m Kramer

download m Kramer

of 29

Transcript of m Kramer

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    1/29

    M AT T HE W H. KR AM E R T h ro win g L i g h t o n th e Ro l e o f Mo ral P rin ci p l es in th e Law

    THROWING LIGHTON THEROLE

    OFMORALPRINCIPLESIN THE

    LAW:

    FurtherReflections

    Matthew H. Kramer

    Churchill College, Cambridge

    Inclusive Legal Positivism, as und erstood throughout this ar ticle, con sists in

    the fo llowing thesis: It can be the case, though it need n ot be th e case, that

    a norms consistency with some or all of the requirements of morality is a

    precondition fo r the nor ms status as a law in this or th at jurisdiction. While

    such a precondition for legal validity is no t inherent in th e concept of law,

    it can be imposed as a threshold test und er the Rule of Recogn ition in an y

    particular legal regime. That test, which can be applied by the officials in

    such a regime to all of the legal no rms therein or to only some subset of

    tho se no rms, is on e of the criteria th at th e officials use for ascertaining th e

    law. Insofar as a criterion of that sort does prevail in any particular legal

    system, then, some degree o f moral worth iness is a n ecessar y condition for

    the legally authoritative force of each norm that is validated thereunder.

    Inclusive Legal Positivism, which readily accepts the possibility of such a

    state of affa irs, is inclusive because it a llows that moral precepts can figure

    amo ng the criteria th at guide of ficials a scertainment of th e law. Inclusivisttheo rists reject th e view that every criterion of law-ascertainment in every

    possible legal system is focused on n on no rmative matters of provenan ce. At

    the same time, the Inclusivists are positivists because they also reject the

    view that ever y possible lega l system includes moral tests amon g its law-as-

    certaining criteria. An Inclusive Legal Positivist insists that such tests are

    contingent features, rather than essential features, of the systems of law

    wherein they are applied.

    Incorpora tionism, as understood throughout this article, con sists in the

    following thesis: It can be the case, though it need not be the case, that anorms correctness as a moral principle is a sufficient cond ition for its status

    as a legal nor m in th is or th at jurisdiction. Albeit the role of mo ral correct-

    ness as a sufficient condition for legal validity is no t inherent in the con cept

    of law, it can ob tain a s such un der the Rule of Recognition in an y particular

    legal regime. An Incorporationist theorist maintains that moral principles

    115

    Legal Theory, 8 (2002), 115143. Prin ted in t he U nited States of America

    Copyright Cambridge University Press 13523252/02 $9.50

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    2/29

    recognized as legally determinative in this manner are indeed preexistent

    legal nor ms, no twithstand ing th at they have perhaps never been laid d own

    in any explicit sources such as legislative enactments or judicial rulings.

    When officials do engage in a practice of treating th e mora l sound ness ofno rms as a sufficient cond ition for the norms legal authoritativeness, they

    have thereby incorporated moral principles into their legal systemeven

    before some or all of the applicable principles have received any explicit

    recogn ition . An Incorpora tionist th eorist, who read ily accepts the possibil-

    ity of such a state o f af fairs, is no netheless a legal positivist because he insists

    that the incorporation of moral principles into a legal systems array of

    norms is contingent rather than inevitable.

    In a recent issue of this jour na l, I defen ded Inclusive Legal Positivism and

    a version of Incorporation ism against some powerful objections leveled atthem by Scott Shapiro.1 Shapiro has now replied to that earlier essay of

    mine, as has Jules Coleman from th e camp o f Incorporationism.2 In what

    follows, I shall endeavor to parry their ripostes in order to clarify my

    wholehearted defense of Inclusive Legal Positivism and my wary defense of

    Incorporationism. Because Shapiro has emerged as the fo remost critic of

    Incorporation ism and Inclusive Legal Positivism, an d because Coleman has

    for years been the lead ing proponent of the Incorpo ration ist doctrine, their

    arguments deserve very serious attention indeed.

    I. HARTAND INCLUSIVELEGALPOSITIVISM

    The first and fo remo st aim o f my earlier ar ticle was to rebut Shapiros claim

    that the norms validated as laws under an Inclusive Rule of Recognition

    cannot con stitute peremptor y reasons for decisions by officials and citizens.

    Whereas any genuinely authoritative legal directives exclude their address-

    ees from acting legitimately on considerations that run athwart th e direc-

    tives terms, a man date validated by an Inclusive Rule of Recognition

    requires its addressees to d eliberate abo ut the merits of giving ef fect to th e

    mandate. So Shapiro has contended: The problem is that [any norm

    validated by an Inclusive Rule of Recognition] cannot make a practical

    difference in theway thatrules are supposed to make practical d ifferences:

    if the agent is required to determine wheth er the rule ought to be fo llowed

    on the merits, then it can count neither as an epistemic tool for authorita-

    tive d esignation nor as a peremptor y reason for action (Shapiro, Way,

    502, emphasis in original). In response to this line of argument, I main-

    1. Matthew Kramer, How Moral Principles Can Enter into theLaw, 6 LEGAL THEORY 83 (2000).I was respon ding there largely to Scott Shap iro, On HartsWayOut, 4 LEGAL THEORY 469 (1998)(h ereinafter cited as Shapiro, Way). I wish to than k Wil Waluchow, Emran Mian, and JulesCo leman for some en lighten ing excha nges of views on the issues discussed herein.

    2. Scott Shapiro, Law, Moral ity, and the Guidance of Conduct, 6 LEGAL THEORY 127 (2000)(hereinafter cited as Shapiro, Law); Jules Coleman, Constrain ts on the Criteri a of Legali ty, 6LEGAL THEORY 171(2000) (h ereinafter cited a s Coleman , C on straints).

    116 MATTHEWH.KRAMER

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    3/29

    tained that a legal norm validated by an Inclusive Rule of Recognition can

    perfectly well partake of peremptoriness. What cannot be true, of course, is

    tha t the scope o f the peremptor y sway of such a n orm is all-encom passing.

    H owever, restrictions on the scope o f a norms peremptoriness are familiarand straightforward and are not in any way at odds with the nature and

    existence of tha t perempto riness.

    Thus, for example, if a legal norm Nis valida ted und er an Inclusive Rule

    of Recognition that withholds validation from any norm that is grossly

    unfa ir, the scope of Ns peremptor y sway do es not encompass gross unfa ir-

    ness but d oes encompass many oth er con siderations such a s ordinar y un-

    fairness and unwisdom. No factors covered by the peremptor y reach of N

    are permissible bases for decisions or actions that are contrary to Ns

    requirements. Some oth er factors such a s gross unfairness fall outside thatreach and can thus warrant d ecisions or action s contrar y to Ns demands.

    However, the upshot of such a state of affairs is not the inexistence of Ns

    peremptoriness, but merely its limitedness in scope. Hence, despite

    Shapiros ingenious arguments, a nor m validated as a law under an Inclu-

    sive Rule of Recogn ition can make a practical difference in exactly the way

    tha t an y authoritative rule is supposed to m ake a practical difference.

    A. Peremptoriness and Applicability

    Shapiro in his rejoinder does not contest the general correctness of my

    defense of Inclusive Legal Positivism, but he declares that H .L.A. Hart could

    not ha ve availed himself of my defense. When seeking to vind icate Inclusive

    Lega l Positivism, I took for gran ted (arguendo) a conception o f authoritative

    no rms as exclusiona r y reasons-for-actiona conception associated origi-

    na lly with G eoffrey Warnock and Joseph Raz, and subsequently drawn upon

    by Har t. I ha d presumed that Sha piro was relying on just such a conception

    and that he was attributing such a conception to Hart. However, he nowsubmits that Harts account of normativity dif fers from the War-

    no ckian/Razian accoun t in ways tha t leave H art un shielded b y my defense

    of Inclusive Lega l P ositivism.

    Und er the Warnockian/Razian analysis of autho ritative normativity, there

    is ample room for restrictions on the scope of a norms peremptoriness.

    Shapiro argues tha t H arts analysis, by contra st, ha s ruled out such restric-

    tions. He contends that Hart viewed authoritative norms as directives that

    put an end to all questions about whether conformity is ad visable

    (Sha piro, Law, 165, emphasis add ed) . Cleaving to tha t view of n ormssoShapiro avouchesH art could n ot fa ll back upon a n otion of scope-restric-

    tions in o rder to maintain th at th e man da tes validated by an Inclusive Rule

    of Recognition are genuinely peremptory. H ence, Shapiro con cludes, my

    vindication o f the Inclusivist stance does no t redound to Ha rts benefit at all.

    Shapiro is alert to the principal difficulty that stands in the way of his

    Throwing Light on the Role of Moral Principles in the Law 117

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    4/29

    renewed critique o f H art: th e wholesale implausibility of a conception of

    legal mandates as directives whose peremptoriness is always unlimited in

    scope. Surely, it would be argued , no rule has absolute force, tha t is, must

    be followed no matter what the reason (Shapiro, Law, 165). One shouldcertainly shrink from attributing to Hart the outlandish view that legal

    no rms are invariably end owed with absolute force. Shapiro af firms tha t the

    appropriate tack here is to distinguish carefully between limitations on a

    norms peremptoriness and limitations o n a norms applicability. H e sug-

    gests tha t, although H art believed in th e unrestricted scope of an y authori-

    tative norms peremptoriness, such a belief was accompanied by an

    awareness that the cond itions for the applicability of a norm are typically

    subject to a number of restrictions. Shapiro expresses this point as follows,

    by indicating how H art would an alyze a situation in which a comman der hasord ered his troops to complete a ten-mile training h ike: The defeasibility

    of a n orders requirements can be explained in terms of the ord ers appli-

    cability conditions. The comman ders ord er car ries with it a set of implicit

    exceptions, e.g., the troops are required to complete the 10 mile hike unless

    they, or their command er, are in serious da nger. . . . There is, thus, no need

    to explain the defeasibility of [n orms] by making reference to the techn ical

    concept of a partially exclusionary scope. Such cases can easily be ex-

    plained in terms of the familiar notion of applicability conditions

    (Shapiro , Law, 16566).3

    H aving d rawn this distinction between limits onperemptor iness and limits on applicability, Shapiro concludes that H art d id

    not posit any limits of the former sort. Consequently, Shapiros original

    critique does tell against Hart, its specific target: [S]ince peremptory

    reasons [in H art s ana lysis as described by Shapiro] have un iversal scopes,

    no one can deliberate about th e merits of following a rule and still treat the

    rule as a peremptor y reason for action (Shapiro, Law, 166).

    Now, although the chief purpose of my earlier article was to uphold

    Inclusive Legal Positivism rather than to defend Hart, a few queries about

    Shapiros argument ought to be raised here. First, the only passage thatShapiro cites in ord er to substantiate h is claim about Harts reliance on the

    no tion of applicability-conditions is from The Concept of Law. That is, the

    passage comes from H arts early work rath er than from his later work. What

    makes this citation problematic is that Shapiro, both in his original article

    and in his more recent piece, has emphasized that the conception of

    norma tivity in the earlier work of H art is significantly divergent from the

    con ception that is to be found in H ar ts later work (Shapiro, Way, 492-94;

    Shapiro, Law, 162). Given the marked shift in Harts position on the

    matt er over time, an extract from his early writings is no t a reliable ind icatorof his views at the much later juncture when his conception of norms as

    peremptor y reason s-for-action gained expression. To know that H art was

    3. Slightly od d, in my view, is the suggestion th at th e no tion o f ap plicability cond ition s isany less clearly a tech nical con cept tha n is the n otion of a pa rtially exclusionar y scope.

    118 MATTHEWH.KRAMER

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    5/29

    still atta ched to the no tion of limited applicability-conditions in distinction

    from limited peremptoriness, we would have to be presented with a ger-

    man e passage from his later writingsa passage in which he gave voice to

    tha t abiding atta chmen t. Shapiro offers no such passage, and (so far as I amaware) there is none.

    Second, even if we leave aside the point just mad e, the examples on which

    Shapiro trades are n ot really apposite. H e d iscusses Harts view of circum-

    stan ces in which a comman der s ord er should not be followed or in which a

    persons promise should not be kept. In oth er words, he discusses situat ions

    tha t clearly involve the inapplicabilityof certa in peremptor y reason s-for-ac-

    tion rather than the inexistencethereof. Und er an Inclusive Rule of Recogni-

    tion, however, the very existence of legal nor ms as legal norms isexactly what

    is at stake. Amanda te that does no t satisfy the moral test(s) laid down by sucha Rule of Recogn ition in some particular legal system is no nexistent therein

    as a legally valid norm. Thus, if we are to flesh o ut H art s und erstan ding of

    auth oritative norms in a way tha t is relevan t to the deba te over the tenability

    of Inclusive Legal Positivism, we have to focus on circumstances where the

    very existence of such no rms is in question . (We might, for instance, ponder

    a situation in which someon e promises to commit a murder. What is in seri-

    ous doubt is whether the promise has any morally binding force at all, rather

    tha n merely whether it will fail to be applicable an d d etermina tive in some

    settings.4

    ) When we con centra te specifically on the matter of the existence oflegal norms as such, we find tha t H art time and again observed that an Inclu-

    sive Rule of Recogn ition d eals with precisely that matter; he d id not d iscuss

    any such Rule of Recognition by reference to applicability-conditions at all.

    In his early work, for example, he wrote tha t [i]n some systems, as in th e

    United States, the ultimate criteria of legal validity explicitly incorporate

    principles of justice or substantive moral values, and that any enactment

    passed by American legislatures in violation of constitution al mora l tests is

    liable to be treated as ul tra vi res, and declared lega lly invalid by the cour ts to

    the extent th at it conflicts with the constitution al provisions.5

    In his laterwriting, he chose virtually the same word s to reiterate his view: [ I]n some sys-

    4. Hart h imself, in th e essay where he a nalyzed legal norms as content-indepen dent per-emptor y reasons for action, referred to th e kind o f situation th at I am envisaging. H is remarksquite plainly tally with my interpretation of his mature con ception of authoritative norms:[T]he giving of a promise is intended to be a reason not merely for the promisor doing theaction when the time comes but for excluding n ormal free deliberation abo ut the m erits ofdoing it. . . . This is true even though the range of po ssible actions which o ne may validlypromise to do is not unlimited and d oes not include grossly immoral actions or those intendedto be harmful to the promisee. H.L.A. Hart, Commands and AuthoritativeReasons, inESSAYS ON

    BENTHAM 243, 255 (O xford : Clar end on Press, 1982).5. H.L.A. Ha rt, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 199, 70 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961) (hereinafter

    cited as Concept) . SeealsoH.L.A. Hart , Positivi sm and theSeparation of Law and Morals, inESSAYS INJURISPRU DENCE AND PHILOSOPHY49, 5455 (O xford : Clarend on Press, 1983). ( The essay just citedwas origina lly published in 71 HARV. L. REV. 593 [1958].) I am of course aware that laws in theUnited States are sometimes found to be unconstitutional as applied, rather than unconstitu-tional tout cour t. While highlighting the latter type of uncon stitutionalitythe type usuallyun derconsideration in the deba tes over Inclusive Legal PositivismI am in no wayd enying the form er.

    Throwing Light on the Role of Moral Principles in the Law 119

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    6/29

    6. H.L.A. Hart, Postscript, in2 THE CONCEPTOF LAW238, 247 (O xford: Clarendon Press, 1994).

    tems of law, as in the U nited States, the ultima te criteria of legal validity . . .

    explicitly incorporate besides pedigree, principles of justice or substantive

    moral values, and these may form the content of legal constitutional re-

    straints.6

    Whenever H art adverted to the centra l issue ad dressed by InclusiveLegal Positivism, he treated it not as an issue pertaining to limitations on

    no rms applicability, but as an issue perta ining to limita tion s on the sheer ex-

    istence of norm s and their peremptoriness. Shapiros exposition of H art s ac-

    count o f authoritative normat ivity, with examples involving an unfo llowed

    comm and and an unkept promise, has tended to obscure this point.

    Third , and perhaps most importan t, even if we grant that H art in his later

    work distinguished sha rply between limits on peremptoriness an d limits on

    applicability, an d even if we gran t that h e took the peremptoriness of legal

    no rms to be all-embracing, we sha ll have no grounds for accepting Shapirosconclusionhis conclusion, q uoted abo ve, that since peremptor y reason s

    [in H art s analysis] h ave universal scopes, no one can deliberate about th e

    merits of following a rule and still treat the rule as a perempto ry reason fo r

    action (Shapiro, Law, 166). The very distinction Shapiro high lights, the

    distinction between limits on applicability and limits on peremptoriness, is

    what blocks his inference. Within a model of legal mandates as norms

    end owed with all-enco mpa ssing perempto riness an d restricted applicability,

    any deliberation about the merits of complying with a mandate will be

    cha racterized as deliberation abo ut the applicability of the man da te in someor all sets of circumstances. Mora l tests laid d own by an Inclusive Rule o f

    Recognition will be cha racterized as giving rise to deliberation o f exactly this

    sort. To be sure, such a characterization is far from cogen t and illumina ting,

    because the model of autho ritative normativity attributed to Hart by Shapiro

    is itself far from cogent and illuminating. Nevertheless, even within the

    unsatisfactory confines of tha t model, there is abund an t room for avoiding

    an y eq ua tion between deliberat ing-on -th e-mer its-of-fo llowing-a-mandate-M

    an d failing-to-trea t-M-as-a-peremptory-reason -for-action. Accord ing to the

    aforementioned model, Mwill be trea ted as a peremptor y reason -for-actionwhenever it has been deemed to be applicable. According to tha t model, the

    question to be an swered by deliberation abo ut the merits of fo llowing Mis

    whether the cond itions for its applicability are ind eed present. Such delib-

    eration, then, d oes not con stitute any incursion into Ms peremptoriness.

    Ergo, even if we concede (arguendo) that Shapiros recountal of Ha rts ma-

    ture con ception of autho ritative normativity is accurate, we should grasp

    tha t H art could quite coherently leave open the possibility of Inclusivist

    constraints on the bindingness of legal nor ms.

    B. A Coda to the Critique

    H aving submitted that H art in his later work perceived th e peremptoriness

    of laws as unrestricted in scope, Shapiro proceeds to consider wheth er Hart

    120 MATTHEWH.KRAMER

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    7/29

    could fruitfully have modified his position. He contends that such a move

    would have been problematic:

    According to Hart, the identity of a legal system is fixed by its rule ofrecogn ition. Because the ru le of recognition is a du ty-imposing r ule, it follows

    tha t a rule is a member of a certain legal system on ly if a judge is und er a duty

    to apply such a rule in a case that comes before her. H owever, if legal rules

    were permitted to have partially exclusiona r y scopes, a judge might be under

    a duty to apply a rule in some cases, but have discretion to apply the same

    rule in other cases. The latter would obtain whenever the rule, even though

    applicable, is defea ted by reasons tha t fell outside its (partially) exclusionar y

    scope. The d uty of a judge to apply applicable ru les would thus be indetermi-

    nateit would obtain in some cases and not in others. Accordingly, the

    identity of any legal system would be indeterminate. (Shapiro, Law, 166.)

    Though Shapiro goes on to avow that th e problem broached in this para-

    graph is not insurmountable, we ought to query whether it is in fact a

    problem at a ll. Let us no te two dubious aspects of h is argument.

    First, when a puta tive legal norm d oes not pa ss the moral test(s) impo sed

    by an Inclusive Rule of Recognition, it is not tr ue tha t a judge has discretion

    to choose between applying and not applying the norm. Instead, he is

    under an obligation to invalidate the norm or at least to abstain from

    applying it. Accord ingly, the req uisite result in such circumstances is no t inany way indeterminateexcept, of course, when there is no determinate

    answer to the question whether the ostensible legal mand ate satisfies the

    relevan t mora l test(s). To be sure, when the latter q uestion does no t lend

    itself to a uniquely correct answer, a judge in the Inclusivist legal system will

    have genuine discretion to opt between applying and not applying the

    ostensible mand ate. H owever, tha t discretion does no t stem from anything

    peculiarly problematic abo ut limits on the peremptoriness of legal norms;

    rath er, it stems from the occurrence of a h ard case in which a key point of

    con tention is no t un ivocally resolvable. Any oth er d ifficult case tha t h ingeson an issue tha t is no t univocally resolvable (even th rough the in trod uction

    of n on -source-based standard s) will similarly engend er a need fo r the exer-

    cise of genuine discretion, regardless of whether the refractory issue is

    connected with Inclusivist constraints. Contrariwise, when the question of

    the fulfillment or no nfulfillment of an Inclusivist mora l test d oes lend itself

    to a uniquely correct a nswer, a judge in the regime th at imposes the test

    do es no t enjoy any discretion o f the sort described by Shapiro.

    Second, also doub tful is Shapiros claim that th e ident ity of a legal system

    would b e indeterminate as a consequence o f the indeterminacy that mightexist in some hard cases. On the one hand, it is generally true that a legal

    system will witness some ha rd cases for which n o uniq uely correct resolu-

    tions a re available even in principle. As a result, the law to be a scertained

    in any particular legal system (In clusivist or non-Inclusivist) is not fully

    determinate. On the other han d, th e indeterminacy tha t obtains is present

    in respect of only a small propor tion of the interaction s amo ng people tha t

    Throwing Light on the Role of Moral Principles in the Law 121

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    8/29

    might engender legal proceedings. Most such interactions never lead to

    lawsuits at all, because the legal implications of the various modes of con-

    duct are so clear-cut. Even amo ng the disputes tha t d o eventua te in legal

    proceedin gs, most are straigh tfor wardly resolvab le. The d ifficult cases stud-ied by law studen ts and legal scho lars constitute only a small proportion of

    the lawsuits that actually materialize and a still smaller proportion of the

    lawsuits tha t could have ma terialized if people had been foolishly obstinate

    enough to engage in them. Even some difficult cases lend themselves to

    uniquely correct resolutions, and thus the instances of genuine indetermi-

    nacy and strong discretion within a legal system are marginal. Although the

    ha rd cases involving full-blown indeterminacy will of course be manifold in

    an enormous legal system (as will wrongly decided cases), and although

    some o f tho se ha rd cases may well be prominent and important, the largemajority of issues add ressed by a legal systems workings are rout ine rath er

    than vexing. Numerous though the truly knotty cases may be in an immense

    legal system, they are vastly outnumbered by cases that can be handled

    readily. Outright indeterminacy is peripheral rather than central.

    Therefore, when con fronted with Shapiros claim ab out th e indetermi-

    nacy of the identity of an y legal system, we should wonder why the ind eter-

    minacy of the law in a small proportion of circumstances would un do the

    determinacy of the overarching legal system within which those circum-

    stan ces arise. Plain ly, much depends here on the purpose of the an alysis orenquiry in connection with which the identity of some legal system has

    become a matter of interest. If our investigations require us to specify a legal

    systems doctrinal details with considerable precision when we are elaborat-

    ing the nature of the overall system, we might have groun ds for affirming

    tha t the absence o f uniq uely correct answers in some h ard cases is sufficient

    to warrant our pronoun cing the identity of the system to be ind etermina te.

    Much more often, however, an enq uiry into the bearings of an overall legal

    regime will no t necessitate such detailed precision . Margina l ind eterminacy

    can be ignored o r a t least can be perceived a s falling well shor t o f un der-mining the determinacy of the regime as a whole. For most theoretical and

    practical purposes, we are justified in concluding that the identity of a legal

    system is not imperiled by the open-end edness of some of its fron tiers.

    Let us ponder a n ana logy. Suppose tha t somebody needs to carr y out a

    highly accurate census of the American population. If the guidelines that

    inform the census have not unequivocally answered certain q uestions about

    membership in the American population, and if there are n o supplemen-

    tar y bases for uneq uivoca l answers to th ose question s, then some degree o f

    indeterminacy will be involved in the conducting of th e census. For exam -ple, suppose that neither the guidelines nor any other relevant decisional

    bases have ordained an answer to the question whether American citizens

    living perman ently abroad (in Cambridge, England, for example) are to be

    classified as members of the American population. Even though the people

    occupying th is indeterminate status typically for m on ly a ver y small propor-

    122 MATTHEWH.KRAMER

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    9/29

    tion of the population, somebody assigned to produce an extremely accu-

    rate census might have to conclude that the existence of such people

    renders the American population indeterminate. For most purposes, how-

    ever, the existence of a few million American citizens residing permanen tlyabroad whose status is no t settled by the census guidelines, ex hypothesiis

    hardly sufficient to warran t an ascription of indeterminacy to the American

    population as a whole. For most purposes, an ascription of determinacy to

    the overall population can withstand some peripheral unsettledness.

    Shapiro might reply that, in the long passage quoted above, he does not

    have in mind difficult cases; instead , he is talking ab out indeterminacy of a

    much more wide-ran ging kind. Such a rejoind er would deflect the objec-

    tion presented in my last few paragraphs, but it would trigger again my

    previous objection. That is, it would seem to posit indeterminacy where infact th ere is none. As has been indicated , when th e moral tests imposed by

    an Inclusivist Rule of Recognition are either determinately satisfied or

    determinately unsatisfied by some apparent legal nor m N, o fficials in the

    Inclusivist regime will not enjoy any strong discretion in regard to the

    validation and application of N. They are under an obligation to recognize

    Nas a legal no rm when the mora l tests (a long with tests of provenance) a re

    determinately met, and they are under an obligation to decline to recogn ize

    Nas a legal norm when those tests are determinately unmet. Un less Shapiro

    is talking a bout d ifficult cases in which neither of these uneq uivoca l obliga-tions is present, his references to indeterminacy are q uite puzzling .

    II. INCORPORATIONISMAND ILLUMINATION

    Although the paramount purpose of my earlier article was to vindicate

    Inclusive Legal Positivism in response to Shapiros formidable critique, a

    secondary aim was to commend a limited version of In corporation ism while

    disapproving of an extreme version. The basic idea underlying extreme

    Incorporation ism was first articulated pro minently by Philip Soper but has

    undergone considerable development and refinement at the hands of

    Coleman.7 While my earlier article queried one main aspect of Colemans

    theor y, I h arbored no d oubts about the significance an d sophistication o f

    his contribution s. Moreover, on most issues surro und ing Inco rpora tionism,

    his work and mine are in full agreement. Indeed , as will be obser ved, bo th

    7. Amon g the relevant pub lications by Co leman are the following: Incorporationism, Conven-

    tional ity, and the Practical Di fference Thesis, 4 LEGAL THEORY 381 (1998) (hereinafter cited asColeman, Incorporationism); Second Thoughts and Other First Impressions, i nANALYZING LAW257, 25878 (Brian Bix ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998); Authori ty and Reason, inTHE AUTONOMY OF LAW 287 (Robert George ed ., Oxford : Clarend on P ress, 1996) (hereinaftercited as Coleman, Authority); Negative and Posit ive Posit ivism, inMARKETS, MORALS, AND TH ELAW 3, 1227 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988). For Sopers pioneering contri-bution, seehis Legal Theory and the Obli gation of a Judge: TheHart / Dworkin Dispute, 75 M IC H . L.REV. 473, 50915 (1977).

    Throwing Light on the Role of Moral Principles in the Law 123

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    10/29

    Shapiro a nd Coleman h ave overestimated th e extent to which I have sough t

    to d istance myself from Co lemans robust Incorpora tionist stance.

    A. Unchallenged Truth

    The modest version of Incorporationism that I espouse is marked by a

    curtailment of the range of circumstances to which the general Incorpo-

    rationist thesis pertains. Like anyone who upholds some variant of that

    thesis, I accept that a norms correctness as a moral principle can be a

    sufficient condition for its status as a legal norm in this or that system

    of law. H oweverunlike Colemans thoroughgoing Incorporationist doc-

    trinemy moderate Incorporationist theory submits that, even in legalsystems where moral correctness does amount to a sufficient condition

    for legal validity, it cannot amount to such a condition in most cases.

    Only in hard cases do any Incorporationist criteria in a Rule of Recog-

    nition become activated. On ly in such cases are mo ral precepts incorpo-

    rated into a legal regime as some o f its nor ms. If a scheme of governan ce

    were instead to treat mo ral cor rectness as a sufficient cond ition for legal

    validity in all circumstances (rather than only in the circumstances that

    breed hard cases), it would lack the regularity and coordination that are

    essential features of anything rightly classifiable as a regime of law. In asociety where every legal judgment by judicial and executive officials is

    a moral judgment through and through, the consentaneity among the

    multifarious determinations of the officials will be too low to enable the

    emergence or continuation of a genuine system of legal norms. If the

    operations of a regime are characterized by a welter of discordant deci-

    sions and clashing rationales not only at its margins but throughout its

    core, then it lacks the regularity that is ind ispensable for its very existence

    as a legal regime.

    As was repeated ly ackno wledged in my earlier article, my rejection of anytho rough going In corporation ist position is based not purely on conceptual

    analysis but also on an empirical assumption . Though my empirical premise

    is general and uncontroversial, it is indeed empirical rather than strictly

    philosoph ical. What I assume is tha t, except in static an d highly ho mogene-

    ous societies not much larger than a handful of families, there will be

    widespread disagreement among people over the answers to most moral

    questions; in any large and complex society, extensive d ivergences among

    peoples moral outlooks are bound to be present. Now, this empirical

    assumption is scarcely novel or co ntroversial. It is accepted by both Shapiroand Coleman , and has often figured saliently in legal and political philoso-

    phy. Hart, for example, relied on such a premise when discussing the

    disadvan tages of a regime o f primar y rules without seconda ry rules (Con-

    cept, 89-90). Some strand s of Rona ld D workins critiques of legal positivism

    in TakingRightsSeriouslydepend on ba sically the same empirical assumption

    124 MATTHEWH.KRAMER

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    11/29

    about the ineliminability of mo ral con troversy.8 H ence, although my disap-

    proval of any robust Incorpora tionist stance is partly empirical ( at a very

    abstract level) an d is no t purely a matter o f con ceptual analysis, the genera l

    drift o f the belief that un derpins my reservations is certainly no t unfamiliarin the domain of legal philosophy. In my earlier article, I therefore pre-

    sumed tha t the o rientation and limits of my misgivings would be plain.

    Unfortunately, both Shapiro and Coleman have taken me to be insisting

    on the falsity (or to be denying the truth) of the robust Incorporationist

    thesis. Each o f them retort s to my earlier article in part by claiming that my

    cha llenge to th e aforemen tioned th esis has tend ed to reveal that that thesis

    is trueas if I had end eavored to suggest other wise. Let us first look briefly

    at this claim by Shapiro and Coleman , and then a t a bolder affirmation o f

    the truth of th e robust Incorporation ist thesis. As will be seen, I can and d o

    8. See especial lyRonald Dworkin, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY 65, 6667 (Cambridge, MA:H ar vard U niversity Press, 1978). See also id. at 3944, 5455, 5968. I am here looking askanceat Coleman s repeated conten tion th at Dworkins critique of a proto-Incorpora tionist versionof legal po sitivism is purely conceptual (Coleman, Constraints, 17980, 181). Q uite plainlyempirical as well as conceptual is the D workinian claim th at any reference to m orality amon gthe criteria o f legality would enta il controversy sufficient to preclude the rule of recognitionfrom gener ating the con vergen ce necessar y to establish its existence as a regula tive social rule(Coleman, Con straints, 179). Dworkin is trading on the same basic empirical assumption o nwhich I rely; no purely conceptual analysis can tell us whether the degree o f con vergence

    stemming from the use of moral criteria will or will not be insufficient to sustain the existenceof a Rule of Recogn ition that encompasses such criteria. Bo th Dworkins argum ent and my ownrejection of thorou ghgoing Inco rpora tionism are partly empiricalthough I am more explicit

    than Dworkin in drawing attention to that characteristic.I should no te a further a nd partly related point o n which I disagree with Pro fessor Co leman

    about certain aspects of Dworkins early work. Along the following lines, Coleman takesexception to Dworkins claim that the availability of moral principles as touchstones foradjudication will eliminate or virtually eliminate judicial discretion: Of course, even as discre-tion owing to the availability of legally binding resources decreases (as the set of availableresources increases), the possibility of d iscretion owing to vagueness increases (as th e set o fcont roversial mora l predicates legally bind ing on officials increases). The same pred icates tha treduce discretion on one front increase it on another: a consequence of Dworkins own viewtha t mora l pred icates are essentially controversial. To defeat the positivist view of discretion,Dworkin has to do more than show that the set of available legal resources on which a judge

    can d raw goes beyon d rules (Coleman , Constraints, 172 n.5; Coleman, In corporationism,406 n.42). Coleman s retort ten ds to b lur the d istinction b etween weak and strong discretion,i.e., between discretion in the application of a dispositive standard and discretion in theabsence o f a ny d ispositive stand ard . D workin ascribes to legal positivism the view that judgesenjoy strong discretion in har d cases. H e seeks to rebut th at view by pointing out tha t judgesare obligated and empowered to resort to moral principlesas determina tive stan dard s for theirdecisions in such cases. He can readily acknowledge that the application of those principleswill a lways involve weakdiscretion because the cor rectness or in correctn ess of any applicationis not strictly demonstrable. He can therefore readily acknowledge that a greater reliance on

    mora l principles will entail an increase in th e exercise of weak discretion. H owever, such anacknowledgment does not at all impair or belie his thesis that the availability of moralprinciples as adjudicative touchstones will significantly reduce the need for judges to exercise

    strongdiscretion. In shor t, Dworkin could en dorse the first two sentences in the latest q uota tion

    from Coleman, so long as we recognize that the augmented discretion and the diminisheddiscretion are of different types. Once we do recognize that point, however, we can see that thethird sentence in the quotation is unsustainableat least if the phrase positivist view of

    discretion refers to the positivist view of discretion as characterized by Dworkin.

    Throwing Light on the Role of Moral Principles in the Law 125

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    12/29

    endorse that bolder affirmation without retracting any of my previous

    animadversions on the thoroughgoing Incorporationist thesis itself. My

    reason s for eschewing that th esis will become more eviden t here than in my

    earlier article.Shapiro and Coleman both contend th at the thoroughgoing Incorpora-

    tionist thesis is a cond itional proposition . As Shapiro writes: [T]he th esis

    of robust incorporationism is conditional in nature. The robust incorpora-

    tionist claims tha t i fa judicial convention arises tha t treats mora l appropri-

    aten ess as the sole condition of legality, thensuch a convention al rule coun ts

    as a rule of recognition (Shapiro, Law, 156, empha ses in original).

    Coleman similarly submits tha t h is version of Incorporation ism is properly

    und erstoo d as a conditional claim: If there are mo ral criteria of legality tha t

    are a ccepted by officials from an internal point of view and practiced by asufficient n umber o f them, and if the bulk of the population complies with

    the rules valid under those criteria, then there is a legal system in which

    mora lity is a con dition of legality (Co leman , Constraints, 182). H aving

    formulated the robust Incorporationist position as a conditional proposi-

    tion, Shapiro and Coleman can then easily demonstrate that my severe

    doubts about the sustainability of a robustly Incorporationist Rule of Rec-

    ognition tend to underscore the truth of the position that I am assailing.

    After all, the antecedent in the conditional proposition is almost always

    falsewhich means that the overall proposition is almost always true re-gard less of the truth -value o f its consequen t. Moreover, because th ere a re

    no groun ds for thinking th at the consequent will be false when the an tece-

    den t is true, we can safely conclude that the cond itional claim of thoro ugh-

    going In corporation ism is invariably true.

    Now, there is absolutely no reason for me to o bject to the n otion tha t the

    centra l thesis of rob ust Incorpora tionism presented a s a conditional propo-

    sition is invariably true. On the contrary, I shall presently argue that a

    slightly bolder rendering of that thesis is likewise true. Before turning to

    tha t alternative rendering, however, we should glan ce at two aspects of th eShapiro/Coleman riposte that may elicit some dissatisfaction in the read er.

    First, the riposte has delineated the thoroughgo ing version of Incorpora-

    tionism in a mann er that seems somewhat ad h oc. H eretofore, the central

    thesis of Incorporationism has sometimes been expressed in other than a

    conditional form. It has quite frequently been expressed as an indicative

    proposition, which is precisely the form in which Shapiro articulates it at

    the outset of his latest article: There is some possible legal system where

    the legality of a norm does depend on some of its moral properties

    (Sha piro, Law, 129).9

    Second, when the robust Incorporationist position

    9. For further indicative renderings of th e central thesis of Incorpo rationism, see, e.g.,Coleman, Autho rity, 30506; Co leman, Incorpora tionism, 382. For some cond itiona l for-mulations, seeBrian Leiter, Realism, Hard Positivi sm, and Conceptual Analysis, 4 LEGAL THEORY533, 535 (1998); Sco tt Shap iro, TheDif ference that Rules Make, inANALYZING LAW 33, 57 (BrianBix ed., Oxford: Clarend on Press, 1998). Slightly more oblique in its cond itiona lity is Coleman ,

    126 MATTHEWH.KRAMER

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    13/29

    is formulated as a conditional proposition, it becomes gratuitously unad ven-

    turous. The truth of such a proposition is consistent with the necessary

    falsehoo d o f both its ant ecedent and its conseq uent.

    Let us, then, concentrate on a version of thorough going Incorporation-ism th at is presented as an ind icative claimthe claim tha t there is at least

    on e possible legal system wherein the cor rectness of no rms as mora l prin-

    ciples is in all circumstances the suff icient con dition fo r their status as legal

    norms. If a n indicative proposition along these lines is true, then neither

    the antecedent nor the consequent of the conditional variant of robust

    Incorporationism is necessar ily false. Tha t is, the ind icative var iant of robust

    Incorporationism is bolder an d thus more interesting than its cond itiona l

    counterpart. Furthermore, it is true. Contrary to what Shapiro and Cole-

    man have supposed, I have always believed th at th e robust Incorporation istthesis in its indicative for m (as well as in its conditional fo rm, of course) is

    true.

    Why, therefore, did my earlier article reject the doctrine o f thoroughgo-

    ing In corporation ism, and why do I con tinue to reject it? The answer to th is

    question lies no t in a mistaken perception o f tha t do ctrine as false but in a

    perception of it as high ly misleading and un illuminating. For a clarification

    of this point, we should recall another argument by Hart in which he

    resorted to some elementar y empirical claims. In his famous discussion of

    the minimum conten t of natural law (Concept, 189-95), he pointed to somebasic characteristics of h uman beings and the world wherein they live, and

    he concluded therefrom that the legal system in any viable society larger

    than a ha nd ful of families must include fund amental interdictory manda tes

    tha t coincide in con tent with cardinal precepts of morality.10 Now, suppose

    tha t an oppon ent were to point out tha t H arts empirical premises do not

    strictly necessitate his conclusion. Such an opponent would accurately

    maintain that, even if we grant Harts premises (as any sensible person

    should), we ought not to regard as logically incoherent the idea that a

    large-scale society can endure without basic legal prohibitions on murder,unprovoked assault, extensive vandalism, and other serious misdeeds.

    Though the sustainability of a society without those prohibitions is stagger-

    ingly unlikely, it is not logically impossible. This imaginar y opponen t would

    thus coun ter H art s position with the following thesis: There is at least one

    possible large-scale society tha t can end ure in the absence of any fund amen-

    tal legal proscriptions. Ought we to think that such a rejoinder would

    expose some significant shortcomings in H art s discussion of th e minimum

    content of natura l law? Hart would doubtless have been unimpressed. H e

    Autho rity, 28788, a nd considerably more o blique is Jules Coleman and Brian Leiter, LegalPositi vism, inA COMPANION TO PHILOSOPHY OF LAW AND LEGAL THEORY 241, 251 (D ennis Pa tter-son ed., Oxford: Blackwell, 1996).

    10. I have argued elsewhere that H arts discussion of th e minimum conten t of natura l lawis fully consistent with legal positivisms insistence on the separability of law and morality. Seemy IN DEFENSE OF LEGAL POSITIVISM ch. 9 (O xford: Oxford U niversity Press, 1999).

    Throwing Light on the Role of Moral Principles in the Law 127

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    14/29

    would have recommended that we dismiss the opponents positionnot

    because it is false, but because (though true) it is trivial and profoundly

    misleading. It aridly describes a bare logical possibility tha t n ever h as been

    actualized and never will be actualized. Tho ugh the opponents thesis iscorrect in submitting that there is not any logical or conceptual incoher-

    ence in the n otion of a dura ble large-scale society where no legal restraints

    whatsoever are placed on serious misdeeds, the likelihood of the emer-

    gence of such a society is so formidably remote tha t it should be disregard ed

    by anyone con structing a theor y of law or government. While the oppo-

    nen ts thesis is no t strictly wron g, it is wholly misguided in wha t it empha -

    sizes. It highlights a fan ciful state o f af fairs that n ever ha s arisen a nd never

    will arise, and it consequently tends to obscure the fact that that state of

    af fairs will no t obta in un der any minimally plausible set o f circumstances.Now, admittedly, the robust version of Incorpora tionism is no t as outland-

    ishly misleading as the imagina r y opponen ts riposte to H art. Although th e

    sustainability of an unalloyedly Incorporationist regime of law in an y society

    larger th an a han dful of families is prodigiously unlikelynot least because

    the task of law-ascertainmen t is carried out by a governments myriad

    executive o fficials as well as by judicial of ficials11it is no t as close to being

    unimaginab le as is the sustainability of a large-scale society without any legal

    curbs on serious wron gs. H ence, a do ctrine that asserts the possibility of an

    unalloyedly Incorporation ist legal regime within a large-scale society is no tquite as misdirected in its emphasis as is the thesis described in my last

    paragraph . All the same, th e robust version o f Incorporation ism h ighlights

    the prospect of a state of affairs that never has obtained and never will

    obt ain in a ny large-scale society. It conseq uently tends to obscure the im-

    portan t fact that such a state o f a ffairs will no t emerge (in a large-scale

    society) under any credible set of circumstances.

    Thus, while the extreme Incorporationist thesis is trueas I have always

    readily accepted12it is unhelpfully distracting and unilluminating and

    11. At one juncture, Shapiro points out that a robustly Incorpora tionist Rule of Recogn itioncould o btain in a legal system with on ly two judges, b oth of whom are twin sisters, atten d th esame chur ch[,] a nd are like-minded on eth ical issues (Sha piro, Law, 156). As isa ttested by myearlier articles several references to th e possibility of a rob ustly Incorpora tionist Rule of Recog-nition in the legal system of an extremelysmall and h omo geneous society, I have no wish whatso-ever to dispute the truth of Shapiros observation. All the same, his observation is irrelevant tothe sorts of societies on which I am concen trating. With r eference to m edium-scale an d large-scale societies, where multitudes of executive/adm inistrative o fficials as well as judicial officialsare obliga ted and empowered to engage in the activity of law-ascertainmen t, a scenario of a two-judge legal regime (with no executive/administrative officials, apparent ly) is perilously close to

    the Austinian depiction of the sovereign as a single person. Ha rt aptlylabeled the latter depictionas a disastrouslycon fusing piece of mythology (Ha rt, Concept, 110).

    12. Ind eed, as can be gath ered from Matthew H . Kramer, LEGAL THEORY, P OLITICAL THEORY,AND DECONSTRUCTION 12830 (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1991), I am more in-clined th an H art to classify a robu stly Incorpora tionist primitive regime of law as a regime of law.

    In my earlier article on In clusivism and In corpor ationism, the on ly sentence tha t might seemto impugn the truth of the robust Incorpo rationist thesis is in the final paragraph, where Icontend that robust Incorporationism as a jurisprudential position is unsound (Kramer,

    128 MATTHEWH.KRAMER

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    15/29

    needlessly problematic. Its virtues are fully shared and its shortcomings

    avoided by a modera te version of Incorpora tionism. To be sure, a ph iloso-

    pher as nimble as Coleman can man age to d evelop a number of insights by

    defending the robust Incorporationist thesis against various conceptualcha llenges. Neverth eless, those same cha llenges must be parried by moder-

    ate Incorporationism, and indeed the latter doctrine can handle them

    more smooth ly (as will be further argued presently).

    Moreover, a mod est Incorporation ist thesis is peculiarly suitable fo r the

    accomplishment of the purpose which Incorporationism was devised to

    fulfill: viz. , the purpose of fending off some of Dworkins early attacks

    against legal positivism, which were focused on the role of moral principles

    as adjudicative touchstones in hard cases. Coleman expresses bemusement

    over my distinction between robust and moderate Incorporationism, alleg-ing tha t it generate[s] more smoke than light. H e contend s that distin-

    guishing among kinds or categories of cases in which [Incorporationist]

    criteria migh t apply . . . is . . . no t a par ticularly helpful dimension on which

    various rules of recogn ition can be ar rayed, and he asserts tha t my position

    would still fail to answer the objection that motivates [Incorporationism]

    in th e first place (Coleman , Con stra ints, 178 n.17, 183). Yet, because the

    motivating objection to which Coleman adverts is Dworkins observation

    tha t mora l principles are invoked by Anglo-American judges to resolve

    some ha rd casesa fact of Anglo-American ad judication tha t D workinbelieves (or believed) to be incompatible with the positivist model of

    lawmy singling out of modest Incorporationism in contradistinction to

    thoroughgoing Incorporationism is entirely apposite.

    To grasp fully the aptn ess of the modera te Incorporation ist thesis in th is

    context, we should reflect briefly on wha t it claims. Tha t thesis does not

    den y anything af firmed by the robust Incorpora tionist doctrine, but simply

    asserts less. It mainta ins tha t th ere is at least one possible large-scale lega l

    system in which the moral correctness of norms is sufficient for their status

    as legal no rms in some or all hard cases. Because this mod erate thesis doesno t in an y way deny the bolder claim of thoroughgo ing Inco rporationism,

    it does no t make the mistake of suggesting tha t that bo lder claim is false. At

    the same time, it draws atten tion to the precise point of conten tion between

    Dworkin and legal positivists; it asserts no more and no less than what is

    necessary to rebut Dworkins criticism. In other words, it asserts what is

    necessar y to respond effectively to th e crux that gave rise to In corporation -

    ist theories. A thesis focused on hard cases is singularly appropriate for

    overcoming an objection that is focused on hard cases. A more sweeping

    thesis is superfluous. (Furthermore, with regard to m y highlighting o f the

    suprano te 1, at 108). In that sentence, a s should ha ve been clear fro m th e rest of my article, Iwas not using th e term un soun d in its technical philosophical sense. I was not asserting th atthe robust Incorporationist position is derived from false premises or is invalidly derived, andtha t it therefore m ay be false. Instead, I was using u nsound mo re loosely to d enote un illumi-nat ingness and misleadingn ess.

    Throwing Light on the Role of Moral Principles in the Law 129

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    16/29

    distinction between easy cases and hard casesthough not with regard to

    certain oth er featuresmy espousal of modest Incorporation ism manifestly

    runs parallel to Harts discussion of linguistic and normative determinacy

    in the seventh chapter of The Concept of Law. H art too k the view that theexistence of a legal system is consistent with pervasive disagreement in the

    systems penumbra but is inconsistent with such disagreement in the sys-

    tems core. I correspondingly take the view tha t th e existence of an y large-

    scale regime of law is con sistent with of ficials reliance on mora l cor rectness

    as the sufficient cond ition fo r legal validity through out the regimes penum-

    bra , but tha t it is incon sistent with any compa rable reliance throughout the

    regimes core. My view follows from a combination of th e H artian view and

    the general empirical assumption that underlies my championing of mod -

    est Incorporationism.)In short, because the Dworkinian attack that impelled the development

    of In corporation ism was concerned with the role of moral precepts in hard

    cases, it can most pertinently be repelled by a thesis oriented toward that

    role in exactly such cases. O f course, to ma inta in as much is not per se to

    establish that modest Incorporationism can surmount all the conceptual

    hurdles that confront it. Shapiros trenchant challenges to Incorporation-

    ism must be met by a modest version of the doctrine as well as by a

    thoroughgoing version. The rest of this essay will seek to reinforce my

    earlier articles efforts to show that a moderate Incorporationist positioncan indeed meet those challengesnot by refuting them (for they are

    irrefutable), but by defusing them.

    Before we move on to re-encounter Shapiros critiques, a quick caveat

    should be entered. Nothing in this subsection is meant in any way to

    depreciate the importan ce and value of purely conceptual argumenta tion.

    When such argumenta tion is illuminating and fruitfulas it very often is,

    no t least in Colemans and Shapiros workit is clearly preferable to argu-

    mentation that relies in part on empirical assumptions. Indeed, my earlier

    articles defense of Inclusive Legal Positivism was strictly conceptual. Mycomplaint herein is on ly about conceptual theses tha t do n ot shed light on

    any past, present, or future states of af fairs (in societies tha t are not tiny and

    high ly homogeneous). Such th eses are mo re misleading than instructive.

    B. What Goes On in Hard Cases

    In my earlier article I unreservedly acknowledged the correctness of

    Shapiros astute observation that the moral principles validated under anIncorporationist Rule of Recognition do not constitute a ny reasons-for-

    action beyon d those con stituted by the In corporation ist criteria themselves.

    His observation plainly applies to a moderately Incorporationist Rule of

    Recogn ition as much as to a ro bust version . My tack in my earlier article was

    no t to gainsay the sound ness of Sha piros argument, but to remove its sting

    130 MATTHEWH.KRAMER

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    17/29

    when it is invoked against modest Incorporationism. Specifically I con-

    tended that, a lthough incorporated moral precepts cannot furn ish judges

    or citizens with any independen t reasons-for-action (i.e., reasons beyond

    those furnished by an Incorporationist Rule of Recognition itself), thatinability is untro ubling in ha rd cases because those precepts are called upon

    to play an altogether different role therein. Because the hard cases lie

    outside th e d eterminate ambits of the source-based legal n orms, and be-

    cause a mildly Incorporationist Rule of Recognition predetermines the

    correct ways of resolving any disputes that do lie outside those ambits, hard

    cases will no t be decided by reference to legal n orms that serve a s partly

    independent reason s-for-action . Mora l precepts invoked to hand le tho se

    cases are obviously no t such reasons, then, b ut are mean s of specifying the

    requirements ord ained by the Incorporation ist stran d in the Rule of Recog-nition. Though the precepts do not add to what the Rule of Recognition

    deman ds, they enable its dema nd s to be spelled out.

    In my earlier article, I described the function of moral precepts in hard

    cases as that of terminating disputes and achieving closure and re-

    solv[ing] the points at issue.13 The last-men tioned ph rase in particular can

    be faulted fo r a lack of clar ity, because it has led Sha piro to miscon strue my

    argument. H e writes: When a rule is used to resolve a dispute, the rule is

    treated a s a reason to decide the dispute in a ccordance with the rule. To

    resolve disputes, therefore, is to guide evaluative behavior. If my argumentis correct, then moral rules that lack pedigrees cannot resolve disputes

    because these rules cannot motivate a judge to resolve a dispute in a

    manner differently than he might have, had he not appealed to the rule

    (Sha piro, Law, 159). Tho ugh Shapiro s misread ing of my remarks is quite

    und erstan dable, it is indeed a misread ing that impels his retort. My accoun t

    of the invocation of moral principles in hard cases does not attribute to

    them the role of independent bases for reach ing certain decisions in tho se

    cases and for eschewing contrar y decisions. Rather, the principles as formu-

    lated by judges are simply the vehicles through which th e dispute-termina t-ing effects of the Incorporationist strand in the Rule of Recognition

    become discernible and gain expression.

    When moral precepts are add uced in h ard cases within a modestly Incor-

    poration ist legal system, th ey operate in two chief ways. First, they ena ble or

    facilitate the end eavors of judges to figure out what the Rule of Recognition

    requires. As Shapiro states, a judge might appeal to moral principles

    themselves to a id him in applying the rule of recogn ition (Shapiro, Law,

    159 n.65). Of course, th is heuristic function do es not consist in providing

    some new reason s for any particular decisions; all decision-determiningreasons in ha rd cases are provided by the mildly Incorporation ist criterion

    in the Rule of Recognition. The moral principles heuristic function con-

    sists instead in clarifying an d distilling the d eman ds of the aforemention ed

    13. Kramer, supranote 1, at 10102.

    Throwing Light on the Role of Moral Principles in the Law 131

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    18/29

    criterion. While cr ystallizing or concretizing those d emands, the moral

    principles do no t add thereto (o r subtract therefrom). They encapsulate at

    an intermediate level the implications of th e Incorpora tionist instruction in

    the Rule of Recognition, and they thereby supply judges with a cognitivehan dle on that abstract instruction.

    In add ition, the moral precepts cited by the modera tely Incorporation ist

    judges are the means by which they express to citizens and their fellow

    of ficials the req uirements of their Rule of Recognition. Although th at Rule

    of Recognition has already settled the proper resolution of each hard case

    to which th ere is a un iquely correct mora l answer, the invoca tion of a mo ral

    principle enables the judges in such a case to indica te persuasively what the

    already-settled resolution is. By add ucing a moral principle to specify quite

    concretely the deman ds of morality in the con text of a knotty dispute thatis not resolvable through recourse to source-based laws, th e judges signal

    the moral sound ness of their decision and its conseq uent con formity with

    the prevailing standa rds of law-ascertain ment. They reaf firm to citizens the

    moral appropriateness and requisiteness of th eir verdict. They reaffirm to

    their fellow of ficials their compliance with the modera tely Incorporation ist

    Rule of Recognition which makes moral requisiteness the touchstone for

    dea ling with h ard cases.

    Thus, when moral precepts are a pplied to the fa cts of h ard cases within

    a mildly Incorporationist regime, they perform both a heuristic functionand a confirmatory function. Moreover, they are fully genuine norms in

    tha t th ey require certain outcomes and disallow con trar y outcomes. Wha t

    they cannot d o, of courseif they have been chosen correctlyis to req uire

    anything other than wha t is required by the mildly Incorpora tionist Rule of

    Recogn ition itself. For Shapiro , tha t inability is suff icient to disqualify those

    sourceless mora l precepts from being rightly classified as legal norms. He

    adheres to a ten et designa ted a s the Pra ctical Difference Thesis, which h e

    states as follows: Legal rules must in principle be capable of securing

    compliance by making a difference to an agents practical reasoning(Shapiro, Law, 129). Because properly incorporated moral principles

    never lead to conclusions other th an those dictated by the Rule of Recog-

    nition under which the principles have been incorporated, they do not

    satisfy the Practical Difference Thesis. They are therefore on ly ersatz legal

    norms, in Shapiros view.

    Let us note a key ambiguity in the Practical Difference Thesis. Is its

    implicit quantifier universal or plurative? That is, does the thesis assert

    something about alllegal nor ms or only about mostlegal norms? Shapiro

    obviously intend s the thesis to be taken a s a conceptua l claim con taining auniversal quan tifier, whereas I subscribe to it a s a partly conceptual and

    partly empirical claim containing a plurative quantifier. Let us probe his

    argument in favor of the th esis as he con strues it.

    Shapiro conn ects the Practical Difference Thesis to a broad er conception

    of law, which he labels as functiona list (Shapiro, Law, 167-69). H e

    132 MATTHEWH.KRAMER

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    19/29

    correctly remarks tha t Ha rtian legal positivism attributes to law the function

    of guiding cond uct by means of the nor ms which a legal system sets forth

    as authoritative standards of behavior. Shapiro presumes that laws fulfill-

    ment of this function entails the capacity of every legal norm to guideconduct: [A]ll legal rules have, as their function , the guidance of cond uct.

    And because a no rms guidance of conduct involves its making a difference

    to peoples practical reason ingby requiring pa tterns of behavior tha t are

    not necessarily already required by the Rule of Recognition in the legal

    system where the norm is locatedShapiro can conclude that no r ule tha t

    is in principle incapab le of making a practical difference can be a legal rule

    (Shapiro, Law, 168).

    The suspect link in this chain of reason ing is the premise th at the

    accomplishment of laws function entails the capacity of everylegal n ormto guide conduct. We n eed to be to ld why a legal systems performan ce

    of that function excludes the possibility that mostof the systems norms,

    as opposed to allof its norms, are endowed with a guiding capacity. Re-

    sponding to some criticisms largely along these lines from Wilfrid

    Waluchow and Kenneth Himma, Shapiro offers the following argument

    in support of his premise: [I]n the case of legal rules and legal institu-

    tions[,] such an inference [an inference that a part has the function F

    just because the whole has the function F] is sound. For legal rules are

    themeansby whichlegal systems guide conduct. We can say tha t the functionof legal rules is to guide conduct because they have been produced by

    legal institutions in order to guide conduct (Shapiro, Law, 169, empha-

    sis in origina l). The argument in th is quota tion d oes no t clinch the ma tter,

    for the quotations last two sentences are just as ambiguous as the initial

    formulation of the Practical Difference Thesis. Each of those sentences

    can stand up per fectly well even if th e phra se legal rules in each of th em

    is taken to denote mostlegal norms rather than allsuch norms. A legal

    system can admirably carry out its function of laying down authoritative

    directives to steer human conduct into prescribed channels, even if someof its norms do not contribute to that function but instead play only

    heuristic and confirmato ry roles. Shapiro canno t settle the choice between

    a un iversal quan tifier and a plurative quan tifier for h is Pra ctical Difference

    Thesis by adverting to the role which H art attributed to law. An ascription

    of that role to law is consistent with the Practical Difference Thesis under

    either interpretation.

    Indeed, the overall guiding function of law can hardly avail Exclusive

    Legal Positivists such as Shapiro, because the difficult cases in which moral

    principles get invoked as decisive stand ard s are ca ses in which the source-based legal norms do not provide determinate guidan ce. Gaps or con flicts

    or ambiguities in the ar ray of source-based n orms give rise to lacunae in

    the guiding sway of law th at are filled (in some regimes) by officials

    resorting to moral principles. For the Exclusive Legal Positivist, the over-

    coming o f those lacunae does no t in an y way mean tha t the invoked moral

    Throwing Light on the Role of Moral Principles in the Law 133

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    20/29

    principles are legal nor ms. As substitutes for legal norms, the principles fill

    in where the law has run out. H ence, an Exclusive Legal P ositivist such as

    Shapiro, who accepts Harts characterization of laws function, must also

    accept that any particular legal system can and does perform that functionnotwithstanding the occurrence of lacunae in the systems matrix of

    source-based norms. Most disputes that arise in the jurisdiction of each

    system are covered by such a matrix, but some of the disputes fall within

    the lacunae. In other words, when Exclusive Legal P ositivists and mod erate

    Incorporationists endorse H arts function alist conception of law, th ey are

    at one in thinking that a legal regimes guiding role is performed across

    most circumstances but not across all circumstances. Neither the Exclusive

    Legal Positivist nor the mod est In corporation ist believes tha t the guidance

    offered by a legal system through its source-based nor ms is seamless o rcompreh ensive. Each believes that at a ny given juncture th e source-based

    norms omit from their coverage a number of possible sets of circum-

    stan ces. All the same, each believes tha t the guiding fun ction of law can be

    fulfilled an d is fulfilled. H ence, the Exclusivist an d the mod erate In corpo-

    rationist differ only over the question how the moral precepts invoked in

    ha rd cases sho uld be classified. Exclusivists will perceive th ose precepts as

    nonlegal nor ms to which judges appeal when the guidance of legal norms

    (i.e., source-based no rms) has run out. Modest Incorpora tionists will per-

    ceive tho se precepts as non guiding legal no rms tha t are add uced by judgesfor heuristic and confirmatory purposes when the guidance of source-

    based legal norms has run out. That is, the sole issue in controversy is

    whether the moral principles are nonlegal norms or nonguiding legal

    no rms. Such an issue cannot be resolved by reference to th e role of law as

    an institution that establishes source-based stand ards for the purpose of

    steering conduct. After all, the Exclusive Legal Positivist and the moderate

    Incorporationist can agree not only in attributing such a role to law, but

    also on the following points: The source-based standard s do n ot pro vide

    determinate guidance in hard cases; the role of law can be achieved and isach ieved despite the ina bility of th e source-based stand ard s to yield d eter-

    minate guidance in certain circumstances; the moral principles relied

    upon by mildly Incorporationist judges in hard cases perform no more

    than heuristic and confirmatory roles. The only area of disagreement,

    then, is the question whether the nonguiding principles invoked in hard

    cases are legal or non legal. Any dispute over that question cann ot be put

    to an end by recourse to the role of law mentioned just above, because

    neither side to the dispute contests that role.

    If we are to break out of the deadlock just described, we shall have to

    marshal arguments that go beyond a focus on laws basic function. My

    earlier article sough t to present just such an a rgumen t by main tain ing tha t

    the considerations that lead us to acknowledge the status of some custom-

    ar y norms as legal mand ates should lead us also to acknowledge th e status

    134 MATTHEWH.KRAMER

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    21/29

    of incorpora ted mo ral principles as legal norms.14 Tha t complicated line o f

    reasoning will not be recapitulated h ere, because Shapiro does not ad dress

    it at all. Nonetheless, what should be noted in the present con text is that

    tha t line of reasoning has been put for ward in an effort to keep the debatebetween Exclusive Legal Positivists and modest Incorpora tionists from

    amo unting to no more than an exchan ge of rival stipulation s. My argument

    tries to of fer a route for moving beyond the frustrating standof f that would

    ensue from such an exchange.

    Let us close this subsection by pond ering the nature of Shapiros Practical

    Difference Thesis, as perceived by a propon ent o f mod erate Incorporation -

    ism. Construed as a purely conceptual claim, that thesis should be re-

    jectedregardless of whether we deem its implicit quantifier to be universal

    or plurative. Coleman is quite correct to maintain as much. If the schemeof governance in a very small an d stable commun ity achieves considerab le

    regularity in its operations on th e ba sis of a robustly Incorpora tionist Rule

    of Recognition, then the conditions for the existence of a legal system are

    satisfied even though the Practical Difference Thesis is not.

    By contra st, when the Practical Difference Thesis is construed as a partly

    empirical claimwhich is how a modest Incorporationist will generally

    cho ose to construe itit is fully acceptable as long as its implicit qua nt ifier

    is plurative rather than universal. So understood, that thesis submits that

    most legal norms constitute partly independent reasons for citizens andof ficials to beha ve in certa in specified ways. Left open is the possibility that

    some legal norms in this or that system are incapable of constituting such

    reasons (tho ugh they are capable of performing h euristic and confirmatory

    functions); moral precepts are just such norms when invoked under a

    mildly Incorporation ist Rule of Recogn ition in h ard cases where the source-

    based legal standards do not yield determinate guidance. Now, we can

    knowto some degree as an empirical matterthat most of the norms in

    an y large-scale system of law will be pa rtly independen t reasons-for-action

    that are ascertainable as such. Where most of the norms applied by alarge-scale scheme of govern an ce do not form such reasons, the scheme will

    lack the regularity and coordination th at are ind ispensable for the existence

    of a legal regime. Ergo , in a large-scale society where a legal system pre-

    vailsi.e., in just about any such society that is tenable at allmost of the

    auth oritative norms applied by of ficials for the assessmen t o f con duct will

    amo unt to reason s-for-action tha t a re not wholly derivative of the reason s

    furnished by the societys Rule of Recognition itself. Such is the message of

    a plurative and partly empirical version of the Pra ctical Difference Thesis,

    which effectively encapsulates the conceptual an d empirical claims of mod-est Incorporation ism. Tha t thesis reserves a place for no n-source-based

    legal norms, but the place is correctly characterized as the domain of

    exceptionality rath er than th e domain of typicality.

    14. Id. at 103-07.

    Throwing Light on the Role of Moral Principles in the Law 135

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    22/29

    C. Regularity in Irregular Circumstances

    Coleman attributes to me the notion that the officials who run a mildly

    Incorporationist legal system will arrive at decisions in hard cases in acoordinated fashion as if they were applying straightfor ward source-based

    legal nor ms. H e writes: I am unpersuaded by Kramers view tha t mod est

    Incorporationism can sustain a legal practice in hard cases, but not more

    genera lly. Surely if there are lots of ha rd cases, then on Kramers view the

    controversiality of morality ought to underm ine the effo rts of o fficials to

    resolve disputes in a coordinated fashion. Controversy is controversy re-

    gardless of the scope of application. Even a narrow scope of applica-

    tion hard casescan be a big problem, since the narrowness of scope says

    nothing at all about how often controversy can arise (Coleman, Con-straints, 183 n.24). Had my earlier article put forward the view Coleman

    ascribes to it, it would ind eed have been vulnerab le to his strictures. In fact,

    however, I sought to emphasize therein that the likelihood of intractable

    disagreements amo ng the officials about the appropriate outcomes in hard

    cases is over whelmingly high . Their shared adheren ce to a mildly Incorpo -

    ration ist Rule of Recogn ition does no t prevent th em from diverging ma rk-

    edly in their selection and application of moral principles for dispatching

    difficult disputes.15 Shapiro acknowledges that I took account of the high

    probability of judicial d isunity, but h e maintains tha t my effort to d eal withit was unsuccessful. He queries whether o fficials can abide by the In corpo-

    rationist criterion in a moderately Incorporationist Rule of Recognition,

    given that the officials decisions in hard cases will be markedly at variance

    with one an oth er, an d given th at un iquely cor rect answers will be available

    in some hard cases under the Incorporationist criterion. In a hard case

    where a uniq uely correct answer is available an d where on ly some officials

    ar rive a t tha t answer, there is no relevan t convergence-of-behavior to the

    extent that is necessary for the existence of a conventional norm. Because

    this pattern o f nonconvergence will obtain in a large majority of hard cases,the Incorporationist criterion in a moderately Incorporationist Rule of

    Recognition cann ot exist as such. After all, if that criterion d oes materialize,

    it materializes as a conventional norm that underlies and presupposes the

    convergent behavior of officials in hard cases. Because that convergent

    behavior is missing, however, the Incorporationist criterion must itself be

    nonexistent. Shapiro presses this point forcefully:

    Rules of recognition are con ventiona l rules, an d conventional r ules must be

    practiced. It is not enough that people try to conform to such ruleswhatmatters is tha t they do as they are req uired to do. If most people who en tered

    churches neglected to take off their hats, but instead mistakenly removed

    their shoes, then th ere would be n o convention in th at community requiring

    the removal of ha ts in church . Hen ce, if Kramer lacks confidence that judges

    15. Id. at 102.

    136 MATTHEWH.KRAMER

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    23/29

    will no rmally conform to th e rule of recogn ition in hard cases, then it cann ot

    be said that a rule of recognition exists that regulates these hard cases.

    (Shapiro, Law, 160.)

    Though Shapiros argument is powerful, it is not irrebuttable. One con-

    sideration tha t part ly defuses his argument is tha t in some hard cases there

    will not be any uniquely correct answers. In each hard case for which no

    determination is uniquely correct, all the officials who operate a mildly

    Incorporationist regime will be acting in accordance with the Incorpora-

    tionist criterion in their Rule o f Recognition so long as their favored

    decisions and justifications are within a range of acceptable decisions and

    justifications. Within that range there will be ample room for clashing

    verdicts. Hence, in hard cases that lack uniquely correct solutions, the

    intractability of disagreement among officials is fully consistent with an

    adherence by every official to an Incorporationist criterion for handling

    such cases. Manifold divergences amon g o fficials concerning the extension

    of such a criterion are compatible with a general consensus on the crite-

    rions intension.

    More significant in the present context is a way of coping with the crux

    posed when a uniquely correct resolution of a difficult case is available

    under a moderately Incorporationist Rule of Recognition. In any such set

    of circumstances, only those officials who arrive at the uniquely correct

    verdict are acting in strict confo rmity with the Incorpora tionist criterion in

    their Rule of Recogn ition . Should we accord ingly conclude tha t there is no

    convergence on that criterion by the o ther officials? And should we thus

    conclude ( with Shapiro) that there is no sufficiently convergent behavior

    to ground the existence of the Incorporationist criterion as a conventional

    norm?

    In reply to th ese q uestions, we should have recourse to a d istinction tha t

    has been highlighted by Coleman in virtually all of his writings on legal

    positivism: the distinction between disagreements over content and dis-

    agreements over application .16 In a hard case where one outcome is

    uniq uely correct und er a moderately Incorporation ist Rule of Recognition,

    the o fficials who plump in goo d fa ith for oth er outcomes are engaged in a

    controversy over the application(rather than th e basic nature) of the Incor-

    porationist criterion in their Rule of Recognition. Even though they are

    wrong and their fellow officials are correct about the application of that

    criterion , they are ind eed differing with their fellow officials over matters of

    application rather than over the matter o f the criterions basic tenor. Their

    misguided implementa tion of that criterion does no t amoun t to a rejection

    of it an d a n embrace of some other law-ascertaining benchmark. They are

    16. Colemans work in this area has been valuable, but it do es not squarely address theprecise problem that I shall be pondering: the question whether, in a hard case where oneoutcome is uniquely correct, officials in a mildly Incorporationist regime who opt for otheroutcomes are conforming to the Incorporationist criterion in their Rule of Recognition.

    Throwing Light on the Role of Moral Principles in the Law 137

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    24/29

    at one with their fellow of ficials in upho lding an Incorpora tionist criterion

    in th eir Rule of Recognition, th ough they are less astute than their fellow

    of ficials in understand ing what tha t criterion requires in part icular settings.

    Two potential rejoinders to the argument in the last paragraph must bedeflected. First, in line with some o f the remarks in Dworkins early assaults

    on legal positivism,17 a critic might o bject tha t my argument presupposes a

    consensus among mildly Incorporationist officials on some formulation of

    the Incorpora tionist criterion in their Rule of Recognition . Yet, the critic

    would retort, a construa l of the officials interaction a long th ese lines would

    implausibly portra y their differences over the Incorporation ist criterion as

    disputes over borderline applications of terms. Second , a critic might simply

    point out that some of the officials in the envisaged legal system are

    misapplying the Incorporationist criterion, perhaps even in every hard casewhere a uniq uely correct answer is available. H ow, then, can we rightly say

    tha t those officials are ad hering to that criterion?

    These two o bjections can be parried by way of the same genera l observa-

    tion. On the one hand, the objections should hardly be dismissed out of

    hand. As the first of them rightly suggests, a depiction of the officials

    dishar mony as a set o f quarrels over borderline uses of words is far from

    compelling. Although a widely accepted formulation of the Incorporation-

    ist criterion in a Rule of Recognition may well crystallize within the h ighly

    reflective and deliberative processes of jural decision-making, one cann otoften credibly maintain that the clashing verdicts of officials in hard cases

    are products of divergent d efinitions of the words in any such formulation .

    Likewise, the secon d of the posited ripostes is warran ted in submitting tha t,

    if strict compliance in the form of correct implementation is an essential

    earmark of adherence to a conventional norm, then the officials who

    misapply an Incorpora tionist criterion in some hard cases are no t adhering

    to that criterion. If there were no alternative basis for deeming them to be

    in compliance with that criterionthat is, if the only sort of compliance

    were strict compliance involving correct a pplication sthen the second ofthe po sited rejoind ers abo ve would be q uite telling in regard to hard cases

    with un iquely correct outcomes.

    On the other hand, fortunately, both of the aforementioned rejoinders

    can be countered by a focus on the patterns of officials arguments and

    justifications. Contrary to what the first objection maintains, the existence

    of the Incorporationist criterion in a modestly Incorporationist Rule of

    Recogn ition d oes not d epend on the emergence of a formulation to which

    all officials subscribe. Instead, it depends on a practice of justification in

    which the Incorpora tionist criterion is immanent as a shared presupposi-tion ( and also as an effect). When the o fficials in a moderately Incorpora-

    tionist regime present th eir decisions in ha rd cases, they seek to explain and

    justify those decisions by reference to considerations that are identifiably

    17. Rona ld Dworkin, supranote 8, at 56, 6263.

    138 MATTHEWH.KRAMER

  • 7/28/2019 m Kramer

    25/29

    moral. Un derlying this practice of moral justification is the Incorporation ist

    criterion in their Rule of Recognition. Though the officials might give

    expression to that criterion in a formulation on which they concur, they

    might cleave to it simply as a tacit preconception that informs their d eci-sions and their articulated rationales. In either event, we can usually best

    und erstan d the disaccord ance in hard cases (within a mildly Inco rpora tion-

    ist legal system) as d isagreements over the implications a nd rankings of

    moral values rath er than over the meanings of words.

    Con trar y to what is con tend ed by the second of the potential objections,

    strict compliance with the Incorporationist criterion in the Rule of Recog-

    nitionviz., compliance that involves correct applications of the concepts

    in th at criterion is no t th e on ly species of compliance. In ha rd cases with

    uniq uely correct outcom es, of ficials who ar rive at th e wrong decisions cannonetheless be upholding their Incorporationist criterion for dealing with

    such cases, so long as they endeavor plausibly to explain tho se decisions by

    reference to pertinent reasons. In this con text, the phrase pertinent rea-

    sons deno tes any consideration s that are identifiable as ethically signifi-

    cant factors that should be taken into account by someon e who is passing

    moral judgment on th e problems which th e officials have to ad dress. Inso-

    far as the off icials credibly tie their verdicts to such factors, they are enga g-

    ing in the process of mora l assessmen t an d moral justification which their

    Incorporationist criterion requires of them. Although they are advocatingerroneous outcomes, they are thereby misapplying their Incorpora tionist

    criterion rather than shifting to some other touchstone. Their upholding

    of that criterion is evidenced by the fact that they appeal to germane

    reasons for their decisions. In other words, they acknowledge the general

    tenor of th e Incorpo rationist strand in their Rule of Recognition by com-

    mending their determinations on the sorts of grounds which that strand

    makes relevant. The fact that t