Human Values Print Out

download Human Values Print Out

of 17

Transcript of Human Values Print Out

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    1/17

    Neurobiology of human values

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    2/17

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    3/17

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    4/17

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    5/17

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    6/17

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    7/17

    Practice of value by RAZ

    2. The Thesis in Brief

    A. The Thesis

    It is time to put some fiesh on the enigmatic remarks made so far. The

    social dependence of values, or at least the aspect of it that concerns me,

    can be expressed as the combination of two theses:The special social dependence thesis claims that some values exist only if

    there are (or were) social practices sustaining them.

    The (general) social dependence thesis claims that, with some exceptions,all values depend on social practices either by being subject to

    the special thesis or through their dependence on values that aresubject to the special thesis.

    III. CHANGE AND UNDERSTANDING

    1. Understanding and ValueTo the extent that it is possible to distinguish them, my emphasis so far

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    8/17

    has been on ontological questions, on the existence of values. It is timeto shift to questions of understanding of values, remembering all along

    that the two cannot be entirely separated.Understanding, rather than knowledge, is the term that comes to

    mind when thinking of evaluative judgments. Judgment, rather than

    mere knowledge, is what the practically wise person possesses. Why?

    What is the difference? It is a matter of degree, with understanding and

    judgment involving typically, FIrst, knowledge in depth, and secondly,

    and as a result, knowledge much of which is implicit. Understanding is

    knowledge in depth. It is connected knowledge in two respects. First,

    knowledge of what is understood is rich enough to place its object in its

    context, to relate it to its location and its neighbourhood, literally and

    metaphorically. Second, knowledge of what is understood is also connected

    to ones imagination, emotions, feelings, and intentions. What

    one understands one can imagine, empathise with, feel for, and be disposed

    to act appropriately regarding. Understanding tends to involve a good deal of implicit knowledge precisely

    because it is connectedknowledge. Its richness exceeds our powers of articulation.

    Understanding is displayed, and put to use, through good judgment.To illustrate the point, think of a simple example of good judgment.

    Jane, we may say, is a good judge of wines. Ask her which wine toserve with the meal. John, by way of contrast, has perfect knowledge of

    the bus timetable. You should ask him which bus to take, but it wouldbe odd to think of him as being a good judge of bus journeys, or as having

    a good judgment of bus journeys, in the way that Jane is clearly a

    good judge of wine because of her excellent judgment regarding wines.

    The difference is that Johns views, perfect though they are, are based on

    one kind of consideration, whereas Jane is judging the bearing of a multitude

    of factors on the choice of wine. Moreover, the ways the different

    factors bear on each other, and on the ultimate choice, defy comprehensive

    articulation. If Jane is articulate and refiective (and to possess good

    judgment she need be neither) she may be able to explain every aspect of

    every one of her decisions, but she cannot describe exhaustively all aspectsof her decisions, let alone provide a general detailed and contentfull1

    procedure for arriving at the choices or opinions she may reach on

    different real and hypothetical occasions, as John can.

    It is not difFIcult to see why values call for understanding and judgment.The connection is most evident regarding speciFIc values. They

    are mixed values, constituted by standards determining ways for idealcombinations of contributing values, and criteria for various relationships

    that objects can have to them (simple instantiation, inversion,etc.). Their knowledge requires knowledge of the various values that

    combine in their mix, and of the way their presence affects the value ofthe object given the presence of other values. Regarding these matters

    whose complexity and dense texture defy complete articulation, knowledgeis connected and implicit, amounting, when it is reasonably refiective

    and reasonably complete, to understanding, and its use, in forming

    opinions and in taking decisions, calls for judgment.

    The case of general values may be less clear. The more general the

    value, the more homogeneous and simple it is likely to be. Can one

    not have knowledge of it without understanding, and apply it without judgment? The apparent simplicity of

    general values is, however, misleading.

    To be sure, one can have limited knowledge of them, as one can

    of more speciFIc values, without understanding. One can know that freedom

    is the value of being allowed to act as one sees FIt. Such one-liners are

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    9/17

    true so far as they go. We FInd them useful because we have the backgroundknowledge that enables us to read them correctly. Relying on abstract

    formulations of the content of values, and denyingthat they need tobe understood in context and interpreted in light of other related values,

    leads to one of the most pernicious forms of fanaticism.

    As I have already mentioned, more general values are explained at

    least in part by the way they feed into more speciFIc ones. The point can

    be illustrated in various ways, appropriate to various examples. There

    could be forms of friendship different, some quite radically so, from

    those that exist today. But one cannot pursue friendship (a relatively

    general value) except through the speciFIc forms it has (this comment

    will be somewhat qualiFIed when we discuss innovation and change below).

    Therefore, knowledge of the value of friendship is incomplete

    without an understanding of its speciFIc forms, with their speciFIc forms

    of excellence.2. Interpretation

    Like aspect-seeing, interpretations admit both of FIxity and of fiexibility.

    That is, it takes an effort for people to see the sense of rival interpretations,

    and the common belief that if I am right the other must be

    wrong is no help in this. Even after one sees the merit of a rival interpretation

    there may be only one that one feels at home with. Yet some people

    can be at home with various ones and feel free to rely on them ondifferent occasions.

    The important point to make is that the social dependence of values

    enables us to understand better such developments and their general

    availability. It enables us to reconcile the objectivity of values with theirfiuidity and sensitivity to social practices, to shared understanding and

    shared meanings. It enables us to combine holding to a FIxed point ofreference, which is essential to thinking of values as objective and to our

    being able to orient ourselves by them, either by trying to realise them

    or through more complex relations to them, and realising that their FIxityis temporary and fragile, which explains how change is often continuous,and no different from their further development in one way rather

    than another, which was equally open. None of this is explainable unlesswe take seriously the contingency at the heart of value.

    Subjectivity of value

    Hume put the view this way:

    Take any action allowd to be vicious: Wilful murder, for

    instance. Examine it in all its lights, and see if you can find

    that matter of fact, or real existence, which you call vice. In

    which-ever way you take it, you find only certain passions,

    motives, volitions and thoughts. There is no other matter of

    fact in the case. The vice entirely escapes you, as long as you

    consider the object. You never can find it, till you turn your

    reflexion into your own breast, and find a sentiment of disapprobation,

    which arises in you, towards this action. . . . So

    that when you pronounce any action or character to be vicious,you mean nothing, but that from the constitution of your

    nature you have a feeling or sentiment of blame from thecontemplation of it. Vice and virtue, therefore, may be compard

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    10/17

    to sounds, colours, heat and cold, which, according tomodern philosophy, are not qualities in objects, but perceptions

    in the mind.l

    There are great differences and conflicts among peoples valuings,

    and social and political life is a matter of resolving those conflicts

    and reconciling opposed interests. But what calls for solution isthe question of which is to prevail. Each opposing interest must

    somehow be accommodated.

    This seems to require of subjectivism both detachment from

    and engagement with the very same experiences, ideas, and beliefs.

    We must stand apart from our color beliefs and our evaluationswhile also holding onto them.

    Our attributing thoughts or beliefs about nonexistent

    things to others therefore does not require that we ourselves

    believe the world to be populated with the things those

    complex ideas represent. We can see how people come to think

    that way without our agreeing that the thoughts they have are true.

    Another view holds that what is being said is that the act is suchthat all human beings of certain kinds would get a certain feeling

    toward it if they knew of it. Both these views see the so-called

    evaluative judgment as a factual assertion about actual or hypothetical

    feelings on the part of certain human beings. In that

    respect they are like the dispositional analysis of an objects color.

    One merit of all theories of this sort is that they preserve one

    striking feature of our evaluative thought. They allow that our

    reactions to the world do involve genuine beliefs about the goodness

    or badness of things. They see us as asserting what we take

    to be truths about the world. And there is very good reason forinsisting that we think of our moral judgments as either true or

    false. Not only do we seem to believe them and assert them andtry to support them by reasoning. Moral sentences can also be

    embedded in other sentences in what certainly looks like a purelytruth-functional way.

    The mind, Hume says, hasa great propensity to spread itself on external objects, and to

    conjoin with them any internal impressions, which they occasion,

    and which always make their appearance at the same time that

    these objects discover themselves to the senses.8 In making moral

    judgments we think we are ascribing moral characteristics to the

    acts we observe; we treat our moral views as if they were, so to

    speak, propositional, but in fact they are mere projections. We

    gild or stain the facts with our feelings, but all that is strictly

    true in what we say is the purely factual, nonevaluative content towhich something in the value-free world could correspond.

    If my moral judgment is a report that I have a certain feeling,or that all human beings would get a certain kind of feeling

    under certain conditions, the kind of feeling in question must be

    identified before we can know what is being said. Not just any

    feeling will do. Hume says that the feeling arising from virtue is

    agreeable, and the feeling of vice is uneasy or unpleasant,

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    11/17

    but in saying that an act is wrong, even if I am indeed sayingsomething about how people do or would feel, I am not saying

    only that they would get unpleasant or disagreeable feelings fromthe act. They might get unpleasant feelings from something they

    eat, but that would not make what they eat bad, or vicious, or

    wrong. So we still need some explanation of what it is to think

    that something is bad, or vicious, and some account of how we canintelligibly attribute such thoughts or attitudes to people.

    Knowing that a blue light is shining on a white wall, Iwill know that a person looking at it sees blue and, if he doesntknow about the light, that he also believes that the wall is blue.

    I know the belief is false, but I can attribute that belief to him.I can do that because of my own general competence in the language

    of color and my knowledge of what colors things are in theenvironment. Similarly, if I do not agree with a persons evaluative

    judgment, I can still correctly attribute it to him and understand

    what it is for him to hold that view, because of my own

    general competence in the language of evaluation and my knowledge

    of the evaluative features of the environment - what thingsare good or bad, better or worse than others.

    This would have the consequence that the only materials

    available to us for understanding what appears to be evaluative

    thought and for seeing how it figures in human action and human

    social arrangements would be simple, isolated feelings with noevaluative content.

    Perhaps

    something like that is what finds expression in the popular halfthought

    that morality is after all just a matter of what people

    want, or what they like or dont like. Or worse still, the thought

    that it is just a matter of whose likes and dislikes are going to prevail.

    And now there is the view, in the United States at least,

    that morality is itself just one among a great many special interests

    that have to be accommodated in society. People are

    thought to be just pushing their own personal interests or seeking

    their own gratifications in one way or another, and the morality

    lobby is encouraged to fight it out with the military, the corporations,

    the doctors, the judges, and so on.

    Morality, for example, is a quite general phenomenon which

    seems distinctive of the human species. No other creatures seemmoved by considerations of good and bad, right and wrong.

    Descartess

    evil demon represented the threat that the way things are independently

    of me might be extremely different from the way I take

    them to be. If the demon exists, he alone exists beyond me, and

    his clever machinations make me think that I live in a world of

    earth and water, trees and buildings, and other people with human

    bodies like the one I think Ive got. He gives me such thoughts

    and beliefs, so they are produced by something objective andindependent of me, but there would be almost nothing in that

    world corresponding to any of those thoughts. They would almostall be false. The challenge of skepticism is to show how I know

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    12/17

    that I do not live in such a world. Once we see human knowledgeas a combination of an objective and a subjective factor in

    this way, and we acknowledge the possibility of a largely or evenentirely subjective source for most of our beliefs, it seems impossible

    to explain how those beliefs could ever amount to knowledgeor reasonable belief.

    Any study of human socialization or human development along

    these lines would be a study of how a human being or a group of

    human beings gets absorbed into a culture whose members alreadyhave some values or other, or how the possession of one set ofvalues gets transformed into possession of another. It would explain

    at most the transmission of values, perhaps even the transmissionof the very idea of value, from those who have it to those who do not.

    We want to understand the nature of any

    evaluative thoughts or attitudes. We ask what their special content

    is, what is really being thought. And that first takes the form

    of asking what would be so if they were true. In trying to answerthat question, either we merely repeat the thought - Killing a

    human being is bad is true if and only if killing a human being

    is bad - and so we do not feel we are explaining it, or we try to

    express its content in other terms that reveal in some illuminating

    way what is really being said. If those further terms are still

    evaluative, we will not feel that we have explained what it is for

    any evaluative thought or attitude to be true; we will simply have

    exchanged one such thought for another.

    So if we are going to make any progress in explaining theevaluative as such, we will either say that having what we call an

    evaluative attitude or opinion is not really a matter of thinkingsomething to be true - but instead is expressing a feeling or issuing

    a prescription or making a recommendation or some such

    thing - or we will say that it is a matter of our thinking truesomething that is really nonevaluative and so could hold in theobjective world - perhaps something about nonevaluative feelings

    that we and others do or would feel under certain conditions.

    I would draw here on the parallel I see with the case of colors.

    If we did not make categorical ascriptions of colors to things

    around us we could not acknowledge the existence of such thingsas perceptions of colors or beliefs about the colors of things on

    the part of human beings. We could not conceive of the worldas containing those very perceptions and beliefs that subjectivism

    about colors claims have nothing corresponding to them

    in reality and are nothing more than our subjective responses toan objectively colorless world.I want to say more about what this idea amounts to and exactly

    what it implies about our understanding of values and colors, and

    what it does not. It says in its strongest form that we cannot think

    of a world in which people perceive particular colors or believe

    that things are colored without ourselves being prepared to ascribe

    color categorically to things in the world. We cannot understand

    human beings to have evaluative opinions or attitudes to the effect

    that such-and-such is good or bad without ourselves sometimesrecognizing the goodness or badness of certain things. And in

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    13/17

    making those ascriptions of color, or of value, we are taking certainthings to be true. We take it to be part of the way things are,

    for example, that grass is green, or that the deliberate killing ofa human being is a very bad thing. Our engagement with, or

    endorsement of, aspects of the world of those general types is

    required for our ascribing to human beings beliefs or attitudes

    with those types of contents. What we take to be facts of the

    world are implicated in our making sense of thoughts of theworld. The two cannot be pried apart completely.

    And this seemsto imply that the truth of the majority of our beliefs is a necessary

    condition of our having them - that if we have any beliefs orattitudes at all, the list of sentences which state the contents of

    those beliefs or attitudes will contain mostly truths. That wouldconnect our beliefs necessarily with the way the world is.

    This is just the position of Kants Critique of Pure Redson,

    perhaps the greatest attempt there has ever been to prove that thetruth about the way the world is cannot come apart in general

    from our thinking and perceiving in the ways we do. Kant thought

    there were necessary conditions of the possibility of all thought

    and experience, and that not all those necessary conditions arethemselves just further thoughts or beliefs. They include as well

    many nonpsychological truths, so not only must we think a certainway, but the world independent of us must be a certain way, in

    general, if we are even able to think of or perceive anything at all.

    Kant saw that some philosophical theory was needed to explain

    this necessary link between thought and experience and the

    world, and his explanation was the theory of transcendental idealism.

    It was the only explanation he thought there could be. We

    can know that the world in general must conform to our thinking

    and perceiving in certain ways because our being able to think and

    perceive what we do actually constitutes the world that we perceive

    and believe in. The price of showing that our thoughts and

    perceptions and the truth of their contents cannot come apart in

    general was that the truth of what we believe about the world

    somehow consists in our having the kinds of thoughts and perceptions

    that we do. The world turns out to be dependent on ourthoughts and perceptions in some way after all. That is a form of

    idealism, which is one variety of what I am calling subjectivism.If we ask in a similar vein how our color beliefs, or our evaluative

    beliefs, could not fail to be true, a more particular version of

    that same idealism or subjectivism will seem like the only possibleanswer. What it is for color judgments to be true, for thereto be a world of colored objects, it would say, is just for human

    beings to agree for the most part in their ascription of colors to

    things. There might be considerable disagreement in particular

    cases, but on the whole there would be nothing more to things

    being colored than human perceivers agreeing in general in the

    perceptions they have and the judgments they make about the

    colors of things. Similarly, for things to have value, and to have

    the particular values they have, would simply be for human beings

    to agree in general in their ascriptions of value to things. Again,

    there is room for wide disagreement and uncertainty, but on the

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    14/17

    whole the truth of value judgments would amount to nothingmore than agreement, or the possibility of agreement, in human

    beings evaluative beliefs.

    Because

    he thought that we cannot conceive of an object without perceiving

    it, he thought that we cannot conceive of an object that remainsunperceived. He concluded that an object could not possibly

    exist unperceived - it is inconceivable. But that is to start

    with the fact that we cannot do something, that we cannot performa certain feat, and to conclude that a certain thing could not

    possibly be so.

    Value ofValues

    How does one define values or a value system?

    A value could be defined as a belief or attitude that you hold close; something that you want to keep as a standardfor judging yourself and the rest of the world. It is the basis for your sense of right and wrong, good or bad.

    Values can be related to health, cultural awareness, spirituality, religion, preservation of nature, integrity, loyalty,wealth, stability and security, creativity, independence, search for fame or peace, personal growth and education.

    Basic Human Values: An OverviewShalom H. SchwartzThe Hebrew University of Jerusalem

    The value concept [is] able to unify the apparently diverse interests of all the sciencesconcerned with human behavior.[Rokeach, 1973]

    A psychologist wrote these words that proclaim the centrality of the value concept.Sociologists [e.g., Williams, 1968] and anthropologists [e.g., Kluckhohn, 1951] have echoed

    similar opinions. These theorists view values as the criteria people use to evaluate actions,people, and events.

    This paper presents a theory within this tradition. The theory1 identifies ten motivationally

    distinct value orientations that people in all cultures recognize, and it specifies the dynamics

    of conflict and congruence among these values. It aims to be a unifying theory for the field of

    human motivation, a way of organizing the different needs, motives, and goals proposed by

    other theories.

    Introduction to the Values TheoryWhen we think of our values, we think of what is important to us in our lives (e.g., security,

    independence, wisdom, success, kindness, pleasure). Each of us holds numerous values with

    varying degrees of importance. A particular value may be very important to one person, but

    unimportant to another. Consensus regarding the most useful way to conceptualize basic

    values has emerged gradually since the 1950s. We can summarize the main features of theconception of basic values implicit in the writings of many theorists and researchers2 as

    follows:

    Values are beliefs. But they are beliefs tied inextricably to emotion, not objective, cold

    ideas.

    Values are a motivational construct. They refer to the desirable goals people strive to

    attain.

    Values transcend specific actions and situations. They are abstract goals. The abstract

    nature of values distinguishes them from concepts like norms and attitudes, which

    usually refer to specific actions, objects, or situations.

    Values guide the selection or evaluation of actions, policies, people, and events. That is,

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    15/17

    values serve as standards or criteria.

    Values are ordered by importance relative to one another. Peoples values form an

    ordered system of value priorities that characterize them as individuals. This hierarchicalfeature of values also distinguishes them from norms and attitudes.

    The Values Theory defines values as desirable, trans-situational goals, varying in importance,that serves as guiding principles in peoples lives. The five features above are common to all

    values. The crucial content aspect that distinguishes among values is the type of motivational

    goal they express. In order to coordinate with others in the pursuit of the goals that are

    important to them, groups and individuals represent these requirements cognitively

    (linguistically) as specific values about which they communicate. Ten motivationally distinct,

    broad and basic values are derived from three universal requirements of the human condition:

    needs of individuals as biological organisms, requisites of coordinated social interaction, and

    survival and welfare needs of groups.

    The ten basic values are intended to include all the core values recognized in cultures around

    the world. These ten values cover the distinct content categories found in earlier value

    theories, in value questionnaires from different cultures, and in religious and philosophical

    discussions of values. It is possible to classify virtually all the items found in lists of specific

    values from different cultures, into one of these ten motivationally distinct basic values.

    Schwartz [Schwartz, 1992, 2005a] details the derivations of the ten basic values. For

    example, a conformity value was derived from the prerequisites of interaction and of groupsurvival. For interaction to proceed smoothly and for groups to maintain themselves,individuals must restrain impulses and inhibit actions that might hurt others. A self-direction

    value was derived from organismic needs for mastery and from the interaction requirementsof autonomy and independence.

    Each of the ten basic values can be characterized by describing its central motivational goal:1. Self-Direction. Independent thought and action; choosing, creating, exploring.

    2. Stimulation. Excitement, novelty, and challenge in life.3. Hedonism. Pleasure and sensuous gratification for oneself.

    4. Achievement. Personal success through demonstrating competence according tosocial standards.

    5. Power. Social status and prestige, control or dominance over people and resources.3

    6. Security. Safety, harmony, and stability of society, of relationships, and of self.7. Conformity. Restraint of actions, inclinations, and impulses likely to upset or harm

    others and violate social expectations or norms.8. Tradition. Respect, commitment, and acceptance of the customs and ideas that

    traditional culture or religion provide the self.4

    9. Benevolence. Preserving and enhancing the welfare of those with whom one is infrequent personal contact (the in-group).5

    10. Universalism. Understanding, appreciation, tolerance, and protection for the welfare

    of all people and for nature.6The comprehensiveness of any set of value orientations in covering the full range of

    motivational goals cannot be tested definitively. However, some evidence is consistent with

    the comprehensiveness of the ten basic values. Local researchers in 18 countries added to thesurvey value items of significance in their culture that they thought might be missing. These

    were assigned a priori to the existing basic values whose motivational goals they were

    expected to express. Analyses including the added value items revealed that these items

    correlated as expected with the core, marker items from the basic values to which they wereassigned. They identified no additional basic values.

    Sources of Value PrioritiesPeoples life circumstances provide opportunities to pursue or express some values moreeasily than others: For example, wealthy persons can pursue power values more easily, and

    people who work in the free professions can express self-direction values more easily. Life

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    16/17

    circumstances also impose constraints against pursuing or expressing values. Havingdependent children constrains parents to limit their pursuit of stimulation values by avoiding

    risky activities. And people with strongly ethnocentric peers find it hard to expressuniversalism values. In other words, life circumstances make the pursuit or expression of

    different values more or less rewarding or costly. For example, a woman who lives in a

    society where common gender stereotypes prevail is likely to be rewarded for pursuingbenevolence values and sanctioned for pursuing power.

    Life Circumstances: How Background Variables Influence Value PrioritiesTypically, people adapt their values to their life circumstances. They upgrade the importancethey attribute to values they can readily attain and downgrade the importance of values whose

    pursuit is blocked [Schwartz & Bardi, 97]. For example, people in jobs that afford freedom ofchoice increase the importance of self-direction values at the expense of conformity values

    [Kohn & Schooler, 1983]. Upgrading attainable values and downgrading thwarted valuesapplies to most, but not to all values. The reverse occurs with values that concern material

    well-being (power) and security. When such values are blocked, their importance increases;when they are easily attained their importance drops. For example, people who suffer

    economic hardship and social upheaval attribute more importance to power and security

    values than those who live in relative comfort and safety [Inglehart, 1997].7

    Peoples age, education, gender, and other characteristics largely determine the life

    circumstances to which they are exposed. These include their socialization and learningexperiences, the social roles they play, the expectations and sanctions they encounter, and the

    abilities they develop. Thus, differences in background characteristics represent differences in

    the life circumstances that affect value priorities.

    The Pattern of Value Relations with Other Variables: An Integrated System

    How age influences valuesIt is common to speak of three systematic sources of value change in adulthood: historical

    events that impact on specific age cohorts (e.g., war, depression), physical ageing (e.g., loss of

    strength or memory), and life stage (e.g., child rearing, widowhood). Each of these sources

    affects value-relevant experiences. They determine the opportunities and constraints people

    confront and their resources for coping.

    CohortsInglehart [1997] demonstrated that older persons in much of the world give higher priority to

    materialist vs. post-materialist values than younger people.9 He interpreted this as a cohort

    effect. People form values in adolescence that change little thereafter. The more economic and

    physical insecurity the adolescents experience, the more important materialist values are to

    them throughout their lives. The lower priority on materialist values in younger cohorts is dueto the increasing prosperity and security many nations have enjoyed during most of the past 50

    years.

    Physical ageingStrength, energy, cognitive speed, memory, and sharpness of the senses decline with age.Although the onset and speed of decline vary greatly, the decline rarely reverses. This suggests

    several hypotheses. With age, security values may be more important because a safe,predictable environment is more critical as capacities to cope with change wane. Stimulation

    values may be less important because novelty and risk are more threatening. Conformity andtradition values may also be more important with age because accepted ways of doing things

    are less demanding and threatening. In contrast, hedonism values may be less important

    because dulling of the senses reduces the capacity to enjoy sensual pleasure. Achievement and,

    perhaps, power values may also be less important for older people who are less able to perform

    demanding tasks successfully and to obtain social approval.

    Life stageOpportunities, demands, and constraints associated with life stages may cause age differences

    in values. Gender influences the experience of life stages, but we focus here on the main effects

  • 8/4/2019 Human Values Print Out

    17/17