Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

download Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

of 14

Transcript of Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    1/14

    This article was downloaded by: [Professor Jim Parry]On: 27 July 2012, At: 09:57Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registeredoffice: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Sport in Society: Cultures, Commerce,

    Media, PoliticsPublication details, including instructions for authors and

    subscription information:

    http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/fcss20

    The power of sport in peacemaking and

    peacekeepingJim Parry

    a

    aFaculty of Physical Education and Sport, Charles University inPrague, Czech Republic

    Version of record first published: 27 Jul 2012

    To cite this article:Jim Parry (2012): The power of sport in peacemaking and peacekeeping, Sport

    in Society: Cultures, Commerce, Media, Politics, DOI:10.1080/17430437.2012.708280

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17430437.2012.708280

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

    This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Anysubstantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing,

    systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.

    The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representationthat the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of anyinstructions, formulae, and drug doses should be independently verified with primarysources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings,demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly orindirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.

    http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/fcss20http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17430437.2012.708280http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/fcss20
  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    2/14

    The power of sport in peacemaking and peacekeeping

    Jim Parry*

    Faculty of Physical Education and Sport, Charles University in Prague, Czech Republic

    This paper argues that sport is not about conflict but competition; not about violencebut controlled aggression; neither is it amoral and value-free but is itself a moralenterprise. The paper provides an analysis of the internal values and the internal logicof sport, which combine to make peace via their isomorphism with politicalliberalism, especially the liberal idea of the contract to contest, and its emphasis onequality, respect, mutuality and other human rights values.It is not only just sportspopularity, but also this peacemaking capacity of sport, which informs its peacekeeping

    potential.

    Introduction

    This paper provides an analysis of the internal values and the internal logic of sport, which

    combine to make peace via their isomorphism with political liberalism, especially the

    liberal idea of the contract to contest, and its emphasis on equality, respect, mutuality and

    other human rights values. It is this peacemaking capacity of sport that informs its

    peacekeeping potential. In doing so, I will be taking a contrary view to those who think

    that sport itself is a form of violent conflict, and so is antithetical to peace promotion; and

    those who think that sport has no (intrinsic) values. So, to begin with, we must clear theground by identifying and rectifying three important mistakes, all expressed in the

    previous sentence, which have led to confusion and obstructed our vision of the nature of

    sport.

    Three important mistakes

    Conflict and competition

    The first mistake is the failure to distinguish between conflict and competition. Kvalsund

    draws attention to what he sees as the dangers of using sport for peace-building purposes.

    He says:

    Sport, in its traditional form, is not a conflict preventative instrument. On the contrary, thenature of sport is exactly the opposite: a physical contest between people or teams withdifferent goals.1

    To begin with, this description of sport is contentious. Contestants do not have different

    goals (if this means aims). Because of the rule-structures of sport, we all have the same

    aims otherwise we could not compete. Of course, I am trying to score at this end, and

    you at that end but we both are trying to score under the same rules. The important point

    here is that Kvalsunds misleading definition leads him to confuse competition with

    ISSN 1743-0437 print/ISSN 1743-0445 online

    q 2012 Taylor & Francis

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17430437.2012.708280

    http://www.tandfonline.com

    *Email: [email protected]

    Sport in Society

    iFirst article, 2012, 113

    y

    y

    y

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17430437.2012.708280http://www.tandfonline.com/http://www.tandfonline.com/http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17430437.2012.708280
  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    3/14

    conflict and they are very different, as I explain below. Furthermore, Kvalsund believes

    that we shall need highly trained operatives in the field to make good the moral

    shortcomings of traditional sport.

    On this account of sport, its very nature provides two massive problems for

    peacekeepers: they take the risk of pouring oil on the flames of conflict, by imitating wargames, and they must accept the huge expense of compensatory provision. This leaves it

    totally unexplained as to why international agencies would think to employ such a flawed

    and inappropriate instrument to the task of peace building. Why choose sport, when its

    nature, according to Kvalsund, is exactly the opposite to the task? Why choose sport,

    when it therefore requires such a level of externally provided resources to mitigate its

    shortcomings? The answer, of course, is that those agencies understand that sporting

    competition is something quite different from conflict.

    The historical transition from conflict to sporting competition may be illustrated with

    the example of the mythical origins of the Olympic Games. The myth of Pelops, one of the

    many myths that seek to explain the origin of the Olympic Games, tells the story of the fall

    of Oenomaus, King of Pisa, who challenged all suitors for his daughter Hippodamea to a

    chariot race. During the race, he would kill each of his adversaries and then place their

    heads among his trophies. Naturally, this discouraged young men from seeking his

    daughters hand, until the arrival of Pelops. He was both fortunate, because Hippodamea

    fell in love with him at first sight, and also clever, because he realized what was going on.

    He conspired with Oenomaus charioteer, Myrtilus, and during the race managed to throw

    Oenomaus from his chariot to his death. Pelops won both Hippodamea and the kingdom,

    but he killed Myrtilus for his treason. To appease the Gods for his murderous wrongdoing,

    so the myth goes, Pelops established the Olympic Games.2

    The myth of Pelops echoes down to the twentieth century, when George Orwell

    described modern sport as war minus the shooting,3

    and Chris Chataway, an Olympicathlete, co-authored a book calledWar Without Weapons.4 The earlier form of contest was

    that of mortal combat, in which the triumph of the victor meant the death of the adversary.

    In the Olympic Games, however, contest took on the nobler form of rule-governed and

    disciplined athletic competition. The lesson of the myth is that the chariot race between

    Pelops and Oenomaus was to be the last deadly incident in the sacred site of Olympia. The

    propensity for murder was civilised and became the drive for victory on the athletic field.

    This shift from primitive mortal combat to fair and peaceful competition constitutes the

    starting point of the Olympic Games.

    Now, we do not have to believe in the myth to be able to appreciate its point: sport is

    not war. Even in boxing, which seems to permit violence, it is only limited and carefullycircumscribed assaults that are permitted. So, for example, a boxer cannot be hit when

    down, or under the belt, or with a rabbit-punch, or between rounds. He cannot be kicked or

    head butted or elbowed, or hit with weighted gloves or set upon by more than one

    opponent. Such considerations indicate the distinctions between boxing and street-

    fighting. The crucial difference is that boxing is a rule-governed contest, and so has certain

    values built into it. Boxing is a competition but not unarmed conflict, never mind

    armed mortal combat.

    But there is a further feature of rule-governed competition, such as in sport: the

    constitutive rules of the sport prescribe modes of cooperation without which the activity

    cannot proceed. And good competition arises out of the relative equality of participants.

    That is to say: sport is not to be characterized as a conflict to establish superiority. The

    foundational values of competitive sport include cooperation and equality, which provide

    the context for competitive activity.

    2 J. Parry

    y

    y

    y

  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    4/14

    Oft-quoted examples of people fighting over sport (such as hooligans outside the

    stadium, or armies on the battlefield) are irrelevant to the above points. People fight over

    love and religion, too but the fact that love (or religion, or sport) can be the occasionfor

    conflict tells us nothing about the intrinsic character of love (or religion, or sport).

    Violence and aggression

    The second mistake is the failure to distinguish between violence and aggression. For

    example, in a recent article on sport, peacekeeping and the prevention of violent conflict,

    Schwery and Eggenberger-Argote write:

    . . . aggression is defined as behavior which aims to injure or harm the opponent. There is adistinction between hostile and instrumental aggression: the former primarily aims at injuringthe opponent, whereas the latter type serves in achieving a sporting goal (e.g. winning points).Different studies have demonstrated that sports activity may very well lead to a channeling ofaggression and that there is a negative correlation between the amount of training and the

    tendency to use violence.5

    Here, aggression is confusingly defined as aiming to injure or harm, which is surely false.

    I can be aggressive without seeking to harm. Then, the distinction between hostile and

    instrumental aggression seems to concede this point, suggesting that instrumental

    aggression does not seek harm. But this is false, too, for I either may or may not aim to

    harm someone whilst achieving my sporting goal. Finally, the notion of violence belatedly

    enters the picture from nowhere, without explanation or definition.

    A simple and much clearer distinction might go as follows: aggression involves

    forceful assertion in achieving ones ends, while violence involves the intention to harm or

    injure.6 Thus, it is quite possible to be aggressive without being violent. A player can be

    both forceful and vigorous without seeking to injure or harm anyone. Violence, however,is centrally to do with intentional harm or injury to others, as well as attempts to harm,

    recklessness as to harm, and negligence. All team sports recognize this simple distinction,

    and so have developed rules against violence but not (of course) against aggression. Most

    team sports just are exercises in controlled aggression.

    Take the example of boxing again, which seems to license violence. Certainly, it

    permits aggressive assaults and attempts to hurt. But hurt is not harm. If the boxer aims to

    hurt but not to cause lasting harm or injury, then he is not being violent in the sense that

    warfare is. A further distinction will help us here, between violent acts and acts of

    violence.7 Any action (e.g. killing or kissing someone) can be done more or less violently.

    So boxing, along with most sports, is violent in the sense that it consists of many violentacts i.e. actions performed violently (vigorously). However, an act of violence is one

    that intends harm or injury, whether or not it is actually performed violently (and there are

    many ways of doing harm gently). Boxing as a sport, while employing violent actions,

    should not permit acts of violence it should not be about trying to, or having to, put the

    opponent in hospital in order to win. (This is the moral objection to some forms of

    gladiatorial boxing, such as prize-fighting.8)

    Nevertheless, it might well be objected that what is wrong with competitive sport is

    that it encourages aggression and seeing the other as an opponent, an enemy. However,

    I would rather suggest that aggression in sport presents opportunities for moral education

    and moral development. When playing sport we exercise our potential for aggression, and

    we may also be tempted by the attractions of violence in pursuit of our aims. I have argued

    elsewhere9 that sport and games can function as laboratories for value experiments, in

    which we are put in the position of having to act, time and time again, sometimes in haste,

    Sport in Society 3

    y

    y

    y

  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    5/14

    under pressure or provocation, either to prevent something or to achieve something, under

    a structure of rules.10

    I believe that the impetus and opportunity for values education here is tremendous. The

    questions are: how do we come to terms with our own behaviour and dispositions,

    motivations and propensities? Is there a route from the potentially risky confrontation thatsport sometimes is, to the development of a self with greater moral resolution? And, more

    generally, is there a possibility for peace and the non-violent conduct of human affairs?

    As Nissiotis said:

    [T]his is the ethical challenge that faces humanity: how to harness the creative and motivatingforces of aggression into the service of humanity. . . . Sport in Olympic practice is one of themost powerful events transforming aggressiveness to competition as emulation. Sports lifemoves on the demarcation line between aggressiveness and violence. It is a risky affair . . .Citius-altius-fortius is a dangerous enterprise on the threshold of power as aggression,violence and domination. But this is, precisely, the immense value of Olympic sports: theychallenge people to react, to pass the test of power. . . 11

    So the claim is that the competitive sports situation challenges individuals to develop anduse their power and aggressiveness; but not, finally, to use this power to control and

    subjugate the other. Sport may produce more assertive and aggressive people, but less

    violent people, as it acts in society as an agent of moral change.

    Intrinsic value

    The third mistake is to think that, because sport can be used in the service of different

    values, it has no values of its own. For example, Sugden flatly asserts: . . . it is my

    considered view that in and of itself sport is of no intrinsic value.12 Instead, he thinks, the

    values are inserted into it by contextual social forces. However, consider these differentclaims:

    (i) sport may be used instrumentally in the service of different values;

    (ii) sport may or may not be played morally;

    (iii) sport is without values of its own (without intrinsic value).

    My view is that neither (i) nor (ii), even if true, entails (iii). I think that there is something

    special about sport in virtue of which it is an excellent tool for peace.

    The moral that these writers wish to draw is that it is all in the method it ishow we

    teach sport that is important, not what we teach. Now, of course method is extremely

    important, but its not everything. If methods were all, and sport had no intrinsic value,why are not those methods being employed in basket-weaving for peace, instead of

    football? Now, Im not against basket-weaving, which could be very useful, but I think

    that sport is more so and not simply because of its popularity (see below), but because of

    its ethical basis. In fact, its very popularity is also to be explained with reference to its

    intrinsically moral nature.

    This is a very old argument. Bailey13 argued against the traditional view that games

    provide a secure avenue to value education that games are in themselves character-

    building. His view that it is possible to play games effectively either morally or not is

    surely incontrovertible see (ii) above. Aspins14 counter-arguments that the constitutive

    rules of games enshrine moral values, and that games are collaborative enterprises which

    ipso facto entail that sport offers opportunities for learning about values seem equally

    sound see (iii) above. It seems to me that everyone is right here since (ii) does not

    entail (iii). Games are, in part, constructed out of values, but this does not guarantee that

    4 J. Parry

    y

    y

    y

  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    6/14

    they will be played morally. So I am with Meakin:15 games provide opportunitiesfor the

    presentation of values. But they are only capable of presenting these opportunities because

    they themselves have intrinsic values.

    Why use sport?

    So sport is not about conflict but competition; not about violence but controlled

    aggression; neither is it amoral and value-free but is itself a moral enterprise. Only for

    those who think differently (those who make one of the above three mistakes) does the

    question arise: why would sport be used? If sport has bad values (violence and conflict) or

    if it has no values of its own, why is it that peace activists seek to use sport (and not

    something else) in the service of their aims?

    An unsatisfactory answer (which is often given) might be that sport is popular

    people like it. However, people also like drugs (with a 30% increase in opiate and cocaine

    use in the last 10 years) and gambling (with a massive increase in sports-related gambling),

    but such popularity is not necessarily a good thing. Secondly, this makes it sound asthough we could just as well use some other medium, such as art, film, dance, chess, hula-

    hooping, or Pokemon-collecting so long as it was popular enough. So a larger claim gets

    made, such as that of Kvalsund, who asserts: Sport is indisputably the most popular

    leisure activity in the world . . . .16

    However, it is not at all clear how this claim might be validated. For a start, it is an

    empirical claim that would require investigation, and I have never seen any such evidence

    offered. But, more importantly, it would require an operational definition of sport, which

    would doubtless be highly contentious (e.g. the Council of Europe definition,17 which is

    simply hopeless). If we have to play the guessing game, my own hypothesis would be that

    The Arts would beat sport in the popularity stakes. Again, the problem of definitionarises, but if we think of poem, play, story, film, book, dance in all its forms, music and

    song, painting and the visual arts, sculpture and the plastic arts, photography, etc., my bet

    would be that more people in the world (well, probably everyone who ever lived) has

    engaged in (or been touched by) the arts but not quite so many in and by sport. If popularity

    was the driver, we should see a similar movement The Arts for Peace and Development. I

    can see many virtues in such a movement, especially with regard to inter-cultural

    understanding, but I do not think the Arts could be anywhere near as successful as sport,

    and this is not because of popularity but because of the kind of thing sport is. Arts tend to

    be culturally specific (hence their utility for cross-cultural understanding), but modern

    sports tend to be less so. Despite their often local origins, they tend to be universalisable.

    This is one of the features which makes them modern sports.18

    And, anyway, some kind of popularity contest is not a good indicator of the

    appropriateness of sport to the task of peacekeeping. Of course, the more popular the better,

    since prior familiarity may well assist introduction and dissemination. So popularity is

    useful but it cannot be ajustification. It does not explain why sport is popular, and why it can

    be so effective in carrying peace-worthy meanings and potentials. We need a better account

    of sport, which will explain its nature, its potential social roles and its popularity.

    Fair play and the logic of sport

    The moral concept of fair playFair play is fundamental to the whole enterprise of sport and to an understanding of sport

    as a social practice. It is partly a moral and partly a logical notion referring to a complex set

    Sport in Society 5

    y

    y

    y

  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    7/14

    of features emerging from principled engagement in competitive sporting activity, and

    three related moral meanings are often distinguished as follows:

    (i) Fair play is primarily a virtue of rule-adherence, which is a duty upon all contestants

    to abide by the rules of the competition; since, by their participation, they are deemed

    to have entered into a contract to contest. This is partly a moral notion, but it is alsothe basis of the logical character of fair play (see Fair Play as a Logical

    Requirement Section).

    (ii) Fair play may also include a commitment to contesting in the spirit of sport, such as

    may lead to supererogatory actions (i.e. good actions over and above those strictly

    required by the rules).

    (iii) Fair play may also sometimes refer to a general attitude towards sport (and even life

    itself) involving respect for others, modesty in victory, serenity in defeat and

    generosity aimed at creating warm and lasting human relations.19

    Competitive sport and inclusive goods

    Although there is perhaps a distinction to be drawn between recreative and competitive

    sport, it is the latter with which we are here concerned, and its defining feature has often

    been seen as raising problems of value. It has been argued that since competitive games are

    necessarily competitive, they are merely ways of beating other people and are therefore

    centrally to do with the morally dubious demonstration of superiority over others.

    However, it seems to me that although competitive games are ways of testing ones

    abilities against anothers they are notmerelythat. While it is true that competitive games

    are contests, which entails competition with a view to establishing a winner and a loser

    (i.e. superiority in respect of the games required abilities), this does not entail that we

    have to have winning as our overriding concern. Rather, it is possible to play to win, whilevaluing above all, for example, the opportunity to exercise speed, strength, determination

    and skill. The inescapably competitive nature of the contest does not impose upon us a

    win at all costs attitude, nor a superiorist mentality.

    The criticism seems to be that the nature of competitive sport commits us to the

    priority of exclusive goods if I win the competition, no one else can. But this is simply

    not true as a full account of what sport is. There are many inclusive goods in competitive

    sports, in which we need to cooperate to produce mutual outcomes. For example, unless

    we are mutually striving (both trying our best to win) it is difficult to produce a good

    contest, which is what we both want.

    The nature and value of a good contest

    Fraleigh20 approaches this issue via an analysis of the logical requirements for a good

    contest.

    First, there is a presupposition of equality of opportunity to contest (equality under the

    rules), without which the game could not allow the expression of those characteristic skills

    and abilities called into play by the rules. Relative ability in regard to just those skills and

    abilities can only be demonstrated when all other variables are strictly controlled, so as to

    permit equality of opportunity to contest. Second, no contest could exist without the

    opponent, which would seem to require at least the minimum respect due to a facilitator

    to one whose own level of performance is a major contributor to the very possibilities for

    excellence and satisfaction open to oneself in that category of endeavour chosen by both.

    Third, although it is clearly possible to break the rules, to do so alters the conditions of the

    6 J. Parry

    y

    y

    y

  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    8/14

    contest, so that a range of abilities not specified by the rules comes into play. A good

    contest will maintain the framework which secures the integrity of the contest, and this

    requires rules adherence and fair play. Fourth, a knowledge of relative abilities is also a

    necessary outcome, and this might be seen as superiorist. But Reddiford21 reminds us that

    you win some, you lose some; and so to make the game the occasion for marking upsuperiorities and inferiorities is a short-term and self-defeating attitude. We play to

    produce an outcome favourable to ourselves, of course, but we do not allow the actual

    outcome to be of persisting importance. Humility and generosity are at least as likely an

    accompaniment to a demonstration of ones relative abilities as overweening pride and

    conceit.

    I would add, fifth, that in games there is a simple right and wrong, easily enforceable

    by a clearly identified authority. At the same time, there is some possibility of differing

    interpretation and judgement. In playing games, we learn how to follow explicit rules, how

    to bend them and evade them, and how to operate within a system of penalties and

    consequences, both official and unofficial. Games are laboratories for value experiments.

    We are put in the position of having to act, time and time again, sometimes in haste, under

    pressure or provocation, either to prevent something or to achieve something, under a

    structure of rules.

    So, such an analysis presents us with a clear set of values which are either presupposed

    by, or are necessary outcomes of, the good contest. This seems to me a clear

    demonstration of the moral basis of sport.

    Fair play as a logical requirement

    However, it often goes unnoticed that the primary nature of fair play in sport is not as a

    moral requirement as rule-adherence, acknowledgement of the spirit of sport, or tryingto be a fair-minded person in general. Rather, its main significance is as a logically

    necessary feature of successful engagement.

    We have already seen, in Fraleighs account, how difficult it is to state what sport is,

    without relying on moral notions. Sport is institutionalized (suggesting some lawful

    authority), it is a contest (suggesting a contract to contest), it is rule-governed (entailing

    equality andobligation) and it requires cooperative co-facilitators (which suggest mutual

    respect). Such an account may begin to indicate the logico-moral basis of sport and thus

    suggest arguments that may be raised against cheating or other rule-breaking. For we may

    ask how cheating relates to the practice of sport; and whether one can have a successful

    sports practice in which cheatingregularlyoccurs. Obviously, the answer depends on thekindandlevelof cheating involved but the primary wrong in (say) doping or unlawful

    violence lies in simple rule-breaking. This is because the rules function as a kind of pre-

    competition agreement which specifies both an athletes eligibility to compete and also his

    rights, duties and responsibilities under the agreed rules. What is wrong with doping, for

    example, is the secretive attempt to evade or subvert such a contract to contest, which

    describes the right of athletes to compete against non-dopers, describes the duties and

    responsibilities of athletes not to dope and pre-determines a dopers non-eligibility to

    compete.

    To freely choose to be accepted into a community of practice entails an obligation to

    duly respect the rules of the practice (or institution) as its lawful authority. To subvert such

    a contract to contest threatens the moral basis of sport, jeopardizes the integrity of the

    sporting community and erodes public support and trust. It is because it is impossible to

    get a game of football going, or keep a competition going, unless the participants have

    Sport in Society 7

    y

    y

    y

  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    9/14

    some grasp on these notions, that sport is an excellent vehicle for the introduction and

    maintenance of moral and political values. Freedom, responsibility, equality, justice and

    respect all these are to be found in the rule-based practices of sport.

    Liberalism and sport isomorphism

    And this is not just an accident. It is often noticed that modern sport emerged at a

    particular historic juncture, in the heyday of political liberalism in Europe in the last third

    of the nineteenth century. This is the basis of the leftist critique of sport as a mirror of

    liberal capitalism. The decreasing popularity of such analyses since 1989 has left open the

    field for liberal accounts, including rights-based accounts, of both sport and politics.

    Sugden22 appeals to a seemingly (and allegedly) universal agreement that validates a

    human rights agenda for sport for development and peace (SDP) but this makes ethics

    both contingent (on actual agreements . . . ) and opportunistic ( . . . that just happen to be in

    place at the moment). There is more to human rights theory than that involving arguments

    for the justification of political liberalism and, along with it, human rights theory. The

    liberal state sees itself as deliberately not choosing any particular conception of the Good

    Life for its citizens to follow. Rather, it sees itself as neutral between alternative

    conceptions of the Good to be found in most modern liberal democracies. In this, it sharply

    distinguishes itself from illiberal states, which embody and enforce one view of the Good

    Life. Rather than promoting one culture over another, it sees itself as tolerant and

    multicultural. Citizens can choose their own version of the Good and pursue their own

    aims and values, independently of the state. In such a state, attention to multicultural ideals

    such as recognition, toleration, respect and equal status for all cultures will become

    increasingly important.

    Multiculturalism is a fact nowadays for most Western societies, and it requires apolitical society to recognize the equal standing of all stable and viable communities

    existing in a society. It outlaws discrimination against groups and individuals on the grounds

    of ethnicity, race, nationality, religion, class, gender or sexual preference. However, some

    of these communities may be authoritarian, illiberal and oppressive so the question arises:

    does multiculturalism apply equally to all communities, or only to liberal ones?

    Rawls23 attempts to draw guidelines for a Law of Peoples acceptable to members of

    both liberal and illiberal cultures, by introducing the notion of reasonable societies.

    These societies, though they may be illiberal, nevertheless follow certain core principles:

    Peace (pursuing their ends through diplomacy and trade).

    Common Good (a conception of justice).Consultation (a reasonable hierarchy thereof).

    Responsibility (citizens recognize their obligations and play a part in social life).

    Freedom (some freedom of conscience/thought).

    Reasonable societies, even illiberal ones, could agree to a Law of Peoples based on such a

    thin liberalism as this and this could be seen very positively: as offering learning

    experiences both ways, as each culture learns from the other. But multiculturalism has its

    limits, and those limits are drawn by the universalistic claims of thin liberalism, supported by

    some form of human rightstheory. As Hollissays, liberal societies . . . must fightforat least a

    minimalist, procedural thesis about freedom, justice, equality and individual rights.24

    In the short term, in the interests of peace and development (or of political or economic

    gain), such basic moral commitments may be temporarily diluted or shelved but they are

    the inalienable bedrock of the possibility of a global multiculturalism. There are limits to

    8 J. Parry

    y

    y

    y

  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    10/14

  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    11/14

    ethical potential. Although sports are widely considered to be pleasurable, which in part

    explains their popularity, their likelihood of gaining wide acceptance lies rather in their

    intrinsic value, which transcends the simply hedonic or relative good. Their ability to

    furnish us with pleasurable experiences depends upon our prior recognition in them of

    opportunities for the development and expression of valued human excellences. They arewidely considered to present such opportunities because, even when in local instantiations,

    their object is to challenge our common human propensities and abilities.

    As we saw above, it is difficult even to state the characteristics of sport without relying

    on terms that carry ethical import, and such meanings must apply across the world of

    sports participation. Without agreement on rule-adherence, the authority of the referee and

    the central shared values of the activity, there could be no sport. The first task of an

    International Federation, for example, is to clarify rules and harmonize understandings so

    as to facilitate the universal practice of its sport.

    The thin values underpinning the rule structures of sport, acceptance of which by all

    participants is a precondition of the continuing existence of sporting competition, support

    at the educational and cultural levels initiatives for peace that might take a more obviously

    political form. Children (and others) who are brought into sporting practices, and who are

    aware of international competitions such as the Olympic Games and the World Cup, are

    thereby becoming aware of the possibilities of international cooperation, mutual respect,

    mutual valuing and the resolution of conflict under agreed rules.

    It is not a surprise that there is an emerging relationship between sports organizations,

    including the Olympic Movement and the United Nations, which are global organizations

    facing similar problems in regard to universality and particularity. The general problem

    faced by both is how they are to operate at a global (universal) level while there exist such

    apparently intractable differences at the particular level.

    Some seek to resolve such difficulties in the sports world by speaking of sport as auniversal language; but this seems to me to under-represent the case. Not just sport, but

    sports organizations, including the IOC, seek to be universal in their values: mutual

    recognition and respect, tolerance, solidarity, equity, anti-discrimination, peace, multi-

    culturalism, etc. This is a quite specific set of values, which are at once a set of universal

    general principles; but which also require differential interpretation in different cultures

    statedin general terms whileinterpretedin the particular.

    This search for universal representations at the interpersonal and political level of our

    common humanity seems to me to be the essence of the optimism and hope of various

    forms of humanism and internationalism. I believe that sport has made an enormous

    contribution to modern society over the past hundred years or so, and that there is a strongcase for sport as an efficient means to these ends.

    The very idea of a closed society is under threat everywhere the people are no longer

    reliant on restricted and controlled forms of information. The Internet, satellite TV, and

    global forms of commerce and communication are all contributing to a democratization of

    information, and the extensive migration of people across continents is producing a new

    cosmopolitanism. It will require increasingly high-levels of dogmatism, authoritarianism,

    isolationism and extremism to sustain closed, exclusivist societies. Their life is limited.

    This, at any rate, has to be our hope, and the hope of any kind of peaceful internationalism

    based on the idea of individual freedom and human rights. Our engagement and

    commitment to the development of global forms of cultural expression such as sport, and

    through them to the development of peace and international understanding, is one way

    that we as individuals can express our commitments, ideals and hopes for the future of

    the world.

    10 J. Parry

    y

    y

    y

  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    12/14

    I hope to have demonstrated that the requirements upon us to play fairly are not simply

    requirements to play morally. They are also requirements to acknowledge the internal

    logic of the practices we call sports, without which participation is just impossible. A

    further suggestion is that this internal logic is founded on values that are isomorphic with

    political liberalism, including the ideas of social contract, equality before the law, justice,toleration and mutual respect.

    Conclusion sports peacekeeping potential

    Of course, sport is not a cure-all, and if sport programmes can be useful in peace-building,

    then they must be implemented as part of a wider set of peace-building strategies. I have

    tried to argue that the very nature of sport lends itself to the task of interpersonal

    understanding and respect, and that the nature of cooperative striving in rule-governed

    competition can lead towards civilized and peaceful resolutions. I have claimed that it is

    this peacemaking capacity of sport that informs its peacekeeping potential.

    Potentials, however, are not always realized. Of course, it is possible to exploit and

    manipulate a social institution towards vested interests. In the case of sport, for example,

    this is what the amateurism/professionalism debate is all about: whether the external

    interests of business and profiteering have changed the very nature of sport; or whether

    they have perverted the nature of sport; or whether their aims are inimical to sport. Or take

    marriage, as another example of a social institution. The ceremony (which might vary

    considerably according to context) announces certain values and draws certain promises.

    It thereby has the potential for principled partnerships. But of course no one claims that

    marriage cannot be used for other purposes: to seal the friendship of kings, to secure access

    to a familys wealth, to gain citizenship, to display a trophy wife, etc. And of course no one

    claims that because people sometimes have these external interests, it follows thatmarriage has no intrinsic values.

    Similarly, sport can be used to earn money, promote a nation, inflate egos, bully the

    weak, vaunt victory, disparage the loser and so on. But this does not mean that sport has no

    (intrinsic) values. To argue that sport has peacemaking capacity and peacekeeping

    potential is to argue that it has a certain intrinsic form and intrinsic values, which lend

    themselves to those tasks. This is why sport is promoted (instrumentally) by peacekeepers,

    even if they do not particularly like sport themselves. A shallow appreciation of sport

    would see its popularity. A deeper understanding of sport would try to explain why it is

    universally popular as a mode of mutual expression of our common humanity. Only if

    we can give some account of the nature and intrinsic values of sport will we be in aposition to identify and promote those values which are the bedrock of its peacekeeping

    potential.

    Acknowledgements

    This paper was written with support from a Research Grant from the Ministry of Education, Youthand Sports MSM 0021620864, Czech Republic; and institutional support PRVOUK P39.

    Notes1

    Kvalsund, Sport and Peace Building, 11.2 Palaeologis, The Institution of the Truce.3 Quoted in Goodhart and Chataway,War Without Weapons, 19.4 Goodhart and Chataway,War Without Weapons.

    Sport in Society 11

    y

    y

    y

  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    13/14

    5 Schwery and Eggenberger-Argote, Sport as a Cure; Jarvis,Sport Psychology, 56.6 See Parry, Aggression and Violence, 2078.7 Parry, Aggression and Violence, 212; Harris,Violence and Responsibility, Chapter 1.8 Parry, Aggression and Violence, 2212.9 Parry, Values in Physical Education.

    10

    Parry, Values in Physical Education, 1445.11 Nissiotis, Psychological and Sociological Motives for Violence in Sport, 1068.12 Sugden, Sport Intervention in Divided Societies, 6.13 Bailey, Games, Winning and Education.14 Aspin, Games Winning and Education.15 Meakin, Moral Values and Physical Education.16 Kvalsund, Sport and Peace Building, 5.17 The Council of Europes The European Sports Charter2001 says: Sport means all forms of

    physical activity which, through casual or organised participation, aim at expressing or improvingphysical fitness and well-being, forming social relationships or obtaining results in competition atall levels. Such a definition is impossibly wide, since it includes walking to work, sunbathing, sexand line-dancing as sports.

    18 Whereas Guttman,From Ritual to Record, 15 55, offers seven characteristics of modern sport,I would suggest that universalisability underlies them, or is a consequence of them see Parry,The Idea of the Record, 204.

    19 Borotra, Olympism and Fair Play, 84.20 Fraleigh,Right Actions in Sport, 416.21 Reddiford, Playing to Win, 115.22 Sugden, Sport Intervention in Divided Societies, 8.23 Rawls, The Law of Peoples, passim.24 Hollis, Is Universalism Ethnocentric?, 42.

    References

    Aspin, D.N. Games Winning and Education Some Further Comments. Cambridge Journal ofEducation5, no. 1 (1975): 5161.Bailey, C. Games, Winning and Education. In Physical Education An Integrating Force, edited

    by I.K. Glaister, 2430, A.T.C.D.E. Conference Report 1974.Borotra, J. Olympism and Fair Play.International Olympic Academy, Report of the Twenty-Third

    Session, edited by IOC 8494. Lausanne: 1985.Council of Europe.The European Sports Charter (revised). Brussels:http://www.sportdevelopment.

    info/index.php?optioncom_content&viewarticle&id87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid59&Itemid82 Council ofEurope, 2001.

    Fraleigh, W. Right Actions in Sport: Ethics for Contestants. Champaign, IL: Human KineticsPublishers, 1984.

    Goodhart, P., and C. Chataway. War Without Weapons. London: WH Allen, 1968.

    Guttman, A.From Ritual to Record: The Nature of Modern Sports. New York: Columbia UniversityPress, 1978.

    Harris, J. Violence and Responsibility. London: Routledge & KP, 1982.Hollis, M. Is Universalism Ethnocentric?. In Multicultural Questions, edited by S. Lukes and

    C. Joppke, 2743. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.Jarvis, M.Sport Psychology. London: Routledge, 2002.Kvalsund, P. Sport and Peace Building. Retrieved online on 6 April 2011 fromhttp://www.toolkits

    portdevelopment.org/html/resources/E0/E034DC82-E2BB-4827-AC8B-E7D1BDFCB288/Sport%20and%20Peace%20paper%20Pelle%20 Kvalsund.pdf.

    Meakin, D.C. Moral Values and Physical Education.Physical Education Review 5, no. 1 (1982):6282.

    Nissiotis, N. Psychological and Sociological Motives for Violence in Sport.International Olympic

    Academy, Report of the Twenty-Third Session, edited by IOC 95108. Lausanne: 1985.Palaeologis, C. The Institution of the Truce in the Ancient Olympic Games.Report of the Fifth

    Summer Session of the International Olympic Academy, edited by Hellenic Olympic Committee:20310. Athens: Hellenic Olympic Committee, 1965.

    12 J. Parry

    y

    y

    y

    http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.toolkitsportdevelopment.org/html/resources/E0/E034DC82-E2BB-4827-AC8B-E7D1BDFCB288/Sport%20and%20Peace%20paper%20Pelle%20%20Kvalsund.pdfhttp://www.toolkitsportdevelopment.org/html/resources/E0/E034DC82-E2BB-4827-AC8B-E7D1BDFCB288/Sport%20and%20Peace%20paper%20Pelle%20%20Kvalsund.pdfhttp://www.toolkitsportdevelopment.org/html/resources/E0/E034DC82-E2BB-4827-AC8B-E7D1BDFCB288/Sport%20and%20Peace%20paper%20Pelle%20%20Kvalsund.pdfhttp://www.toolkitsportdevelopment.org/html/resources/E0/E034DC82-E2BB-4827-AC8B-E7D1BDFCB288/Sport%20and%20Peace%20paper%20Pelle%20%20Kvalsund.pdfhttp://www.toolkitsportdevelopment.org/html/resources/E0/E034DC82-E2BB-4827-AC8B-E7D1BDFCB288/Sport%20and%20Peace%20paper%20Pelle%20%20Kvalsund.pdfhttp://www.toolkitsportdevelopment.org/html/resources/E0/E034DC82-E2BB-4827-AC8B-E7D1BDFCB288/Sport%20and%20Peace%20paper%20Pelle%20%20Kvalsund.pdfhttp://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82http://www.sportdevelopment.info/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=87:council-of-europe-2001-the-european-sports-charterrevised-brussels-council-of-europe-&catid=59&Itemid=82
  • 8/12/2019 Jim Parry - The Power of Sport in Peacemaking and Peacekeeping

    14/14

    Parry, J. Values in Physical Education. InValues Across the Curriculum, edited by P. Tomlinsonand M. Quinton, 13457. London: Falmer Press, 1986.

    Parry, J. Violence and Aggression in Contemporary Sport. In Ethics and Sport, edited byM.J. McNamee and S.J. Parry, 20524. London: Routledge, 1998.

    Parry, J. The Idea of the Record.Sport in History 26, no. 2 (2006): 197 214.

    Rawls, J. The Law of Peoples. In On Human Rights, edited by S. Shute and S. Hurley, 4182.New York: Basic Books, 1993.

    Reddiford, G. Playing to Win.Physical Education Review 5, no. 2 (1982): 10715.Schwery, R., and N. Eggenberger-Argote. Sport as a Cure to Mitigate Negative Syndromes of

    Anomie and to Prevent Violent Conflicts. ICSSPE Bulletin, no. 40 (January 2004). Retrievedonline on 6 April 2011 fromhttp://www.icsspe.org/bulletin/drucken_a4b0b691.php.html.

    Sugden, J. Sport Intervention in Divided Societies: Pragmatic Realism and a Human RightsApproach. Play Fair! The official publication of the European Fair Play Movement 17, no.Academic Supplement, no. 7 (2008-2, 2009-1): 68.

    Sport in Society 13

    y

    y

    y

    http://www.icsspe.org/bulletin/drucken_a4b0b691.php.htmlhttp://www.icsspe.org/bulletin/drucken_a4b0b691.php.html