Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

27
Copyright © 2015 Active Education peped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio ns Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God And its relation to his ethical thought

Transcript of Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Page 2: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

In a nutshell

• The 'argument' is found in the Critique of Pure Reason and the Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals

• It is often described as a priori, inductive as it needs no experience.

• It is difficult to divorce this from Kant's general system of ethics.

• Ought implies can

• The moral world must be achievable • But it isn't in this life• Therefore the moral world must be a future one (eschatological)• There must be a distribution of happiness to the extent we are worthy to be happy• This needs a wise regent to arbitrate. (i.e. God)

• God is, therefore, a necessary postulate of pure, practical reason• God gives morality its telos but does not invent it.

Page 3: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

Types of statements and reasoning• Before we can understand Kant’s moral

argument, we must understand his view of reason:

• Kant seems to have a high and optimistic view of human reason. Indeed, it is axiomatic for his philosophical and ethical arguments that humans are able to discover truth using their reason.

• His cosmology places humans with one foot in the “phenomenal” realm – inhabited by animals, driven by desire, and one in the “noumenal” realm – inhabited by God and angels, driven by reason. Thus, we are "amphibious" (as Prof. Douglas Hedley writes)

• Kant identifies different kinds of propositions:

Phenomenal Realm –animals -driven by instinct

Noumenal Realm –God/Angels -

driven by reason

humans

Page 4: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

a posteriori and a priori

• an a posteriori proposition is one whose justification relies on experience

• e.g. “There are many poets who have never versified, and there are many

versifiers who shall never answer to the name of ‘poet.’” (Sir Philip Sidney)

• an a priori proposition is one whose justification does not rely on experience…

• e.g. There are 3 angles in a triangle

You, sir, are no poet!

Page 5: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

Analytic and synthetic statements• Analytic = The subject concepts contain the predicate* concept.

• E,g, the concept of a bachelor contains the notion of being unmarried [unless you’re talking about a Bachelor of Arts]

• Thus true or false by definition “all bodies are extended” (i.e. occupy space).

• Synthetic = The subject concepts do not contain the predicate concept: • the concept of a rich bachelor does not contain notion of his desiring a wife . [cf Pride and

Prejudice!]• Thus true or false empirically e.g. “All bodies are heavy.”

• Question: “all unicorns are white” – analytic or synthetic?

*A predicate is something that is being attributed to a subject, such as the sharpness of a knife or the wisdom of the fool. NB Ayer seems to use the terms Analytic & Synthetic slightly differently in the 20th Century

Page 6: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

Kant’s 4 types of propositions

1. a priori analytic2. a priori synthetic3. a posteriori analytic4. a posteriori synthetic

a) It is a truth universally acknowledged that a single man in possession of a good fortune must be in want of a wife. b) The First World War preceded the Second World Warc) 7 + 5 = 12d) Some teachers are patronising

Match the types to

examples:

Page 7: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

Kant’s 4 types of propositions

1. a priori analytic2. a priori synthetic3. a posteriori analytic4. a posteriori synthetic

d) Some teachers are patronising

Which doesn’t work?

a) It is a truth universally acknowledged that a single man in possession of a good fortune must be in want of a wife.

b) The First World War preceded the Second World War

c) 7 + 5 = 12

For Kant, a posteriori analytic is a non-sense.

Page 8: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

a priori synthetic

• In an a priori synthetic proposition, new information is learned that is not contained in

statements themselves.

• In Kant’s example of 5+7=12, the concept of 12 is not contained, separately, within the

concept of 5 or 7, yet we do not need experience of 5 and 7 things to work out that

5+7=12

• Kantian ethics is a priori, synthetic (without experience, but the predicate is not

contained within the subject)

• E.g. “Lying is unethical” – the predicate unethical is not contained within the concept of

lying, but we do not have to experience lying to work out that it is unethical.

Page 10: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

What may I hope?

• “All hope concerns happiness.” • This is "the satisfaction of all our inclinations"

• Humans can hope to be happy to the extent they are worthy of happiness.

• Kant then identifies three laws we tend to follow:• The law prudence, the law of nature and the moral law

Page 11: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

The law of prudence • Doing something in order to achieve some end “from the motive of

happiness.”• E.g I will revise because it might help me pass my exam

• Sounds like Bentham!

• Kant recognises that we are often driven by this law.

• His example: we sometimes decide not to lie because we realise that we might not be trusted in the future if found out – it would not benefit us in the future and thus is not prudent.

• However this is stupid because we cannot be certain what will make us happy. "[Man] is not capable of determining with complete certainty, in accordance with any principle, what will make him truly happy, because omniscience would be required for that."

• This is not moral !

Page 12: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

Law of nature

• The naturalistic fallacy derives an ought from an is or a can.• i.e. From a state of affairs is drawn the false conclusion that this state of

affairs should be.

• E.g. 'Humans seek pleasure. Therefore humans ought to seek pleasure.''

• Just because you can does not mean you should!

• "I can cheat in my exam" does not mean you ought to.

• This is not moral!Politician’s Logic: Something must be done!This is somethingTherefore I should do it!

- Sir Humphrey Appleby, Yes Minister

Page 13: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

The moral law…

• “…commands how we should behave in order even to be worthy of happiness.”

• Is entirely based on obligation

• This is the opposite of the natural law –

• I should do x, therefore x is good.

• E.g. I ought to revise, therefore revision is moral.

• One is obligated to obey the moral law regardless of one's feelings

• Because…

Page 14: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

The good will

• Is the only consistently good thing. • i.e. The will to do what one must do is always good.

"The good will is good not through what it effects or accomplishes, not through its efficacy for attaining any intended end, but only through its willing, i.e., good in itself" (Groundwork, Preface)

• Wanting to help others is not consistently good (helping a criminal to evade justice)

• Compare to Aquinas' idea of synderesis and the desire to do good and avoid evil

Page 15: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

Difference with three laws

Law of prudence Law of nature Moral law

I should not cheat on my partner because I might get found out.

I feel like cheating on my partner so I should

I should be faithful to my partner

I should kill this armed bandit before he kills me

I must not lie

I could steal this unicycle and get away on it

Add to the table with further examples

Page 16: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

Imperfect and holy wills

• Because our wills are imperfect, there is no necessary relationship between moral truths/laws and our will.

• Nothing compels us to moral action from the fact of the moral truths.

• E.g. We might reason that being kind to people is good but that doesn't compel us to be kind to people

• Thus we need an imperative to direct our wills.• E.g "Be kind to people"

• However a holy will, such as God's, is wholly in accordance with moral truths and therefore needs no imperatives.

• God is not a moral agent

Moral truths

Page 17: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

Ought implies can

• If we are to be obliged to do something, it must be possible for us to do.

• We cannot be obliged to fly out of a window since cannot do it!

• I ought to do the washing up• It must be possible for me to do so.

• However, it is not always possible to be moral in this world

For since [moral precepts] command that these actions ought to happen, they must also be able to happen, and there must therefore be possible a special kind of systematic unity, namely the moral.

Page 18: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

The moral world• Is intelligible

• Is where everyone is moral

• Must be possible

• Isn't possible here.

• Therefore must be a world that is future to us

• It “really can and should have its influence on the sensible world.”

• Presumably this links to Kant's notion of the "kingdom of ends" which he says, in the Groundwork is possible as "every rational being must act as if it were through its maxims always a legislative member" of/in.

I call the world as it would be if it were in conformity with all moral laws …a moral world

Page 19: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

Self-rewarding morality

• Kant suggests that, in the moral world, “freedom, partly moved and partly restricted by moral laws would itself be the cause of the general happiness.”

• Rational beings would be the “authors of their own enduring welfare” as well as that of others.

• However, this “rests on the condition that everyone do what he should.”

• This clearly hasn’t happened yet!

When everyone autonomously acts according to the moral law,

they will be happy

Page 20: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

Summum bonum – the highest good

• “I call the idea of such an intelligence, in which the morally most perfect will, combined with the highest blessedness, is the cause of all happiness in the world, insofar as it stands in exact relation with morality, the ideal of the highest good.”

• This highest good is the end, or aim of all morality then – its telos.

• Again, this goes back to Kant’s idea of the moral world.

Page 21: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

The necessary postulation

i.e. We must postulate the existence of God and an eschatological moral world if we are to be obligated to do anything and if there is to be a distribution of happiness to the extent that we are worthy of happiness.

Although the senses do not present us with anything except a world of appearances, we must assume the moral world to be a consequences of our conduct in the sensible world; and since the latter does not offer such a connection to us, we must assume the former to be a world that is future for us. Thus God and a future life are two presuppositions that are not to be separated from the obligation that pure reason imposes on us in accordance with principle of that very same reason.”

Page 22: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

God – the wise regent • In order for happiness to be “distributed precisely in

accordance with morality” it must be done so by a “wise author and regent.”

• A (weak) analogy might be that of a teacher distributing grades to students based on their performance in a test.

• Everyone regards moral laws as commands• Disobeying these carries a threat• Obeying them carries a promise.• “This, however, they could not do if they did not lie in a necessary

being, as the highest good, which alone can make possible such a purposive unity.”

• i.e. God gives the moral law its purpose

The very-much-not-wise-Prince Regent in Blackadder III

Page 23: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

Nature of God

• In order for morality to achieve its unified end, the wise regent must be a single, rational, perfect will – or else there would be disunity

• "for how, with different wills should we find complete unity of ends?"• This solves one of the problems Hume identified with the teleological and

cosmological arguments in his question, why not more than one designer (or efficient cause).

• Omnipotent – "so that nature and its relation to morality and nature may be subject to it"

• Omniscient – "that it may know the most secret springs of our sentiments and their moral worth" – .i.e. so the goodness of our wills can be judged

• Omnipresent – so it can be near to effect justice

• Eternal – so it may never fail.

Page 24: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

If there were no God…• Morality would not achieve its end

• “Without a God and a world that is now not visible to us but is hoped for, the majestic ideas of morality are, to be sure, objects of approbation and admiration, but not incentives."

• “Thus happiness in exact proportion with the morality of rational beings, through which they are worthy of it, alone constitutes the highest good."

Page 25: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

Common misconceptions with the moral argument

• “Kant argues we should act morally to be worthy of happiness.”• NO! We do not act morally to gain brownie points – to be worthy of happiness.

This is not moral and goes against the deontological nature of his ethical theory.• Indeed, by acting to make yourself worthy of happiness you would not be

worthy of happiness!• That it takes the form of a deductive argument

• God is a necessary postulate. He must be assumed but cannot be proven. • Remember Kant rejects the cosmological argument (mostly for its basis on the

ontological argument). He also rejects natural theology. • Speculative reason cannot bring us to God.

• “God determines what the moral law is.” • NO! (see the next slide)

Page 26: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

Kant vs Euthyphro• Kant clearly rejects the horn of the dilemma that states things are good

because God commands them.

• He also says that, having arrived at the conclusion that there must be a God, we do not forget the process of moral reasoning and revert back to some sort of divine command theory.

• If we merely followed divine commands, morality would be heteronomous, not autonomous.

• Remember one of the problems in the original Euthyphro dialogue was that in a polytheistic system the gods disagree. Poseidon hates Odysseus but Athene loves him. Thus why what is pious cannot be merely what is beloved by the gods. But, for Kant there is only one God.

We will not regard things to be obligatory because they are divine commands but rather we will regard them to be divine

commands because we are internally obligated to them.

“Are things pious because they are loved by the gods, or do the gods love them because they are pious?” -Socrates to Euthyphro in Plato’s Euthyphro

Page 27: Kant's Moral Argument for the existence of God

Copyright © 2015 Active Educationpeped.org/philosophicalinvestigatio

ns

A Caveat• Having arrived at the necessary postulation of God, we cannot

then start from God and work backwards – in some sort of Divine Command Theory.

• “Now when practical reason has attained this high point, namely the concept of a single original being as the highest good, it must not undertake to start out from this concept and derive the moral laws themselves from it.”

• It was “these [moral] laws alone whose inner practical necessity led us to the presupposition of a self-sufficient cause or a wise world-regent in order to give effect to these laws.”