Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific...

30

Transcript of Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific...

Page 1: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great
Page 2: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

The Logic of Scientif icDiscovery

‘One of the most important philosophical works of ourcentury.’

Richard Wollheim, The Observer

‘Wonderfully exhilarating.’Naomi Bliven, New Yorker

Page 3: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great
Page 4: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

Karl

PopperThe Logic of Scientif icDiscovery

London and New York

Page 5: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

Logik der Forschung first published 1935by Verlag von Julius Springer, Vienna, Austria

First English edition published 1959by Hutchinson & Co.First published by Routledge 1992

First published in Routledge Classics 2002by Routledge11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001

Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group

© 1959, 1968, 1972, 1980 Karl Popper© 1999, 2002 The Estate of Karl Popper

All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprintedor reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic,mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafterinvented, including photocopying and recording, or inany information storage or retrieval system, withoutpermission in writing from the publishers.

British Library Cataloguing in Publication DataA catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library

Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication DataA catalogue record for this book has been requested

ISBN 0–415–27843–0 (hbk)ISBN 0–415–27844–9 (pbk)

This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005.

“To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’scollection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.”

ISBN 0-203-99462-0 Master e-book ISBN

Page 6: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

TO MY WIFEwho is responsible for the revival of this book

Page 7: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great
Page 8: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

CONTENTS

Translators’ Note xiiPreface to the First Edition, 1934 xvPreface to the First English Edition, 1959 xviii

PART I Introduction to the Logic of Science

1 A Survey of Some Fundamental Problems 31 The Problem of Induction2 Elimination of Psychologism3 Deductive Testing of Theories4 The Problem of Demarcation5 Experience as a Method6 Falsifiability as a Criterion of Demarcation7 The Problem of the ‘Empirical Basis’8 Scientific Objectivity and Subjective Conviction

2 On the Problem of a Theory of Scientific Method 279 Why Methodological Decisions are Indispensable

10 The Naturalistic Approach to the Theory of Method11 Methodological Rules as Conventions

Page 9: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

PART II Some Structural Components of a Theory of Experience

3 Theories 3712 Causality, Explanation, and the Deduction of Predictions13 Strict and Numerical Universality14 Universal Concepts and Individual Concepts15 Strictly Universal and Existential Statements16 Theoretical Systems17 Some Possibilities of Interpreting a System of Axioms18 Levels of Universality. The Modus Tollens

4 Falsifiability 5719 Some Conventionalist Objections20 Methodological Rules21 Logical Investigation of Falsifiability22 Falsifiability and Falsification23 Occurrences and Events24 Falsifiability and Consistency

5 The Problem of the Empirical Basis 7425 Perceptual Experiences as Empirical Basis:

Psychologism26 Concerning the So-Called ‘Protocol Sentences’27 The Objectivity of the Empirical Basis28 Basic Statements29 The Relativity of Basic Statements. Resolution of

Fries’s Trilemma30 Theory and Experiment

6 Degrees of Testability 9531 A Programme and an Illustration32 How are Classes of Potential Falsifiers to be Compared?33 Degrees of Falsifiability Compared by Means of the

Subclass Relation34 The Structure of the Subclass Relation.

Logical Probability35 Empirical Content, Entailment, and Degrees

of Falsifiability36 Levels of Universality and Degrees of Precision

contentsviii

Page 10: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

37 Logical Ranges. Notes on the Theory of Measurement38 Degrees of Testability Compared by Reference

to Dimensions39 The Dimension of a Set of Curves40 Two Ways of Reducing the Number of Dimensions

of a Set of Curves

7 Simplicity 12141 Elimination of the Aesthetic and the Pragmatic

Concepts of Simplicity42 The Methodological Problem of Simplicity43 Simplicity and Degree of Falsifiability44 Geometrical Shape and Functional Form45 The Simplicity of Euclidean Geometry46 Conventionalism and the Concept of Simplicity

8 Probability 13347 The Problem of Interpreting Probability Statements48 Subjective and Objective Interpretations49 The Fundamental Problem of the Theory of Chance50 The Frequency Theory of von Mises51 Plan for a New Theory of Probability52 Relative Frequency within a Finite Class53 Selection, Independence, Insensitiveness, Irrelevance54 Finite Sequences. Ordinal Selection and

Neighbourhood Selection55 n-Freedom in Finite Sequences56 Sequences of Segments. The First Form of the

Binomial Formula57 Infinite Sequences. Hypothetical Estimates

of Frequency58 An Examination of the Axiom of Randomness59 Chance-Like Sequences. Objective Probability60 Bernoulli’s Problem61 The Law of Great Numbers (Bernoulli’s Theorem)62 Bernoulli’s Theorem and the Interpretation of

Probability Statements63 Bernoulli’s Theorem and the Problem of Convergence

contents ix

Page 11: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

64 Elimination of the Axiom of Convergence. Solutionof the ‘Fundamental Problem of the Theory of Chance’

65 The Problem of Decidability66 The Logical Form of Probability Statements67 A Probabilistic System of Speculative Metaphysics68 Probability in Physics69 Law and Chance70 The Deducibility of Macro Laws from Micro Laws71 Formally Singular Probability Statements72 The Theory of Range

9 Some Observations on Quantum Theory 20973 Heisenberg’s Programme and the

Uncertainty Relations74 A Brief Outline of the Statistical Interpretation of

Quantum Theory75 A Statistical Re-Interpretation of the

Uncertainty Formulae76 An Attempt to Eliminate Metaphysical Elements by

Inverting Heisenberg’s Programme; with Applications77 Decisive Experiments78 Indeterminist Metaphysics

10 Corroboration, or How a Theory Stands up to Tests 24879 Concerning the So-Called Verification of Hypotheses80 The Probability of a Hypothesis and the Probability

of Events: Criticism of Probability Logic81 Inductive Logic and Probability Logic82 The Positive Theory of Corroboration: How a

Hypothesis may ‘Prove its Mettle’83 Corroborability, Testability, and Logical Probability84 Remarks Concerning the Use of the Concepts ‘True’

and ‘Corroborated’85 The Path of Science

APPENDICES

i Definition of the Dimension of a Theory 283ii The General Calculus of Frequency in Finite Classes 286

contentsx

Page 12: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

iii Derivation of the First Form of the BinomialFormula 290

iv A Method of Constructing Models of RandomSequences 293

v Examination of an Objection. The Two-SlitExperiment 297

vi Concerning a Non-Predictive Procedure ofMeasuring 301

vii Remarks Concerning an Imaginary Experiment 305

NEW APPENDICES

*i Two Notes on Induction and Demarcation,1933–1934 312

*ii A Note on Probability, 1938 319*iii On the Heuristic Use of the Classical Definition

of Probability 325*iv The Formal Theory of Probability 329*v Derivations in the Formal Theory of Probability 356*vi On Objective Disorder or Randomness 369

*vii Zero Probability and the Fine-Structure ofProbability and of Content 374

*viii Content, Simplicity, and Dimension 392*ix Corroboration, the Weight of Evidence, and

Statistical Tests 402*x Universals, Dispositions, and Natural or

Physical Necessity 440*xi On the Use and Misuse of Imaginary

Experiments, Especially in Quantum Theory 464*xii The Experiment of Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen.

A Letter from Albert Einstein, 1935 481

INDICES, compiled by Dr. J. Agassi

Name Index 489Subject Index 494

contents xi

Page 13: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

TRANSLATORS’ NOTE

The Logic of Scientific Discovery is a translation of Logik der Forschung, publishedin Vienna in the autumn of 1934 (with the imprint ‘1935’). Thetranslation was prepared by the author, with the assistance of Dr. JuliusFreed and Lan Freed.

The original text of 1934 has been left unchanged for the purpose ofthe translation. As usual, the translation is a little longer than the ori-ginal. Words and phrases for which no equivalent exists had to beparaphrased. Sentences had to be broken up and rearranged—the moreso as the text to be translated was highly condensed: it had been dras-tically cut several times to comply with the publisher’s requirements.Yet the author decided against augmenting the text, and also againstrestoring cut passages [except for a few words indicated by squarebrackets or footnotes].

In order to bring the book up to date, the author has added newappendices and new footnotes. Some of these merely expand the text,or correct it; but others explain where the author has changed hismind, or how he would now reframe his arguments.

All new additions—new appendices and new footnotes—aremarked by starred number; and where old footnotes have beenexpanded, the expansion is also marked by a star (unless it consistsonly of a reference to the English edition of a book originally quotedfrom a German edition).

Page 14: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

In these new starred additions, references will be found to a sequelto this volume, entitled Postscript to the Logic of Scientific Discovery (in threevolumes). Though they complement each other, they are independent.

It should also be mentioned that the numbering of the chapters ofthe present volume has been changed. In the original, they were num-bered i to ii (part i), and i to viii (part ii). They are now numberedthrough from 1 to 10.

translators’ note xiii

Page 15: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

Hypotheses are nets: only he who casts will catch.Novalis

Page 16: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1934

The hint that man has, after all, solved his most stubbornproblems . . . is small solace to the philosophic connoisseur;for what he cannot help fearing is that philosophy will neverget so far as to pose a genuine problem.

M. Schlick (1930)

I for my part hold the very opposite opinion, and I assert thatwhenever a dispute has raged for any length of time, espe-cially in philosophy, there was, at the bottom of it, never aproblem about mere words, but always a genuine problemabout things.

I. Kant (1786)

A scientist engaged in a piece of research, say in physics, can attack hisproblem straight away. He can go at once to the heart of the matter: tothe heart, that is, of an organized structure. For a structure of scientificdoctrines is already in existence; and with it, a generally acceptedproblem-situation. This is why he may leave it to others to fit hiscontribution into the framework of scientific knowledge.

The philosopher finds himself in a different position. He does notface an organized structure, but rather something resembling a heap ofruins (though perhaps with treasure buried underneath). He cannot

Page 17: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

appeal to the fact that there is a generally accepted problem-situation;for that there is no such thing is perhaps the one fact which is generallyaccepted. Indeed it has by now become a recurrent question inphilosophical circles whether philosophy will ever get so far as to posea genuine problem.

Nevertheless there are still some who do believe that philosophy canpose genuine problems about things, and who therefore still hope toget these problems discussed, and to have done with those depressingmonologues which now pass for philosophical discussions. And if bychance they find themselves unable to accept any of the existing creeds,all they can do is to begin afresh from the beginning.

vienna, Autumn 1934.

preface, 1934xvi

Page 18: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

There is nothing more necessary to the man of science than its history,and the logic of discovery . . . : the way error is detected, the use ofhypothesis, of imagination, the mode of testing.

Lord Acton

Page 19: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

PREFACE TO THEFIRST ENGLISH EDITION, 1959

In my old preface of 1934 I tried to explain—too briefly, I am afraid—my attitude towards the then prevailing situation in philosophy, andespecially towards linguistic philosophy and the school of languageanalysts of those days. In this new preface I intend to explain myattitude towards the present situation, and towards the two mainschools of language analysts of today. Now as then, language analystsare important to me; not only as opponents, but also as allies, in so faras they seem to be almost the only philosophers left who keep alivesome of the traditions of rational philosophy.

Language analysts believe that there are no genuine philosophicalproblems, or that the problems of philosophy, if any, are problems oflinguistic usage, or of the meaning of words. I, however, believe thatthere is at least one philosophical problem in which all thinking menare interested. It is the problem of cosmology: the problem of understandingthe world—including ourselves, and our knowledge, as part of the world. All science iscosmology, I believe, and for me the interest of philosophy, no lessthan of science, lies solely in the contributions which it has made to it.For me, at any rate, both philosophy and science would lose all theirattraction if they were to give up that pursuit. Admittedly, understand-ing the functions of our language is an important part of it; butexplaining away our problems as merely linguistic ‘puzzles’ is not.

Page 20: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

Language analysts regard themselves as practitioners of a methodpeculiar to philosophy. I think they are wrong, for I believe in thefollowing thesis.

Philosophers are as free as others to use any method in searching fortruth. There is no method peculiar to philosophy.

A second thesis which I should like to propound here is this.The central problem of epistemology has always been and still is the

problem of the growth of knowledge. And the growth of knowledge can bestudied best by studying the growth of scientific knowledge.

I do not think that the study of the growth of knowledge can bereplaced by the study of linguistic usages, or of language systems.

And yet, I am quite ready to admit that there is a method whichmight be described as ‘the one method of philosophy’. But it is notcharacteristic of philosophy alone; it is, rather, the one method of allrational discussion, and therefore of the natural sciences as well as of phil-osophy. The method I have in mind is that of stating one’s problemclearly and of examining its various proposed solutions critically.

I have italicized the words ‘rational discussion’ and ‘critically’ in order tostress that I equate the rational attitude and the critical attitude. Thepoint is that, whenever we propose a solution to a problem, we oughtto try as hard as we can to overthrow our solution, rather than defendit. Few of us, unfortunately, practise this precept; but other people,fortunately, will supply the criticism for us if we fail to supply itourselves. Yet criticism will be fruitful only if we state our problem asclearly as we can and put our solution in a sufficiently definite form—aform in which it can be critically discussed.

I do not deny that something which may be called ‘logical analysis’can play a role in this process of clarifying and scrutinizing our prob-lems and our proposed solutions; and I do not assert that the methodsof ‘logical analysis’ or ‘language analysis’ are necessarily useless. Mythesis is, rather, that these methods are far from being the only oneswhich a philosopher can use with advantage, and that they are in noway characteristic of philosophy. They are no more characteristic ofphilosophy than of any other scientific or rational inquiry.

It may perhaps be asked what other ‘methods’ a philosopher mightuse. My answer is that though there are any number of different

preface, 1959 xix

Page 21: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

‘methods’, I am really not interested in enumerating them. I do notcare what methods a philosopher (or anybody else) may use so long ashe has an interesting problem, and so long as he is sincerely trying tosolve it.

Among the many methods which he may use—always depending,of course, on the problem in hand—one method seems to me worthmentioning. It is a variant of the (at present unfashionable) historicalmethod. It consists, simply, in trying to find out what other peoplehave thought and said about the problem in hand: why they had to faceit: how they formulated it: how they tried to solve it. This seems to meimportant because it is part of the general method of rational discus-sion. If we ignore what other people are thinking, or have thought inthe past, then rational discussion must come to an end, though each ofus may go on happily talking to himself. Some philosophers have madea virtue of talking to themselves; perhaps because they felt that therewas nobody else worth talking to. I fear that the practice of philo-sophizing on this somewhat exalted plane may be a symptom of thedecline of rational discussion. No doubt God talks mainly to Himselfbecause He has no one worth talking to. But a philosopher shouldknow that he is no more godlike than any other man.

There are several interesting historical reasons for the widespreadbelief that what is called ‘linguistic analysis’ is the true method ofphilosophy.

One such reason is the correct belief that logical paradoxes, like that ofthe liar (‘I am now lying’) or those found by Russell, Richard, andothers, need the method of linguistic analysis for their solution, withits famous distinction between meaningful (or ‘well-formed’) andmeaningless linguistic expressions. This correct belief is then com-bined with the mistaken belief that the traditional problems ofphilosophy arise from the attempt to solve philosophical paradoxes whosestructure is analogous to that of logical paradoxes, so that the distinc-tion between meaningful and meaningless talk must be of central im-portance for philosophy also. That this belief is mistaken can be shownvery easily. It can be shown, in fact, by logical analysis. For this revealsthat a certain characteristic kind of reflexivity or self-reference whichis present in all logical paradoxes is absent from all the so-calledphilosophical paradoxes—even from Kant’s antinomies.

preface, 1959xx

Page 22: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

perception or knowledge or belief by the analysis of the phrases ‘I see’or ‘I perceive’, or ‘I know’, ‘I believe’, ‘I hold that it is probable’; orperhaps by that of the word ‘perhaps’.

Now to those who favour this approach to the theory of knowledge Ishould reply as follows. Although I agree that scientific knowledge ismerely a development of ordinary knowledge or common-sense know-ledge, I contend that the most important and most exciting problemsof epistemology must remain completely invisible to those who con-fine themselves to analysing ordinary or common-sense knowledge orits formulation in ordinary language.

I wish to refer here only to one example of the kind of problem Ihave in mind: the problem of the growth of our knowledge. A littlereflection will show that most problems connected with the growth ofour knowledge must necessarily transcend any study which is confinedto common-sense knowledge as opposed to scientific knowledge. Forthe most important way in which common-sense knowledge grows is,precisely, by turning into scientific knowledge. Moreover, it seemsclear that the growth of scientific knowledge is the most important andinteresting case of the growth of knowledge.

It should be remembered, in this context, that almost all the prob-lems of traditional epistemology are connected with the problem ofthe growth of knowledge. I am inclined to say even more: from Plato toDescartes, Leibniz, Kant, Duhem and Poincaré; and from Bacon,Hobbes, and Locke, to Hume, Mill, and Russell, the theory ofknowledge was inspired by the hope that it would enable us not only toknow more about knowledge, but also to contribute to the advanceof knowledge—of scientific knowledge, that is. (The only possibleexception to this rule among the great philosophers I can think of isBerkeley.) Most of the philosophers who believe that the characteristicmethod of philosophy is the analysis of ordinary language seem to havelost this admirable optimism which once inspired the rationalist trad-ition. Their attitude, it seems, has become one of resignation, if notdespair. They not only leave the advancement of knowledge to thescientists: they even define philosophy in such a way that it becomes,by definition, incapable of making any contribution to our knowledgeof the world. The self-mutilation which this so surprisingly persuasivedefinition requires does not appeal to me. There is no such thing as an

preface, 1959xxii

Page 23: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

The main reason for exalting the method of linguistic analysis, how-ever, seems to have been the following. It was felt that the so-called ‘newway of ideas’ of Locke, Berkeley, and Hume, that is to say the psycho-logical or rather pseudo-psychological method of analysing our ideasand their origin in our senses, should be replaced by a more ‘objective’and a less genetic method. It was felt that we should analyse words andtheir meanings or usages rather than ‘ideas’ or ‘conceptions’ or‘notions’; that we should analyse propositions or statements or sen-tences rather than ‘thoughts’ or ‘beliefs’ or ‘judgments’. I readily admitthat this replacement of Locke’s ‘new way of ideas’ by a ‘new way ofwords’ was an advance, and one that was urgently needed.

It is understandable that those who once saw in the ‘new way ofideas’ the one true method of philosophy may thus have turned to thebelief that the ‘new way of words’ is the one true method of philo-sophy. From this challenging belief I strongly dissent. But I will makeonly two critical comments on it. First, the ‘new way of ideas’ shouldnever have been taken for the main method of philosophy, let alone forits one true method. Even Locke introduced it merely as a methodof dealing with certain preliminaries (preliminaries for a science ofethics); and it was used by both Berkeley and Hume chiefly as aweapon for harrying their opponents. Their own interpretation of theworld—the world of things and of men—which they were anxious toimpart to us was never based upon this method. Berkeley did not basehis religious views on it, nor Hume his political theories (though hebased his determinism on it).

But my gravest objection to the belief that either the ‘new way ofideas’ or the ‘new way of words’ is the main method ofepistemology—or perhaps even of philosophy—is this.

The problem of epistemology may be approached from two sides:(1) as the problem of ordinary or common-sense knowledge, or (2) as theproblem of scientific knowledge. Those philosophers who favour the firstapproach think, rightly, that scientific knowledge can only be an exten-sion of common-sense knowledge, and they also think, wrongly, thatcommon-sense knowledge is the easier of the two to analyse. In thisway these philosophers come to replace the ‘new way of ideas’ by ananalysis of ordinary language—the language in which common-senseknowledge is formulated. They replace the analysis of vision or

preface, 1959 xxi

Page 24: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

essence of philosophy, to be distilled and condensed into a definition.A definition of the word ‘philosophy’ can only have the character of aconvention, of an agreement; and I, at any rate, see no merit in thearbitrary proposal to define the word ‘philosophy’ in a way that maywell prevent a student of philosophy from trying to contribute, quaphilosopher, to the advancement of our knowledge of the world.

Also, it seems to me paradoxical that philosophers who take pride inspecializing in the study of ordinary language nevertheless believe thatthey know enough about cosmology to be sure that it is in essence sodifferent from philosophy that philosophy cannot make any contribu-tion to it. And indeed they are mistaken. For it is a fact that purelymetaphysical ideas—and therefore philosophical ideas—have been ofthe greatest importance for cosmology. From Thales to Einstein, fromancient atomism to Descartes’s speculation about matter, from thespeculations of Gilbert and Newton and Leibniz and Boscovic aboutforces to those of Faraday and Einstein about fields of forces,metaphysical ideas have shown the way.

Such are, in brief, my reasons for believing that even within theprovince of epistemology, the first approach mentioned above—thatis to say, the analysis of knowledge by way of an analysis of ordinarylanguage—is too narrow, and that it is bound to miss the mostinteresting problems.

Yet I am far from agreeing with all those philosophers who favourthat other approach to epistemology—the approach by way of ananalysis of scientific knowledge. In order to explain more easily where Idisagree and where I agree, I am going to sub-divide the philosopherswho adopt this second approach into two groups—the goats and thesheep, as it were.

The first group consists of those whose aim is to study ‘the languageof science’, and whose chosen philosophical method is the construc-tion of artificial model languages; that is to say, the construction ofwhat they believe to be models of ‘the language of science’.

The second group does not confine itself to the study of the languageof science, or any other language, and it has no such chosen philo-sophical method. Its members philosophize in many different ways,because they have many different problems which they want to solve;and any method is welcome to them if they think that it may help them

preface, 1959 xxiii

Page 25: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

to see their problems more clearly, or to hit upon a solution, howevertentative.

I turn first to those whose chosen method is the construction ofartificial models of the language of science. Historically, they too taketheir departure from the ‘new way of ideas’. They too replace the(pseudo-) psychological method of the old ‘new way’ by linguisticanalysis. But perhaps owing to the spiritual consolations offered by thehope for knowledge that is ‘exact’ or ‘precise’ or ‘formalized’, thechosen object of their linguistic analysis is ‘the language of science’rather than ordinary language. Yet unfortunately there seems to be nosuch thing as ‘the language of science’. It therefore becomes necessaryfor them to construct one. However, the construction of a full-scaleworking model of a language of science—one in which we couldoperate a real science such as physics—turns out a little difficult inpractice; and for this reason we find them engaged in the constructionof intricate working models in miniature—of vast systems of minutegadgets.

In my opinion, this group of philosophers gets the worst of bothworlds. By their method of constructing miniature model languagesthey miss the most exciting problems of the theory of knowledge—those connected with its advancement. For the intricacy of the outfitbears no relation to its effectiveness, and practically no scientific theoryof any interest can be expressed in these vast systems of minutiae.These model languages have no bearing on either science or commonsense.

Indeed, the models of ‘the language of science’ which these philo-sophers construct have nothing to do with the language of modernscience. This may be seen from the following remarks which apply tothe three most widely known model languages. (They are referred to innotes 13 and 15 to appendix *vii, and in note *2 to section 38.) Thefirst of these model languages lacks even the means of expressing iden-tity. As a consequence, it cannot express an equation: it does not con-tain even the most primitive arithmetic. The second model languageworks only as long as we do not add to it the means of provingthe usual theorems of arithmetic—for example, Euclid’s theoremthat there is no greatest prime number, or even the principle thatevery number has a successor. In the third model language—the most

preface, 1959xxiv

Page 26: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

elaborate and famous of all—mathematics can again not be formulated;and, what is still more interesting, there are no measurable propertiesexpressible in it. For these reasons, and for many others, the threemodel languages are too poor to be of use to any science. They are also,of course, essentially poorer than ordinary languages, including eventhe most primitive ones.

The limitations mentioned were imposed upon the model languagessimply because otherwise the solutions offered by the authors to theirproblems would not have worked. This fact can be easily proved, and ithas been partly proved by the authors themselves. Nevertheless, they allseem to claim two things: (a) that their methods are, in some sense orother, capable of solving problems of the theory of scientific know-ledge, or in other words, that they are applicable to science (while infact they are applicable with any precision only to discourse of anextremely primitive kind), and (b) that their methods are ‘exact’ or‘precise’. Clearly these two claims cannot both be upheld.

Thus the method of constructing artificial model languages is incap-able of tackling the problems of the growth of our knowledge; and itis even less able to do so than the method of analysing ordinary lan-guages, simply because these model languages are poorer than ordin-ary languages. It is a result of their poverty that they yield only the mostcrude and the most misleading model of the growth of knowledge—the model of an accumulating heap of observation statements.

I now turn to the last group of epistemologists—those who do notpledge themselves in advance to any philosophical method, and whomake use, in epistemology, of the analysis of scientific problems, theor-ies, and procedures, and, most important, of scientific discussions. Thisgroup can claim, among its ancestors, almost all the great philosophersof the West. (It can claim even the ancestry of Berkeley despite the factthat he was, in an important sense, an enemy of the very idea ofrational scientific knowledge, and that he feared its advance.) Its mostimportant representatives during the last two hundred years were Kant,Whewell, Mill, Peirce, Duhem, Poincaré, Meyerson, Russell, and—atleast in some of his phases—Whitehead. Most of those who belong tothis group would agree that scientific knowledge is the result of thegrowth of common-sense knowledge. But all of them discovered thatscientific knowledge can be more easily studied than common-sense

preface, 1959 xxv

Page 27: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

knowledge. For it is common-sense knowledge writ large, as it were. Its veryproblems are enlargements of the problems of common-sense know-ledge. For example, it replaces the Humean problem of ‘reasonablebelief ’ by the problem of the reasons for accepting or rejecting scien-tific theories. And since we possess many detailed reports of the discus-sions pertaining to the problem whether a theory such as Newton’s orMaxwell’s or Einstein’s should be accepted or rejected, we may look atthese discussions as if through a microscope that allows us to studyin detail, and objectively, some of the more important problems of‘reasonable belief’.

This approach to the problems of epistemology gets rid (as do theother two mentioned) of the pseudo-psychological or ‘subjective’method of the new way of ideas (a method still used by Kant). Itsuggests that we analyse scientific discussions, and also scientific prob-lem situations. And so it can help us to understand the history ofscientific thought.

I have tried to show that the most important of the traditional prob-lems of epistemology—those connected with the growth of knowledge—transcend the two standard methods of linguistic analysis and requirethe analysis of scientific knowledge. But the last thing I wish to do,however, is to advocate another dogma. Even the analysis of science—the ‘philosophy of science’—is threatening to become a fashion, aspecialism. yet philosophers should not be specialists. For myself, I aminterested in science and in philosophy only because I want to learnsomething about the riddle of the world in which we live, and theriddle of man’s knowledge of that world. And I believe that only arevival of interest in these riddles can save the sciences and philosophyfrom narrow specialization and from an obscurantist faith in theexpert’s special skill, and in his personal knowledge and authority;a faith that so well fits our ‘post-rationalist’ and ‘post-critical’age, proudly dedicated to the destruction of the tradition of rationalphilosophy, and of rational thought itself.

Penn, Buckinghamshire, Spring 1958.

preface, 1959xxvi

Page 28: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS, 1960 and 1968

I wish to thank Mr. David G. Nicholls for communicating to me theadmirable passage, now printed on page xvii, which he discoveredamong the Acton Manuscripts in the Library of Cambridge University(Add. MSS 5011:266). The reprint of the book gives me the welcomeopportunity to quote this passage.

Summer 1959

In this second English edition four short Addenda have been added to theappendices. Minor mistakes have been corrected, and I have made a fewlinguistic improvements. Misprints have been corrected that werebrought to my notice by Imre Lakatos, David Miller, and AlanMusgrave. They also suggested many new entries in the Index ofSubjects. I am very grateful to them.

My greatest debt is to Paul Bernays who, shortly after this book hadappeared in English, checked through my axiomatization of the prob-ability calculus, especially the new appendix *v. I value his approvalmore highly than I can express in words. It does not, of course, absolveme from bearing the sole responsibility for any mistake I may havemade.

November 1967 K. R. P.

preface, 1959 xxvii

Page 29: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great
Page 30: Karl Popper: The Logic of Scientific Discoverypreview.kingborn.net/79000/f02b9529eca249e7a8a2d2085077bb09.pdf · Objective Probability 60 Bernoulli’s Problem 61 The Law of Great

Part IIntroduction to theLogic of Science