ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark...

21
Jed Allen [email protected] An ActionBased Approach to Implicit Theory of Mind Interactivist Summer Institute, 2015 Jedediah WP Allen [email protected] Bilkent University Ankara Turkey There is growing evidence for the conclusion that infants possess a rudimentary understanding of other people’s beliefs as representational states. The empirical basis for this conclusion comes from looking time studies indicating that infants are able to pass “ageappropriate” FalseBelief (FB) tasks (Onishi & Baillargeon, 2005; Surian, Caldi, & Sperber, 2007). FB tasks are particularly important because they have long been regarded as a litmus test for the possession of a “theory of mind” (Premack & Woodruff, 1978). However, the ability to reason about another person’s false beliefs has traditionally been assumed to develop during the preschool years (Wellman, Cross, & Watson, 2001). Therefore, the dissociation between tasks creates an apparent problem: why do older children fail traditional FB tasks if their younger peers already posses the relevant ability? To solve this dissociation, researchers are converging on the idea that infants possess an implicit Theory of Mind (ToM) while older children possess an explicit ToM (Low & Perner, 2012). However, without a theoretical model of implicit knowledge that allows for the possibility of epistemic reflection and emergence, the implicitexplicit distinction will not be able to adequately explain the task dissociations for which it has been invoked. Further, an epistemically robust notion of implicitness will require adopting an actionbased approach to mind more broadly. In further consequence, socialcognitive theory can reject the takenfor granted assumption of a folkpsychological ontology for understanding other’s actions.

Transcript of ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark...

Page 1: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

Jed  Allen  [email protected]    

An  Action-­‐Based  Approach  to  Implicit  Theory  of  Mind    

Interactivist  Summer  Institute,  2015    

Jedediah  WP  Allen  [email protected]  Bilkent  University  Ankara  Turkey  

 There  is  growing  evidence  for  the  conclusion  that  infants  possess  a  rudimentary  understanding  of  other  people’s  beliefs  as  representational  states.    The  empirical  basis  for  this  conclusion  comes  from  looking  time  studies  indicating  that  infants  are  able  to  pass  “age-­‐appropriate”  False-­‐Belief  (FB)  tasks  (Onishi  &  Baillargeon,  2005;  Surian,  Caldi,  &  Sperber,  2007).    FB  tasks  are  particularly  important  because  they  have  long  been  regarded  as  a  litmus  test  for  the  possession  of  a  “theory  of  mind”  (Premack  &  Woodruff,  1978).    However,  the  ability  to  reason  about  another  person’s  false  beliefs  has  traditionally  been  assumed  to  develop  during  the  preschool  years  (Wellman,  Cross,  &  Watson,  2001).    Therefore,  the  dissociation  between  tasks  creates  an  apparent  problem:  why  do  older  children  fail  traditional  FB  tasks  if  their  younger  peers  already  posses  the  relevant  ability?  To  solve  this  dissociation,  researchers  are  converging  on  the  idea  that  infants  possess  an  implicit  Theory  of  Mind  (ToM)  while  older  children  possess  an  explicit  ToM  (Low  &  Perner,  2012).    However,  without  a  theoretical  model  of  implicit  knowledge  that  allows  for  the  possibility  of  epistemic  reflection  and  emergence,  the  implicit-­‐explicit  distinction  will  not  be  able  to  adequately  explain  the  task  dissociations  for  which  it  has  been  invoked.    Further,  an  epistemically  robust  notion  of  implicitness  will  require  adopting  an  action-­‐based  approach  to  mind  more  broadly.    In  further  consequence,  social-­‐cognitive  theory  can  reject  the  taken-­‐for-­‐granted  assumption  of  a  folk-­‐psychological  ontology  for  understanding  other’s  actions.    

Page 2: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

Mark Bickhard [email protected] Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous System Dynamics Inter- and En- Activism The Anticipative Brain: Two Approaches An Interactivist Perspective on Ethics Robert Campbell [email protected] Robert  L.  Campbell,  Psychology,  Clemson  University,  Clemson,  South  Carolina,  USA    Moral  Psychology  and  the  Interactivist  Ontology  of  the  Person    This  tutorial  will  present  key  principles  of  the  interactivist  ontology  of  the  person  as  they  pertain  to  the  pursuit  of  goals  and  values,  and  to  character  and  its  invariants.    The  ease  of  implementation  within  this  ontology  will  be  assessed  for  a  variety  of  conceptions  of  morality  in  the  Western  tradition:  Aristotle’s  virtue  ethics,  Kant’s  rule-­‐based  morality  (and  its  psychological  derivatives  such  as  the  theories  of  Piaget  and  Kohlberg),  and  Haidt’s  sentiment-­‐based  theory  of  six  moral  foundations.      Robert  L.  Campbell,  Psychology,  Clemson  University,  Clemson,  South  Carolina,  USA    Writing  about  Psychology    A  recent  book  by  Michael  Billig,  Learn  to  Write  Badly:  How  to  Succeed  in  the  Social  Sciences,  incisively  criticizes  the  prevailing  manner  in  which  psychology  books  and  articles  are  written.    The  main  points  of  his  critique  will  be  illustrated  and  defended.    Billig  recommends:  (1)  using  technical  terms  only  when  they  are  demonstrably  more  precise  than  everyday  language;  (2)  cutting  down  on  the  use  of  passive  sentences;  

Page 3: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

(3)  using  clauses  with  active  verbs  in  place  of  nouns  or  noun  phrases;  (4)  writing  about  people  rather  than  “things”  (reified  concepts  or  variables);  (5)  avoiding  technical  terms  when  they  are  mainly  functioning  to  market  the  writer.           David Eck [email protected]  1.  Major  Themes:  large-­‐scale  social  coordination  patterns,  first-­‐personal  agency    2.  Title:  Applying  Participatory  Sense-­‐Making  to  Epistemic  Communities:  The  Danger  of  Reifying  Coordination  Patterns        3.  Extended  Abstract    Hanne  De  Jaegher  and  Ezequiel  Di  Paolo’s  (2007,  2008)  concept  of  participatory  sense-­‐making  has  addressed  an  important  lacuna  within  the  enactive  movement  in  cognitive  science—namely,  the  movement’s  implications  for  social  theory.  Applied  to  two-­‐person  interactions,  participatory  sense-­‐making  shows  how  epistemically  productive  social  coordination  does  not  presuppose  individual  cognitive  mechanisms.  But  applying  participatory  sense-­‐making  and  enactivism  more  generally  to  larger-­‐scale  and  longer-­‐term  social  contexts  has  proven  difficult:  most  efforts  have  reified  social  interaction  patterns  and  consequently  obscured  the  role  of  the  idiosyncratic,  future-­‐oriented  first-­‐personal  agent.  To  examine  this  issue,  I  begin  with  De  Jaegher’s  attempts  to  expand  the  scope  of  participatory  sense-­‐making.    

De  Jaegher’s  extension  of  participatory  sense-­‐making  has  centered  on  the  notion  of  a  participation  spectrum.  This  spectrum  is  based  on  degrees  of  social  coordination:  on  one  side  of  the  spectrum  lies  mere  “orientation”  and,  on  the  other,  “joint  sense-­‐making.”  In  the  latter  case,  it  may  be  very  difficult  or  even  impossible  to  tease  out  each  individual’s  distinct  contributions  due  to  high  coordination  between  participants.  In  cases  of  orientation,  by  contrast,  there  is  low  orientation  and,  as  a  result,  it  is  easy  to  delineate  each  individual’s  contributions.  While  the  social  coordination  spectrum  can  be  a  useful  tool  in  assessing  the  interdependence  within  a  given  interaction,  it  has  also  been  linked  to  the  affective  character  of  social  interaction.  The  latter  link  is  first  proposed  by  De  Jaegher,  Di  Paolo,  and  Gallagher  (2010).    

De Jaegher, Di Paolo, and Gallagher (2010) tentatively propose that the coordination spectrum is a general indicator of the affective character of social interaction. Their proposal is based on empirical studies of psychotherapy in which there is a correlation between, on the one hand, high bodily coordination of therapist and patient and, on the other, a patient’s positive assessment of the therapy session. Over a series of articles, De Jaegher expands on the social coordination spectrum, especially the

Page 4: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

latter suggestion that high coordination correlates with positive affective states (e.g., Fuchs and De Jaegher 2009, McGann and De Jaegher 2009, De Jaegher 2013). Even though the connection between the coordination spectrum and the affective character of interaction is indexed to a specific context in De Jaegher, Di Paolo, and Gallagher (2010), this qualification and any other proviso is scanty if not entirely absent from De Jaegher’s subsequent efforts.

De Jaegher proposes a number of spectra based on the social coordination spectrum. Among her many efforts, I will concentrate on McGann and De Jaegher (2009) and De Jaegher (2013): the former captures the tight link between the spectra and the privileging of motility, while the latter shows the extent to which De Jaegher is willing to give motility explanatory priority. Beginning with the former: the  main  goal  of  McGann  and  De  Jaegher  (2009)  is  to  give  an  account  of  social  perception  in  terms  of  social  contingencies  and  thereby  link  participatory  sense-­‐making  to  O’Regan  and  Noë’s  (2001)  sensorimotor  contingency  theory.  Towards  this  end,  McGann  and  De  Jaegher  recast  joint  sense-­‐making  and  orientation,  the  opposite  poles  of  the  social  coordination  spectrum,  in  terms  of  fluid  and  rigid  interactions,  respectively.  In  this  context,  fluidity  appears  as  sensitivity  to  social  contingencies.  That  is  to  say,  being  socially  skilled  entails  the  ability  to  improvise  based  on  our  own  and  others’  changing  emotional  states  (p.  427-­‐28).  Lack  of  social  skill,  by  contrast,  implies  rigidity  and  predictability,  an  inability  to  engage  one’s  particular  audience.  In  making  this  connection  with  O’Regan  and  Noë’s  sensorimotor  contingency  theory,  McGann  and  De  Jaegher  erode  some  of  participatory  sense-­‐making’s  value:  interpreting  sociality  in  terms  of  unpredictability  dovetails  with  O’Regan  and  Noë’s  general  privileging  of  quantifiable  movement  over  first-­‐personal  experience.  Likewise,  De  Jaegher’s  application  of  fluidity  and  rigidity  to  political  theory  suggests  that  she  too  believes  that  motility  holds  a  general  explanatory  priority  over  first-­‐personal  experience.      

Drawing upon Gilligan and Richards (2009), De Jaegher (2013) frames the fluid-rigid dichotomy in terms of horizontal democratic forms of association in contrast to top-down patriarchal social organizations, respectively. The connection is ambitious, representing an attempt to show participatory sense-making’s relevance to analyzing entire societies. This extension is predicated on yet another spectrum, the spectrum of power symmetry. De Jaegher writes, “When interacting with another person, or with an institution, one or other partner may be more or less ‘dominant,’ more or less influential. In such asymmetric relations or interactions, the degree of influence that each partner has is different” (p. 23). Greater power symmetry corresponds to the high coordination of joint sense-making and a positive affective character; greater power asymmetry corresponds to the low coordination of mere orientation and a negative affective character. In this manner, the significance of social interaction is confined to one-dimensional spectra. In attributing affective meaning to coordination patterns irrespective of participants’ first-personal experiences, De Jaegher reifies the patterns. Diagnosing De Jaegher’s extension of participatory sense-making serves as a useful lens for considering other problematic attempts to apply enactivism to large-scale social contexts, such as Pierre Steiner and John Stewart’s structural normativity and Richard Menary’s Cognitive Integrationism.

Page 5: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

Steiner and Stewart’s structural normativity undermines first-personal agency by positing an objective set of communal norms. Steiner and Stewart (2009) argue that enactivism is by itself ill-equipped to account for humans’ higher-level cognitive abilities and thus human social domains. To supplement enactivism, Steiner and Stewart draw upon the “Pittsburgh School” of philosophy, arguing that there is a qualitative difference between humans’ language capabilities and other animals’ “stereotyped” communication. Accordingly, on this view, humans’ distinctive language capacities generate an objective social domain. Social domains consist of normative structures that are acquired and enforced via language. Joining a social domain requires heteronomous submission to its normative structure; a member who violates a social norm risks expulsion from a particular domain. Given this picture of language and objective social domains, the role of first-personal agents is even more greatly marginalized than in De Jaegher’s account. Menary’s Cognitive Integrationism, in turn, drops Steiner and Stewart’s human exceptionalism but retains the general picture of an objective set of communal norms.

In presenting Cognitive Integrationism, one of Menary’s primary concerns is to present an account of cognitive practices that addresses the issue of cognitive bloat (regarding cognitive bloat, see Rupert 2004). The cognitive bloat issue, Menary argues, stems from confusing mere “artifact extension” with “encultured cognition.” Whereas the former only involves an “outsourcing” or “offloading” of cognition, the latter transforms the cognitive character of the epistemic agent. Accordingly, physical artifacts should not be counted as part of an epistemic agent—thus blunting the cognitive bloat concern—but rather only the communal norms that guide how to skillfully manipulate artifacts. Analogous to Steiner and Stewart’s notion of heteronomous submission, Menary models the acquisition of skills as the internalization of cognitive norms. Using one of his favorite examples of a cognitive practice, Menary (2012,  152) describes learning a written language as follows: “the  inside  is  transformed  to  be  more  like  the  outside  (as  a  kind  of  reverse  parity  principle).”  The  notion  of  reverse  parity,  in  which  all  “internal”  skills  and  norms  are  the  product  of  previous  engagements  with  cognitive  practices,  highlights  the  affinity  with  Steiner  and  Stewart’s  account.  Although  by  dropping  the  human  exceptionalism  of  the  Pittsburgh  School  and  its  attendant  focus  on  the  nature  of  human  language,  Menary  has  more  resources  to  model  the  acquisition  of  communal  norms—Menary  and  Kirchhoff  (2013),  for  instance,  draw  upon  Hubert  Dreyfus’s  (1986)  account  of  embodied  expertise.  While  Cognitive  Integrationism  is  thus  an  advance  over  Steiner  and  Stewart’s  structural  normativism,  the  role  of  the  first-­‐personal  agent  is  still  marginalized  by  the  underlying  notion  of  an  internalization  of  objective  communal  norms.    

The basic insight of participatory sense-making is that coordination dynamics endogenously emerge within the actual interaction between agents. In order to preserve this insight while addressing larger-scale social contexts, I sketch two interrelated aspects of the epistemic agent that are absent from De Jaegher’s extension: first, the agent’s prospective orientation and, second, the opaqueness of coordination factors. The first aspect relates to Mark Bickhard’s (Bickhard and Terveen 1996, Bickhard 2002) account of error-guided learning, the second to Isabela Granic’s (2002) notion of behavioral attractors. Jointly, both aspects stand in stark contrast to the notion of a shared set of objective social norms: social interaction’s epistemic significance derives from the ineliminable differences between agents rather than a shared set of internalized norms.

Page 6: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

Using the problematic nature of structural normativity and Cognitive Integrationism as a cautionary reference point, I argue against attributing any substantive meaning or affective character to coordination patterns without incorporating the first-personal perspectives of the participants.

 References      Bickhard, Mark H. 2002. "Critical principles: On the negative side of rationality." New

Ideas in Psychology 20 (1):1-34.

Bickhard, Mark H, and Loren Terveen. 1996. Foundational issues in artificial intelligence and cognitive science: Impasse and solution. Vol. 109. New York: Elsevier.

De Jaegher, Hanne. 2013. "Rigid and fluid interactions with institutions." Cognitive Systems Research 25:19-25.

De Jaegher, Hanne, and Ezequiel Di Paolo. 2007. "Participatory sense-making." Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6 (4):485-507.

De Jaegher, Hanne, and Ezequiel Di Paolo. 2008. "Making sense in participation: An enactive approach to social cognition." Emerging Communication 10:33.

De Jaegher, Hanne, Ezequiel Di Paolo, and Shaun Gallagher. 2010. "Can social interaction constitute social cognition?" Trends in cognitive sciences 14 (10):441-447.

Dreyfus, Hubert L, and Stuart E Dreyfus. 1986. Mind over machine. New York: Free Press.

Fuchs, Thomas, and Hanne De Jaegher. 2009. "Enactive intersubjectivity: Participatory sense-making and mutual incorporation." Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8 (4):465-486.

Gilligan, Carol, and David AJ Richards. 2009. The Deepening Darkness: Patriarchy, Resistance, and Democracy's Future. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Granic, Isabela. 2002. "The Self-Organization of Parent-Child Relations: Beyond Bidirectional Models." In Emotion, development, and self-organization: Dynamic systems approaches to emotional development, edited by Marc D. Lewis and Isabela Granic, 267-297. New York: Cambridge University Press.

McGann, Marek, and Hanne De Jaegher. 2009. "Self–other contingencies: Enacting social perception." Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8 (4):417-437.

Page 7: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

Menary, Richard, and Michael Kirchhoff. 2013. "Cognitive transformations and extended expertise." Educational Philosophy and Theory: Incorporating ACCESS 46 (6):610-623.

O'Regan, J Kevin, and Alva Noë. 2001. "A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness." Behavioral and brain sciences 24 (05):939-973.

Rupert, Robert D. 2004. "Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition." The Journal of philosophy:389-428.

Steiner, Pierre, and John Stewart. 2009. "From autonomy to heteronomy (and back): The enaction of social life." Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8 (4):527-550.

   Paweł  Gładziejewski  Institute  of  Philosophy  and  Sociology,  Polish  Academy  of  Sciences  

ul.  Nowy  Świat  72,  00-­‐330  Warsaw,  Poland  

Phone  number:  (+48)  518  096  011  

E-­‐mail:  [email protected]  

 

1. Major   theme:   Critical   examination   of   the   relation   between   practical   and  

representational  normativity,  in  particular  of  the  possibility  of  reducing  the  latter  to  

the  former.  

 

2. Paper  title:  Representation  and  (inter)action:  a  moderate  proposal  

 

3. Extended  abstract:  

 

  Cognitive   systems   are   related   to   their   environments   in   two   prima   facie  

distinct  ways,  both  of  which  can  be  construed  as  normative  in  nature.  First,  there  is  

the   practical   relation:   organisms   interact   with   their   environments,   and   those  

interactions  can  either  succeed  or  fail.  Second,  there  is  the  representational  relation.  

Minded   creatures   can   internally   represent   worldly   states   of   affairs,   i.e.   have  

contentful   internal   states  which   can  be  accurate  or   inaccurate   (true  or   false)  with  

respect   to   how   the   world   actually   is.   What   is   the   metaphysical   and   explanatory  

Page 8: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

connection  between  the  two  ways  of  being  related  to  environment,  if  there  is  any?  Is  

the   representational   content   somehow   determined   or   constituted   by   practical  

engagements   with   the   world?   Can   the   representational   normativity   be   somehow  

explained   in   terms   of   practical   normativity?   It   seems   that     there   are   at   least   two  

positions  which  one  might  hold  with  respect  to  those  questions:  

 

Intellectualism:  There  exists  no  strong  or  theoretically  significant  

connection  between   representational   content   and   the  normativity  

of   action.   Representational   content   is   not   determined   or  

constituted   by   action.   And   action   does   not   play   any   explanatory  

role   with   respect   to   how   content   arises.   Something   else   entirely  

determines/constitutes/explains   representational   content   (e.g.  

some   correspondence   or   natural   relation   between   the  

representation  itself  and  what  is  represented).1  

 

Interactivism:   There   is   a   strong   and   theoretically   significant  

connection  between   representational   content   and   the  normativity  

of   action.   Representational   content   is   wholly   determined   or  

constituted   by   being   appropriately   related   to   action.   And   we   can  

provide  a  complete  explanation  of  content  in  terms  of  this  relation  

to  action.2  

 

                                                                                                               1  We   might   imagine   Super-­‐Intellectualism,   a   position   which   reverses   the   order   of  

metaphysical/explanatory   relationship   and   claims   that   normativity   of   action   is  

constituted/determined/explained  by  the  normativity  of  representation.  To  keep  things  simple,  I  will  

not  discuss  this  option  here.  2  This  is  not  to  suggest  that  Interactivism  denies  any  sort  of  relevance  of  factors  other  than  action  for  

content.   Nonetheless,   I   take   Interactivism   to   be   committed   to   a   claim   that   (1)   non-­‐action-­‐related  

factors  are  never  necessary  for  representational  content  and  (2)  action-­‐related  factors  are  sufficient  

for  representational  content.  

Page 9: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

  Proponents  of  Interactivism  sometimes  charge  Intellectualism  with  inability  

to   explain   how   representational   error   detection   is   possible.   That   is,   on   the  

Intellectualist  view  of  things,  it  remains  a  mystery  how  cognitive  systems  can  have  

access  to  whether  they  accurately  represent  the  environments,  and  so  how  they  are  

capable   of   error-­‐based   learning.   It   is   the   ability   to   explain   representational   error  

detection   that   is   supposed   to   constitute   a   major   advantage   of   Interactivism   over  

Intellectualism.  Roughly  speaking,  from  the  Interactivist  perspective,  organisms  can  

detect   representational   error   indirectly,   through   detecting   failures   of   those  

(inter)actions  which  confer  content  on  representational  states.    

  One   might   get   an   impression   that   when   discussing   the   relation   between  

practical   and   representational   normativity,   Intellectualism   and   Interactivism  

exhaust   all   the   theoretical   options   and   thus   we   face   the   dilemma   of   choosing  

between  either  of  the  two.  But  this  is  clearly  a  false  alternative,  as  an  intermediate  

position  is  also  available:  

 

The  Moderate  View:  There  is  a  strong  and  theoretically  significant  

connection  between   representational   content   and   the  normativity  

of   action.   Representational   content   is   partly   determined   or  

constituted  by  being  appropriately  related  to  action.  And  we  can  in  

part  explain  content  in  terms  of  this  relation  to  action.  

 

  In  my  talk,   I  will  attempt   to  achieve   two  things.  First,   I  will   try   to  elucidate  

what   the  Moderate   View   amounts   to.   In   particular,   I  will   sketch   a   view   on  which  

representational  content  is  co-­‐constituted  both  by  the  representation’s  involvement  

in   action-­‐guidance   as   well   as   by   the   structural   resemblance   holding   between   the  

representation  and  what  is  represented.  Second,  I  will  argue  that  the  Moderate  View  

has  the  advantages  of  both  Intellectualism  and  Interactivism,  without  sharing  (what  

I   take   to   be)   their   disadvantages.   In   particular,   similarly   to   Interactivism,   the  

moderate  position  can  explain  how  representational  error  detection  is  possible.  At  

the   same   time,   the  Moderate   View   avoids  what   I   take   to   be   a  major   drawback   of  

Interactivism.   It   seems   that   by   postulating   such   a   tight   link   between   content   and  

Page 10: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

action,   Interactivism   often   makes   representational   talk   explanatorily   vacuous.  

Simply  speaking,  representations  often  play  no  separate  and  significant  explanatory  

role  in  the  Interactivist  story.  I  will  argue  that  the  Moderate  View  does  not  give  rise  

to   this   problem,   since   it   provides   us   with   a   clear   distinction   between  

representational  and  non-­‐representational  action-­‐guiding  mechanisms.  

 

 

Abel  R.  Hernández-­‐Ulloa  [email protected]  Multicausal  Abductive  Reasoning  as  an  interactivist  account  for  “scientific  

discovery”  Guanajuato  University,  México  

    Russell  Hanson  (1961)  challenged  the  accepted  idea  that  there  is  no  logic  of  scientific   discovery.   He   states   that   if   there   are   reasons   to   suggest   a   particular  hypothesis  then  it  is  possible  to  consider  some  kind  of  logic  of  scientific  discovery.  The   question   is   how   it   is   possible   to   generate   a   particular   hypothesis   to   explain  some  surprising  phenomena  within  the  boundaries  of  an  accepted  theory.  In  some  cases   it  would   be   a   question   of:   how   it   is   possible   to   generate   a   new   theory.   It   is  proposed   that   the   inference   of   the   best   explanation   of   surprising   phenomena   has  some  regularities.  This  particular  kind  of  inference  to  the  best  explanation  is  called  abductive   inference   (Aliseda,   1997).     Jerry   Fodor   (2000)   has   challenged   the  available  psychological  theories  about  how  human  minds  work  because  they  lack  of  an   explanation   for   abductive   reasoning.   Previously,   claiming   an   anticonstructivist  approach,   he   discarded   any   theory   of   learning   and   the   theories   committed   to   the  perspective   of   developmental   psychology   (Fodor,   1992).   Bickhard   developed   a  theory   that   presents   a   solution   to   Fodor’s   perspective   through   the   alternative  position  now  acknowledged  as  interactivism  (Bickhard,  2003;  Campbell  &  Bickhard,  1992).  The  interactivism  emphasize  the  fact  that  there  has  been  an  emergence  of  the  representation   and,   furthermore,   there   can   also   be   considered   the   emergence   of  normative   representation.  From   this   approach   the  mind   is   conceived  as   a  process  that  operates  as  an  evolving  self  regulated  open  system.  In  order  to  exemplify  some  of  these  key  ideas  about  the  emergence  of  new  knowledge,  I  will  present  the  results  from  an  empirical  study  on  multicausal  abductive  reasoning.  This  study  shows  how,  after  a  brief  training  to  understand  the  main  features  of  a  ‘multicausal’  system,  some  participants  are  able   to  develop  hypotheses   in  order   to  explain  new  observations.  Such  hypotheses  emerge  in  a  gradual  process  in  which  successive  tentative  working  hypotheses  are  adapted  to  new  information.          

Page 11: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

ALISEDA,  A.  (1997)  Seeking  Explanations:  Abduction  in  Logic,  Philosophy  of  Science  and  Artificial  Intelligence.,  PhD  thesis,  Institute  for  Logic,  Language  and  Computation  (ILLC),  University  of  Amsterdam,  The  Netherlands  

 BICKHARD,  M.  H.  (2003).  Mind  as  Process.  In  F.  G.  Riffert,  M.  Weber  (Eds.)  Searching  

for  New  Contrasts.  (285-­‐294).  Vienna:  Peter  Lang.  URL:  http://www.lehigh.edu/~mhb0/mindasprocess.pdf  FODOR,  J.  A.  (1992)  Fixation  of  Belief  and  Concept  Acquisition.  IN  SMITH,  L.  (Ed.)  

Jean  Piaget:  Critical  Assessments.  London,  Routledge.  FODOR,  J.  A.  (2000)  The  mind  doesn't  work  that  way  :  the  scope  and  limits  of  

computational  psychology,  Cambridge,  Mass.,  MIT  Press.      

Dr.  Annette  Hohenberger  [email protected]  

Major  themes  of  the  paper:  Cognition  and  Representation;  Representation  emergent  in  action  systems;  Development  

Paper  title:  The  role  of  perception  in  an  action-­‐based  approach  to  object  representation  

Extended  abstract:    

Allen  and  Bickhard  (2013)  advocate  an  action-­‐based  approach  to  object  representation  in  order  to  transcend  both  nativism  and  empiricism  which  are  both  trapped  in  foundationalism,  i.e.,  they  resort  to  innate  atomic  representations.  Allen  and  Bickhard  claim  that  objects  are  not  represented  in  virtue  of  the  referents  in  the  environment  they  stand  in  for  but  in  virtue  of  the  anticipated  (inter)actions  they  afford  for  some  agent.  Their  action-­‐based  approach  avoids  conceptual  and  methodological  problems  which  are  ubiquitous  in  the  field  of  cognitive  developmental  research  and  allows  for  representational  emergence,  i.e.,  the  active  construction  of  object  representations  out  of  interactions  with  these  objects,  as  first  proposed  by  Piaget  (1954).    In  their  developmental  reconstruction  of  representational  emergence  they  reject  correspondence  as  the  basis  of  the  relation  between  the  representing  and  the  represented  entity  and  rather  determine  anticipation  as  the  basis  of  two  essential  properties  of  representation  –  aboutness  (intentionality)  and  truth  value.  In  this  paper,  I  am  suggesting  how  action  can  be  vindicated  as  a  proper  basis  of  object  and  action  representation,  namely  by  invoking  perception  as  an  indispensable  counterpart  of  action  and  as  the  locus  of  anticipation.  This  extension  is  relevant  to  cognitive  development  (ontogenetic  and  phylogenetic)  in  particular  and  to  action  science,  more  generally.      

Page 12: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

My  suggestion  invokes  a  theory  with  a  long  and  eventful  tradition  in  cognitive  psychology,  namely  ideo-­‐motor  theory  (Stock  &  Stock,  2004).  First  being  proposed  in  the  18th  century  and  then  constantly  being  improved  until  today,  ideo-­‐motor  theory  claims  that  (motor)  actions  are  represented,  instigated  and  controlled  in  terms  of  the  perceptual  anticipation  of  their  goal  objects  and  their  desired  distal  goal  states  (Prinz,  1997;  Hommel,  Müsseler,  Aschersleben,  &  Prinz,  2001).  Thus,  perception  (of  intended  action  outcomes)  and  action  are  two  sides  of  the  same  medal,  sharing  a  common  code  during  processing.  Common  coding  (Prinz,  1997)  obviates  the  need  of  translating  between  them,  as  in  traditional  information-­‐processing  theories.  It  rather  claims  that  the  two  are  representationally  equivalent  (at  some  point  of  cognitive  processing),  collapsing  the  traditional  tripartite  sequence  of  perception  –  cognition  –  action  into  a  unitary  ideo-­‐motor  concept  of  cognition.  Ideo-­‐motor  theory  has  a  strong  empirical  foundation  at  the  behavioral  and  neuro-­‐scientific  level,  in  adult  as  well  as  in  developmental  research  (Prinz,  Beisert,  &  Herwig,  2013).  I  suggest  invoking  the  perceptual  aspect  of  the  ideo-­‐motor  complex  as  the  locus  of  anticipation  which  plays  a  major  role  in  Bickhard  and  colleagues’  action-­‐based  account  (Bickhard,  2009a+b;  Allen  &  Bickhard,  2013;  Campbell,  2010;  among  many  others).  In  Bickhard  and  colleagues’  account,  the  future  directedness  of  anticipation  provides  the  agent  an  expectation  of  how  her  interaction  in  the  current  context  would  proceed  and  whether  it  might  possibly  succeed.  Van  Geert  &  Steenbeek  (2013)  call  these  anticipations  “pre-­‐presentations”  and  grant  them  an  important  role  in  development,  e.g.,  by  facilitating  subsequent  interactions  with  a  particular  object  and  allowing  for  increasingly  more  differentiated  actions.  In  ideo-­‐motor  theory  anticipation  is  explicitly  attributed  to  perception.  In  order  to  engage  with  an  object  in  the  environment  through  some  purposeful,  goal-­‐direct  behavior,  e.g.,  grasping  a  mug  of  tea,  the  agent  is  invoking  the  perceptual  image  of  its  anticipated  distal  goal  state,  e.g.,  holding  the  mug  in  her  hand  (and  drinking  the  tea).  Through  the  perceptual  loop,  ideo-­‐motor  theory  can  bridge  the  otherwise  insurmountable  rift  between  the  intention  to  act  (in  the  mind)  and  the  motor  act  (of  the  body)  itself.  Thus,  ideo-­‐motor  theory  answers  the  mind-­‐body  problem,  namely  how  willed  action  is  possible:  the  mind  can  instruct  the  body  to  move  only  via  the  activation  of  the  perceptual  image  of  the  distal  action  effects.  The  proximal  motor  act  is  left  to  the  peripheral  motor  system  itself.  Perceptual  instruction  is  possible  through  bilateral  associations  that  are  formed  during  the  cognitive  and  motor  development  of  the  agent,  starting  in  the  first  year  of  life.  These  connections  work  both  ways:  from  (firstly  unintentional)  motor  acts  to  perception  of  their  outcomes,  and,  later,  intentionally,  from  perception  to  action.  While  action  is  not  anticipatory  by  itself,  perception  is,  as  when  the  agent  is  simulating  the  desired  result  state  of  the  action.  This  simulation  activates  and  instigates  the  corresponding  motor  program  and  the  action  is  launched.  Lastly,  ideo-­‐motor  theory  accounts  for  a  major  but  often  neglected  aspect  of  object  and  action  representation  which  goes  beyond  mere  considerations  of  affordances,  namely  the  motivational  aspect:  why  do  we  act  at  all?    

Allen,  J.  W.P.  &  Bickhard,  M.  H.  (2013).  Stepping  off  the  pendulum:  Why  only  an  action-­‐based  approach  can  transcend  the  nativist-­‐empiricist  debate.  Cognitive  Development  28,  96-­‐133.    

Page 13: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

Bickhard,  M.  H.  (2009a).  Interactivism:  A  manifesto.  New  Ideas  in  Psychology  27,  85-­‐95.  Bickhard,  M.  H.  (2009b).  The  biological  foundations  of  cognitive  science.  New  Ideas  in  Psychology  27,  

75-­‐84.  Campbell,  R.  (2010).  The  emergence  of  action.  New  Ideas  in  Psychology  28(3),  283-­‐295.    Hommel,  B.,  Müsseler,  J.,  Aschersleben,  G.,  &  Prinz,  W.  (2001).  The  theory  of  event  coding  (TEC):  A  

framework  for  perception  and  action  planning.  Behavioral  and  Brain  Sciences  24,  849-­‐878.  Piaget,  J.  (1954).  The  construction  of  reality  in  the  child.  New  York:  Basic.  Prinz,  W.  (1997).  Perception  and  action  planning.  European  Journal  of  Cognitive  Psychology  9,  129-­‐

154.  Prinz,  W.,  Beisert,  M.,  &  Herwig,  A.  (2013).  Action  science.  Foundations  of  an  emerging  discipline.  

Cambridge,  MA:  MIT  Press. Stock,  A.  &  Stock,  C.  (2004).  A  short  history  of  ideo-­‐motor  action.  Psychological  Research  68,  176-­‐188.  Van  Geert,  P.L.C.  &  Steenbeek,  H.  W.  (2013).  (P)  (re)  presentations:  What  are  they  and  how  do  they  

develop?  Commentary  on  “Stepping  off  the  pendulum:  Why  only  an  action-­‐based  approach  can  transcend  the  nativist-­‐empiricist  debate.”  By  J.  Allen  &  M.  Bickhard.  Cognitive  Development  28,  138-­‐143.    

 

Author  or  co-­‐authors  with  names,  addresses,  telephone  number,  and  e-­‐mail  address:  

Assoc.  Prof.  Dr.  Annette  Hohenberger  Middle  East  Technical  University  (METU)  Informatics  Institute,  Department  of  Cognitive  Science  Cankaya  Ilcesi  Universiteler  Mah.  Dumlupinar  Bulvari  1  06800  Ankara  TURKEY    Tel.:  ++90  (0)  312  210  3789  Fax:    ++90  (0)  312  210  3745    e-­‐mail:  [email protected]          

Page 14: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

Chris Janeke [email protected] Interactivist  Summer  Institute:    [email protected]  Main  Theme:  Cognition  and  representation  Title:      Exploring  the  postcognitivist  era:    A  perspective  from  cognitive  psychology        Abstract  During  the  cognitivist  era,  a  notion  of  symbolic  representations  coupled  with  a  computational  theory  of  mind  prevailed  as  the  dominant  approach  in  cognitive  psychology.    This  ‘rules  and  representation’  type  of  cognitive  architecture  achieved  a  paradigmatic  status  during  the  1970s  and  80s,  but  it  has  now  been  largely  abandoned  in  favour  of  a  number  of  alternative  conceptions  of  cognition  and  mind  that  reject  at  least  some  of  the  key  assumptions  underlying  either  the  representational  or  computational  aspects  of  the  cognitivist  paradigm.        In  this  presentation  I  try  to  illuminate  aspects  of  this  changing  landscape  of  research.    However,  since  this  is  a  large  and  complicated  domain  of  research,  only  three  significant  strands  of  research  falling  within  this  ‘postcognitivist’  research  tradition  are  briefly  examined,  and  my  perspective  is  mostly  based  on  that  of  cognitive  psychology.      The  three  strands  of  research  that  will  be  considered  range  from  a  relatively  mild  ‘revisioning’  of  the  cognitivist  approach,  to  a  more  radical  rejection  of  its  core  postulates.        I  first  consider  connectionism  in  which  much  of  the  flavour  of  the  computational  paradigm  is  still  retained,  albeit  in  a  parallel  distributed  processing  framework.    However,  connectionism  does  part  with  the  cognitivist  tradition  because  it  is  based  on  a  subsymbolic  representational  scheme,  and    it  advances  a  statistical  learning  mechanism.    This  use  of  statistical  computation  entails  a  novel  way  of  thinking  about  the  origins  of  knowledge  as  ‘emerging’  from  the  learning  and  processing  activity  of  massively  interconnected  processing  units  in  large  networks.      The  standard  connectionist  approach  is  a  relatively  mild  amendment  of  the  cognitivist  tradition,  but  a  stronger  version  of  this  approach  posits  that  cognitive  explanations  should  be  supplanted  with  concepts  and  theories  at  the  neural-­‐level.    This  approach  is  therefore  eliminative.    A  second  important  manifestation  of  postcognitive  research  is  this  eliminative,  reductionist  approach  to  cognition.  The  availability  of  brain  imaging  technologies  (e.g.  fMRI,  MEG),  progress  in  neuroscience  in  uncovering  brain  mechanisms  at  the  cellular  level,  and  the  considerable  funding  opportunities  associated  with    large  scale  projects  such  as  the  human  connectome  and  blue  brain  are  all  forces  that  are  currently  driving  a  bottoms-­‐up,    reductionist      orientation  in  cognitive  psychology.    This  has  fostered    a    ‘molecules  to  mind’    style  of  explanation,  so  that  John  Bickle  argues  for  a  “ruthless  reductionism”  in  terms  of  which  theories  and  explanations  of  psychological  phenomena  are  reduced  to  concepts  and  mechanisms  at  the  neural  level.          The  third  strand  of  postcognitivist  research  that  I  will  discuss  is  the  most  radical,  because  it  discards  both  the  computational  and  representational  tenets    of  the  cognitivist  tradition.    The  radical  embodied  perspective  that  is  described  in,  for  example,  Chemero  (2011),  argues  for  a  perspective  in  which  concepts  of  space,  

Page 15: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

direct  perceptual  experience,  and  bodily  interaction  with  the  world  form  the  basis  for  psychological  knowledge  and  also  the  explanation  of  behaviour.        In  this  approach  the  internalist,  brain-­‐in-­‐a-­‐vat  conception  of  cognition  and  behaviour  is  rejected,  and  an  interactive  perspective  involving  brain/mind,  body,  and    behaviour  is  presented  and  modelled  using  dynamical  systems  theory.    The  approach    is  therefore  non-­‐representational  and  also  non-­‐mechanistic  because  there  is  no  attempt  to  elucidate  a  purely  internal  cognitive  mechanism;  instead  explanation  is  aimed  at  clarifying  the  dynamical  interaction  of    mind,  perception  and  action  in  an  environment.        An  equally  radical  rejection  of  the  cognitivist  notion  of  mechanism    is  provided  by  the  recent  exploration  of  aspects  of  quantum  theory  in  cognitive  psychology,  and  a  new  field  called  ’quantum  cognition’  has  even  emerged  from  this  research.    In  this  field  no  assumptions  or  claims  are  made  about  the  physical  structure  of  the  brain,  instead  the  focus  is  simply  on  exploring  the  use  of  the  mathematical  theory  of  quantum  probability  as  a  basis  for  modelling  aspects  of  human  cognition.    Hence,  there  is  no  attempt  to  capture  internal  cognitive  representations  and  mechanisms,  a  purely  mathematical,  descriptive  theory  of  cognition  is  presented.    I  conclude  by  briefly  drawing  a  few  implications  and  mention  the  problem  of  distinguishing  between  a  realist  and  instrumentalist  conceptions  of  computation  and  representation  in  both  cognitivist  and  postcognitivist  theories.    Reference  Chemero,  A.  (2011).  Radical  embodied  cognitive  science.  MIT  Press.      Author:    Chris  Janeke      Associate  Professor,  Department  of  Psychology,  University  of  South  Africa    Address:    TvW  Building  5-­‐108,    Department  of  Psychology,  University  of  South  Africa,    P  O  Box  392,  Pretoria,  0003,  Republic  of  South  Africa  Tel:  +27  124298218,  email:  [email protected]          Alex  Levine  [email protected]    Synchronic  and  Diachronic  Emergence    Contributors  to  the  literature  on  interactivism  and  process  metaphysics  have  criticized  received  views  on  emergence  in  a  number  of  different  senses  of  the  word.    First,  substance-­‐metaphysical  approaches  have  historically  left  the  problem  of  change  intractable.    In  contemporary  approaches  to  mind,  this  legacy  has  made  it  difficult  if  not  impossible  for  heirs  to  the  substance-­‐metaphysical  tradition  to  explain  how  aspects  of  mind  (including  the  functional  normativity  of  cognition,  language,  etc.)  can  evolve  and  develop.    Evolution  and  development  are  examples  of  diachronic  emergence.    At  the  same  time,  similar  substance-­‐metaphysical  presuppositions  have  made  it  difficult  to  account  for  emergence-­‐at-­‐a-­‐time,  or  what  I  call  synchronic  emergence.    Jaegwon  Kim,  for  example,  has  famously  argued  that  the  

Page 16: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

emergence  of  the  higher-­‐level  properties  of  cognitive  systems  must  be  understood  as  mere  supervenience,  with  such  properties  ultimately  reducible  to  the  properties  and  structures  of  a  microphysical  substrate.    In  this  paper,  I  ask  whether  it  makes  sense  to  consider  the  programmatic  critique  of  inadequate  accounts  of  emergence  as  addressing  one  target,  or  two.    To  what  extent  must  synchronic  and  diachronic  emergence  be  understood  as  involving  similar  dynamics  and  similar  ontologies?    I  argue  that  despite  deep  kinship,  the  two  are  not  identical.    Sensitivity  to  differences  will  increase  the  efficacy  of  critique.      Raamy  Majeed  [email protected]    TITLE:  From  Process  Philosophy  to  Quietism:  A  ‘Daoist’  Account  of  Consciousness    ABSTRACT:  Daojia,  the  philosophical  tradition  associated  with  Daoism,  provides  its  own  brand  of  epistemology  and  metaphysics.  The  former  can  be  interpreted  as  espousing  a  form  of  Quietism  not  too  dissimilar  from  the  one  attributed  to  the  latter  Wittgenstein:  that  the  role  of  philosophy  is  to  defuse  linguistic  and  conceptual  confusions  instead  of  offering  up  positive  theses  of  its  own.  Moreover,  and  somewhat  paradoxically,  the  latter  can  be  viewed  as  offering  a  process  ontology;  though  of  a  non-­‐theistic  variety  that  is  more  naturalistic  than  the  one  made  popular  by  Whitehead,  and  yet  distinct  from  other  naturalistic  accounts,  such  as  those  of  Bickhard  and  Campbell.  In  this  paper,  I  aim  to  explain  how  we  can  employ  the  Daoist  process  philosophy  to  argue  for  a  Quietist  account  of  phenomenal  consciousness.      Marcin  Milkowski  [email protected]    Does  system-­‐detectable  error  imply  methodological  solipsism?    It  has  been  argued  that  a  proper  account  of  system-­‐detectable  error  in  cognitive  representation  requires  that  content  supervenes  on  the  intrinsic  properties  of  the  cognitive  agent  (Bickhard  1993).  The  purpose  of  my  talk  is  to  ask  whether  this  implies  that  interactivism  endorses  methodological  solipsism.  Previous  work  on  the  interactivist  model  did  not  focus  on  the  externalism  /  internalism  debate,  and  just  because  of  the  immense  popularity  of  these  distinction  this  issue  needs  to  be  tackled.  I  will  defend  a  claim  that  the  basic  anticipatory  representations,  being  inherently  context-­‐sensitive,  should  not  be  framed  in  internalist  terms;  rather  they  supervene  on  the  ongoing  interaction  between  cognitive  processes  and  its  milieu.  For  this  reason,  they  are  not  intrinsic  to  the  cognitive  agent.  At  the  same  time,  contents  may  be  still  accessible  to  the  cognitive  system,  as  it  logically  supervenes  on  its  interaction;  there  is  no  observer-­‐dependence  in  error-­‐detectability.  If  this  

Page 17: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

argument  is  correct,  depending  on  the  spatiotemporal  scale  of  cognitive  interactions,  there  may  be  contents  that  can  be  only  partially  accessed  by  an  individual  agent  but  still  subject  to  (partial  and  fallible)  evaluation  by  a  whole  interacting  community  of  agents.     Melvin Woody [email protected]

“Freedom  and  Trauma”  -­‐  Abstract    

Recent  events  have  forced  the  U.S.  to  contend  with  traumatic  injury  –  physical,  psychic  and  social.  That  tragic  calamity  is  most  vividly  realized  in  the  torrent  of  traumatized  veterans  that  overwhelms  both  military  and  VA  medical  facilities.  Confrontation  with  trauma  challenges  philosophers  and  politicians  to  acknowledge  the  limits  of  freedom.    Yet  to  be  free  is  to  be  vulnerable  to  the  threat  of  trauma,  since  freedom  cannot  exist  without  a  supporting  and  confining  world,  the  source  of  obstacles,  opportunities  -­‐-­‐  and  assaults.    In  order  to  inhabit  such  a  world  and  realize  its  choices  in  action  freedom  must  be  embodied  and  its  body  must  not  only  be  capable  of  action,  but  must  also  be  receptive  to  determination  by  the  world.    Freedom  is  therefore  inherently  mortal  and  always  at  risk  of  paralysis  or  defeat.      I  will  explore  the  relations  between  trauma  and  freedom  by  focusing  on  the  pathology  of  post-­‐traumatic  stress  disorder  and  comparing  the  paralysis  characteristic  of  post-­‐traumatic  stress  disorder  with  physical  trauma  and  paralysis.      While  still  capable  of  acting  upon  the  world,  victims  of  post-­‐traumatic  stress  disorder  are  captivated  by  past  events  that  they  cannot  assimilate,  forget  or  consign  to  normal  memory.      In  the  midst  of  the  helplessness  of  a  traumatic  event,  the  self  preserves  itself  by  dissociating  from  the  self  that  is  determined  by  the  world  and,  often,  from  its  own  body.    But  the  saving  strategy  leaves  the  post-­‐traumatic  self  alienated  and  still  helplessly  ensnared  by  a  past  that  it  cannot  leave  behind  because  it  has  become  embodied  in  the  body  that  it  disowned  in  order  to  survive.     Georgi Stojanov [email protected]  Representation  Revisited  (Again):  15  years  of  ISI      At  the  beginning  of  the  new  millennium,  15  years  ago  when  we  started  the  ISI  meetings,  it  was  an  exciting  time  to  work  in  the  field  of  cognitive  sciences  (from  robotics,  via  philosophy  of  mind,  to  psychology  and  other  related  fields).  Alternatives  to  the  so  called  “symbolic”  and  “connectionist”  models  started  to  gain  in  popularity,  trying  to  suggest  new  potential  answers  to  the  old  questions.  Here  are  some  of  those:  “embodied  and  embedded  cognition”,  “extended  mind/  distributed  cognition”,  “anticipation  based  representation”  “epigenetic  robotics”.  Of  course,  this  is  not  to  say  that  the  ideas  were  not  there  before  but  to  underline  that  they  were  

Page 18: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

never  in  the  “mainstream  research”.  We  felt  that  many  of  these  “new  wave”  approaches  shared  one  thing  or  another  with  Bickhard’s  interactivism,  and  initiating  ISI  was  our  attempt  to  bring  these  people  together  and  articulate  a  firm  theoretical  framework.    Fast  forward  to  today’s  scene.  At  least  within  the  context  of  cognitive  robotics,  we  can  definitely  say  that  the  classical  (the  Shakey  –  no  pun  intended)  approach  is  all  but  dead.  Todays’  cognitive  roboticists  are  likely  to  be  familiar  at  least  with  some  developmental  psychology,  will  be  working  with  physical  robots  in  non-­‐specifically  crafted  “mini  worlds”,  and  on  real-­‐life  problems  (from  urban  rescue  to  assistive  robotics).  Current  vocabulary  includes:  SLAMs,  probability,  uncertainty,  Markov  models,  Kalman  filters,  clustering,  big  data,  to  mention  but  a  few.    In  my  presentation,  I  will  try  to  paint  a  broad  picture  of  the  evolution  of  the  notion  of  representation  (of  knowledge,  of  environment)  and  the  variety  of  its  implementation  in  the  period  of  these  past  15  years.        Ioannis  Xenakis  [email protected]  Argyris Arnellos [email protected]  

 Feelings  and  the  construction  of  perceptual  content  Ioannis  Xenakis1  &  Argyris  Arnellos2  1Department  of  Product  and  Systems  Design  Engineering,  University  of  the  Aegean,  Syros,  Greece  2The  KLI  Institute,  Klosterneuburg,  Austria  e-­‐mail:  [email protected];  [email protected]  

Abstract    A  cognitive  agent  should  exhibit  the  capacity  to  differentiate  between  situations  in  the  environment  in  order  to  be  able  to  orientate  itself  towards  those  interactions  that  will  better  satisfy  its  norms.  In  this  way,  agents  actively  construct  a  relation  between  them  and  their  world.  This  relation  is  not  pre-­‐given  but  emergent  and  evoked  during  interaction,  and  it  thus  constitutes,  even  in  its  primitive  forms  interactive  potentialities,  where  the  agent  actively  constructs  a  body-­‐mind-­‐environment  relation,  according  to  which  it  perceives  the  surroundings  as  appropriate  conditions  for  future  interactions.    We  understand  the  perceptual  content  as  emergent,  and  with  a  normativity  that  derives  from  biological  normative  functions.  Perception  has  a  twofold  normative  function;  namely  to  signal  the  agent  for  both  internal  and  external  modifications  

Page 19: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

that  will  be  useful  for  action-­‐selection.  Considering  perception  as  a  preparatory-­‐anticipatory  process,  agents  are  in  place  not  only  to  functionally  detect  the  related  inputs  but  also  to  actively  evaluate  them  with  respect  to  the  consequences  they  have  for  their  norms.  In  other  words,  the  content  of  perception  emerges  when  the  agent  detects  and  evaluates  the  indications  of  possible  interactions,  namely,  the  actions  being  available  to  the  agent  at  the  exact  time  of  interaction  (Bickhard,  2011).    While  the  content  of  perception  must  be  understood  in  terms  of  truth  conditions,  it  should  not  always  imply  a  successful  contribution  to  the  world  since  the  evaluated  appropriateness  of  a  possible  interaction  may  also  be  prone  to  dysfunction  or  failure,  thereby  increasing  the  uncertainty  in  perception.  Therefore,  agents  develop  ways  to  handle  and  reduce  this  uncertainty.  Learning  and  inference  are  two  important  processes,  which  result  in  the  reduction  of  uncertainty.  Through  learning  agents  could  develop  ways  to  evaluate  indications  of  possible  interactions,  to  anticipate  the  result  of  their  perceptual  outcomes,  to  prepare  themselves,  and  to  possibly  learn  to  modify  their  actions  when  things  just  do  not  go  well  (Bickhard  &  Richie,  1983;  Christensen  &  Hooker,  2000).  However,  agents  do  not  always  perceive  situations  with  which  they  are  familiar.  In  those  interactive  cases,  cognitive  agents  can  also  develop  ways  (functions)  to  perceive  their  environments  and  reduce  their  interactive  uncertainty.    Our  claim  here  is  that  feelings  do  not  only  play  an  important  role  in  the  reduction  of  interactive  uncertainty  (Bickhard,  2000)  but  they  also  have  an  active  role  in  the  construction  of  the  perceptual  content  facilitating  the  emergence  of  interactive  potentialities.    It  is  known  that  feelings  play  a  major  role  in  action-­‐selection:  an  active  contribution  to  the  preparation  for  action.  This  type  of  emotional  preparation  may  promote  actions  related  to  fundamental  physiological  functioning,  for  instance,  by  triggering  the  elicitation  of  autonomic  (e.g.,  a  change  in  heart  rate)  and  endocrine  responses  (e.g.,  the  release  of  adrenaline),  to  higher  levels  of  cognitive  actions  such  as  playing  music,  writing  books,  painting,  appreciating  and  classifying  art,  etc.  (Rolls,  2011;  Xenakis  &  Arnellos,  2014;  2015).  Contemporary  bibliography  in  cognitive  psychology  and  the  science  science  of  emotions  suggests  that  feelings  function  by  providing  significance  to  the  current  situation.  The  main  argument  is  that  emotional  episodes  are  constructed  during  the  meaning  making  process  playing  thus  a  central  role  (Wilson-­‐Mendenhall,  Barrett,  Simmons,  &  Barsalou,  2011).  It  is  now  accepted  that  there  is  no  ontological  distinction  between  ‘hot’  and  ‘cold’  cognitions.  All  thoughts  or  actions  are  more  or  less  infused  by  feelings.  “Thinking”  is  not  a  fundamentally  different  sort  of  psychological  activity  than  “feeling”  when  the  agent  is  about  to  construct  the  active  state  that  determines  what  the  environment  means  to  it.  How  the  agent  perceives  an  object  and  how  it  feels  about  it  should  be  considered  as  facets  of  the  same  concrete  experience  (Duncan  &  Barrett,  2007).  In  this  way,  it  sounds  invalid  to  speak  strictly  for  affective  and  non-­‐affective  perceptions.  As  Duncan  and  Barrett  argue  “the  fact  that  thoughts  and  feelings  are  experienced  as  different  is  important,  and  needs  to  be  explained,  but  is  not,  in  and  of  itself,  evidence  that  they  are  fundamentally  different  kinds  of  phenomena”  (p.1203).    Emotional  evaluations  detect  for  opportunities  and  threats,  the  existence  or  not  of  a  possible  interaction,  and  influence  the  agent  with  feelings  of  how  a  possible  act  may  

Page 20: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

result.  The  normative  function  of  these  feelings  is  the  elicitation  of  signals  (interactive  values)  that  derive  from  the  prospects  for  norm  satisfaction  or  failure  (Rolls  2011).  In  other  words,  feelings  are  outcome  of  processes  through  which  the  agent  evaluates  modifications  that  take  place  internal  or/and  external  to  its  organization  with  respect  to  its  norms.  Such  emotional  signals  produce  anticipatory  values,  whose  intensity  is  a  crucial  aspect  that  influences  the  potential  motivation  to  satisfy  those  norms.  The  normativity  of  feelings  is  inherited  to  the  perceptual  content.    Considering  that  perception  blends  ‘hot’  and  ‘cold’  processes,  the  content  of  perception  does  not  involve  strictly  identified  indications  that  concern  “invariants,  constancies,  sensorimotor  contingencies,  etc.”  as  characteristics  of  the  object  in  consideration  and  an  answer  to  how  objects  are  or  look.  Rather,  a  normative  perceptual  content  entails  that  the  object  comes  always  to  experience  as  an  interactive  opportunity  having  a  value,  and  thus  having  always  the  possibility  to  be  dysfunctional.      The  above  view  is  in  contrast  to  classic  conceptions  of  emotional  theory  that  want  feelings  to  be  outcomes  of  conceptual  thoughts  that  are  added  to  experience  as  evaluative  judgments  or  combinations  of  beliefs  and  desires.  Our  argument  is  that  feelings  are  elicited  in  perception  as  the  agent  constructs  the  range  of  interactive  potentialities  by  assigning  to  each  of  them  values  that  influence  the  agent’s  anticipatory  system  in  predicting  a  potential  effect  that  each  possible  action  might  have  according  to  its  norms.  Since  emotional  values  emerge  mostly  on  uncertain  conditions,  where  the  agent’s  competence  in  such  interactive  challenges  is  minimal,  feelings  provide  an  important  function  to  perception  by  aiding  the  agent  to  resolve  its  interactive  uncertainty.  Feelings  influence  the  content  of  perception  with  interactive  (anticipatory)  values  that  prepare  the  agent  to  decide  between  possible  actions  through  the  development  of  strategies  for  the  reduction  of  its  uncertainties  and  the  control  of  its  experience.  This  makes  feelings  a  crucial  aspect  of  perception  through  which  the  agent  assigns  values  to  indications  of  possible  interactions  and  may  differentiate  situations  in  the  environment  during  action-­‐selection.  In  sum,  cognitive  agents  do  not  emotionally  evaluate  situations  after  they  first  know  what  they  look  like,  but  they  feel  the  significance  of  the  situations,  as  they  perceive  them.      

References  Bickhard,  M.  H.  (2000).  Motivation  and  Emotion:  An  Interactive  Process  Model.  In  R.  D.  Ellis  &  N.  Newton  (Eds.),  The  Caldron  of  Consciousness:  Motivation,  Affect  and  Self-­‐organization  (pp.  161–178).  Philadelphia,  USA:  John  Benjamins  Publishing  Company.  Bickhard,  M.  H.  (2011).  The  Dynamics  of  Acting.  Humana  Mente,  (15),  177–187.  Bickhard,  M.  H.,  &  Richie,  D.  M.  (1983).  On  the  Nature  of  Representation:  A  Case  Study  of  James  Gibson’s  Theory  of  Perception.  Praeger  Pub.  

Page 21: ISI 2015 Abstracts25May15 - Lehigh Universityinteract/isi2015/ISI2015... · 2015. 5. 25. · Mark Bickhard mhb0@lehigh.edu Parmenides to Persons Interactivism and Central Nervous

Christensen,  W.  D.,  &  Hooker,  C.  A.  (2000).  An  interactivist-­‐constructivist  approach  to  intelligence:  Self-­‐directed  anticipative  learning.  Philosophical  Psychology,  13(1),  5–45.  Duncan,  S.,  &  Barrett,  L.  F.  (2007).  Affect  is  a  form  of  cognition:  A  neurobiological  analysis.  Cognition  &  Emotion,  21(6),  1184–1211.  Rolls,  E.  T.  (2011).  The  Origins  of  Aesthetics:  A  Neurobiological  Basis  for  Affective  Feelings  and  Aesthetics.  In  E.  Schellekens  &  P.  Goldie  (Eds.),  The  Aesthetic  Mind:  Philosophy  and  Psychology  (pp.  116–165).  Oxford,  USA:  Oxford  University  Press.  Wilson-­‐Mendenhall,  C.  D.,  Barrett,  L.  F.,  Simmons,  W.  K.,  &  Barsalou,  L.  W.  (2011).  Grounding  emotion  in  situated  conceptualization.  Neuropsychologia,  49(5),  1105–1127.    Xenakis, I., & Arnellos, A. (2014). Aesthetic perception and its minimal content: a

naturalistic perspective. Frontiers in Psychology, 5(1038). Xenakis, I., & Arnellos, A. (2015). Aesthetics as an Emotional Activity That Facilitates

Sense-Making: Towards an Enactive Approach to Aesthetic Experience. In A. Scarinzi (Ed.), Aesthetics and the Embodied Mind: Beyond Art Theory and the Cartesian Mind-Body Dichotomy (pp. 245–259). Springer Netherlands. Retrieved from http://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-017-9379-7_15