Health Care Ethics

22
Ch. 3, Principles of Beneficence and Nonmaleficence

description

Ch. 3, Principles of Beneficence and Nonmaleficence. Health Care Ethics. Definitions. Beneficence = doing good, usually to another person or persons Nonmaleficence = avoiding evil, usually to another person or persons - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Transcript of Health Care Ethics

Page 1: Health Care Ethics

Ch. 3, Principles of Beneficence and Nonmaleficence

Page 2: Health Care Ethics

Beneficence = doing good, usually to another person or persons

Nonmaleficence = avoiding evil, usually to another person or persons

We are typically thought to have duties of beneficence and nonmaleficence; in some circumstances these ethical duties are important enough that they generate legal duties … examples?

See here.

Page 3: Health Care Ethics

Ch. 3, under the titles • The Impossibility of Doing All Good, and • The Impossibility of Avoiding All Evil,

the book suggests our inability to do all good for others, and avoid all evil for them, excuses us from an obligation to do all good and avoid all evil.

The principle assumed but not discussed directly is the Ought Implies Can principle, which says:

For it to be true that S has an obligation to do X, S must be able to do X.

Page 4: Health Care Ethics

So, the book notes, p 58, that space and time limit our duties …

• time keeps us from being obliged to help, say, Abe Lincoln

• space keeps us from being obliged to help folks in other states or countries (or across the street)

• our talents limit us• available technology limits us, and even• personal risk limits us.

These are all limits on beneficence.

Page 5: Health Care Ethics

p 60 (4th ed. 59) discusses how our inability to avoid risks limits our duties to avoid risks …

Risks to self: Crossing the street (getting hit by a car) Taking aspirin (Reyes syndrome) Even staying in bed (bedsores)

Risks of condoning the unethical: Living in a country that is unfair to minorities Joining a company that pollutes Joining a hospital that employs bad doctors or nurses

These are all limits on nonmaleficence.

Page 6: Health Care Ethics

Not only does the inability to help others limit our duties of beneficence, so does fair distribution.

Does it make sense to try to meet the mere desires of some while the needs of others are unmet?

To help address that question, the book defines

Necessary Goods = goods required for remaining human maintaining dignity

Page 7: Health Care Ethics

The list of necessary goods … Nourishment Shelter Clothing “membership in social groups

necessary for the psychological growth of the person”

Health care?

The book puts off questions about health care till chapter 4.

Consider Peter Singer’s model of giving 1/5th of your income to world hunger relief. Who bears the burden, exactly, of providing these ‘necessary’ goods?

Page 8: Health Care Ethics

What does “membership in social groups necessary for the

psychological growth of the person,”

at the bottom of page 60 (4th ed. 59), mean?

P 61 (4th ed. 60), bottom:“most of the goods we have to do are specified by

social agreement, whether through law or custom, as well as through relationships, roles, or agreements.”

So, for children: family, primary and secondary education; for adults: citizenship & professions

Page 9: Health Care Ethics

In health care, benefits professionals are obliged to provide are specified in part by their

• relationship (doctor/patient)

• role (from custodian to doctor or administrator)

• agreements (from formal contracts to ‘may I help you into that chair?’)

Page 10: Health Care Ethics

Near the end of the section:

“the physician or nurse cannot profess to do more than their particular education and skills permit, nor can they do more than the patient agrees to.... These two limits or specifications—one by talent, the other by agreement—must be kept in mind at all times in health care ethics.”

The quotation above leads naturally into specification of nonmaleficence (as in, trying to do more than your talents permit might produce injury)…

Page 11: Health Care Ethics

The first principle of nonmaleficence is:

Primum Non Nocere (prē-muJm -nōn-no-kā-rā):First, do no harm

The phrase is attributed to Hippocrates in various forms. While the principle is not controversial, the question of what constitutes harm in particular circumstances and when to trade harm for other benefits complicates its application.

Page 12: Health Care Ethics

P 62-63, the book rejects Thomas Aquinas’ principle of double effect (read the last paragraph) in favor of the principle of proportionality; we’ll focus on the latter principle.

Principle of Proportionality:Provided the action does not go

directly against the dignity of the individual person (the intrinsic good), there must be a proportionate good to justify risking the evil effect.

Page 13: Health Care Ethics

4 factors that aid in assessing proportionality:1. Alternatives (always choose the path to a good

that produces the least evil as a byproduct)2. The level of good and evil (recognize that some

goods are better than others, some evils worse than others)

3. The probability of the good or evil (unlikely goods and evils count less than certain ones in calculating proportionate reasons)

4. The causal influence of the agent (what level of contribution your actions make to the evil produced in a group setting)

Page 14: Health Care Ethics

P 66: Under Preliminary Summary:

Reformulation (from “do good”?) of principle of Beneficence: Do good unless the consequences of

doing good produce a disproportionate evil

Reformulation (from First, do no harm?) of the principle of nonmaleficence: Avoid evil and evil consequences unless

you have a proportionate reason for risking or permitting them

Page 15: Health Care Ethics

What results from the previous discussion for the patient’s obligation of beneficence and nonmaleficence regarding their own health?

Take care of your health as long as, all things considered, this does not produce more harm than good – p67

Why the qualifier ‘all things considered’? … (next slide)

Page 16: Health Care Ethics

The book includes the qualifier because patients have many obligations that compete with their obligation to their own health (say, the health of their children, service to their country, etc.).

Only the patient’s obligation, stated in a principle of beneficence and nonmaleficence, includes the qualifier ‘all things considered’; the health professional and or surrogate cannot weight the patient’s obligations for them.

Page 17: Health Care Ethics

The health care provider’s obligations regarding beneficence and nonmaleficence are guided by the Medical Indications Principle:

Granted informed consent, the physician should do what is medically indicated, such that, from a medical point of view, more good than evil will result

Page 18: Health Care Ethics

Consider:Kid A hurt his arm when pushed down the stairs

by a bully at school (presents with a bruise and acts aloof)

Kid B hurt his arm playing on the monkey bars (has trouble raising arm, but can do so)

Kid C hurt his arm doing a stupid stunt on a skateboard, illegally (has a scary looking lump and discoloration mid forearm, can’t lift his arm)

Also, Kid C is in the most pain, B second most, A in very little pain

Following the Medical Indications Principle, only kids B and C qualify for x-rays, say. How do you decide who goes first between Kids B and C?

Is pain a medical indicator?Is the kid’s responsibility a medical indicator?

Page 19: Health Care Ethics

Skip to page 76-78 and read discussion of Beneficence and the Right to Refuse Patients

Read / consider #1 in the ‘Cases for Analysis’, p. 79

Page 20: Health Care Ethics

Ideally, the surrogate simply presents the patient’s judgments when the patient can’t speak for him or herself, therefore, the first principle of surrogate obligation is called:

The Substituted Judgment principle

Complications arise when doubts about surrogate accuracy enter. Studies show surrogates are regularly wrong. (p 71, Ethics)

Page 21: Health Care Ethics

When patients were never competent, or were competent but failed to make their wishes known, two principles guide surrogates:

The Best Interests principle, and The Rational Choice principle

The best interests principle says to do what is in the patient’s best interests excluding the interests of even family, loved ones, and friends

Page 22: Health Care Ethics

The rational choice principle, in contrast, expands relevant considerations to include everything the patient might consider in making their decisions (concern for family and friends, duties to family and friends, desires that conflict with their own personal welfare, etc.)

Compare the application of these principles, p 72, Ethics.