same thing as to look at

    others, or the world, with a just and loving gaze. To be good is not always a virtue. When

    we tell a child to be good, we usually dont mean that he is to show compassion, but that he is

    to obey us, and follow the rules. Children brought up to be good often grow into expert

    pleasers, at the cost of their own voice and identity. Moreover, what may look as good

    behavior, may in fact be motivated by all kinds of more or less obscure feelings: a sense of

    guilt; a misunderstood sense of duty; masochistic self-sacrifice. A person looking at the

    world through the lens of such feelings certainly doesnt see it clearly.

    For Simone Weil, to look at ones neighbour with the right attention is to see him so

    clearly that we give him the help he actually needs, not the help we intellectually believe he

    needs.47 To give that sort of help may not make us look good, in either sense of the word. If

    we are obsessed with our own efforts to appear good, we also risk underestimating evil, or

    not seeing it for what it is. An attentive gaze isnt moralizing, but it doesnt shrink from

    judgment when required. In fact, to describe a phenomenon as clearly as we can is to express

    a judgment. In Norway, we often believe that to be good is to make sure we never say

    anything critical about someone else. But avoidance is not a moral virtue. To withhold the

    47 Se Weil, tudes scolaires, 262.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    30

    truth from someone is to deprive him of an opportunity to face reality. The attentive gaze

    the just and loving gaze must be capable of contemplating evil, otherwise its aspirations

    will be hollow.

    Maybe it is because I believe in the power of ordinary language to say something true

    about reality that I was so shocked by the first two expert psychiatrists testimony in court. In

    their report, and during the trial, Synne Srheim and Torgeir Husby revealed what a

    scientistic understanding of psychiatry, based entirely on the checklists of the diagnostic

    manual ICD-10.48 They were deeply skeptical about ordinary languages capacity to convey

    truth. They appeared not to have a moral vocabulary, and they were quite incapable of

    reflecting on their own categories.

    However, in spite of their allegiance to pure science, they inevitably based key

    findings on their own understanding of what is to count or not count as ordinary language,

    apparently without realizing it. One example would be their claim that the mass murderers

    language, in interviews and in his manifesto was full of neologisms of the kind typical for

    psychosis. Under cross-examination, however, it turned out their criterium for a neologism

    was simply their own sense of what counts as ordinary language: a neologism, they said, is a

    word that we take to be used in an incomprehensible way.49

    But if this is the only language we have to speak of what happened on 22 July, well

    never understand what happened that day. In court, this became very apparent. On Thursday

    14th June, during the cross-examination of Srheim and Husby, the presiding judge, Wenche

    Arntzen, had to take on the role as a moral philosopher:

    48 ICD-10 is WHOs diagnostic manual. It is organized according to similar principles

    as the American Psychiatry Associations handbooke DSM-V. 49 ord som brukes p en uforstelig mte for oss VG-Nett, 22/7-rettssaken: Ord-

    for-ord dag 38 (torsdag 14. juni), VG-Nett, 15. juni (endret 17. juni) 2012. .

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    31

    Judge Arntzen: As to this question about who shall live and who shall die. Is it

    a delusion because it so immoral?

    Psychiatrist Srheim: Now you confuse me.

    Arntzen: You are saying that nobody can decide who shall die, that morally

    speaking nobody can have this responsibility?

    Srheim: The way we see it, no single individual has the responsibility for

    who gets to live and die.

    Arntzen: Well, many people have that responsibility in the sense of the death

    penalty, and in war. These are phenomena that exist.

    Srheim: Yes, you are of course right.

    Arntzen: But to call it a delusion. Is it because it is so immoral?

    Srheim: No, I am thinking of the examples you mentioned about war, and to

    sentence someone to death, its impossible that he, sitting there in his

    childhood bedroom would belong in one of those categories, and really

    believe that he was in a position to discover who should live and who should

    die.

    Arntzen: Yes, there is a transition from legitimate through a wide spectrum to

    illegitimate homicide. Terrorist actions may have an ideological basis.

    Couldnt this be experienced as a vocation, however absurd it might be?

    Srheim: I think we begin from a simpler starting point than you, in your

    position as judge, has the opportunity to do. Our starting point is that he was

    sitting there alone, and quite seriously spent years figuring out who would

    have to die. []50

    50 Dommer Arntzen: Ogs dette med hvem som skal leve og hvem som skal d, er det

    en beskrivelse av en vrangforestilling fordi det er s umoralsk? Rettspsykiater Srheim: N ble jeg forvirret.

    Arntzen: Dere sier at ingen kan bestemme hvem som skal d, men ingen kan vel i moralsk forstand ha dette ansvaret. Srheim: Snn som vi vet det, er det ingen enkeltindivider som har et ansvar for hvem som skal leve og hvem som skal d. Arntzen: Det er jo mange som har ansvaret for det i betydningen ddsstraff og krig. Det er et fenomen som eksisterer. Srheim: Ja, det har du selvflgelig rett i. Arntzen: Men det fre det som en vrangforestilling. Er det fordi det er s umoralsk? Srheim: Nei, jeg tenker de eksemplene du sa om krig og ved ilegge noen ddsstraff, det er umulig at hvordan han p gutterommet skulle komme inn i en av de kategoriene og mente han var i posisjon til finne ut hvem som skulle leve og d.

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    32

    The very fact that Srheims reaction was to be confused by Arntzens clear

    questions about morality and ideology, reveal that it is possible to practice psychiatry at the

    highest level without ever engaging in moral reflection. Judge Arntzens questions, on the

    other hand, show that the persons who actually were carrying the burden of deliberating

    about the sanity or insanity of the mass murderer, to assess the degree of responsbility he had

    for his actions, discovered that they simply couldnt do this from a purely positivistic

    perspective.

    The 22 July trial certainly demonstrated that a scientistic understanding of the soul is

    neither infallible nor particularly interesting. But it wasnt just the trial that showed that we

    need different concepts, a different gaze, a gaze that doesnt immediately reduce the

    difficulty of reality to the simplistic and flattening categories on a questionnaire. The debate

    raging around every aspect of what happened on 22 July has shown that we have to develop

    our capacity to discuss moral questions about action and responsibility. This is why we need

    a new focus on language and attention.

    The mass murderer of 22 July is the product of a society in which nobody has

    troubled themselves with the need for a just and loving gaze. He is a distorted caricature of

    the worst in postmodern society. He is Gordon Gekko and Patrick Bateman rolled into one.51

    Maybe this is even more striking in the case of the Norwegian terrorist, since his horrendous

    actions, and his unspeakably chilling manifesto with its deadly marketing metaphors were put

    together after the financial crisis, which mercilessly revealed how the same logic, and the

    Arntzen: Ja, du har en overgang fra rettmessig drap og et spekter over [til] fullstendig urettmessig. Terrorhandlinger kan vre ideologisk begrunnet, er ikke det et selvopplevd kall s absurd det enn kan vre? Srheim: Jeg tror vi tar et enklere utgangspunkt enn dommeren har anledning til ta. Vrt utgangspunkt er at der satt han alene og i dypeste alvor brukte han r finne ut hvem som mtte d. [...22/7-rettssaken: Ord-for-ord dag 38 51 Maybe I should add Jordan Belfort, so memorably portrayed by Leonardo di Caprio

    in The Wolf of Wall Street (2013).

  • April 14, 2015 / Toril Moi

    33

    same language, led to economic catastrophe for millions of ordinary workers all over the

    world.

    A society that refuses to take the demand for genuine attention seriously, and rejects

    the very idea of a just and loving gaze as so much unscientific sentimentalism, will be cold

    and bureaucratic. In such a society, leaders will consider themselves managers, content to

    have carried out correct protocol. They wont ask themselves if they have looked at the

    situations for which they are responsible with genuine attention. Nor will they ask themselves

    whether they really understand what actions are required to solve the problems they are

    dealing with. Instead, they will continue to make and follow bureaucratic rules. When

    disaster strikes, they will hide behind their rules and regulations, and their vague, lifeless and

    peculiarly impersonal language. When we have to sort through the rubble, and find out what

    such people take responsibility for, we will certainly feel that reality keeps slipping through

    our fingers.