Inquiry and Democracy

download Inquiry and Democracy

of 14

Transcript of Inquiry and Democracy

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    1/14

    1

    Inquiry and Democracy:John Dewey on the Experimental Method and its Implications for Political Life

    Charles J. Sentell

    University of Cambridge

    Department of History and Philosophy of Science and Medicine

    Introduction

    A central theme in John Deweys philosophy is that the experimental method be more fully

    integrated into all forms of human inquiry. Taking modern science as the central case of this

    method, Dewey generalizes its forms into a theory of inquiry, which he intends for use within

    all areas of human activity. If this spread of the experimental method were to occur, Dewey

    claims, it would affect an important reconstruction in the way individuals and communities

    approach particular problematic situations, formulate various proposals for consideration, and

    decide upon courses of action in solution to those problems. Thus, the significance of

    Deweys theory of inquiry is that he intends it to be a description of the method by which all

    problems are resolved, not just scientific, but moral, social, and political problems as well.

    And through this socio-political relevance, the most important consequence of Deweyan

    inquiry becomes clear, namely, that inquiry is central to the project of generating and

    sustaining democracy not only at the political level, but in the interstitial spaces of everyday

    life as well. In this essay I will examine Deweys conception of experimental inquiry in

    terms of its relationship to his democratic theory. In particular, I will engage a recentargument concerning the nature and place of pluralism within Deweys conception of

    democracy and show that this problem emerges only by neglecting a central aspect of his

    theory of inquiry.

    The Experimental Method

    To adequately understand the connection between Deweys account of experimental method

    and his political philosophy, it is valuable to get a sense of his broader philosophical project.

    At the beginning of his career, Dewey identified himself with the neo-Hegelian tradition of

    T.H. Green in Britain and George Morris in the United States (Westbrook 1991: 13).

    Although he eventually rejected the central tenets of neo-Hegelianism, these early

    philosophical commitments are important because, as I will show later, some of its

    underlying features never quite disappear from his thinking. As these commitments waned,

    however, Dewey began to think that the problems were not just with idealism, but were

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    2/14

    2

    symptoms of a larger problem within philosophy itself. In two major works,Reconstruction

    in Philosophy (1920) and The Quest for Certainty (1929), Dewey presents a new meta-

    philosophical position, which renders a trenchant critique on the mainstream philosophical

    tradition.

    According to Dewey, philosophy is just one type of thinking among many that

    attempts to find varying degrees of certainty in an uncertain world. In terms of the

    philosophical tradition, Dewey traces this quest for certainty from the Greeks, who held

    that if philosophy were truly to aim at certainty, it could not be concerned with the realm of

    doing or making, but must focus its efforts on the search for the eternally and necessarily

    true. Dewey traces this bifurcation between knowledge and action, between theory and

    practice, through the modern philosophies of Locke, Spinoza, Kant, and extrapolates its

    effects for much of the epistemologically and metaphysically oriented philosophy that

    follows in their wake. By maintaining this division between theory and practice, Dewey

    claims, the mainstream philosophical tradition has divorced itself from the very conditions

    that gave rise to it in the first place, namely, the uncertainties of everyday life.

    Deweys account of the rise and nature of philosophy is thus genealogical,

    psychological, and evolutionary in character. It is genealogicalin that it traces the major

    suppositions, methods, and aims of philosophy through its history to show that, while

    philosophy may have once been the direct outgrowth and response to a given cultures needs

    and desires, it is now an institutionalized discipline wherein the central questions have

    become obscure reifications with little bearing to everyday life. It ispsychologicalin that it

    claims there is a cognitive need for philosophy within individuals and cultures: philosophy

    constructs systems of thought that give certainty to our actions and meaning to our lives.

    And it is evolutionary in that the urge to philosophize, to seek adequate answers to the

    complex range of problematic phenomena, is itself simple and basic to the continuation of

    life. For Dewey, philosophy grows out of the problems of life, it does not stand over and

    against an independent reality that is beyond normal reach; it emerges organically from our

    fumbling about the world, rather than being handed down through transcendent rationality.

    This view is meant to release philosophy from the quagmire of timeless questions and call

    it back to cultural relevancy by addressing the concerns and problems that face communities

    in the present. When philosophy accomplishes this, it ceases to be a device for dealing with

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    3/14

    3

    the problems of philosophers and becomes a method, cultivated by philosophers, for dealing

    with the problems of men [and women]. (MW 10: 46).

    Philosophy can best achieve this by taking its cue from modern science. For Dewey,

    the most significant contribution of science to culture was not any specific discovery or

    invention, but the formulation and refinement of the experimental method. The development

    of this method is so significant that Dewey advocates the range of its application be extended

    well beyond the scope of scientific inquiry. By experimental method, Dewey does not

    denote a method in the strict sense; it is not a codified method, applied in a uniform manner,

    across a range of contexts. It refers, rather, to the general methodological comportment that

    has been at the heart of modern science since Bacon. This method consists of taking ideas,

    utilizing them in actual contexts, and evaluating their efficacy based upon consequences.

    Dewey characterizes it as a method of knowing that is self-corrective in operation; that

    learns from failures as from successes (MW 12: 259). It is a method wherein discovery and

    inquiry are synonymous as an occupation. Science is apursuit, not a coming into possession

    of the immutable(MW 12: 263). In other words, the goal of inquiry is not to find a final

    solution, but to find a solution that satisfies a particular problematic situation and thereby

    allows the inquirer to move on to other problems. Dewey notes that [t]heory in fact that

    is, in the conduct of scientific inquiry has lost ultimacy. Theories have passed into

    hypotheses (MW 12: 276). So Dewey holds scientific inquiry to be a hypothetical, ongoing

    process that orients itself to human needs and interests.

    In his last major work, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (1939), Dewey presents his most

    systematic account of the nature and structure of the experimental method, or simply, inquiry.

    It is important to note that this is the work he considered most important to his overall

    philosophy. The basic idea in Logic is that all inquiry arises within the context of a

    problematic situation and aims to resolve that situation by transforming it into an

    unproblematic one. Dewey defines inquiry as the controlled or directed transformation of

    an indeterminate situation into one that is so determinate in its constituent distinctions and

    relations as to convert the elements of the original situation into a unified whole. (LW 12:

    109) Within this framework, all inquiry has an existential basis; all genuine problems have

    their source in actual problematic experiences. Dewey identifies two existential matrices of

    inquiry the biological and the cultural that form the necessary background conditions

    from which all inquiry arises. Inquiry, then, is not a free-floating process that rational beings

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    4/14

    4

    engage in when and whence they choose, but is a direct consequence of an organisms

    general interaction with its environment.

    Dewey presents his theory of inquiry in terms of a reconstruction of Aristotelian

    logic. In the same manner that he critiqued the mainstream philosophical tradition, Dewey

    claims that Aristotelian logic has outlived its concomitant worldview and must be revised in

    terms of the modern scientific understanding of the world. Again, a central element of

    Deweys thought is that all forms of thinking are ideational constructs that arise within a

    given culture so as to deal with a particular set of problems and concerns. Logic is no

    exception to this, and Aristotles logic should be understood in a historical context that

    enabled a particular culture to deal with problematic situations in a manner congruent to their

    overall view of the nature of reality. It is not the case, Dewey claims, that Aristotles logic

    embodies the necessary and fixed logical forms of reality that timelessly obtain; rather,

    Aristotelian logic was relevant, and grounded in, the subject-matter of natural science as

    that subject-matter, the structure of nature, was then understood. (LW 12: 416).

    The problem with the current conception of logic and inquiry is that it retains an old

    logical structure in the face of a new understanding of the world. Dewey points out that

    modern science has dramatically changed our view of the nature of the world: no longer is

    the world considered to consist of fixed essences moving toward their predetermined end.

    Rather, the world is now generally conceived to be in flux, in movement not toward some

    pre-given end, but developing from where it currently is. The consequences of this viewpoint

    call for a complete reconstruction of logical concepts, and throughout Logic Dewey expands

    upon the specific ways in which logical theory is changed by it. But for present purposes, it

    suffices to note that within Deweyan inquiry, logic is simply another conceptual apparatus

    deployed for the purpose of dealing with problematic situations; it is not an exemplification

    of the forms of Reality apprehended through Reason. To consider logic otherwise constitutes

    what Dewey called the hypostatization of an instrument, and is a common feature of the

    types of inquiry he was arguing against (LW 12: 155).

    Since the forms of inquiry originate directly from existentially based problematic

    situations, the material (i.e. the contents) of inquiry gain added significance. Dewey claims

    that the logical structure of inquiry is based upon, and transformed by, the existential material

    being inquired about. He says that formal [logical] conceptions arise out of the ordinary

    transactions; they are not imposed upon them from on high or from any external and a priori

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    5/14

    5

    source. But when they are formed they are also formative; they regulate the proper conduct

    of the activities out of which they develop. (LW 12: 106) Dewey illustrates this by using

    the example of our common sense notions of legality and how, once these notions are put

    through legislative processes and formally codified, they become the structures by which

    further notions of legality (typically) develop. In this way, logical forms are taken to be both

    the products of inquiry, as well as its constitutive forms. They are products, which, when

    taken and re-integrated within inquiry, become part of the very structure of future inquiry.

    Inquiry is thus formative and trans-formative: it is formative in that, through its very

    processes, it determines a scheme for ordering further discourse, and trans-formative in that it

    reconditions experience such that the problematic situation is transformed through its

    solution, i.e. it is no longer problematic.

    Given these characteristics, the contours of Deweyan inquiry can be summarized as

    follows: 1) Inquiry is an ongoing, hypothetical process, which is guided by the experimental

    attitude to the extent that it takes various hypotheses and judges their validity according to

    applied consequences. While the short-term goal of inquiry is the resolution of immediate

    problematic situations, the nature of inquiry necessitates that inquiry itself remain dynamic

    and ongoing in the search for new ways of understanding and explanation. 2) The

    problematic contents of inquiry originate from our immediate interactions with the

    surrounding environment, as well as from the cultural milieu into which we are thrown. The

    objects and substances that form the content of inquiry are themselves hypothetical in nature

    and modified according to the degree to which they fit into, and function within, a

    problematic situation, or system of such situations. They are not based upon essences or

    intrinsic natures, but are the operational correlatives of the structural forms of inquiry. 3) The

    structure of inquiry is formed in conjunction with the contents of inquiry, thus placing

    structural and material elements in a reciprocal relationship that shapes the way inquiry is

    conducted in the future. This makes logical forms functional and instrumental, rather than

    structural and a priori. When all these features are taken together and utilized within an

    actual nexus of inquiry, they comprise what Dewey referred to simply as active

    intelligence.

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    6/14

    6

    Democracy

    With these characteristics in mind, it is appropriate to understand Deweys philosophy of

    science as a type of naturalism wherein rational inquiry emerges organically from our

    experiences of problematic situations. As I mentioned earlier, one of Deweys early

    philosophical influences was Hegel and the neo-Hegelianism of the late nineteenth-century. I

    also indicated that some aspects of this influence carry over into his mature pragmatic

    philosophy. I think a clear example of this influence is found in Deweys conception of

    inquiry. This conception, I propose, can be thought of as a type of secularized Hegelianism,

    with a dose of Darwinism added as the catalyst for change. Dewey gives up the Geistin

    exchange for a conception of inquiry that is an autonomous, self-perpetuating system wherein

    progress is defined in evolutionary terms. In place of the Hegelian eschatology, Dewey

    establishes the dialectic of hypothetical inquiry as the process out of which all knowledge

    develops. Nothing is outside inquiry; the methods and contents of inquiry are produced

    internally through a type of hermeneutic circle wherein the content becomes the justification

    for the method, and the method becomes the justification for the content.

    Progress within inquiry, then, is not teleological; it is an evolutionary, problem-

    oriented development that depends upon the ability to adapt current ways of thinking to new

    problematic situations. This account makes Deweys notion of progress strikingly similar to

    Thomas Kuhns idea of progress, which holds that progress is properly understood as

    progress-from, rather than progress-to some given end (1996: 162). It also grounds Deweys

    conception of inquiry within a particular tradition. While there may be an end-in-view

    directing inquiry to solve a specific set of problems, future inquiries are always dependent

    upon what is secured through prior inquiry. The contents and methods of previous inquiries,

    in other words, are the necessary materials out of which new ideas are made.

    For Dewey there is no dualism of scheme and content; indeed, there is no dualism at

    all. The bifurcations between knowledge and action, theory and practice, and appearance and

    reality all collapse within the Deweyan conception of inquiry. And because Dewey grounds

    all inquiry within actual existential situations, it is correct to say that the unity of method is

    grounded in the unity of nature. Nature itself develops through experimentation, and by

    consciously employing this method in the service of more humane problems and inquiries we

    are to some extent able to control our own evolution.

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    7/14

    7

    I belabour these points precisely because the nature and structure of experimental

    inquiry is the model upon which Dewey bases his conception of democracy. Deweyan

    inquiry, in other words, is the larger concept, and Deweyan democracy is situated under its

    aegis. And while inquiry and democracy are analogous in a number of ways, it is crucial to

    get clearer on just how they are analogous so that a proper understanding of each is reached.

    One thing that is clear it that Deweys entire project rejects views which take as their

    starting point antecedently given conditions or essential natures. Against essentializing any

    object of inquiry, Dewey eschews the antecedently given and the predetermined end of

    inquiry in scientific as well as political inquiry. He says that it is not the business of

    political philosophy and science to determine what the state in general should or must be.

    What they may do is to aid in creation of methods such that experimentation may go on less

    blindly, less at the mercy of accident, more intelligently, so that men [and women] may learn

    from their errors and profit by their successes. (LW 2: 257) Deweys proposal for

    implementing the experimental attitude within the socio-political sphere can thus be thought

    of as a type of political experimentalism.

    This political experimentalism is structurally analogous to inquiry in that it is an on-

    going process whose main aim is not final completion, but continual development. In The

    Public and its Problems (1926), Dewey claims that, regarded as an idea, democracy is not

    an alternative to other principles of associated life. It is the idea of community life itself. It

    is an ideal in the only intelligible sense of an ideal: namely, the tendency and movement of

    some thing which exists carried to its final limit, viewed as completed, perfected. Since

    things do not attain such fulfilment but are in actuality distracted and interfered with,

    democracy in this sense is not a fact and never will be. (LW 2: 328) The idea of

    democracy, then, is a regulative ideal: it is not something that will ever be fully consummated

    in practice, but a goal toward which we are continually striving.

    But democracy, for Dewey, entails more than simply a democratic form of

    government. It is above all a way of life, which is essentially the idea that democracy is a

    substantive social ideal rather than justa procedural, and thus merely political, form of

    government. He says, the troubleis that we have taken democracy for granted; we have

    thought and acted as if our forefathers had founded it once and for all. We have forgotten

    that it has to be enacted anew every generation, in every year and day, in the living relations

    of person to person in all social forms and institutions (LW 11: 416). In this way,

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    8/14

    8

    democracy is a way of shared social inquiry toward the resolution of common social

    problems that requires a reflective and engaged citizenry so as to be effective. To get a better

    idea of just how far this expands typical conceptions of democracy, I think it is helpful to

    compare the notions of procedural and substantive democracy to the methods and content of

    inquiry.

    A procedural conception of democracy places the onus of democratic work on formal

    governmental structures, which are constructed to mitigate disputes and manage social

    differences. These governmental institutions precisely the features so often identified with

    being the essence of democracy are for Dewey only means. He says, [u]niversal suffrage,

    recurring elections, responsibility of those who are in political power to the voters, and the

    other factors of democratic government are means that have been found expedient for

    realizing democracy as the truly human way of living. They are not a final end and a final

    value. They are to be judged on the basis of their contribution to end (LW 11: 218). In this

    way, the procedural aspects of democracy are analogous to the methods of inquiry: they are

    the evolving means through which democratic ends are realized. The substantive aspects of

    democracy, on the other hand, are analogous to the contents of inquiry; they are the

    problematic social situations that call for amelioration through cooperative inquiry

    (Campbell 1993: 17). Just as within the structure of inquiry, where the methods and contents

    develop and are justified in reciprocal relation, so too do the procedural and substantive

    aspects of democracy develop in a mutually dependent way. Thus, it is clear that Dewey is

    not opposed to a formal conception of democracy, but just that his substantive view of

    democracy includes and goes beyondit.

    As already shown, the correlative dependence of method and content within inquiry

    shapes the way inquiry is conducted in the future. In this way, the process of inquiry

    produces its own regulative norms, which, in turn, define the proper ends of inquiry.

    Analogously, the conjunctive development of the procedural and substantive aspects of

    democracy establishes the ideal ends of democracy. Thus, both Deweyan inquiry and

    democracy are normative in nature: they establish internally, through their very processes, the

    regulative norms that direct future activity toward a given end. The regulative norms of

    inquiry establish both the primary aim of inquiry (i.e. the resolution of problematic

    situations) and the proper means by which that end can be achieved, namely through a

    hypothetical, experimental approach to inquiry itself. As democracy is a form of shared

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    9/14

    9

    social inquiry, the regulative norms of inquiry establish the ideal end of democracy, which

    Dewey identifies as the necessity of participation of every mature human being in formation

    of the values that regulate the living of men [and women] together, as well as the proper

    means by which that end is realized (LW 11: 217). So just as Dewey collapses the dualism

    of scheme and content within inquiry, he also collapses the dualism between the procedural

    means and substantive ends of democracy. Both are correlative aspects of an ongoing

    process whereby the regulative norms of inquiry (which are themselves in process) guide the

    identification of effective means to achieve the given end.

    Pluralism

    With these similarities in mind, I would now like to turn and highlight a significant problem,

    which manifests itself in various ways through the problem of pluralism (Talisse, 2003; Cf.

    Capps, 2002; Stuhr, 1993, 2002; West, 1998). The formulation of this problem is interesting

    precisely because it applies equally to Deweyan inquiry and Deweyan democracy. Let me

    expand upon this a bit.

    Within the frameworks of Deweyan inquiry and democracy, one is compelled to ask

    two questions: First, for who exactly is a problematic situation actually a problem? And,

    second, what constitutes an adequate solution to such a problem? In The Public and its

    Problems Dewey identifies the public in a distinct, abstract sense, namely, as a group of

    individuals that are directly or indirectly affected by a certain transaction such that they are

    joined by the need to have that effect systematically attended to (LW 2: 245-6). For example,

    individuals living adjacent to a toxic waste disposal plant form a public to the extent that

    leakage from the plant is seeping into their ground water, causing various birth defects

    among the unborn, etc. These people are joined by the need to have these effects attended to

    by local officials and the administrators of the plant.

    So the key feature of Deweys formulation is that a public is defined by a given set of

    effects. Dewey recognizes, however, that this broad definition merely resituates the problem:

    It is not that there is no public, no large body of persons having a common interest in the

    consequences of social transactions. There is too much public, a public too diffused and

    scattered and too intricate in compositionwith little to hold these different publics together

    in an integrated whole (LW 2: 320). This diversity of publics leads to the second, more

    important, question: if there are too many publics, how are they supposed to coordinate

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    10/14

    10

    activities and interests in ways that allow for effective resolution? If interests and

    consequences are so diverse, how can any solution satisfy the myriad interests of different,

    and indeed disparate, publics? Dewey recognizes that this problem is dialogical when he

    says, the essential needis the improvement of the methods and conditions of debate,

    discussion and persuasion. That is the problem of the public. (LW 2: 365) This is the basic

    problem of pluralism: how are various groups, with various and oftentimes mutually

    exclusive interests, supposed to coordinate so as to resolve fundamental differences?

    In this regard, Robert Talisse makes the striking argument that Deweyan democracy

    is not open to pluralism. The type of pluralism he has in mind implies that there is no

    substantive and basic value that could win the consensus of an entire population of rational

    persons (2003: 4). This type of pluralism commits us to accepting that various groups can

    (and often do) formulate different, mutually exclusive solutions to the basic problems

    affecting human life. Given the problem of pluralism, then, democracy is limited to its

    procedural aspects, which are to ensure that various incommensurable viewpoints peacefully

    coexist. If Deweyan democrats are to retain the substantive aspect of democracy, Talisse

    argues, they are forced to reject pluralism precisely on the grounds that it is out of step with

    the notion of democracy as cooperative social inquiry. And this is where the problem of

    pluralism connects to Deweys conception of inquiry.

    Throughout the Logic, Dewey refers to the methods of inquiry he describes as the

    methods of inquiry, not simply as a valid method of inquiry among others. Take, for

    example, Deweys claim that [w]e know that some methods of inquiry are better than others

    in just the same way we know that some methods of surgery, farming, road-making,

    navigating, or what-not are better than others (LW 12: 108). Or his claim that [i]f

    inferences made and conclusions reached are to be valid, the subject-matter dealt with and

    the operations employed must be such as to yield identical results for all who infer and

    reason. If the same evidence leads different persons to different conclusions, then either the

    evidence is only speciously the same, or one conclusion (or both) is wrong (LW 12: 50).

    These passages show Deweys insistence that there are better and worse methods of inquiry,

    and that there are perfectly good reasons to reject certain types of inquiry. It is important to

    remember, though, that the methods of inquiry are themselves undergoing constant

    development, and thus the standards by which inquiry is judged proper are also involved in

    this ongoing process. The point to notice regarding the problem of pluralism, however, is

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    11/14

    11

    that Deweyan inquiry presupposes that a genuine agreement as to the best solution of any

    given problem social or otherwise is at least possible. Again, nothing is outside of

    inquiry; the methods of experimental inquiry, Dewey held, are the tools by which all

    problems could be resolved in the long run. So pluralism is incompatible with Deweyan

    democracy precisely because, at a certain point, it gives up on Deweyan inquiry.

    The upshot of Talisses argument is that Deweyan democrats must 1) affirm the

    normative priority of the values embedded within Deweyan inquiry and 2) exclude those

    who reject such norms from political discourse (2003: 12-13). While the first aspect of this

    conclusion seems entirely correct, the latter aspect seems wrongheaded in that it only pushes

    the problem back a level. How is one to persuade those who do not value the regulative

    norms of Deweyan democracy that they shouldvalue them before they are ever engaged in

    discourse? If you exclude from political discourse those who do not value the norms of

    Deweyan democracy, it seems that there is no recourse to be had. And in a time when this

    seems to be the problematic situation within culture (i.e. when political dialogue is

    deadlocked, both domestically and internationally, by numerous forms of fundamentalism)

    this is neither a viable nor an acceptable solution. So while Talisse is correct to point out that

    pluralism is inconsistent within Deweyan inquiry and democracy, he misses the larger reason

    why this is so, namely, in the way in which pluralism casts the nature of beliefs.

    Sidney Hook once remarked regarding Deweys philosophy that it is not whatyou

    believe that matters, but how you believe it (1939: 236). This is essentially the problem with

    pluralism: it characterizes beliefs such that they are things to hold onto rigidly and literally,

    that different beliefs are things that can be ultimately incommensurable. This is precisely

    what Dewey was disputing within Logic. By conceiving of inquiry as an internally

    constitutive process wherein both the form and content change in relation to the ongoing

    process of engaging actual problematic situations, Dewey makes believing itself a

    hypothetical activity. The regulative norms of Deweyan inquiry, in other words, define a

    comportment to how we hold beliefs. In the end, Deweys conception of experimental

    inquiry does not simply lie on the surface; it goes all the way down, so to speak, and commits

    those who accept it to not only a set of regulative norms, but also to a radically new

    conception of belief.

    In my view, this constitutes the most important, if not also the most difficult, idea in

    Deweys entire philosophy. The nature and possibility of living hypothetically, living with a

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    12/14

    12

    recurring question mark beside your beliefs, is clearly a difficult stance to maintain. Even

    within scientific inquiry, which is the system upon which Dewey bases his theory of inquiry,

    we are apt to wonder whether scientists actually hold their methods and objects

    hypothetically. In the abstract it seems acceptable to say they do, but when talking with

    practicing scientists one gets the distinct impression that they believe in their objects and

    theories just as literally as anyone. It also seems clear that most people do not come to hold

    their beliefs about personal, social, and political matters in a hypothetical way either.

    Tradition and authority still seem to trump experimentalism and openness. The present ways

    of believing, put bluntly, are far from where Deweyan inquiry and democracy seem actual, or

    even possible.

    Talisse suggests that Deweyans begin to construct arguments against pluralism

    (2003: 12). And while his point is taken, I think Deweyans would do much better to address

    the deeper problem regarding how people hold their beliefs in the first place. Simply put,

    pluralism does not seem to be the problem. If anything, pluralism seems to be a step in the

    right direction for those who hold their beliefs fundamentally and are eager to impose those

    beliefs upon everyone else. So rather than engaging pluralists, Deweyans ought to cut out the

    theoretical middleman and initiate a public dialogue concerning the consequences that come

    from how beliefs are held.

    The issue, Dewey says, is a matter of choice, and choice is always a matter of

    alternatives. What the method of intelligence, thoughtful valuation will accomplish, if once it

    be tried, is for the result of trial to determine (LW 1: 437). This hypothetical comportment

    to beliefs, like all ideas, must be tried in actual situations, with concrete agents and concrete

    problems, and judged according to its consequences for practical life. But before this trial

    can begin, a significant reconstruction in how beliefs are held remains the predominant

    challenge for Deweyans today.

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    13/14

    13

    Bibliography

    A note on the references to Deweys work. Since publication of the complete scholarly

    editions of John Deweys works (37 volumes altogether), references have been standardized

    in the following form: (LW 3:75). The LW refers to The Later Works, with corresponding

    references made to The Middle Works (MW), and The Early Works (EW). The first number

    in the sequence refers to the volume within that series, while the second number is the actual

    page reference.

    Campbell, James. 1993. Democracy as Cooperative Inquiry, in John Stuhr (ed.),

    Philosophy and the Reconstruction of Culture, Albany: SUNY Press.

    Capps, John. 2002. Achieving Pluralism (Why AIDS Activists are Different from

    Creationists), in Burke, Hester, and Talisse (eds.), Deweys Logical Theory: New Studies

    and Interpretations, Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press.

    Dewey, John. 1976-1983. 1976-1983. The Need for a Recovery in Philosophy, in John

    Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1925, Volume 10. Jo Ann Boydston (ed.). 15 vols.

    Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    ----------. 1976-1983. Philosophy and Democracy, in John Dewey: The Middle Works,

    1899-1925, Volume 11. Jo Ann Boydston (ed.). 15 vols. Carbondale: Southern IllinoisUniversity Press.

    ----------. 1976-1983. Reconstruction in Philosophy, in John Dewey: The Middle Works,

    1899-1925, Volume 12. Jo Ann Boydston (ed.). 15 vols. Carbondale: Southern Illinois

    University Press.

    ----------. 1981-1990. Experience and Nature, in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953,

    Volume 1. Jo Ann Boydston (ed.). 17 vols. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    ----------. 1981-1990. The Public and its Problems, inJohn Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-

    1953, Volume 2. Jo Ann Boydston (ed.). 17 vols. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University

    Press.

    ----------. 1981-1990. The Quest for Certainty, inJohn Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953,

    Volume 4. Jo Ann Boydston (ed.). 17 vols. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

  • 8/7/2019 Inquiry and Democracy

    14/14

    14

    ----------. 1981-1990. Liberalism and Social Action, in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-

    1953, Volume 11. Jo Ann Boydston (ed.). 17 vols. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University

    Press.

    ----------. 1981-1990. Authority and Social Change, in John Dewey: The Later Works,

    1925-1953, Volume 11. Jo Ann Boydston (ed.). 17 vols. Carbondale: Southern Illinois

    University Press.

    ----------. 1981-1990. Democracy is Radical, in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-

    1953, Volume 11. Jo Ann Boydston (ed.). 17 vols. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University

    Press.

    ----------. 1981-1990. Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, inJohn Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-

    1953, Volume 12. Jo Ann Boydston (ed.). 17 vols. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University

    Press.

    ----------. 1981-1990. Freedom and Culture, in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953,

    Volume 13. Jo Ann Boydston (ed.). 17 vols. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    ----------. 1981-1990. Creative Democracy The task before us, inJohn Dewey: The Later

    Works, 1925-1953, Volume 14. Jo Ann Boydston (ed.). 17 vols. Carbondale: Southern

    Illinois University Press.

    Hook, Sidney. 1939. John Dewey: An Intellectual Portrait. New York: Prometheus Books.

    Kuhn, Thomas. 1996. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of

    Chicago Press.

    Stuhr, John. 1993. Democracy as a Way of Life, in John Stuhr (ed.), Philosophy and the

    Reconstruction of Culture, Albany: SUNY Press.

    ----------. 2002. Power/Inquiry, in Burke, Hester, and Talisse (eds.), Deweys Logical

    Theory: New Studies and Interpretations, Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press.

    Talisse, Robert. 2003. Can Democracy be a Way of Life? Deweyan Democracy and the

    Problem of Pluralism, Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, v. 39, no. 1, pp. 1-21.

    West, Cornel. 1989. The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism.

    London: Macmillian Press.

    Westbrook, Robert B. 1991. John Dewey and American Democracy, Ithaca: CornellUniversity Press.