Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

29
Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism

Transcript of Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Page 1: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Epistemology

Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl

4. Foundationalism

Page 2: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Justified beliefs

We think that there are beliefs which are justified, and which are not justified.

We have good reasons to accept some beliefs, but of course there are beliefs which we don't accept.

It is justified that:

Hemoglobin in the blood is what transports oxygen from the lungs or gills to the rest of the body (i.e. the tissues) where it releases the oxygen for cell use.

Napoleon has lost a battle at Waterloo.

Ordinary beliefs like: This course is held on Budapest University of Technology.

It is not justified that: There are extraterrestrial intelligent beings, and they have already visited the Earth.

Page 3: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

The foundation of justified beliefs

Some beliefs are known or justifiedly believed only because some other beliefs are known or justifiedly believed.

When we a justification for a belief, we usually appeal to other beliefs.

Questions: Should all beliefs be supported by other beliefs?

Are there beliefs which cannot be doubted? Is there an absolute certain ground of our knowledge?

Are some beliefs rightly believed apart from receiving support from other beliefs? What is the nature of the proper support between beliefs?

Page 4: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

How do you know...?

There are conditions in which we accept a statement without further justification.

(When I'm reading):„ I am reading.”,

„Budapest is the capital of Hungary.”,

„The water freezes at the temperature of 0 degrees centigrade.”

We don't doubt them.

But of course there are conditions in which we usually require a justification.

If someone makes a statement, and others don't accept it, or ask for reasons to believe it.

Page 5: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

How do you...?

When we ask: „How do you know that?”, we ask for a justification.

Examples: Debates in everyday life.

On the court the prosecutor wants to prove that the defendant is guilt.

Scientific theories require justification. (There are different methods and requirements of justification.)

But there might be situations in which even the statement 'Budapest is the capital of Hungary' requires for a justification. (A foreign turist confuses Bucharest with Budapest.)

Whan if the requirement of justification can be applied to every beliefs? What if everything can be doubted?

Page 6: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

The regress argument P1: If there is a justification of our beliefs, then it leads to the

infinite or ends at an unjustified belief or runs in a circle or there are self-justified beliefs.

P2: The infinite reasoning cannot be a proper justification of our beliefs.

P3: The circular reasoning cannot be a proper justification of our beliefs.

P4: Appealing to unjustified belief cannot be proper justification.

P5: There are no self-justified beliefs.

C: None of our beliefs are justified.

Page 7: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Argument for foundationalism Foundationalism is a one of possible responses to the sceptical

conclusion of the regress argument.

Foundationalist rejects P5, and claims that: there are self-justified beliefs.

These are basic beliefs. They are immediatly justified beliefs. Their justification is a non-infential justification.

These basic beliefs are usually considered incorrigible, infallible, certain.

The basic beliefs support the other beliefs. Non-basic beliefs are justified if they can be inferred from basic beliefs.

Page 8: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

The structure of knowledge

Page 9: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Foundationalism

Some beliefs are basic beliefs, and that the rest of one’s beliefs inherit their epistemic status (knowledge or justification) in virtue of receiving support from the basic beliefs.

Two main problems: What are the basic beliefs, and what kind of special character do they have?

How can the basic beliefs provide appropriate support in favour of other, non-basic beliefs?

Page 10: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Classical version of foundationalism

Basic beliefs must be justified independently of reasoning.

Because a belief which can only be justified by inference, its justification is dependent on the justification of other beliefs from which the reasoning proceeds.

Ordinary perceptual beliefs can be fallible.

Examples of perceptual errors: If I see a red shirt in green light I may think it is black.

They are influenced by expectations: If I expect to see my father sitting behind the desk, I may think I do see him if someone is sitting there who resembles him.

There are possible cases of perceptual illusion (and hallucination.)

Page 11: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Perceptual beliefs and fallibility

Problem: If perceptual beliefs are fallible, it seems that need further justification, and hence cannot provide the stopping point for justification.

Therefore the fallible perceptual beliefs cannot be ultimate basis of our knowledge.

Traditional answer of foundationalism: Basic beliefs are not the ordinary perceptual beliefs.

Ordinary perceptual beliefs are about physical objects (or lead me to have beliefs about the external objects.) 'This is a hand.'

I can be mistaken about what I see, but I cannot be mistaken about what it seems to me.

Page 12: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

'It seems to me...'I looked at paper, it seems to white. And I cannot be mistaken

about: it seems to white.

This is certain, infallible, I cannot doubt about it.

We must use very restricted formulations.

It appears to me white.

It remains certainly true even if my perception is wrong.

Page 13: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

'It seems to me it is bent.'

'The pencil is bent.' - false, if the pencil is not bent.

But if the pencil looks to me bent, then it is certainly true that: 'The pencil seems to me bent.'

Page 14: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Classical foundationalism

Classical foundationalism: 1. Our basic beliefs are beliefs about our sensory experience. 'How do you know...?' questions lead to beliefs of immediate experience ('Because I see /hear.. it.')

The basic beliefs are about my present state sensory experience.

2. These beliefs are considered infallible.

3. Other beliefs can be derived from the basic beliefs about sensory experiences.

Other version – Vienna Circle: protocoll-sentences are the basic beliefs - “N.N has made a certain observation (at such and such conditions).”

(or 'confirmations' are the basic beliefs. 'Now it seems to me blue.')

Justified (verified) if and only if it can be derived from the protocoll sentences.

Page 15: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Basic beliefs about experience

Classical foundationalism:

Basic beliefs are beliefs about the phenomenal character of my own present state experiences.

Now it appears to me...

These beliefs are infallible, incorrigible, cannot be doubted.

These beliefs provide the ultimate basis of our knowledge. They are self-justified.

These basic beliefs provide justification for other beliefs.

A belief is justified if and only if it is a basic belief or can be justified by means of basic beliefs (or by a belief which is justified by basic beliefs...).

Page 16: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Incorrigible beliefs

Definition:

Incorrigibility: A proposition P is incorrigible for a person S if and only if (1) it is necessarily true that if S believes P then P is true, and (2) it is necessarily true that if S believes ~P then P is false.

Believing P should guarantee that P is true, and believing ~P should guarantee that P is false.

This is attempt to define incorrigibility for propositions: No one could be in a position to correct an incorrigible belief.

Beliefs about the external world are corrigible, but according to classical foundationalism appearance beliefs are incorrigible (cannot be doubted).

Page 17: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Problems with definition

But there are beliefs which are certain (in a sense) and no one could be in a position to correct them which are not self-justifying.

When I believe in complex and true mathematical theorem, I cannot be wrong, but it doesn't mean that I have a justification. (example: Fermat theorem)

And mathematical theorems remain true (in some sense) even if one disbelieves them.

They are not incorrigible according to the definition.

Page 18: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Another definition: self-presenting

We have certain knowledge about our own mental states. If I'm in a mental state (I have pain), then it is neccessary that I'm aware it.

This is an other formulation of incorrigility of basic beliefs.

Self-presenting: A belief p is self-presenting if it neccessary true that if the proposition p is true at t, than I believe p at t.

'I feel pain.' If I'm in this state (I feel pain), it is neccessary that I'm aware it, it cannot be unnoticed by me.

Page 19: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Problems with foundationalism

None of the definitions of 'infallibility', 'incorrigibilty' are proper coherent definitions of 'being justified'.

Problem: What does it mean 'neccessary true'?

1. Logical sense: 'The p proposition is true at t'. 'I believe non-p at t' are inconsisent propositions.

But: p:'I'm awake' this is proposition about my own mental state, and if I'm really awake I believe that I'm awake. But is possible that I'm mistaken.

Problem: Being self-presenting doesn't mean that the belief is justified. I belive that p, when p is true. But it doesn't mean that p is (self-)justified. I may believe p when p is false.

Page 20: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Problems with foundationalism

2. Self-presenting in weaker sense:

Self-presenting is not equal to being justified.

Let p: 'I'm in a brain state S.' Suppose that it is true (because of certain causal laws) that whenever I'm in a brain states S, I always believe that 'I'm in a brain state S', but of course I can image a situation when: 1, I'm in brain state S 2, I believe that, but my belief isn't justified.

Example: A brain scientist causes my brain state S, and my belief as well. In this case my belief cannot be considered as a justified belief.

Page 21: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Problems with justification

Suppose that we have infallible beliefs (or phenomenal states).

Problem: 1, How can we infer to non-basic beliefs? What is relation between the basic and non-basic beliefs?

These appearences (or 'appearance beliefs') are subjective. They are about my own present experiences, but not about the external world. How can they establish beliefs about the external world?

2, The non-basic beliefs are fallible, even if the basic beliefs are infallible. Because we don't have conclusive reasons to conclude to non-basic beliefs.

Non-basic beliefs can be only probably true, even if the basic beliefs are infallible.

Page 22: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Problems with justification

Classical foundationalism: justification of non-basic beliefs by means of inference

Justification by inference. Suppose that appearance beliefs are infallible in a sense. (They cannot be false.)

1. Deductive valid inference.

P1: Now A seems to me red – infallible (basic)

P2: If something seems to me red, it is red. - fallible

C: A is red.

Modus ponens, deductively valid, but P2 is not true. There are possible cases when I have perceptual errors.

Even if P1 is true, C might be false.

Page 23: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Problems with justification

2. Inductive reasoning (hypothetical reasoning).

P1: Now A seems to me red. - infallible (basic)

P2: Usually when something seems to me red, it is (probably) red.

C: It is red.

Conclusion might be false, even all premises are true, because it is an inductive inference (generalisation or hypothetical reasoning.).

Final conclusion: Even if we have infallible, basic beliefs, our other, non-basic beliefs are all fallible (they can be only probably true).

Why are we seeking the infallible foundations of knowledge? At the best, a very narrow part of our knowledge is infallible (in some sense), but our most important part of knowledge remains fallible (science etc.).

Page 24: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Problems with foundationalismAre beliefs are foundations of our knowledge? Or experiences are the

foundations, and beliefs are based on direct phenomeal experiences (which have a non-propositional content)?

Foundationalist theory has problems if the justification is considered as an inference between beliefs (or other mental states.)

1.) I believe that it is white paper, because it seems to me it is white (I have an experience).

2.) Or: It belive in the proposition 'It seems white' is true.

1: How can we infer from a mental state which is not a proposition to a proposition (belief)? Inference is logical relation between propositions.

2: The basic belief would be: 'It seems to me white', but this belief is justified only because in fact I'm in a certain mental state. Therefore this belief cannot be basic.

Page 25: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Problems of justification

Classical foundationalism: p is justified if p is basic belief (state) or can be derived from justified beliefs.

But most of our knowledge depends on testimony.

Napoleon has lost a battle at Waterloo in 1815. There is a planet, Neptune which is 17 times the mass of Earth and orbits the Sun at a distance approximately 30 times the Earth-Sun distance .

These propositions cannot be derived from my present (or past) sensory experiences (sense-data). I'm not familiar with the evidences for these claims.

My beliefs (and knowledge) depend on others. I trust in other people's claims.

But this trust cannot be entirely justified according to the notion of justification of the classical, empiricist foundationalism.

Page 26: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Classical (strong) foundationalism- summary

The theory is inadequate for a philosophical reconstruction of our knowledge.

We know much about the world around us, the facts about the past and about the universe and about microscopic entities.

Even if this reconstruction is restricted to facts about an individual’s own mind it is nearly impossible to find out how we can get back to our ordinary picture of the world.

This strong version of foundationalism is not productive. We 'know' that we know a lot of things which are not (or cannot) be justified by means of my immediate sensory experience.

Page 27: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Weaker formulations of foundationalism

William Alston argues for a different version of foundationalism. The former objections seem to harmless against this theory.

Distinction between epistemic beliefs and non-epistemic beliefs. Epistemic beliefs are beliefs whose content contains an epistemic concept such as knowledge or justification.

Non-epistemic belief does not contain an epistemic concept.

The belief that there is a red circle before me is not an epistemic belief because does not contain any epistemic concepts.

The belief that I am justified in believing that there is a red, circle before me is an epistemic belief.

The classical version of foundationalism didn't make this distinction.

Page 28: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Weaker formulations of foundationalism

An argument against (classical) foundationalism might require that to be justified in believing that p one must justifiedly believe that I am justified in believing that p.

Alston: 1. I can justifiedly believe that p, unless I'm justified in 'I'm justifiedly belief that p'.

2.Foundationalism doesn't require that: 'being justified' and 'the ability of making a justification' are the same.

S can be justified in believing that she has hands without being in a position to exhibit her justification. S is justified in believing that she has existed for more than five minutes but she cannot demonstrate her justification.

Page 29: Epistemology Tihamér Margitay – Péter Hartl 4. Foundationalism.

Foundationalism without infallibility

3. Immediately justified beliefs may be fallible, revisable, and dubitable.

S’s belief that she has hands is might be false and revised in light of future evidence.

Perhaps she has been fitted with a prosthetic device that looks and functions just like a normal hand.

But when she looks and appears to see a hand, she is fully justified in believing that she has hands.

Externalism: Justification is not just a (logical) relation between my mental states (beliefs of perceptions).

Being justified depends on factors which are external compared to my mind.